File size: 104,640 Bytes
6fa4bc9
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
1001
1002
1003
1004
1005
1006
1007
1008
1009
1010
1011
1012
1013
1014
1015
1016
1017
1018
1019
1020
1021
1022
1023
1024
1025
1026
1027
1028
1029
1030
1031
1032
1033
1034
1035
1036
1037
1038
1039
1040
1041
1042
1043
1044
1045
1046
1047
1048
1049
1050
1051
1052
1053
1054
1055
1056
1057
1058
1059
1060
1061
1062
1063
1064
1065
1066
1067
1068
1069
1070
1071
1072
1073
1074
1075
1076
1077
1078
1079
1080
1081
1082
1083
1084
1085
1086
1087
1088
1089
1090
1091
1092
1093
1094
1095
1096
1097
1098
1099
1100
1101
1102
1103
1104
1105
1106
1107
1108
1109
1110
1111
1112
1113
1114
1115
1116
1117
1118
1119
1120
1121
1122
1123
1124
1125
1126
1127
1128
1129
1130
1131
1132
1133
1134
1135
1136
1137
1138
1139
1140
1141
1142
1143
1144
1145
1146
1147
1148
1149
1150
1151
1152
1153
1154
1155
1156
1157
1158
1159
1160
1161
1162
1163
1164
1165
1166
1167
1168
1169
1170
1171
1172
1173
1174
1175
1176
1177
1178
1179
1180
1181
1182
1183
1184
1185
1186
1187
1188
1189
1190
1191
1192
1193
1194
1195
1196
1197
1198
1199
1200
1201
1202
1203
1204
1205
1206
1207
1208
1209
1210
1211
1212
1213
1214
1215
1216
1217
1218
1219
1220
1221
1222
1223
1224
1225
1226
1227
1228
1229
1230
1231
1232
1233
1234
1235
1236
1237
1238
1239
1240
1241
1242
1243
1244
1245
1246
1247
1248
1249
1250
1251
1252
1253
1254
1255
1256
1257
1258
1259
1260
1261
1262
1263
1264
1265
1266
1267
1268
1269
1270
1271
1272
1273
1274
1275
1276
1277
1278
1279
1280
1281
1282
1283
1284
1285
1286
1287
1288
1289
1290
1291
1292
1293
1294
1295
1296
1297
1298
1299
1300
1301
1302
1303
1304
1305
1306
1307
1308
1309
1310
1311
1312
1313
1314
1315
1316
1317
1318
1319
1320
1321
1322
1323
1324
1325
1326
1327
1328
1329
1330
1331
1332
1333
1334
1335
1336
1337
1338
1339
1340
1341
1342
1343
1344
1345
1346
1347
1348
1349
1350
1351
1352
1353
1354
1355
1356
1357
1358
1359
1360
1361
1362
1363
1364
1365
1366
1367
1368
1369
1370
1371
1372
1373
1374
1375
1376
1377
1378
1379
1380
1381
1382
1383
1384
1385
1386
1387
1388
1389
1390
1391
1392
1393
1394
1395
1396
1397
1398
1399
1400
1401
1402
1403
1404
1405
1406
1407
1408
1409
1410
1411
1412
1413
1414
1415
1416
1417
1418
1419
1420
1421
1422
1423
1424
1425
1426
1427
1428
1429
1430
1431
1432
1433
1434
1435
1436
1437
1438
1439
1440
1441
1442
1443
1444
1445
1446
1447
1448
1449
1450
1451
1452
1453
1454
1455
1456
1457
1458
1459
1460
1461
1462
1463
1464
1465
1466
1467
1468
1469
1470
1471
1472
1473
1474
1475
1476
1477
1478
1479
1480
1481
1482
1483
1484
1485
1486
1487
1488
1489
1490
1491
1492
1493
1494
1495
1496
1497
1498
1499
1500
1501
1502
1503
1504
1505
1506
1507
1508
1509
1510
1511
1512
1513
1514
1515
1516
1517
1518
1519
1520
1521
1522
1523
1524
1525
1526
1527
1528
1529
1530
1531
1532
1533
1534
1535
1536
1537
1538
1539
1540
1541
1542
1543
1544
1545
1546
1547
1548
1549
1550
1551
1552
1553
1554
1555
1556
1557
1558
1559
1560
1561
1562
1563
1564
1565
1566
1567
1568
1569
1570
1571
1572
1573
1574
1575
1576
1577
1578
1579
1580
1581
1582
1583
1584
1585
1586
1587
1588
1589
1590
1591
1592
1593
1594
1595
1596
1597
1598
1599
1600
1601
1602
1603
1604
1605
1606
1607
1608
1609
1610
1611
1612
1613
1614
1615
1616
1617
1618
1619
1620
1621
1622
1623
1624
1625
1626
1627
1628
1629
1630
1631
1632
1633
1634
1635
1636
1637
1638
1639
1640
1641
1642
1643
1644
1645
1646
1647
1648
1649
1650
1651
1652
1653
1654
1655
1656
1657
1658
1659
1660
1661
1662
1663
1664
1665
1666
1667
1668
1669
1670
1671
1672
1673
1674
1675
1676
1677
1678
1679
1680
1681
1682
1683
1684
1685
1686
1687
1688
1689
1690
1691
1692
1693
1694
1695
1696
1697
1698
1699
1700
1701
1702
1703
1704
1705
1706
1707
1708
1709
1710
1711
1712
1713
1714
1715
1716
1717
1718
1719
1720
1721
1722
1723
1724
1725
1726
1727
1728
1729
1730
1731
1732
1733
1734
1735
1736
1737
1738
1739
1740
1741
1742
1743
1744
1745
1746
1747
1748
1749
1750
1751
1752
1753
1754
1755
1756
1757
1758
1759
1760
1761
1762
1763
1764
1765
1766
1767
1768
1769
1770
1771
1772
1773
1774
1775
1776
1777
1778
1779
1780
1781
1782
1783
1784
1785
1786
1787
1788
1789
1790
1791
1792
1793
1794
1795
1796
1797
1798
1799
1800
1801
1802
1803
1804
1805
1806
1807
1808
1809
1810
1811
1812
1813
1814
1815
1816
1817
1818
1819
1820
1821
1822
1823
1824
1825
1826
1827
1828
1829
1830
1831
1832
1833
1834
1835
1836
1837
1838
1839
1840
1841
1842
1843
1844
1845
1846
1847
1848
1849
1850
1851
1852
1853
1854
1855
1856
1857
1858
1859
1860
1861
1862
1863
1864
1865
1866
1867
1868
1869
1870
1871
1872
1873
1874
1875
1876
1877
1878
1879
1880
1881
1882
1883
1884
1885
1886
1887
1888
1889
1890
1891
1892
1893
1894
1895
1896
1897
1898
1899
1900
1901
1902
1903
1904
1905
1906
1907
1908
1909
1910
1911
1912
1913
1914
1915
1916
1917
1918
1919
1920
1921
1922
1923
1924
1925
1926
1927
1928
1929
1930
1931
1932
1933
1934
1935
1936
1937
1938
1939
1940
1941
1942
1943
1944
1945
1946
1947
1948
1949
1950
1951
1952
1953
1954
1955
1956
1957
1958
1959
1960
1961
1962
1963
1964
1965
1966
{
    "paper_id": "2021",
    "header": {
        "generated_with": "S2ORC 1.0.0",
        "date_generated": "2023-01-19T07:24:27.437204Z"
    },
    "title": "Applied Temporal Analysis: A Complete Run of the FraCaS Test Suite",
    "authors": [
        {
            "first": "Jean-Philippe",
            "middle": [],
            "last": "Bernardy",
            "suffix": "",
            "affiliation": {
                "laboratory": "Centre for Linguistic Theory and Studies in Probability",
                "institution": "University of Gothenburg",
                "location": {}
            },
            "email": ""
        },
        {
            "first": "Stergios",
            "middle": [],
            "last": "Chatzikyriakidis",
            "suffix": "",
            "affiliation": {
                "laboratory": "Centre for Linguistic Theory and Studies in Probability",
                "institution": "University of Gothenburg",
                "location": {}
            },
            "email": ""
        }
    ],
    "year": "",
    "venue": null,
    "identifiers": {},
    "abstract": "In this paper, we propose an implementation of temporal semantics that translates syntax trees to logical formulas, suitable for consumption by the Coq proof assistant. The analysis supports a wide range of phenomena including: temporal references, temporal adverbs, aspectual classes and progressives. The new semantics are built on top of a previous system handling all sections of the FraCaS test suite except the temporal reference section, and we obtain an accuracy of 81 percent overall and 73 percent for the problems explicitly marked as related to temporal reference. To the best of our knowledge, this is the best performance of a logical system on the whole of the FraCaS.",
    "pdf_parse": {
        "paper_id": "2021",
        "_pdf_hash": "",
        "abstract": [
            {
                "text": "In this paper, we propose an implementation of temporal semantics that translates syntax trees to logical formulas, suitable for consumption by the Coq proof assistant. The analysis supports a wide range of phenomena including: temporal references, temporal adverbs, aspectual classes and progressives. The new semantics are built on top of a previous system handling all sections of the FraCaS test suite except the temporal reference section, and we obtain an accuracy of 81 percent overall and 73 percent for the problems explicitly marked as related to temporal reference. To the best of our knowledge, this is the best performance of a logical system on the whole of the FraCaS.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Abstract",
                "sec_num": null
            }
        ],
        "body_text": [
            {
                "text": "The semantics of tense and aspect has been a long standing issue in the study of formal semantics since the early days of Montague Grammar and a number of different ideas have been put forth to deal with them throughout the years. Recent proposals include the works of the following authors: Dowty (2012); Prior and Hasle (2003) ; Steedman (2000) ; Higginbotham (2009) ; Fernando (2015) . The semantics of tense and aspect have been also considered in the study of Natural Language Inference (NLI). The various datasets for NLI that have been proposed by the years contain examples that have some implicit or explicit reliance on inferences related to tense and aspect. One of the early datasets used to test logical approaches, the FraCaS test suite (Cooper et al., 1996) contains a whole section dedicated to temporal and aspectual inference (section 7 of the dataset). This part of the FraCaS test suite has been difficult to tackle. That is, so far, no computational system has been capable to deal with it in its entirety: when authors report accuracy over the FraCaS test suite they skip this section. In fact, they also often skip the anaphora and ellipsis sections, the exception being the system presented by Chatzikyriakidis (2017, 2019) , which includes support for anaphora and ellipsis but still omit the temporal section. 1 In this paper, we take up the challenge of providing a computationally viable account of tense and aspect to deal with the section 7 of the FraCaS test suite. Our account is not meant to be a theoretically extensive account of tense and aspect, but rather an account that is driven by the need to cover the test suite in a way that is general enough to capture the test suite examples, while still covering the rest of the FraCaS test suite.",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 306,
                        "end": 328,
                        "text": "Prior and Hasle (2003)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF22"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 331,
                        "end": 346,
                        "text": "Steedman (2000)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF24"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 349,
                        "end": 368,
                        "text": "Higginbotham (2009)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF13"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 371,
                        "end": 386,
                        "text": "Fernando (2015)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF12"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 751,
                        "end": 772,
                        "text": "(Cooper et al., 1996)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF10"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 1218,
                        "end": 1247,
                        "text": "Chatzikyriakidis (2017, 2019)",
                        "ref_id": null
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 1336,
                        "end": 1337,
                        "text": "1",
                        "ref_id": null
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Introduction",
                "sec_num": "1"
            },
            {
                "text": "The account is evaluated on the entailment properties of various temporal and aspectual examples, as given by the test suite. As such, we are not getting into the discussion of how tense and aspect might affect grammaticality or infelicitousness of various sentences. We assume that the sentences of the FraCaS suite are syntactically and semantically correct, and strive to produce accurate logical representations given that assumption. We further assume that the entailment annotations of various problems are valid, and we use those to evaluate the correctness of the logical representations of sentences.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Introduction",
                "sec_num": "1"
            },
            {
                "text": "The paper is structured as follows: in Section 2, we give a brief summary of the computational frameworks whose various subsystems rely on. In particular, the Grammatical Framework is used to construct the syntactic parser, the Coq proof assistant checks all the reasoning and a monad-based dynamic semantics deals with Montague-style se- 1 One can consider that MacCartney and Manning (2007) have made a run against the whole test suite. However, they do not deal with multi-premise cases. Consequently only 36/75 cases in the temporal section are attempted. The general accuracy of the system is .59, and .61 for the temporal section. Our system, as shown Table 1 , presents considerable improvements in coverage and accuracy over that of MacCartney and Manning. mantics, and references (anaphora). We also provide some brief remarks on temporal semantics. In Section 3, we discuss the main aspects of the compositional semantics of our system, using various examples from the FraCaS suite to illustrate its effectiveness. In Section 5, we evaluate how our system performs with respect to the FraCaS suite. We ran the system across the whole suite: our system is thus the first which is capable of handling the complete FraCaS test suite. Yet, we are interested in particular in the performance on the temporal section. In Section 6, we conclude and discuss avenues for future work.",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 339,
                        "end": 340,
                        "text": "1",
                        "ref_id": null
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 363,
                        "end": 392,
                        "text": "MacCartney and Manning (2007)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF15"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 741,
                        "end": 764,
                        "text": "MacCartney and Manning.",
                        "ref_id": null
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 658,
                        "end": 665,
                        "text": "Table 1",
                        "ref_id": null
                    }
                ],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Introduction",
                "sec_num": "1"
            },
            {
                "text": "Our temporal analysis places itself in the context of a complete NLI system -which is why we can test it on the FraCaS suite. In this section we give a brief overview of the phases of the system, referring the reader to published work for details.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Temporal-Semantics in a Logic-based NLI System",
                "sec_num": "2"
            },
            {
                "text": "GF The first phase of the system, parsing, is taken care of by the Grammatical Framework (GF, Ranta (2004) ), which is a powerful parser generator for natural languages, based on type-theoretical abstract grammars. The present work leverages a syntactic representation of the FraCaS test suite in GF abstract syntax, in effect a GF FraCaS treebank (Ljungl\u00f6f and Siverbo, 2011) . Thanks to this, we skip the parsing phase and avoid any syntactic ambiguity. For the purpose of this paper, the important feature of GF syntax is that it aims at a balance of sufficient abstraction to provide a semanticallyrelevant structure, but at the same time it embeds sufficiently many syntactic features to be able to reconstruct natural-language text. That is, the parse trees generally satisfy the homomorphism requirement of Montague (1970 Montague ( , 1974 , and we can focus on the translation of syntactic trees to logical forms. Consequently, the system presented here does not aim at textual natural language understanding, but rather provides a testable, systematic formal semantics of temporal phenomena. Example (1) shows an example abstract syntax tree and its realisation in English.",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 94,
                        "end": 106,
                        "text": "Ranta (2004)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF23"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 348,
                        "end": 376,
                        "text": "(Ljungl\u00f6f and Siverbo, 2011)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF14"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 814,
                        "end": 828,
                        "text": "Montague (1970",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF17"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 829,
                        "end": 846,
                        "text": "Montague ( , 1974",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF19"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Temporal-Semantics in a Logic-based NLI System",
                "sec_num": "2"
            },
            {
                "text": "Dynamic Semantics Parse trees are then processed by a dynamic semantic component. Its role is essentially to support (non-temporal) anaphora, using a monadic-based dynamic semantics, gen-erally following the state of the art in this matter (Unger, 2011; Charlow, 2015 Charlow, , 2017 . Our particular implementation has weaknesses in certain areas (including group readings and counting; see Bernardy et al. (2020) for details) but non-temporal anaphoroi in the testsuite are generally resolved as they should be: on the whole accuracy is not affected significantly by issues in this subsystem.",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 240,
                        "end": 253,
                        "text": "(Unger, 2011;",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF25"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 254,
                        "end": 267,
                        "text": "Charlow, 2015",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF7"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 268,
                        "end": 283,
                        "text": "Charlow, , 2017",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF8"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 392,
                        "end": 414,
                        "text": "Bernardy et al. (2020)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF5"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Temporal-Semantics in a Logic-based NLI System",
                "sec_num": "2"
            },
            {
                "text": "As it is the case for other basic phenomena, there is not much interaction between our treatment of time and non-temporal anaphora. Critical exceptions are discussed in Section 3 and Section 5.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Temporal-Semantics in a Logic-based NLI System",
                "sec_num": "2"
            },
            {
                "text": "Montagovian Semantics Non-withstanding special support for anaphora, the core of the translation of syntax trees to logical form follows a standard montagovian semantics. In brief, sentences are interpreted as propositions, verbs and noun-phrases as predicates. We use type-raising of noun-phrases, to support quantifiers (Montague, 1974) .",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 322,
                        "end": 338,
                        "text": "(Montague, 1974)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF19"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Temporal-Semantics in a Logic-based NLI System",
                "sec_num": "2"
            },
            {
                "text": "We support additionally the basic constructions and phenomena present in the testsuite, including adjectives, adverbs, nouns, verbs, anaphora, etc. The method is outlined by Montague (1970 Montague ( , 1973 ), but we direct the reader to our previous work for details Chatzikyriakidis (2017, 2019) , but the particular treatment of such phenomena is essentially independent from our treatment of time: in this paper we simply ignore these aspects beyond the fact that they are handled correctly in the FraCaS testsuite, except in a few pathological cases.",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 174,
                        "end": 188,
                        "text": "Montague (1970",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF17"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 189,
                        "end": 206,
                        "text": "Montague ( , 1973",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF18"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 268,
                        "end": 297,
                        "text": "Chatzikyriakidis (2017, 2019)",
                        "ref_id": null
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Temporal-Semantics in a Logic-based NLI System",
                "sec_num": "2"
            },
            {
                "text": "Inference using Coq Logical forms are then fed to the Coq interactive theorem prover (proof assistant). Coq is based on the calculus of co-inductive constructions (Werner, 1994) We do not use any co-induction (or even induction) in this paper, relying on the pure lambda-calculus inner core of Coq. Coq is a very powerful reasoning engine that makes it fit for implementing natural language semantics. Coq also supports dependent typing and subtyping. Both concepts are instrumental in expressing NL semantics (Chatzikyriakidis and Luo, 2014) . Besides, on a more practical side, it works well for the the task of NLI, when the latter is formalised as a theorem proving task: its many tactics mean that many tasks in theorem proving are trivialised. In particular, all problems of time-intervals inclusion, which occur in every temporal problems, are solved with Coq's linear arithmetic tactic.",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 163,
                        "end": 177,
                        "text": "(Werner, 1994)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF27"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 510,
                        "end": 542,
                        "text": "(Chatzikyriakidis and Luo, 2014)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF9"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Temporal-Semantics in a Logic-based NLI System",
                "sec_num": "2"
            },
            {
                "text": "In montagovian semantics, (intransitive) verbs are one-place predicates; in types, they are functions from entities to propositions (e \u2192 t). Our basic approach is to generalise the interpretation of verbs, so that it takes two additional time parameters, one corresponding to the starting time of the action and one corresponding to its stopping time ((e \u00d7 time \u00d7 time) \u2192 t). For example, if John walked between t 0 and t 1 , we would have: walk(john, t 0 , t 1 ). From now on we will call an interval of time points [t 0 , t 1 ] a timespan, where t 0 and t 1 are elements of the time type, which is represented in Coq as an abstract ordered ring. Every timespan [t 0 , t 1 ] has the property t 0 \u2264 t 1 : it starts no later than it stops. (We are thus using a simple Newtonian model of time, corresponding to a layman intuition of a linear constant flow of time.)",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "In principle, common nouns and adjectives should undergo the same procedure. For simplicity we will however only consider verbs from now on. (In fact, even in our implementation we chose not to extend nouns nor adjectives with timespan parameters. This choice limits the increase in complexity of the formulas compared to non-temporal semantics, at the expense of inaccuracy for a couple of problems in the FraCaS test suite: problems 271 and 272 use a an adjective as a copula which is subject to temporal reasoning.)",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "(271) A unknown P1 Smith was present.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "P2 Jones was present.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "P3 Smith was present after Jones was present. H Jones was present before Smith was present.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Temporal Context We adjust the montagovian semantics so that the interpretation of every category (propositions, verb phrases, etc.) takes a temporal context as an additional parameter, which serves as a time reference for the interpretation of all time-dependent semantics within the phrase. (While some categories do not need this temporal context, we pass it everywhere for consistency.) This context propagates through the compositional interpretation down to lexical items with atomic representation (verbs). By default, every interpretation passes the temporal context down to its components without changing it. However some key elements will act on it on nontrivial ways, which we proceed to detail below. This temporal context is an optional timespan. That is, it can be a timespan or an explicitly unspecified context. The timespan in the context is optional because, in certain situations, the semantics is different depending on whether a timespan has been specified externally or not, as we explain below. A non-present timespan will be represented as \u2212. If a semantic function does not depend on the temporal context at all, we will write * instead.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Tenses The principal non-trivial manipulators of timespans are tense markers. In our syntax, inherited from GF, tenses are represented syntactically as an attribute of clauses. An illustration of a pasttense clause and its interpretation follows in Example (1). Notice in particular the past argument to the useCl constructor.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "(1) A scandinavian won the nobel prize.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "useCl past pP os",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "(predV P (detCN (detQuant indef Art numSg) scandinavian CN ) (complSlash (slashV \uf732a win V \uf732) (detCN (detQuant indef Art numSg) nobel prize CN )))",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "In our semantics we deal only with present and past tenses (simple and continuous). Indeed we find that FraCas does not exercise additional specific tenses. (When a more complicated tense is used, the additional information is also carried by adverbs or adverbial phrases, in a more specific way). While we believe that many other tenses can be captured under the same general framework, we leave a detailed study to further work. Even though we discuss a refinement to handle the past continuous at the end of this section, the procedure to handle tense annotations is as follows:",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "\u2022 If the tense is the past, and the temporal context is unspecified, then we locally quantify over a time interval [t 0 , t 1 ], such that t 1 < now, where now is a logical constant representing the current timepoint. The temporal context then becomes this interval.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "\u2022 If the tense is the present and the temporal context is unspecified, then the temporal context becomes the simple (now, now) interval.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "\u2022 If the temporal context is specified (for example due to the presence of an adverb or an adverbial clause, such as \"before James swam\"), then the tense does not create a new interval, but it may constrain it. Typically, a past tense adds the constraint that the temporal context ends before the timepoint now.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Temporal Adverbs The other single most important source of interesting timespans are adverbs. Most of the temporal adverbs fall in either of the following categories:",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "exact For such adverbs, an exact interval is provided. In fact, such adverbs typically specify a single point in time (so the start and the end of the interval coincide).",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "at 5 pm, s ( * ) = s (5pm, 5pm)",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "existentially quantifying The majority of temporal adverbs existentially quantify over a timespan. Examples include \"since 1991\", \"in 1996\", \"for two years\", etc. The common theme is to introduce the interval and then restrict its bounds or its duration in some way. Sometimes the restriction is an equality, as in \"for exactly two hours\". In the following example we show the inclusion constraint, for \"in 1992\". in 1992,",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "s ( * ) = \u2203t 1 , t 2 .[t 1 , t 2 ] \u2286 1992, s (t 1 , t 2 )",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "In the FraCaS test suite, we normally do not find several time-modifying adverbs modifying a single verb phrase. Indeed, sentences such as \"in 1992, in 1991 john wrote a novel\" are infelicitous. This justifies ignoring the input timespan in the above interpretation -we are in particular not interested in modelling felicity with our semantics, only giving an accurate semantics when the input is felicitous.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "universally quantifying A few adverbs introduce intervals via a universal quantification (sometimes with a constraint). Examples include \"always\" and \"never\".",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "If there is no explicit time context, then \"always\" has no constraint on the interval, otherwise the quantified interval must be included in it:",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "always s (t 0 , t 1 ) = \u2200t 0 , t 1 .[t 0 , t 1 ] \u2286 [t 0 , t 1 ], s (t 0 , t 1 )",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Note that here we do use the input interval, resulting in a correct interpretation for phrases such as \"In 1994, Itel was always on time.\" .",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Aside: aspectual classes in the literature In this paper we borrow several notions from classical temporal semantics such as \"stative\", \"achievement\", \"activity\", etc., even though our definitions do not perfectly match the classical ones. We explain our precise meaning for these terms in the body of the paper. Nevertheless, we refer the reader to Steedman (2000) for an extensive review of formal temporal semantics. For the cognoscenti, we can already point out some differences in terminology: we use the term activity as a general term which encompasses the three classical notions of activites, achievements and accomplishments. Indeed, insofar as the test suite is concerned, we find that these three categories can be collapsed into a single one (they are subject to Eq. (1)). That is, it is sufficient for the testsuite to distinguish between events and states. (In this paper, we always assume that the problems in the FraCaS testsuite are correctly annotated.)",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 350,
                        "end": 365,
                        "text": "Steedman (2000)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF24"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Time references and aspectual classes A common theme in the testsuite is the reference to previous occurrences of an event: To be able to conclude that there is entailment, as the testsuite expects, we have to make sure that the two occurrences of \"Jones left\" (in P1 and P2) refer to the same time intervals. For this purpose we postulate unicity of action for certain time-dependent propositions:",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "unicity P : P (t 1 , t 2 ) \u2192 P (t 3 , t 4 ) \u2192 (t 1 = t 3 ) \u2227 (t 2 = t 4 ) (1)",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Unicity of action holds only if the aspectual class of the proposition P is activity (Steedman, 2000) (which, for our purposes, includes achievements and accomplishments as well).",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 85,
                        "end": 101,
                        "text": "(Steedman, 2000)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF24"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "(The difference between activity and accomplishments on the one hand and achievement on the other hand is that for the latter, time intervals can be assumed to be of nil duration. In reality, this is an oversimplification as achievements are usually of short duration, but not nil. However, this plays little role in our analysis. As far as we can tell the FraCaS test suite does exercise temporal semantics to such a level of precision.)",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Unicity of action plays the role of event coreference in (neo-)Davidsonian accounts (Parsons, 1990) . It is also a fine-grained principle, allowing coreference to take into account certain arguments when referencing. As we detail below, taking arguments into account yields is critical to handle repeatability of achievements.",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 84,
                        "end": 99,
                        "text": "(Parsons, 1990)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF21"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Unicity of action appears to be a non-logical principle. Indeed, it is quite possible that \"Jones left\" several times. However, it seems that this principle is never contradicted by the testsuite. As such, even though unicity of action is only a pragmatic rule, it can be taken as a valid one by default: it is only when we have a sufficiently constrained situation that one should reject it. Consider the following discourse:",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "(1) Smith left at 1pm.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "(2) Smith went to his appointment with the lawyer. (3) Smith left at 4pm.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "One would normally not say that there is contradiction. However if the middle sentence were not present, a contradiction should be flagged. We leave such discourse analysis as future work, and simply apply unicity of action everywhere: it is valid uniformly in the FraCaS test suite for activity aspect classes.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Statives A contrario, if P is stative, then we get a time-interval subsumption property:",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "subsumption P : [t 3 , t 4 ] \u2286 [t 1 , t 2 ] \u2192 P (t 1 , t 2 ) \u2192 P (t 3 , t 4 )",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "This principle is used to reason about problem (314), below (note that \"Smith\" is used as a surname in the FraCaS and can take both feminine and masculine values):",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "(314) P1 Smith arrived in Paris on the 5th of May, 1995. P2 Today is the 15th of May, 1995. P3 She is still in Paris. H Smith was in Paris on the 7th of May, 1995.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Indeed, from P3 we get that Smith was in Paris between May 5th and May 15th. Because \"being in Paris\" is stative, we also get that Smith was in Paris in any sub-interval. Contrary to unicity of action, subsumption is always valid.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Class-modifying adverbs It should be noted that some adverbs can locally disable the application of subsumption. For example, problem 299 features the sentence \"Smith lived in Birmingham for exactly a year\". Even though \"live\" is normally stative, one can no longer apply subsumption in the context of \"exactly a year\" -this can be done by propagating another context flag in the montagovian semantics (in addition to the temporal context).",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "(Un)repeatable Achievements The principle of using unicity of action interacts well with the usual interpretation of existential quantifiers (and anaphora). Indeed, using it, we can refute problem (279), as expected by the testsuite:",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "(279) P1 Smith wrote a novel in 1991.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "H Smith wrote it in 1992.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Indeed, following our account, the above (contradictory) inference problem is to be interpreted as",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "\u2200x.novel(x)\u2227 \u2203t 1 , t 2 .[t 1 , t 2 ] \u2286 1991 \u2227 write(smith, x, t 1 , t 2 )\u2227 \u2203t 3 , t 4 .[t 3 , t 4 ] \u2286 1992 \u2227 write(smith, x, t 3 , t 4 ) \u2212\u2192\u22a5",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "(2) Note here that the scope for the existential is extended beyond the scope of P1, and its polarity switched (to universal). This extension can follow the account of Unger (2011), and our implemented analysis of anaphora (Bernardy et al., 2020; Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis, 2019) .",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 223,
                        "end": 246,
                        "text": "(Bernardy et al., 2020;",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF5"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 247,
                        "end": 283,
                        "text": "Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis, 2019)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF4"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Thanks to the unicity of action of write(smith, x, ...) (the subject and direct object are fixed) we find [t 1 , t 2 ] = [t 3 , t 4 ], and due to the years 1991 and 1992 being disjoint we obtain contradiction. In sum, no special notion of accomplishment is needs to be invoked: we only need the principle of unicity of action.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Yet, the testsuite instructs that we should not be able to refute problem (280), with the justification that \"wrote a novel\" is a repeatable accomplishment:",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "(280) P1 Smith wrote a novel in 1991.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "H Smith wrote a novel in 1992.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Here our interpretation is:",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "(\u2203x.novel(x)\u2227 \u2203t 1 , t 2 .[t 1 , t 2 ] \u2286 1991 \u2227 write(smith, x, t 1 , t 2 ))\u2227 (\u2203y.novel(y)\u2227 \u2203t 3 , t 4 .[t 3 , t 4 ] \u2286 1992 \u2227 write(smith, y, t 3 , t 4 )) \u2212\u2192\u22a5",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Our analysis does not need to treat this last case specially. Indeed, even if write(smith, x, ., .) is an activity and thus subject to unicity of action, in (280), x is quantified existentially; we have two different actions: write(smith, x, t 1 , t 2 ) and write(smith, y, t 3 , t 4 ), because x = y, and thus we cannot deduce equality of the intervals t 1 , t 2 and t 3 , t 4 . In turn, the hypothesis cannot be refuted.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Action-modification Verbs The final class of lexemes carrying a temporal-dependent semantics are verbs taking a proposition as argument, like \"finish\", \"start\", etc. These verbs modify the temporal context in non-trivial ways. Consider for example \"finish to ...\". The timespan of the argument of \"finish\" should end within the timespan of the finishing action:",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "finish to s (t 0 , t 1 ) = \u2203(t 0 , t 1 ).t 1 \u2208 [t 0 , t 1 ] \u2227 s (t 0 , t 1 )",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Progressive Aspect We treat verbs in the progressive form as different semantically from the non-progressive form. For example, \"John was writing a book\" is encoded as \u2203(t 1 , t 2 ).t 1 \u2264 t 2 , t 2 \u2264 now, P ROG write(John, book, t 1 , t 2 ), while \"John wrote a book\" is encoded as \u2203(t 1 , t 2 ).t 1 \u2264 t 2 , t 2 \u2264 now, write(John, book, t 1 , t 2 ). This distinction is necessary because in our analysis the progressive form (P ROG write) is subject to subsumption. That is, if John is writing in the interval [t 1 , t 2 ] then he is writing in any sub-interval of [t 1 , t 2 ]. This interpretation corresponds to the idea that the action takes place continuously over the whole interval. However, the same cannot be said of the non-continuous form (write): the end-points of the interval indicate the time needed to complete the achievement. (For example, \"John wrote a book in 1993\" neither entails \"John wrote a book in January 1993\" nor \"John wrote a book in December 1993\".) (In fact, write, in the non-progressive from, is on the contrary subject to unicity.) Finally, we also have write(x, y, t 1 , t 2 ) \u2192 P ROG write(x, y, t 1 , t 2 ).",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "That is, the achievement (or activity in our terminology) variant implies the stative variant, for the same interval. Consequently we get the entailment from \"John wrote a book in 1993\" to \"John was writing a book in 1993\", but not the other way around.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "We note however that this interpretation differs only slightly from the usual accounts of the progressive in the literature. Ogihara (2007) summarises the position of Bennett and Partee (1978) as follows: a progressive sentence is true at an inter-",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 125,
                        "end": 139,
                        "text": "Ogihara (2007)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF20"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 167,
                        "end": 192,
                        "text": "Bennett and Partee (1978)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF2"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "val [t 0 , t 1 ] iff there is an interval [t 0 , t 1 ] such that [t 0 , t 1 ]",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "is a non-final subinterval of [t 0 , t 1 ] and the progressive sentence is true at [t 0 , t 1 ]. This is very similar to our approach (subsumption for the progressive form only), but there is a difference regarding final intervals. Yet in our view this difference is hard to justify: we cannot see why \"John was writing a book in 1993\" entails that he was writing it January, February, etc. but not in December. Ogihara (2007) argues that this simple account of the progressive fails to reject a sentence such as \"Lee is resembling Terri.\" while \"Lee is walking\" is acceptable. We argue instead that the latter should be rejected for pragmatic reasons. Indeed, when a predicate holds for a very long interval, one typically uses the simple present tense in English. Therefore the continuous form pragmatically implies that the predicate holds for a limited interval. But, without further context, the predicate \"resemble Terri\" does not vary over time (while \"walk\" generally does). Therefore the continuous form \"Lee is resembling Terri\" is confusing: one implies a limited interval, but the semantics of resembling normally yield an unlimited interval. Because we do not account for pragmatics, we prefer to retain the simplest account based on the subinterval property (which we call subsumption here).",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 412,
                        "end": 426,
                        "text": "Ogihara (2007)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF20"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "Finally we stress that not all verbs are subject to the stative/achievement distinction induced by the progressive. For example, the phrases \"John ran\" and \"John was running\" appear to be logically equivalent, for entailment purposes.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Our Treatment of Time",
                "sec_num": "3"
            },
            {
                "text": "To give a sense of the additional details necessary to deal with the precision demanded by a proofassistant such as Coq we show how problem (279) is worked out in full details.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Worked out example",
                "sec_num": "4"
            },
            {
                "text": "We start with input trees in GF format, given by Ljungl\u00f6f and Siverbo (2011) . They can be rendered as follows: s_279_1_p= sentence (useCl past pPos (predVP (usePN (lexemePN \"smith_PN\")) (advVP (complSlash (slashV2a (lexemeV2 \"write_V2\"))) (detCN (detQuant indefArt numSg) (useN (lexemeN \"novel_N\")))) (lexemeAdv \"in_1991_Adv\"))) s_279_3_h= sentence (useCl past pPos (predVP (usePN (lexemePN \"smith_PN\")) (advVP (complSlash (slashV2a (lexemeV2 \"write_V2\")) (usePron it_Pron)) (lexemeAdv \"in_1992_Adv\"))))",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 49,
                        "end": 76,
                        "text": "Ljungl\u00f6f and Siverbo (2011)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF14"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Worked out example",
                "sec_num": "4"
            },
            {
                "text": "Of particular note is the use of the pronoun \"it\", and the fact that adverbial expressions such that \"in 1992\" are lexicalized. We also follow the GF convention to postfix lexical items with the name of their category. Most of the other categories follow usual naming conventions. We remind the reader that \"slash\" categories are used to swap the order of arguments (compared to non-slashed categories of similar names).",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Worked out example",
                "sec_num": "4"
            },
            {
                "text": "Our dynamic and temporal semantics gives the following interpretation for s_279_1_p implies s_279_3_h. (IS_INTERVAL Date_19920101 f /\\ IS_INTERVAL g Date_19921231 /\\ IS_INTERVAL f g /\\ appTime f g (write_V2 a) (PN2object smith_PN)))))).",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Worked out example",
                "sec_num": "4"
            },
            {
                "text": "In the above, one should remark the top-level quantification over the novel (as explained in Section 3), the quantification over time intervals as individual timepoints, and the use of custom operators for several constructions (FORALL, Not, IS_INTERVAL, appTime). This use of custom operators is useful for several generalisations (for example, we have quantifiers such as MOST in addition to FORALL -see Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis (2017) ) Unfolding the definitions for these operators yield the following proposition:",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 406,
                        "end": 444,
                        "text": "Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis (2017) )",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF3"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Worked out example",
                "sec_num": "4"
            },
            {
                "text": "forall x : object, novel_N x -> (exists b c : Z, Date_19910101 <= b /\\ c <= Date_19911231 /\\ b <= c /\\ write_V2 x SMITH b c) -> (exists f g : Z, Date_19920101 <= f /\\ g <= Date_19921231 /\\ f <= g /\\ write_V2 x SMITH f g) -> False",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Worked out example",
                "sec_num": "4"
            },
            {
                "text": "This is very close to our idealised representation of the problem Eq. (2). One difference is the use of abstract Coq integers for timepoints. Using a discrete time allows us to use predefined Coq tactics. The discrete nature of integers does not interfere with the reasoning.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Worked out example",
                "sec_num": "4"
            },
            {
                "text": "Finally, we can show a Coq proof for the above proposition: The intros and destruct tactics serve bookkeeping purposes. The critical part is the use of the writeUnique axiom, which witnesses the aspectual class of the predicate write V2. The proof is completed by the use of the lia tactic, which is embeds a decision procedure for linear arithmetic problems 2 . Fortunately, lia can take care of all the problems which arise in the FraCaS testsuite.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Worked out example",
                "sec_num": "4"
            },
            {
                "text": "Our target is the FraCaS testsuite, which aims at covering a wide range of common natural-language phenomena. The suite is structured according to the semantic phenomena involved in the inference process for each example, and contains nine sections: Quantifiers, Plurals, Anaphora, Ellipsis, Adjectives, Comparatives, Temporal, Verbs and Attitudes. The system described here focuses on the Temporal section. However, it also supports the other eight sections. To our knowledge this is the first system which attempts to target the temporal section in full. But in fact, our system even provides support for all the other sections. Thus, a couple of decades Table 1 : Accuracy of our system compared to others. \"This\" refers to the approach presented in this paper. When a system does not handle the nominal number of test cases (shown in the second column), the actual number of test cases attempted is shown below the accuracy figure, in smaller font. \"FC\" refers to the work of Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis (2017) , and \"FC2\" its followup (Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis, 2019) . \"MINE\" refers to the approach of Mineshima et al. (2015) , \"NUT\" to the CCG system that utilises the first-order automated theorem prover nutcracker (Bos, 2008) , and \"LP\" to the system presented by Abzianidze (2015). A dash indicates that no attempt was made for the section.",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 980,
                        "end": 1016,
                        "text": "Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis (2017)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF3"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 1042,
                        "end": 1079,
                        "text": "(Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis, 2019)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF4"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 1115,
                        "end": 1138,
                        "text": "Mineshima et al. (2015)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF16"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 1231,
                        "end": 1242,
                        "text": "(Bos, 2008)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF6"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 657,
                        "end": 664,
                        "text": "Table 1",
                        "ref_id": null
                    }
                ],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Results and Evaluation",
                "sec_num": "5"
            },
            {
                "text": "after its formulation, we propose a first attempt at covering the whole suite. As such, there it is no other system to compare our system with, in all aspects. We can however compare with systems which target parts of the FraCaS testsuite, as shown in Table 1 .",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 252,
                        "end": 259,
                        "text": "Table 1",
                        "ref_id": null
                    }
                ],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Results and Evaluation",
                "sec_num": "5"
            },
            {
                "text": "Interaction with anaphora One reason explaining the lower performance of our system on some sections of the testsuite is that our interpretation of time interacts imperfectly with anaphora and ellipsis. Consider the following example:",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Results and Evaluation",
                "sec_num": "5"
            },
            {
                "text": "(232) P1 ITEL won more orders than APCOM did. P2 APCOM won ten orders. H ITEL won at least eleven orders.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Results and Evaluation",
                "sec_num": "5"
            },
            {
                "text": "In the first premise, our system essentially resolves the ellipsis to get the following reading: \"ITEL won X orders and APCOM won Y orders and X > Y .\". One would need each of the verb phrases \"won X orders\" and \"won Y orders\" to introduce their own timespans with existential quantifiers. However, the organisation of our system is such that the existentials are introduced before the ellipsis is expanded. Consequently we get a wrong interpretation and the inference cannot be made.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Results and Evaluation",
                "sec_num": "5"
            },
            {
                "text": "We have presented a first attempt for a computational approach dealing with the temporal section of the FraCaS test suite. To do this, we have provided a simplified taxonomy of aspectual classes for verb phrases, guided by the applicability of the unicity of action and temporal subsumption properties. While part of this simplification is accidental (conflation of activity and accomplishment), we find that other parts (the automatic distinction between repeatable and unrepeatable achievements) constitute theoretical improvements.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Conclusions and Future Work",
                "sec_num": "6"
            },
            {
                "text": "Besides inference, formal interpretation of tense is found in natural-language interfaces to databases. Of note is the work of Androutsopoulos et al. (1998) , which handles many of the time-aware adverbial clauses that we address. However, we cover many more logical aspects of inference, such as coreference via unity of action and interaction with quantifiers.",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 127,
                        "end": 156,
                        "text": "Androutsopoulos et al. (1998)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF1"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Conclusions and Future Work",
                "sec_num": "6"
            },
            {
                "text": "Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis (2019) presented a logical system for handling 8 of the 9 sections of the FraCaS test suite, but excluded section 7, suggesting that it requires many examples that need an ad hoc treatment. Here, we took up this challenge and have shown that a system similar to theirs can be extended to cover the remaining section of the test suite, without considerably decreasing the performance of the rest of the sections. This is indeed a common problem with logical approaches, namely the fact that one can have theoretically motivated implementations of individual phenomena, e.g. anaphora, ellipsis, quantifiers, temporal reference etc., but when one tries to put all these together into a unified system, this proves to be a daunting task. We believe that this paper presents an exception, and provides a system that can deal with all these different semantic phenomena under a unified system with very good results. We use the same combination of a number of well-studied tools as Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis (2019) : type theory, parsing using the Grammatical Framework (GF), Monadic Dynamic Semantics and proof assistant technology (Coq). The system achieves an accuracy of 0.73 on the Temporal Section and 0.81 overall. The whole system, including data sets, is available at the following url: https://github. com/GU-CLASP/FraCoq/tree/iwcs2021.",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 1006,
                        "end": 1042,
                        "text": "Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis (2019)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF4"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Conclusions and Future Work",
                "sec_num": "6"
            },
            {
                "text": "One of the things to be looked at is fixing the issues associated with parts of the test suite that \"broke\" when the temporal analysis was introduced. Some of these have been already mentioned: interaction of the temporal variables with anaphora.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Conclusions and Future Work",
                "sec_num": "6"
            },
            {
                "text": "Another extension of this work is to reflect more temporal semantic inference properties in an extended test suite. Indeed, there as properties which are not captured in the FraCaS test suite, such as fine-grained examples of lexical and grammatical aspect, as well as the interaction between those two, for example cases where one needs to actually distinguish between achievements and accomplishments on the basis of their inferential properties:",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Conclusions and Future Work",
                "sec_num": "6"
            },
            {
                "text": "( * 1) P1 John found his keys.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Conclusions and Future Work",
                "sec_num": "6"
            },
            {
                "text": "H John was finding his keys (UNK).",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Conclusions and Future Work",
                "sec_num": "6"
            },
            {
                "text": "( * 2) P1 John wrote a book. H John was writing a book (YES).",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Conclusions and Future Work",
                "sec_num": "6"
            },
            {
                "text": "In the first of the two examples involving an achievement verb, the inference is UNK, since there is no guarantee that the action is noninstantaneous. To the contrary, for accomplishment verbs, the inference follows.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Conclusions and Future Work",
                "sec_num": "6"
            },
            {
                "text": "Further cases to be included in an extended Fra-CaS future suite involve examples where the interaction between different tenses needs to be captured: 3 ( * 3) P1 When the phone rang, John had entered the house. H John entered the house before the phone rang (YES).",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Conclusions and Future Work",
                "sec_num": "6"
            },
            {
                "text": "Finally it would be desirable to improve automation of the system, and evaluate it on a larger test set. As it stands Coq fully checks the proof of entailment for each (provable) problem. However, the construction of such proofs has demanded human intervention. It would be desirable to fully automate the proof construction step. For this to make sense however we need a much larger test suite, properly separated into a development and a (secret) test set. Otherwise, only the limited power 3 While this work was completed, the work by (Vashishtha et al., 2020) was published. The authors present a five datasets to be used for the training of neural models' ability to capture temporal reasoning. It would be interesting to check the amount of data covered, most specifiaclly the level of finegrainedness of temporal reasoning needed to capture those examples, as compared to what we have been discussing in this paper. We thank an anonymous reviewer for bringing this work to our attention. of the logic prevents us (or any followup work) to fine-tune the rules of the system until one gets full coverage. This kind of observation holds in general of any rule-based system, and thus applies not only to the proof-construction phase, but also to the underlying dynamic semantics and parsing phase (which is limited only by the power of the language and frameworks used for its implementation). In sum, contrary to statistical approaches to language understanding, the value of the present work lies not in the bare accuracy numbers which we are able to achieve, but in the details of how we do so: the of set of rules which we use, which is described in detail here and in the work which we base ourselves upon (Bernardy et al., 2020; Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis, 2019) .",
                "cite_spans": [
                    {
                        "start": 538,
                        "end": 563,
                        "text": "(Vashishtha et al., 2020)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF26"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 1714,
                        "end": 1737,
                        "text": "(Bernardy et al., 2020;",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF5"
                    },
                    {
                        "start": 1738,
                        "end": 1774,
                        "text": "Bernardy and Chatzikyriakidis, 2019)",
                        "ref_id": "BIBREF4"
                    }
                ],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Conclusions and Future Work",
                "sec_num": "6"
            },
            {
                "text": "It solves linear goals over rings by searching for linear refutations and cutting planes",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "",
                "sec_num": null
            }
        ],
        "back_matter": [
            {
                "text": "The research reported in this paper was supported by grant 2014-39 from the Swedish Research Council, which funds the Centre for Linguistic Theory and Studies in Probability (CLASP) in the Department of Philosophy, Linguistics, and Theory of Science at the University of Gothenburg. We are grateful to our colleagues in CLASP for helpful discussion of some of the ideas presented here. We also thank anonymous reviewers for their useful comments on an earlier draft of the paper.",
                "cite_spans": [],
                "ref_spans": [],
                "eq_spans": [],
                "section": "Acknowledgements",
                "sec_num": null
            }
        ],
        "bib_entries": {
            "BIBREF0": {
                "ref_id": "b0",
                "title": "A tableau prover for natural logic and language",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Lasha Abzianidze",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2015,
                "venue": "Proceedings of EMNLP15",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Lasha Abzianidze. 2015. A tableau prover for natural logic and language. In Proceedings of EMNLP15.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF1": {
                "ref_id": "b1",
                "title": "Time, tense and aspect in natural language database interfaces",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Ion",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Androutsopoulos",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Graeme",
                        "middle": [
                            "D"
                        ],
                        "last": "Ritchie",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Peter",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Thanisch",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 1998,
                "venue": "",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Ion Androutsopoulos, Graeme D Ritchie, and Peter Thanisch. 1998. Time, tense and aspect in natural language database interfaces. arXiv preprint cmp- lg/9803002.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF2": {
                "ref_id": "b2",
                "title": "Toward the logic of tense and aspect in English",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Michael",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Bennett",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Barbara",
                        "middle": [
                            "Hall"
                        ],
                        "last": "Partee",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 1978,
                "venue": "",
                "volume": "84",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Michael Bennett and Barbara Hall Partee. 1978. To- ward the logic of tense and aspect in English, vol- ume 84. Indiana University Linguistics Club Bloom- ington.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF3": {
                "ref_id": "b3",
                "title": "A type-theoretical system for the fracas test suite: Grammatical framework meets coq",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Jean-",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Philippe",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Bernardy",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Stergios",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Chatzikyriakidis",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2017,
                "venue": "IWCS 2017-12th International Conference on Computational Semantics-Long papers",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Jean-Philippe Bernardy and Stergios Chatzikyriakidis. 2017. A type-theoretical system for the fracas test suite: Grammatical framework meets coq. In IWCS 2017-12th International Conference on Computa- tional Semantics-Long papers.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF4": {
                "ref_id": "b4",
                "title": "A wide-coverage symbolic natural language inference system",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Jean-",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Philippe",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Bernardy",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Stergios",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Chatzikyriakidis",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2019,
                "venue": "Proceedings of the 22nd Nordic Conference on Computational Linguistics. ACL",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Jean-Philippe Bernardy and Stergios Chatzikyriakidis. 2019. A wide-coverage symbolic natural language inference system. In Proceedings of the 22nd Nordic Conference on Computational Linguistics. ACL.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF5": {
                "ref_id": "b5",
                "title": "A computational treatment of anaphora and its algorithmic implementation: Extended version",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Jean-Philippe",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Bernardy",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Stergios",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Chatzikyriakidis",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Aleksandre",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Maskharashvili",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2020,
                "venue": "Available on the first author's homepage",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Jean-Philippe Bernardy, Stergios Chatzikyriakidis, and Aleksandre Maskharashvili. 2020. A computational treatment of anaphora and its algorithmic implemen- tation: Extended version. Available on the first author's homepage: https://jyp.github.io/ pdf/phoroi.pdf or online https://bit.ly/ 2xQ4G2M.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF6": {
                "ref_id": "b6",
                "title": "Wide-coverage semantic analysis with boxer",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Johan",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Bos",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2008,
                "venue": "Step 2008 conference proceedings",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "277--286",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Johan Bos. 2008. Wide-coverage semantic analysis with boxer. In Semantics in text processing. Step 2008 conference proceedings, pages 277-286.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF7": {
                "ref_id": "b7",
                "title": "Monadic dynamic semantics for anaphora. Ohio State Dynamic Semantics Workshop",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Simon",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Charlow",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2015,
                "venue": "",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Simon Charlow. 2015. Monadic dynamic semantics for anaphora. Ohio State Dynamic Semantics Work- shop.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF8": {
                "ref_id": "b8",
                "title": "A modular theory of pronouns and binding",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Simon",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Charlow",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2017,
                "venue": "Logic and Engineering of Natural Language Semantics (LENLS)",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Simon Charlow. 2017. A modular theory of pronouns and binding. In Logic and Engineering of Natural Language Semantics (LENLS) 14. Springer.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF9": {
                "ref_id": "b9",
                "title": "Natural language inference in coq",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Stergios",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Chatzikyriakidis",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Zhaohui",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Luo",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2014,
                "venue": "Journal of Logic, Language and Information",
                "volume": "23",
                "issue": "4",
                "pages": "441--480",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Stergios Chatzikyriakidis and Zhaohui Luo. 2014. Nat- ural language inference in coq. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 23(4):441-480.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF10": {
                "ref_id": "b10",
                "title": "Using the framework",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "R",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Cooper",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "D",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Crouch",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "J",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Van Eijck",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "C",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Fox",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "J",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Van Genabith",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "J",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Jaspars",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "H",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Kamp",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "D",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Milward",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "M",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Pinkal",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "M",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Poesio",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "S",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Pulman",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 1996,
                "venue": "The FraCaS consortium",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "R. Cooper, D. Crouch, J. van Eijck, C. Fox, J. van Gen- abith, J. Jaspars, H. Kamp, D. Milward, M. Pinkal, M. Poesio, and S. Pulman. 1996. Using the framework. Technical report LRE 62-051r, The FraCaS consortium. ftp://ftp.cogsci.ed.ac. uk/pub/FRACAS/del16.ps.gz.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF11": {
                "ref_id": "b11",
                "title": "Word meaning and Montague grammar: The semantics of verbs and times in generative semantics and in Montague's PTQ",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "David R Dowty",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2012,
                "venue": "",
                "volume": "7",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "David R Dowty. 2012. Word meaning and Montague grammar: The semantics of verbs and times in gen- erative semantics and in Montague's PTQ, volume 7. Springer Science & Business Media.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF12": {
                "ref_id": "b12",
                "title": "The semantics of tense and aspect. The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Tim",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Fernando",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2015,
                "venue": "",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "203--236",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Tim Fernando. 2015. The semantics of tense and as- pect. The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory, pages 203-236.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF13": {
                "ref_id": "b13",
                "title": "Tense, aspect, and indexicality",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "James",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Higginbotham",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2009,
                "venue": "OUP Oxford",
                "volume": "26",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "James Higginbotham. 2009. Tense, aspect, and indexi- cality, volume 26. OUP Oxford.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF14": {
                "ref_id": "b14",
                "title": "A bilingual treebank for the FraCas test suite",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "P",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Ljungl\u00f6f",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "M",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Siverbo",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2011,
                "venue": "",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "P. Ljungl\u00f6f and M. Siverbo. 2011. A bilingual treebank for the FraCas test suite. Clt project report, Univer- sity of Gothenburg.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF15": {
                "ref_id": "b15",
                "title": "Natural logic for textual inference",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Bill",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Maccartney",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "D",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Christopher",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Manning",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2007,
                "venue": "Proceedings of the ACL-PASCAL Workshop on Textual Entailment and Paraphrasing",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "193--200",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Bill MacCartney and Christopher D Manning. 2007. Natural logic for textual inference. In Proceedings of the ACL-PASCAL Workshop on Textual Entail- ment and Paraphrasing, pages 193-200. Associa- tion for Computational Linguistics.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF16": {
                "ref_id": "b16",
                "title": "Higher-order logical inference with compositional semantics",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Koji",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Mineshima",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Yusuke",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Miyao",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Daisuke",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Bekki",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2015,
                "venue": "Proceedings of EMNLP",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Koji Mineshima, Yusuke Miyao, and Daisuke Bekki. 2015. Higher-order logical inference with composi- tional semantics. In Proceedings of EMNLP.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF17": {
                "ref_id": "b17",
                "title": "English as a formal language",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Richard",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Montague",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 1970,
                "venue": "Linguaggi nella Societa e nella Tecnica",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Richard Montague. 1970. English as a formal lan- guage. In Linguaggi nella Societa e nella Tecnica.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF18": {
                "ref_id": "b18",
                "title": "The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary english",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Richard",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Montague",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 1973,
                "venue": "Approaches to natural language",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "221--242",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Richard Montague. 1973. The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary english. In Approaches to natural language, pages 221-242. Springer.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF19": {
                "ref_id": "b19",
                "title": "The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary english",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Richard",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Montague",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 1974,
                "venue": "",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Richard Montague. 1974. The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary english. In Richmond Thomason, editor, Formal Philosophy. Yale UP, New Haven.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF20": {
                "ref_id": "b20",
                "title": "Tense and aspect in truthconditional semantics",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Toshiyuki",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Ogihara",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2007,
                "venue": "Lingua",
                "volume": "117",
                "issue": "2",
                "pages": "392--418",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Toshiyuki Ogihara. 2007. Tense and aspect in truth- conditional semantics. Lingua, 117(2):392-418.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF21": {
                "ref_id": "b21",
                "title": "Events in the Semantics of English",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Terence",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Parsons",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 1990,
                "venue": "",
                "volume": "5",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Terence Parsons. 1990. Events in the Semantics of En- glish, volume 5. MIT press Cambridge, MA.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF22": {
                "ref_id": "b22",
                "title": "Papers on time and tense",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "N",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Arthur",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Prior",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "F",
                        "middle": [
                            "V"
                        ],
                        "last": "Per",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Hasle",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2003,
                "venue": "",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Arthur N Prior and Per FV Hasle. 2003. Papers on time and tense. Oxford University Press on Demand.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF23": {
                "ref_id": "b23",
                "title": "Grammatical framework",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Aarne",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Ranta",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2004,
                "venue": "Journal of Functional Programming",
                "volume": "14",
                "issue": "2",
                "pages": "145--189",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Aarne Ranta. 2004. Grammatical framework. Journal of Functional Programming, 14(2):145-189.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF24": {
                "ref_id": "b24",
                "title": "The productions of time",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Mark",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Steedman",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2000,
                "venue": "",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Mark Steedman. 2000. The productions of time. Draft. Available at http://www. cogsci. ed. ac. uk/steedman/papers. html.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF25": {
                "ref_id": "b25",
                "title": "Dynamic semantics as monadic computation",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Christina",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Unger",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2011,
                "venue": "JSAI International Symposium on Artificial Intelligence",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "68--81",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Christina Unger. 2011. Dynamic semantics as monadic computation. In JSAI International Symposium on Artificial Intelligence, pages 68-81. Springer.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF26": {
                "ref_id": "b26",
                "title": "Temporal reasoning in natural language inference",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Siddharth",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Vashishtha",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Adam",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Poliak",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Yash",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Kumar Lal",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Benjamin",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Van Durme",
                        "suffix": ""
                    },
                    {
                        "first": "Aaron",
                        "middle": [
                            "Steven"
                        ],
                        "last": "White",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 2020,
                "venue": "Findings of the Association for Computational Linguistics: EMNLP 2020",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "4070--4078",
                "other_ids": {
                    "DOI": [
                        "10.18653/v1/2020.findings-emnlp.363"
                    ]
                },
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Siddharth Vashishtha, Adam Poliak, Yash Kumar Lal, Benjamin Van Durme, and Aaron Steven White. 2020. Temporal reasoning in natural language infer- ence. In Findings of the Association for Computa- tional Linguistics: EMNLP 2020, pages 4070-4078, Online. Association for Computational Linguistics.",
                "links": null
            },
            "BIBREF27": {
                "ref_id": "b27",
                "title": "Une th\u00e9orie des constructions inductives",
                "authors": [
                    {
                        "first": "Benjamin",
                        "middle": [],
                        "last": "Werner",
                        "suffix": ""
                    }
                ],
                "year": 1994,
                "venue": "",
                "volume": "",
                "issue": "",
                "pages": "",
                "other_ids": {},
                "num": null,
                "urls": [],
                "raw_text": "Benjamin Werner. 1994. Une th\u00e9orie des constructions inductives. PhD thesis, Universit\u00e9 de Paris 7.",
                "links": null
            }
        },
        "ref_entries": {
            "FIGREF0": {
                "type_str": "figure",
                "text": "P1 Smith left after Jones left. P2 Jones left after Anderson left. H Did Smith leave after Anderson left?",
                "uris": null,
                "num": null
            },
            "FIGREF1": {
                "type_str": "figure",
                "text": "))))) -> Not (exists (f: Time), ((exists (g: Time),",
                "uris": null,
                "num": null
            }
        }
    }
}