Datasets:
Tasks:
Text Generation
Modalities:
Text
Sub-tasks:
language-modeling
Languages:
English
Size:
100K - 1M
License:
File size: 14,669 Bytes
afd65d6 |
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148 149 150 151 152 153 154 155 156 157 158 159 160 161 162 163 164 165 166 167 168 169 170 171 172 173 174 175 176 177 178 179 180 181 182 183 184 185 186 187 188 189 190 191 192 193 194 195 196 197 198 199 200 201 202 203 204 205 206 207 208 209 210 211 212 213 214 215 216 217 218 219 220 221 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 244 245 246 247 248 249 250 251 252 253 254 255 256 257 258 259 260 261 262 263 264 265 266 267 268 269 270 271 272 273 274 275 276 277 278 279 280 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288 289 290 291 292 293 294 295 296 297 298 299 300 301 302 303 304 305 306 307 308 309 310 311 312 313 314 315 316 317 318 319 320 321 322 323 324 325 326 327 328 329 330 331 332 333 334 335 336 337 338 339 340 341 342 343 344 |
\chapter{Breaking the continuum hypothesis}
We now use the technique of forcing to break the
Continuum Hypothesis by choosing a good poset $\Po$.
As I mentioned earlier, one can also build a model
where the Continuum Hypothesis is true;
this is called the \emph{constructible universe},
(this model is often called ``$V=L$'').
However, I think it's more fun when things break\dots
%\section{Forcing $V \neq L$ is really easy}
%As a small aside, to check we're on the right track we show the following result.
%
%\begin{theorem}[$V \ne L$]
% Let $M$ be a countable transitive model of $\ZFC$.
% Let $\Po \in M$ be \emph{any} splitting poset,
% and let $G \subseteq \Po$ be $M$-generic.
% Then $M[G] \vDash (V \neq L)$.
%\end{theorem}
%\begin{proof}
% Since $L$ has a $\Sigma_1$ definition,
% we have \[ L^{M[G]} = L^M \subseteq M \subsetneq M[G] \]
% where the last part follows from $G \notin M[G]$.
%\end{proof}
%
%Thus $M[G] \vDash \ZFC + (V \ne L)$ for any splitting poset $\Po$,
%and we are one step closer to breaking $\CH$.
\section{Adding in reals}
Starting with a \emph{countable} transitive model $M$.
We want to choose $\Po \in M$ such that $(\aleph_2)^M$ many real numbers appear,
and then worry about cardinal collapse later.
Recall the earlier situation where we set $\Po$ to be the infinite complete binary tree; its nodes can be thought of as partial functions $n \to 2$ where $n < \omega$.
Then $G$ itself is a path down this tree; i.e.\ it can be encoded as a total function $G : \omega \to 2$,
and corresponds to a real number.
\begin{center}
\begin{asy}
size(8cm);
pair P = Drawing("\varnothing", (0,4), dir(90), red);
pair P0 = Drawing("0", (-5,2), 1.5*dir(90), red);
pair P1 = Drawing("1", (5,2), 1.5*dir(90));
pair P00 = Drawing("00", (-7,0), 1.4*dir(120));
pair P01 = Drawing("01", (-3,0), 1.4*dir(60), red);
pair P10 = Drawing("10", (3,0), 1.4*dir(120));
pair P11 = Drawing("11", (7,0), 1.4*dir(60));
pair P000 = Drawing("000", (-8,-3));
pair P001 = Drawing("001", (-6,-3));
pair P010 = Drawing("010", (-4,-3), red);
pair P011 = Drawing("011", (-2,-3));
pair P100 = Drawing("100", (2,-3));
pair P101 = Drawing("101", (4,-3));
pair P110 = Drawing("110", (6,-3));
pair P111 = Drawing("111", (8,-3));
draw(P01--P0--P00);
draw(P11--P1--P10);
draw(P0--P--P1);
draw(P000--P00--P001);
draw(P100--P10--P101);
draw(P010--P01--P011);
draw(P110--P11--P111);
draw(P--P0--P01--P010--(P010+2*dir(-90)), red+1.4);
MP("G", P010+2*dir(-90), dir(-90), red);
\end{asy}
\end{center}
We want to do something similar,
but with $\omega_2$ many real numbers instead of just one.
In light of this, consider in $M$ the poset
\[
\Po = \opname{Add} \left( \omega_2, \omega \right)
\defeq \left( \left\{ p : \omega_2 \times \omega \to 2,
\dom(p) \text{ is finite} \right\},
\supseteq \right).
\]
These elements $p$ (conditions) are ``partial functions'':
we take some finite subset of $\omega_2 \times \omega$ and map it into $2=\{0,1\}$.
(Here $\dom(p)$ denotes the domain of $p$,
which is the finite subset of $\omega_2 \times \omega$ mentioned.)
Moreover, we say $p \le q$ if $\dom(p) \supseteq \dom(q)$
and the two functions agree over $\dom(q)$.
\begin{ques}
What is the maximal element $1_\Po$ here?
\end{ques}
\begin{exercise}
Show that a generic $G$ can be encoded as a function $\omega_2 \times \omega \to 2$.
\end{exercise}
%Let $G \subseteq \opname{Add}(\omega_2, \omega)$ be an $M$-generic.
%We claim that, like in the binary case, $G$ can be encoded as a function $\omega_2 \times \omega \to 2$.
%To see this, consider $\alpha \in \omega_2$ and $n \in \omega$; we have the dense set
%\[ D_{\alpha, n}
% = \left\{ p \in \opname{Add}(\omega_2, \omega)
% \mid (\alpha, n) \in \dom(p) \right\}
%\]
%(this is obviously dense, given any $p$ add in $(\alpha, n)$ if it's not in there already).
%So $G$ hits this dense set, meaning that for every $(\alpha, n)$ there's a function in $G$ which defines it.
%Using the fact that $G$ is upwards closed and a filter, we may as before we may interpret $G$ as a function $\omega_2 \times \omega \to 2$.
\begin{lemma}[$G$ encodes distinct real numbers]
For $\alpha \in \omega_2$ define
\[ G_\alpha = \left\{ n \mid G\left( \alpha,n \right) = 0 \right\} \in \PP(\NN). \]
Then $G_\alpha \neq G_\beta$ for any $\alpha \neq \beta$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
We claim that the set
\[ D = \left\{ q \mid \exists n \in \omega :
q\left( \alpha, n \right) \neq q\left( \beta, n \right)
\text{ are both defined}
\right\} \]
is dense.
\begin{ques}
Check this.
(Use the fact that the domains are all finite.)
\end{ques}
% This is pretty easy to see.
% Consider $p \in \opname{Add}(\omega_2, \omega)$.
% Then you can find an $n$ such that
% neither $(\alpha, n)$ nor $(\beta, n)$ is defined,
% just because $\dom(p)$ is finite.
% Then you make $p'$ as $p$ plus $p'( (\alpha, n) ) = 1$
% and $p'( (\beta, n) ) = 0$.
% Hence the set is dense.
Since $G$ is an $M$-generic it hits this dense set $D$.
Hence $G_\alpha \neq G_\beta$.
\end{proof}
Since $G \in M[G]$ and $M[G] \vDash \ZFC$,
it follows that each $G_\alpha$ is in $M[G]$.
So there are at least $\aleph_2^M$ real numbers in $M[G]$.
We are done once we can show there is no cardinal collapse.
\section{The countable chain condition}
It remains to show that with $\Po = \opname{Add}(\omega, \omega_2)$, we have that
\[ \aleph_2^{M[G]} = \aleph_2^M. \]
In that case, since $M[G]$ will have $\aleph_2^M = \aleph_2^{M[G]}$ many reals, we will be done.
To do this, we'll rely on a combinatorial property of $\Po$:
\begin{definition}
We say that $A \subseteq \mathcal P$ is a \vocab{strong antichain}
if for any distinct $p$ and $q$ in $A$, we have $p \perp q$.
\end{definition}
\begin{example}[Example of an antichain]
In the infinite binary tree,
the set $A = \{00, 01, 10, 11\}$ is a strong antichain
(in fact maximal by inclusion).
\end{example}
This is stronger than the notion of ``antichain'' than you might be used to!\footnote{%
In the context of forcing, some authors use ``antichain'' to refer to ``strong antichain''.
I think this is lame.}
We don't merely require that every two elements are incomparable,
but that they are in fact \emph{incompatible}.
\begin{ques}
Draw a finite poset and an antichain of it which is not strong.
\end{ques}
\begin{definition}
A poset $\Po$ has the \vocab{$\kappa$-chain condition}
(where $\kappa$ is a cardinal) if all strong antichains
in $\Po$ have size less than $\kappa$.
The special case $\kappa = \aleph_1$ is called the \vocab{countable chain condition},
because it implies that every strong antichain is countable.
\end{definition}
We are going to show that if the poset has the $\kappa$-chain condition
then it preserves all cardinals greater than $\kappa$.
% or was it > \kappa?
In particular, the countable chain condition will show that $\Po$ preserves all the cardinals.
Then, we'll show that $\opname{Add}(\omega, \omega_2)$ does indeed have this property.
This will complete the proof.
We isolate a useful lemma:
\begin{lemma}[Possible values argument]
Suppose $M$ is a transitive model of $\ZFC$ and $\Po$ is a partial order
such that $\Po$ has the $\kappa$-chain condition in $M$.
Let $X,Y \in M$ and let $f: X \to Y$
be some function in $M[G]$, but $f \notin M$.
Then there exists a function $F \in M$, with $F: X \to \PP(Y)$ and such that
for any $x \in X$,
\[ f(x) \in F(x) \quad\text{and}\quad \left\lvert F(x) \right\rvert^M < \kappa. \]
\end{lemma}
What this is saying is that if $f$ is some new function that's generated,
$M$ is still able to pin down the values of $f$ to at most $\kappa$ many values.
\begin{proof}
The idea behind the proof is easy: any possible value of $f$ gives us some condition in
the poset $\Po$ which forces it.
Since distinct values must have incompatible conditions,
the $\kappa$-chain condition guarantees
there are at most $\kappa$ such values.
Here are the details.
Let $\dot f$, $\check X$, $\check Y$ be names for $f$, $X$, $Y$.
Start with a condition $p$ such that $p$ forces the sentence
\[ \text{``$\dot f$ is a function from $\check X$ to $\check Y$''}. \]
We'll work just below here.
For each $x \in X$, we can consider (using the Axiom of Choice) a maximal strong antichain $A(x)$
of incompatible conditions $q \le p$ which forces $f(x)$ to equal some value $y \in Y$.
Then, we let $F(x)$ collect all the resulting $y$-values.
These are all possible values, and there are less than $\kappa$ of them.
\end{proof}
\section{Preserving cardinals}
As we saw earlier, cardinal collapse can still occur.
For the Continuum Hypothesis we want to avoid this possibility,
so we can add in $\aleph_2^M$ many real numbers and have $\aleph_2^{M[G]} = \aleph_2^M$.
It turns out that to verify this, one can check a weaker result.
\begin{definition}
For $M$ a transitive model of $\ZFC$ and $\Po \in M$ a poset,
we say $\Po$ \vocab{preserves cardinals} if
$\forall G \subseteq \Po$ an $M$-generic,
the model $M$ and $M[G]$ agree on the sentence ``$\kappa$ is a cardinal'' for every $\kappa$.
Similarly we say $\Po$ \vocab{preserves regular cardinals} if $M$ and $M[G]$
agree on the sentence ``$\kappa$ is a regular cardinal'' for every $\kappa$.
\end{definition}
Intuition:
In a model $M$, it's possible that two ordinals which are in bijection in $V$ are no longer in bijection in $M$.
Similarly, it might be the case that some cardinal $\kappa \in M$ is regular,
but stops being regular in $V$ because some function $f : \ol\kappa \to \kappa$ is cofinal but happened to only exist in $V$.
In still other words, ``$\kappa$ is a regular cardinal '' turns out to be a $\Pi_1$ statement too.
Fortunately, each implies the other.
We quote the following without proof.
\begin{proposition}[Preserving cardinals $\iff$ preserving regular cardinals]
Let $M$ be a transitive model of $\ZFC$.
Let $\Po \in M$ be a poset.
Then for any $\lambda$,
$\Po$ preserves cardinalities less than or equal to $\lambda$
if and only if $\Po$ preserves regular cardinals less than or equal to $\lambda$.
Moreover the same holds if we replace ``less than or equal to''
by ``greater than or equal to''.
\end{proposition}
Thus, to show that $\Po$ preserves cardinality and cofinalities
it suffices to show that $\Po$ preserves regularity.
The following theorem lets us do this:
\begin{theorem}[Chain conditions preserve regular cardinals]
Let $M$ be a transitive model of ZFC, and let $\Po \in M$ be a poset.
Suppose $M$ satisfies the sentence ``$\Po$ has the $\kappa$ chain condition and $\kappa$ is regular''.
Then $\Po$ preserves regularity greater than or equal to $\kappa$.
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}
Use the Possible Values Argument.
\Cref{prob:chain}.
\end{proof}
In particular, if $\Po$ has the countable chain condition then $\Po$ preserves \emph{all} the cardinals (and cofinalities).
Therefore, it remains to show that $\opname{Add}(\omega, \omega_2)$ satisfies the countable chain condition.
\section{Infinite combinatorics}
We now prove that $\opname{Add}(\omega, \omega_2)$ satisfies the countable chain condition.
This is purely combinatorial, and so we work briefly.
\begin{definition}
Suppose $C$ is an uncountable collection of finite sets.
$C$ is a \vocab{$\Delta$-system} if there exists a \vocab{root} $R$
with the condition that for any distinct $X$ and $Y$
in $C$, we have $X \cap Y = R$.
\end{definition}
\begin{lemma}
[$\Delta$-System lemma] Suppose $C$ is an uncountable collection of finite sets.
Then $\exists \ol C \subseteq C$ such that $\ol C$ is an uncountable $\Delta$-system.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
There exists an integer $n$ such that $C$ has uncountably many guys of length $n$.
So we can throw away all the other sets, and just assume that all sets in $C$ have size $n$.
We now proceed by induction on $n$.
The base case $n=1$ is trivial, since we can just take $R = \varnothing$.
For the inductive step we consider two cases.
First, assume there exists an $a \in C$ contained in uncountably many $F \in C$.
Throw away all the other guys.
Then we can just delete $a$, and apply the inductive hypothesis.
Now assume that for every $a$, only countably many members of $C$ have $a$ in them.
We claim we can even get a $\ol C$ with $R = \varnothing$.
First, pick $F_0 \in C$.
It's straightforward to construct an $F_1$ such that $F_1 \cap F_0 = \varnothing$.
And we can just construct $F_2, F_3, \dots$
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}
For all $\kappa$, $\opname{Add}(\omega, \kappa)$ satisfies the countable chain condition.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Assume not. Let
\[ \left\{ p_\alpha : \alpha < \omega_1 \right\} \]
be a strong antichain. Let
\[ C = \left\{ \dom(p_\alpha) : \alpha < \omega_1 \right\}. \]
Let $\ol C \subseteq C$ be such that $\ol C$ is uncountable, and $\ol C$ is a $\Delta$-system with root $R$.
Then let
\[ B = \left\{ p_\alpha : \dom(p_\alpha) \in R \right\}. \]
Each $p_\alpha \in B$ is a function $p_\alpha : R \to \{0,1\}$,
so there are two that are the same.
\end{proof}
Thus, we have proven that the Continuum Hypothesis cannot be proven in $\ZFC$.
\section\problemhead
\begin{problem}
\label{prob:chain}
Let $M$ be a transitive model of ZFC, and let $\Po \in M$ be a poset.
Suppose $M$ satisfies the sentence ``$\Po$ has the $\kappa$ chain condition and $\kappa$ is regular''.
Show that $\Po$ preserves regularity greater than or equal to $\kappa$.
\begin{hint}
Assume not, and take $\lambda > \kappa$ regular in $M$;
if $f : \ol \lambda \to \lambda$,
use the Possible Values Argument on $f$ to generate a function in $M$
that breaks cofinality of $\lambda$.
\end{hint}
\begin{sol}
It suffices to show that $\Po$ preserves regularity greater than or equal to $\kappa$.
Consider $\lambda > \kappa$ which is regular in $M$,
and suppose for contradiction that $\lambda$ is not regular in $M[G]$.
That's the same as saying that there is a function $f \in M[G]$,
$f : \ol \lambda \to \lambda$ cofinal, with $\ol \lambda < \lambda$.
Then by the Possible Values Argument,
there exists a function $F \in M$ from $\ol \lambda \to \PP(\lambda)$
such that $f(\alpha) \in F(\alpha)$ and $\left\lvert F(\alpha) \right\rvert^M < \kappa$
for every $\alpha$.
Now we work in $M$ again.
Note for each $\alpha \in \ol\lambda$,
$F(\alpha)$ is bounded in $\lambda$ since $\lambda$ is regular in $M$ and
greater than $\left\lvert F(\alpha) \right\rvert$.
Now look at the function $\ol \lambda \to \lambda$ in $M$ by just
\[ \alpha \mapsto \cup F(\alpha) < \lambda. \]
This is cofinal in $M$, contradiction.
\end{sol}
\end{problem}
|