Datasets:

Modalities:
Text
Languages:
English
Libraries:
Datasets
License:
File size: 14,669 Bytes
afd65d6
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
\chapter{Breaking the continuum hypothesis}
We now use the technique of forcing to break the
Continuum Hypothesis by choosing a good poset $\Po$.
As I mentioned earlier, one can also build a model
where the Continuum Hypothesis is true;
this is called the \emph{constructible universe},
(this model is often called ``$V=L$'').
However, I think it's more fun when things break\dots

%\section{Forcing $V \neq L$ is really easy}
%As a small aside, to check we're on the right track we show the following result.
%
%\begin{theorem}[$V \ne L$]
%	Let $M$ be a countable transitive model of $\ZFC$.
%	Let $\Po \in M$ be \emph{any} splitting poset,
%	and let $G \subseteq \Po$ be $M$-generic.
%	Then $M[G] \vDash (V \neq L)$.
%\end{theorem}
%\begin{proof}
%	Since $L$ has a $\Sigma_1$ definition,
%	we have \[ L^{M[G]} = L^M \subseteq M \subsetneq M[G] \]
%	where the last part follows from $G \notin M[G]$.
%\end{proof}
%
%Thus $M[G] \vDash \ZFC + (V \ne L)$ for any splitting poset $\Po$,
%and we are one step closer to breaking $\CH$.

\section{Adding in reals}
Starting with a \emph{countable} transitive model $M$.

We want to choose $\Po \in M$ such that $(\aleph_2)^M$ many real numbers appear,
and then worry about cardinal collapse later.

Recall the earlier situation where we set $\Po$ to be the infinite complete binary tree; its nodes can be thought of as partial functions $n \to 2$ where $n < \omega$.
Then $G$ itself is a path down this tree; i.e.\ it can be encoded as a total function $G : \omega \to 2$,
and corresponds to a real number.

\begin{center}
	\begin{asy}
		size(8cm);
		pair P = Drawing("\varnothing", (0,4), dir(90), red);
		pair P0 = Drawing("0", (-5,2), 1.5*dir(90), red);
		pair P1 = Drawing("1", (5,2),  1.5*dir(90));
		pair P00 = Drawing("00", (-7,0), 1.4*dir(120));
		pair P01 = Drawing("01", (-3,0), 1.4*dir(60), red);
		pair P10 = Drawing("10", (3,0),  1.4*dir(120));
		pair P11 = Drawing("11", (7,0),  1.4*dir(60));

		pair P000 = Drawing("000", (-8,-3));
		pair P001 = Drawing("001", (-6,-3));
		pair P010 = Drawing("010", (-4,-3), red);
		pair P011 = Drawing("011", (-2,-3));

		pair P100 = Drawing("100", (2,-3));
		pair P101 = Drawing("101", (4,-3));
		pair P110 = Drawing("110", (6,-3));
		pair P111 = Drawing("111", (8,-3));

		draw(P01--P0--P00);
		draw(P11--P1--P10);
		draw(P0--P--P1);
		draw(P000--P00--P001);
		draw(P100--P10--P101);
		draw(P010--P01--P011);
		draw(P110--P11--P111);

		draw(P--P0--P01--P010--(P010+2*dir(-90)), red+1.4);
		MP("G", P010+2*dir(-90), dir(-90), red);
	\end{asy}
\end{center}

We want to do something similar,
but with $\omega_2$ many real numbers instead of just one.
In light of this, consider in $M$ the poset
\[
	\Po = \opname{Add} \left( \omega_2, \omega \right)
	\defeq \left( \left\{ p : \omega_2 \times \omega \to 2,
		\dom(p) \text{ is finite} \right\},
	\supseteq \right).
\]
These elements $p$ (conditions) are ``partial functions'':
we take some finite subset of $\omega_2 \times \omega$ and map it into $2=\{0,1\}$.
(Here $\dom(p)$ denotes the domain of $p$,
which is the finite subset of $\omega_2 \times \omega$ mentioned.)
Moreover, we say $p \le q$ if $\dom(p) \supseteq \dom(q)$
and the two functions agree over $\dom(q)$.

\begin{ques}
	What is the maximal element $1_\Po$ here?
\end{ques}

\begin{exercise}
	Show that a generic $G$ can be encoded as a function $\omega_2 \times \omega \to 2$.
\end{exercise}

%Let $G \subseteq \opname{Add}(\omega_2, \omega)$ be an $M$-generic.
%We claim that, like in the binary case, $G$ can be encoded as a function $\omega_2 \times \omega \to 2$.
%To see this, consider $\alpha \in \omega_2$ and $n \in \omega$; we have the dense set
%\[ D_{\alpha, n}
%	= \left\{ p \in \opname{Add}(\omega_2, \omega)
%	\mid (\alpha, n) \in \dom(p) \right\}
%\]
%(this is obviously dense, given any $p$ add in $(\alpha, n)$ if it's not in there already).
%So $G$ hits this dense set, meaning that for every $(\alpha, n)$ there's a function in $G$ which defines it.
%Using the fact that $G$ is upwards closed and a filter, we may as before we may interpret $G$ as a function $\omega_2 \times \omega \to 2$.

\begin{lemma}[$G$ encodes distinct real numbers]
	For $\alpha \in \omega_2$ define
	\[ G_\alpha = \left\{ n \mid G\left( \alpha,n \right) = 0 \right\} \in \PP(\NN). \]
	Then $G_\alpha \neq G_\beta$ for any $\alpha \neq \beta$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
	We claim that the set
	\[ D = \left\{ q \mid \exists n \in \omega :
		q\left( \alpha, n \right) \neq q\left( \beta, n \right)
		\text{ are both defined}
	\right\} \]
	is dense.
	\begin{ques}
		Check this.
		(Use the fact that the domains are all finite.)
	\end{ques}
%	This is pretty easy to see.
%	Consider $p \in \opname{Add}(\omega_2, \omega)$.
%	Then you can find an $n$ such that
%	neither $(\alpha, n)$ nor $(\beta, n)$ is defined,
%	just because $\dom(p)$ is finite.
%	Then you make $p'$ as $p$ plus $p'( (\alpha, n) ) = 1$
%	and $p'( (\beta, n) ) = 0$.
%	Hence the set is dense.

	Since $G$ is an $M$-generic it hits this dense set $D$.
	Hence $G_\alpha \neq G_\beta$.
\end{proof}

Since $G \in M[G]$ and $M[G] \vDash \ZFC$,
it follows that each $G_\alpha$ is in $M[G]$.
So there are at least $\aleph_2^M$ real numbers in $M[G]$.
We are done once we can show there is no cardinal collapse.

\section{The countable chain condition}
It remains to show that with $\Po = \opname{Add}(\omega, \omega_2)$, we have that
\[ \aleph_2^{M[G]} = \aleph_2^M. \]
In that case, since $M[G]$ will have $\aleph_2^M = \aleph_2^{M[G]}$ many reals, we will be done.

To do this, we'll rely on a combinatorial property of $\Po$:
\begin{definition}
	We say that $A \subseteq \mathcal P$ is a \vocab{strong antichain}
	if for any distinct $p$ and $q$ in $A$, we have $p \perp q$.
\end{definition}
\begin{example}[Example of an antichain]
	In the infinite binary tree,
	the set $A = \{00, 01, 10, 11\}$ is a strong antichain
	(in fact maximal by inclusion).
\end{example}
This is stronger than the notion of ``antichain'' than you might be used to!\footnote{%
	In the context of forcing, some authors use ``antichain'' to refer to ``strong antichain''.
	I think this is lame.}
We don't merely require that every two elements are incomparable,
but that they are in fact \emph{incompatible}.
\begin{ques}
	Draw a finite poset and an antichain of it which is not strong.
\end{ques}

\begin{definition}
	A poset $\Po$ has the \vocab{$\kappa$-chain condition}
	(where $\kappa$ is a cardinal) if all strong antichains
	in $\Po$ have size less than $\kappa$.
	The special case $\kappa = \aleph_1$ is called the \vocab{countable chain condition},
	because it implies that every strong antichain is countable.
\end{definition}

We are going to show that if the poset has the $\kappa$-chain condition
then it preserves all cardinals greater than $\kappa$.
% or was it > \kappa?
In particular, the countable chain condition will show that $\Po$ preserves all the cardinals.
Then, we'll show that $\opname{Add}(\omega, \omega_2)$ does indeed have this property.
This will complete the proof.

We isolate a useful lemma:
\begin{lemma}[Possible values argument]
	Suppose $M$ is a transitive model of $\ZFC$ and $\Po$ is a partial order
	such that $\Po$ has the $\kappa$-chain condition in $M$.
	Let $X,Y \in M$ and let $f: X \to Y$
	be some function in $M[G]$, but $f \notin M$.

	Then there exists a function $F \in M$, with $F: X \to \PP(Y)$ and such that
	for any $x \in X$,
	\[ f(x) \in F(x) \quad\text{and}\quad \left\lvert F(x) \right\rvert^M < \kappa. \]
\end{lemma}
What this is saying is that if $f$ is some new function that's generated,
$M$ is still able to pin down the values of $f$ to at most $\kappa$ many values.

\begin{proof}
	The idea behind the proof is easy: any possible value of $f$ gives us some condition in
	the poset $\Po$ which forces it.
	Since distinct values must have incompatible conditions,
	the $\kappa$-chain condition guarantees
	there are at most $\kappa$ such values.

	Here are the details.
	Let $\dot f$, $\check X$, $\check Y$ be names for $f$, $X$, $Y$.
	Start with a condition $p$ such that $p$ forces the sentence
	\[ \text{``$\dot f$ is a function from $\check X$ to $\check Y$''}. \]
	We'll work just below here.

	For each $x \in X$, we can consider (using the Axiom of Choice) a maximal strong antichain $A(x)$
	of incompatible conditions $q \le p$ which forces $f(x)$ to equal some value $y \in Y$.
	Then, we let $F(x)$ collect all the resulting $y$-values.
	These are all possible values, and there are less than $\kappa$ of them.
\end{proof}

\section{Preserving cardinals}
As we saw earlier, cardinal collapse can still occur.
For the Continuum Hypothesis we want to avoid this possibility,
so we can add in $\aleph_2^M$ many real numbers and have $\aleph_2^{M[G]} = \aleph_2^M$.
It turns out that to verify this, one can check a weaker result.

\begin{definition}
	For $M$ a transitive model of $\ZFC$ and $\Po \in M$ a poset,
	we say $\Po$ \vocab{preserves cardinals} if
	$\forall G \subseteq \Po$ an $M$-generic,
	the model $M$ and $M[G]$ agree on the sentence ``$\kappa$ is a cardinal'' for every $\kappa$.
	Similarly we say $\Po$ \vocab{preserves regular cardinals} if $M$ and $M[G]$
	agree on the sentence ``$\kappa$ is a regular cardinal'' for every $\kappa$.
\end{definition}
Intuition:
In a model $M$, it's possible that two ordinals which are in bijection in $V$ are no longer in bijection in $M$.
Similarly, it might be the case that some cardinal $\kappa \in M$ is regular,
but stops being regular in $V$ because some function $f : \ol\kappa \to \kappa$ is cofinal but happened to only exist in $V$.
In still other words, ``$\kappa$ is a regular cardinal '' turns out to be a $\Pi_1$ statement too.

Fortunately, each implies the other.
We quote the following without proof.
\begin{proposition}[Preserving cardinals $\iff$ preserving regular cardinals]
	Let $M$ be a transitive model of $\ZFC$.
	Let $\Po \in M$ be a poset.
	Then for any $\lambda$,
		$\Po$ preserves cardinalities less than or equal to $\lambda$
		if and only if $\Po$ preserves regular cardinals less than or equal to $\lambda$.
	Moreover the same holds if we replace ``less than or equal to''
	by ``greater than or equal to''.
\end{proposition}

Thus, to show that $\Po$ preserves cardinality and cofinalities
it suffices to show that $\Po$ preserves regularity.
The following theorem lets us do this:
\begin{theorem}[Chain conditions preserve regular cardinals]
	Let $M$ be a transitive model of ZFC, and let $\Po \in M$ be a poset.
	Suppose $M$ satisfies the sentence ``$\Po$ has the $\kappa$ chain condition and $\kappa$ is regular''.
	Then $\Po$ preserves regularity greater than or equal to $\kappa$.
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}
	Use the Possible Values Argument.
	\Cref{prob:chain}.
\end{proof}

In particular, if $\Po$ has the countable chain condition then $\Po$ preserves \emph{all} the cardinals (and cofinalities).
Therefore, it remains to show that $\opname{Add}(\omega, \omega_2)$ satisfies the countable chain condition.

\section{Infinite combinatorics}
We now prove that $\opname{Add}(\omega, \omega_2)$ satisfies the countable chain condition.
This is purely combinatorial, and so we work briefly.

\begin{definition}
	Suppose $C$ is an uncountable collection of finite sets.
	$C$ is a \vocab{$\Delta$-system} if there exists a \vocab{root} $R$
	with the condition that for any distinct $X$ and $Y$
	in $C$, we have $X \cap Y = R$.
\end{definition}

\begin{lemma}
	[$\Delta$-System lemma] Suppose $C$ is an uncountable collection of finite sets.
	Then $\exists \ol C \subseteq C$ such that $\ol C$ is an uncountable $\Delta$-system.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
	There exists an integer $n$ such that $C$ has uncountably many guys of length $n$.
	So we can throw away all the other sets, and just assume that all sets in $C$ have size $n$.

	We now proceed by induction on $n$.
	The base case $n=1$ is trivial, since we can just take $R = \varnothing$.
	For the inductive step we consider two cases.

	First, assume there exists an $a \in C$ contained in uncountably many $F \in C$.
	Throw away all the other guys.
	Then we can just delete $a$, and apply the inductive hypothesis.

	Now assume that for every $a$, only countably many members of $C$ have $a$ in them.
	We claim we can even get a $\ol C$ with $R = \varnothing$.
	First, pick $F_0 \in C$.
	It's straightforward to construct an $F_1$ such that $F_1 \cap F_0 = \varnothing$.
	And we can just construct $F_2, F_3, \dots$
\end{proof}

\begin{lemma}
	For all $\kappa$, $\opname{Add}(\omega, \kappa)$ satisfies the countable chain condition.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
	Assume not. Let
	\[ \left\{ p_\alpha : \alpha < \omega_1 \right\} \]
	be a strong antichain.  Let
	\[ C = \left\{ \dom(p_\alpha) : \alpha < \omega_1 \right\}. \]
	Let $\ol C \subseteq C$ be such that $\ol C$ is uncountable, and $\ol C$ is a $\Delta$-system with root $R$.
	Then let
	\[ B = \left\{ p_\alpha : \dom(p_\alpha) \in R \right\}. \]
	Each $p_\alpha \in B$ is a function $p_\alpha : R \to \{0,1\}$,
	so there are two that are the same.
\end{proof}

Thus, we have proven that the Continuum Hypothesis cannot be proven in $\ZFC$.

\section\problemhead
\begin{problem}
	\label{prob:chain}
	Let $M$ be a transitive model of ZFC, and let $\Po \in M$ be a poset.
	Suppose $M$ satisfies the sentence ``$\Po$ has the $\kappa$ chain condition and $\kappa$ is regular''.
	Show that $\Po$ preserves regularity greater than or equal to $\kappa$.
	\begin{hint}
		Assume not, and take $\lambda > \kappa$ regular in $M$;
		if $f : \ol \lambda \to \lambda$,
		use the Possible Values Argument on $f$ to generate a function in $M$
		that breaks cofinality of $\lambda$.
	\end{hint}
	\begin{sol}
		It suffices to show that $\Po$ preserves regularity greater than or equal to $\kappa$.
		Consider $\lambda > \kappa$ which is regular in $M$,
		and suppose for contradiction that $\lambda$ is not regular in $M[G]$.
		That's the same as saying that there is a function $f \in M[G]$,
		$f : \ol \lambda \to \lambda$ cofinal, with $\ol \lambda < \lambda$.
		Then by the Possible Values Argument,
		there exists a function $F \in M$ from $\ol \lambda \to \PP(\lambda)$
		such that $f(\alpha) \in F(\alpha)$ and $\left\lvert F(\alpha) \right\rvert^M < \kappa$
		for every $\alpha$.

		Now we work in $M$ again.
		Note for each $\alpha \in \ol\lambda$,
		$F(\alpha)$ is bounded in $\lambda$ since $\lambda$ is regular in $M$ and
		greater than $\left\lvert F(\alpha) \right\rvert$.
		Now look at the function $\ol \lambda \to \lambda$ in $M$ by just
		\[ \alpha \mapsto \cup F(\alpha) < \lambda. \]
		This is cofinal in $M$, contradiction.
	\end{sol}
\end{problem}