Datasets:

Modalities:
Text
Languages:
English
Libraries:
Datasets
License:
File size: 39,089 Bytes
afd65d6
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
\chapter{Unique factorization and the class group}


Commutative rings in general do not admit unique factorization. 
Nonetheless, for many rings (``integrally closed'' rings), which
includes the affine coordinate rings one obtains in algebraic geometry when
one studies smooth varieties, there is an invariant called the ``class
group'' that measures the failure of unique factorization. This ``class
group'' is a certain quotient of codimension one primes (geometrically,
codimension one subvarieties) modulo rational equivalence.

Many even nicer rings have the convenient property that their localizations at prime
ideals \emph{factorial}, a key example being the coordinate ring of an affine
nonsingular variety. 
For these even nicer rings, an alternative method of defining the class group
can be given: the class group corresponds to the group of isomorphism
classes of \emph{invertible modules}. Geometrically, such invertible modules
are line bundles on the associated variety (or scheme).

\section{Unique factorization}

\subsection{Definition}
We begin with the nicest of all possible cases, when the ring itself admits
unique factorization.



Let $R$ be a domain.  
\begin{definition} 
A nonzero element $x \in R$ is \textbf{prime} if $(x)$ is a prime ideal.
\end{definition} 

In other words, $x$ is not a unit, and if $x \mid ab$, then either $x \mid a$
or $x \mid b$. 

We restate the earlier \cref{earlyUFD} slightly.
\begin{definition} 
A domain $R$ is \textbf{factorial} (or a \textbf{unique factorization domain},
or a \textbf{UFD}) if every nonzero noninvertible element $x \in R$ factors as a
product $ x_1 \dots x_n$ where each $x_i$ is prime. 
\end{definition}

Recall that a \emph{principal ideal domain} is a UFD (\cref{PIDUFD}), as is a
\emph{euclidean} domain (\cref{EDPID}); actually, a euclidean domain is  a PID.
Previously, we imposed something seemingly slightly stronger: that the
factorization be unique. We next show that we get that for free.

\begin{proposition}[The fundamental theorem of arithmetic]
This factorization is essentially unique, that is, up to multiplication by units.
\end{proposition} 
\begin{proof} Let $x \in R$ be a nonunit. 
Say $x = x_1 \dots x_n = y_1 \dots y_m$ were two different prime
factorizations. Then $m,n>0$. 

We have that $x_1 \mid y_1 \dots y_m$, so $x_1 \mid y_i$ for some $i$. But
$y_i$ is prime. So $x_1$ and $y_i$ differ by a unit. By removing each of these,
we can get  a smaller set of nonunique factorizations. 
Namely, we find that
\[ x_2 \dots x_n = y_1 \dots \hat{y_i} \dots y_m  \]
and then we can induct on the number of factors.
\end{proof} 

The motivating example is of course:
\begin{example} 
$\mathbb{Z}$ is factorial. This is the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, and
follows because $\mathbb{Z}$ is a euclidean domain.  The same observation
applies to a polynomial ring over a field by \cref{polyringED}.
\end{example} 

\subsection{Gauss's lemma}

We now show that factorial rings are closed under the operation of forming
polynomial rings.

\begin{theorem}[Gauss's lemma]
If $R$ is factorial, so is the polynomial ring $R[X]$.
\end{theorem} 
In general, if $R$ is a PID, $R[X]$ will \emph{not} be a PID. For instance,
$\mathbb{Z}[X]$ is not a PID: the prime ideal $(2, X)$ is not principal.

\begin{proof} 
In the course of this proof, we shall identify the prime elements in $R[X]$.
We start with a lemma that allows us to compare factorizations in $K[X]$ (for
$K$ the quotient field) and $R[X]$; the advantage is that we already know the
polynomial ring over a \emph{field} to be  a UFD.
\begin{lemma} Suppose $R$ is a unique factorization domain with
quotient field $K$.
Suppose $f \in R[X]$ is irreducible in $R[X]$ and there is no nontrivial common divisor of
the coefficients of $f$. Then $f$ is irreducible in $K[X]$.
\end{lemma} 
With this in mind, we say that a polynomial in $R[X]$ is \textbf{primitive} if
the coefficients have no common divisor in $R$.

\begin{proof} Indeed, suppose we had a factorization
\[ f = gh,  \quad g, h \in K[X], \]
where $g,h$ have degree $\geq 1$. 
Then we can clear denominators to find a factorization
\[ rf  = g' h'  \]
where $r \in R - \left\{0\right\}$ and $g', h' \in R[X]$. By clearing
denominators as little as possible, we may assume that $g',h'$ are primitive. 
To be precise, we divide $g', h'$ by their \emph{contents.} Let us define:

\begin{definition} 
The \textbf{content} $\cont (f)$ of a polynomial $f \in R[X]$ is the greatest common
divisor of its coefficients.  The content of an element $f$ in $K[X]$ is defined
by considering $r \in R$ such that $rf \in R[X]$, and taking $\cont(rf)/r$.
This is well-defined, modulo elements of $R^*$, and we have $\cont(sf) = s \cont f$ if $s \in K$.
\end{definition}

To say that the content lies in $R$ is to say that the polynomial is in $R[X]$;
to say that the content is a unit is to say that the polynomial is primitive. 
Note that a monic polynomial in $R[X]$ is primitive.

So we have:
\begin{lemma} 
Any element of $K[X]$ is a product of $\cont(f)$ and something primitive in
$R[X]$.
\end{lemma} 
\begin{proof} 
Indeed, $f/\cont(f)$ has content a unit.  It therefore cannot have anything in the
denominator. Indeed, if it had a term $r/p^i X^n$ where $r ,p \in R$ and $p
\nmid r$ is prime, then the content would divide $r/p^i$. It thus could not be
in $R$. 
\end{proof} 

\begin{lemma} 
$\cont(fg) = \cont(f) \cont(g)$ if $f,g \in K[X]$. 
\end{lemma} 
\begin{proof} 
By dividing $f,g$ by their contents, it suffices to show that the product of
two primitive polynomials in $R[X]$ (i.e. those with no common divisor of all
their coefficients) is itself primitive. Indeed, suppose $f,g$ are primitive
and $p \in R$ is a prime. Then $\overline{f}, \overline{g} \in R/(p)[X]$ are
nonzero. Their product $\overline{f}\overline{g}$ is also not zero because
$R/(p)[X]$ is a domain, $p$ being prime. In particular, $p$ is not a common
factor of the coefficients of $fg$. Since $p$ was arbitrary, this completes the
proof.
\end{proof} 

So return to the main proof. We know that $f =  gh$. We divided $g,h$ by their
contents to get $g', h' \in R[X]$. We had then
\[ r f = g' h', \quad r \in K^*.  \]
Taking the contents, and using the fact that $f, g', h'$ are primitive, we have then:
\[ r = \cont(g') \cont(h') = 1 \quad \mathrm{(modulo \ } R^*).  \]
But then $f = r^{-1} g' h'$ shows that $f$ is not irreducible in $R[X]$,
contradiction. 
\end{proof} 


Let $R$ be a ring. Recall that an element is \textbf{irreducible} if it admits
no nontrivial factorization. The product of an irreducible element and a unit
is irreducible.
Call a ring \textbf{finitely irreducible} if every element in the ring admits a
factorization into finitely many irreducible elements. 

\begin{lemma} 
A ring $R$ is finitely irreducible if every ascending sequence of
\emph{principal} ideals in $R$ stabilizes.
\end{lemma} 
A ring such that every ascending sequence  of ideals (not necessarily
principal) stabilizes is said to be \emph{noetherian;} this is a highly useful
finiteness condition on a ring.
\begin{proof} 
Suppose  $R$ satisfies the ascending chain condition on principal ideals. Then
let $x \in R$. We would like to show it can be factored as a product of
irreducibles. 
So suppose $x$ is not the product of finitely many irreducibles. In particular,
it is reducible: $x = x_1 x_1'$, where neither factor is a unit. One of this
cannot be written as a finite product of irreducibles. Say it is $x_1$.
Similarly, we can write $x_1 = x_2 x_2''$ where one of the factors, wlog $x_2$,
is not the product of finitely many irreducibles. Repeating inductively gives
the ascending sequence
\[ (x) \subset (x_1) \subset (x_2) \subset \dots,  \]
and since each factorization is nontrivial, the inclusions are each nontrivial.
This is a contradiction.
\end{proof} 

\begin{lemma} 
Suppose $R$ is a UFD. Then every ascending sequence of principal ideals in
$R[X]$ stabilizes.  In particular, $R[X]$ is finitely irreducible.
\end{lemma} 
\begin{proof} 
Suppose $(f_1) \subset (f_2) \subset \dots \in R[X]$. Then each $f_{i+1} \mid
f_{i}$. In particular, the degrees of $f_i$ are nonincreasing, and consequently
stabilize. Thus for $i \gg 0$, we have $\deg f_{i+1} = \deg f_i$.
We can thus assume that all the degrees are the same. In this case, if $i \gg
0$ and $k>0$, 
$f_{i}/f_{i+k} \in R[X]$ must actually lie in $R$ as $R$ is a domain. 
In particular, throwing out the first few elements in the sequence if
necessary, it follows that our sequence looks like
\[ f, f/r_1, f/(r_1r_2), \dots \]
where the $r_i \in R$. However, we can only continue this a finite amount of
time before the $r_i$'s will have to become units since $R$ is a UFD. (Or $f
 = 0$.) 
So the sequence of ideals stabilizes. 
\end{proof} 

\begin{lemma} 
Every element in $R[X]$ can be factored into a product of irreducibles.
\end{lemma} 
\begin{proof} Now evident from the preceding lemmata.
\end{proof} 
Suppose $P$ is an irreducible element in $R[X]$. I claim that $P$ is prime.
There are two cases:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $P \in R$ is a prime in $R$. Then we know that $P \mid f$ if and only if
the coefficients of $f$ are divisible by $P$. In particular, $P \mid f$ iff $P
\mid \cont (f)$. It is now clear that $P \mid fg$ if and only if $P$ divides
one of $\cont(f), \cont(g)$ (since $\cont(fg) = \cont(f) \cont(g)$). 
\item $P$ does not belong to $R$. Then $P$ must have content a unit or it would
be divisible by its content. 
So $P$ is irreducible in $K[X]$ by the above reasoning. 

Say we have an expression
\[ P \mid fg, \quad f,g \in R[X].  \]
Since $P$ is irreducible, hence prime, in the UFD (even PID) $K[X]$, we have
that $P $ divides one of $f,g$ in $K[X]$. Say we can write
\[ f = q P , q \in K[X].  \]
Then taking the content shows that $\cont(q) = \cont(f) \in R$, so $q \in
R[X]$. It follows that $P \mid f$ in $R[X]$. 
\end{enumerate}

We have shown that every element in $R[X]$ factors into a product of prime
elements. From this, it is clear that $R[X]$ is a UFD.
\end{proof} 


\begin{corollary} 
The polynomial ring $k[X_1, \dots, X_n]$ for $k$ a field is factorial.
\end{corollary} 
\begin{proof} 
Induction on $n$.
\end{proof} 

\subsection{Factoriality and height one primes}

We now want to give a fancier criterion for a ring to be a UFD, in terms of the
lattice 
structure on $\spec R$. This will require a notion from dimension theory (to be
developed more fully later).
\begin{definition} 
Let $R$ be a domain. A prime ideal $\mathfrak{p} \subset R$ is said to be of
\textbf{height one} if $\mathfrak{p}$ is minimal among ideals
containing $x$ for some nonzero $x \in R$. 
\end{definition} 
So a prime of height one is not the zero prime, but it is as close to zero as
possible, in some sense. When we later talk about dimension theory, we will
talk about primes of any height. In a sense, $\mathfrak{p}$ is ``almost''
generated by one element.

\begin{theorem} \label{heightonefactoriality} 
Let $R$ be a noetherian domain. The following are equivalent:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $R$ is factorial. 
\item Every height one prime is principal.
\end{enumerate}
\end{theorem} 
\begin{proof} 
Let's first show 1) implies 2). Assume $R$ is factorial and $\mathfrak{p}$ is
height one, minimal containing $(x)$ for some $x \neq 0 \in R$. 
Then $x$ is a nonunit, and it is nonzero, so it has a prime factorization
\[ x = x_1 \dots x_n, \quad \mathrm{each \ } x_i \ \mathrm{prime}.  \]
Some $x_i \in \mathfrak{p}$ because $\mathfrak{p}$ is prime. In particular,
\[ \mathfrak{p} \supset (x_i) \supset (x).  \]
But $(x_i)$ is prime itself, and it contains $(x)$. The minimality of
$\mathfrak{p}$ says that $\mathfrak{p}  = (x_i)$. 

Conversely, suppose every height one prime is principal. Let $x \in R$ be
nonzero and a nonunit. We want
to factor $x$ as a product of primes. 
Consider the ideal $(x) \subsetneq R$. As a result, $(x)$ is contained in a
prime ideal. Since $R$ is noetherian, there is a minimal prime ideal
$\mathfrak{p}$ containing $(x)$.  Then $\mathfrak{p}$, being a height one
prime, is principal---say $\mathfrak{p}=(x_1)$. It follows that $x_1 \mid x$
and $x_1$ is prime.
Say 
\[ x = x_1 x_1'.  \]
If $x_1'$ is a nonunit, repeat this process to get $x_1' = x_2 x_2'$ with $x_2$ a prime element. 
Keep going; inductively we have
\[ x_k = x_{k+1}x_{k+1}'.  \]
If this process stops, with one of the $x_k'$  a  unit, we get a prime
factorization of $x$. Suppose the process
continues forever. Then we would have
\[ (x) \subsetneq (x_1') \subsetneq (x_2') \subsetneq (x_3') \subsetneq \dots,  \]
which is impossible by noetherianness. 
\end{proof} 

We have seen that unique factorization can be formulated in terms of prime
ideals.


\subsection{Factoriality and normality}

We next state a generalization of the ``rational root theorem'' as in high
school algebra.
\begin{proposition} \label{factorialimpliesnormal}
A factorial domain is integrally closed.
\end{proposition} 

\begin{proof} 
\add{proof -- may be in the queue already}
\end{proof} 

\section{Weil divisors}

\label{weildivsec}
\subsection{Definition}
We start by discussing Weil divisors.
\begin{definition} 
A \textbf{Weil divisor} for $R$ is a formal linear combination $\sum n_{i}
[\mathfrak{p}_i]$ where the $\mathfrak{p}_i$ range over height one primes of
$R$. So the group of Weil divisors is the free abelian group on the height one
primes of $R$. We denote this group by $\weil(R)$.
\end{definition} 


The geometric picture behind Weil divisors is that a Weil divisor is like a
hypersurface: a subvariety of codimension one.

\subsection{Valuations}



\subsection{Nagata's lemma} We finish with a fun application of the exact
sequence of Weil divisors to a purely algebraic statement about factoriality.

\begin{lemma} 
Let $A$ be a normal noetherian domain. 
\end{lemma} 

\begin{theorem} 
Let $A$ be a noetherian domain, $x \in A-\left\{0\right\}$. Suppose $(x)$ is
prime and $A_x$ is factorial. Then $A$ is factorial. 
\end{theorem} 
\begin{proof} 
We first show that $A$ is normal (hence regular in codimension one).
Indeed, $A_x$ is normal. So if $t \in K(A)$ is integral over $A$, it lies in
$A_x$. 
So we need to check that if $a/x^n \in A_x$ is integral over $A$ and $x \nmid
x$, then $n=0$.
Suppose we had an equation
\[ (a/x^n)^N + b_1 (a/x^n)^{N-1} + \dots + b_N = 0.  \]
Multiplying both sides by $x^{nN}$ gives that
\[ a^N \in xR,  \]
so $x \mid a$ by primality.

Now we use the exact sequence
\[ (x) \to \mathrm{Cl}(A) \to \mathrm{Cl}(A_x) \to 0.  \]
The end is zero, and the image of the first map is zero. So
$\mathrm{Cl}(A)=0$. Thus $A$ is a UFD.
\end{proof} 





\section{Locally factorial domains}

\subsection{Definition}
\begin{definition} 
A noetherian domain $R$ is said to be \textbf{locally factorial} if
$R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is factorial for each $\mathfrak{p}$ prime.
\end{definition} 

\begin{example} 
The coordinate ring $\mathbb{C}[x_1, \dots, x_n/I$ of an algebraic variety is
locally factorial if the variety is smooth. We may talk about this later. 
\end{example} 

\begin{example}[Nonexample]
Let $R$ be $\mathbb{C}[A,B,C,D]/(AD - BC)$. The spectrum of $R$ has maximal
ideals consisting of 2-by-2 matrices of determinant zero. This variety is very
singular at the origin. It is not even locally factorial at the origin.

The failure of unique factorization comes from the fact that
\[ AD = BC  \]
in this ring $R$. This is a prototypical example of a ring without unique
factorization. The reason has to do with the fact that the variety has a
singularity at the origin. 
\end{example} 

\subsection{The Picard group}

\begin{definition} 
Let $R$ be a commutative ring. An $R$-module $I$ is \textbf{invertible} if
there exists $J$ such that
\[ I \otimes_R J \simeq R.  \]
Invertibility  is with respect to the tensor product.
\end{definition} 

\begin{remark} \label{linebundremark}
In topology, one is often interested in classifying \emph{vector bundles} on
spaces. In algebraic geometry, a module $M$ over a ring $R$ gives (as in
\cref{}) a sheaf of abelian groups over the topological space $\spec R$; this
is supposed to be an analogy with the theory of vector bundles. (It is not so
implausible since the Serre-Swan theorem (\cref{}) gives an equivalence of
categories between the vector bundles over a compact space $X$ and the
projective modules over the ring $C(X)$ of continuous functions.) 
In this analogy, the invertible modules are the \emph{line bundles}.
The definition has a counterpart in the topological setting: for instance, a
vector bundle $\mathcal{E} \to X$ over a space $X$ is a line bundle (that is,
of rank one) if and only if there is a vector bundle $\mathcal{E}' \to X$ such
that $\mathcal{E} \otimes \mathcal{E}'$ is the trivial bundle $X \times
\mathbb{R}$.
\end{remark} 

There are many equivalent characterizations.

\begin{proposition} 
Let $R$ be a ring, $I$ an $R$-module. TFAE:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $I$ is invertible.   
\item $I$ is finitely generated and $I_{\mathfrak{p}} \simeq R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ for all primes
$\mathfrak{p} \subset R$.
\item $I$ is finitely generated and there exist $a_1, \dots, a_n \in R$ which generate $(1)$
in $R$ such that
\[ I[a_i^{-1}]\simeq R[a_i^{-1}].  \]
\end{enumerate}
\end{proposition} 
\begin{proof} 
First, we show that if $I$ is invertible, then $I$ is finitely generated. 
Suppose $I \otimes_R J \simeq R$. This means that $1 \in R$ corresponds to an
element
\[ \sum i_k \otimes j_k \in I \otimes_R J .  \]
Thus, there exists a finitely generated submodule $I_0\subset I$ such that the map $I_0 \otimes J \to I
\otimes J$ is surjective. Tensor this with $I$, so we get a surjection
\[ I_0 \simeq I_0 \otimes J \otimes I \to I \otimes J \otimes I \simeq I  \]
which leads to a surjection $I_0 \twoheadrightarrow I$. This implies that $I$
is finitely generated 

\textbf{Step 1: 1 implies 2.}
We now show 1 implies 2. Note that if $I$ is invertible, then $I \otimes_R R'$
is an invertible $R'$ module for any $R$-algebra $R'$; to get an inverse of
$I \otimes_R R'$,
tensor the inverse of $I$ with $R'$.
In particular, $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is an invertible $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$-module
for each $\mathfrak{p}$. As a result, 
\[ I_{\mathfrak{p}}/\mathfrak{p} I_{\mathfrak{p}}  \]
is invertible over the \emph{field} $R_{\mathfrak{p}}/\mathfrak{p}R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. This means
that 
$ I_{\mathfrak{p}}/\mathfrak{p} I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is a one-dimensional vector
space over the residue field. (The invertible modules over a vector space are
the one-dimensional spaces.)
Choose an element $x \in I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ which generates
$I_{\mathfrak{p}}/\mathfrak{p}I_{\mathfrak{p}}$.  Since $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is
finitely generated, Nakayama's lemma shows that $x$ generates $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$.

We get a surjection $\alpha: R_{\mathfrak{p}} \twoheadrightarrow I_{\mathfrak{p}}$
carrying $1 \to x$.  We claim that this map is injective.
This will imply that $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is free of rank 1. So, let $J$ be an
inverse of $I$ among $R$-modules, so that $I \otimes_R J = R$; the same
argument as above provides a surjection
$ \beta: {R}_{\mathfrak{p}} \to J_{\mathfrak{p}}$. 
Then $\beta' = \beta \otimes 1_{I_{\mathfrak{p}}}: I_{\mathfrak{p}} \to
R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is also a surjection.
Composing, we get a surjective map
\[ R_{\mathfrak{p}} \stackrel{\alpha}{\twoheadrightarrow} I_{\mathfrak{p}}
\stackrel{\beta'}{\twoheadrightarrow} R_{\mathfrak{p}}  \]
whose composite must be multiplication by a unit, since the ring is local. Thus
the composite is injective and $\alpha$ is injective. 
It follows that $\alpha$ is an isomorphism, so that $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is free
of rank one.

\textbf{Step 2: 2 implies 3.}
Now we show 2 implies 3. Suppose $I$ is finitely generated with generators $\left\{x_1, \dots, x_n\right\} \subset I$ and $I_{\mathfrak{p}} \simeq
R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ for all $\mathfrak{p}$. Then for each $\mathfrak{p}
$, we can choose an element $x$ of $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ generating
$I_{\mathfrak{p}}$ as $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$-module. 
By multiplying by the denominator, we can assume that $x \in I$. 
By assumption, we can then find $a_i,s_i \in R$ with
\[ s_i x_i = a_i x \in R  \]
for some $s_i \notin \mathfrak{p}$ as $x$ generates $I_{\mathfrak{p}}$. This means that $x$ generates $I$ after inverting the $s_i$. It
follows that $I[1/a] = R[1/a]$ where $a = \prod s_i \notin \mathfrak{p}$.
In particular, we find that there is an open covering $\{\spec
R[1/a_{\mathfrak{p}}] \}$ of $\spec R$ (where $a_{\mathfrak{p}} \notin
\mathfrak{p}$) on which $I$ is isomorphic to $R$. 
To say that these cover $\spec R$ is to say that the $a_{\mathfrak{p}}$
generate $1$. 

Finally, let's do the implication 3 implies 1.  Assume that we have the
situation of $I[1/a_i] \simeq R[1/a_i]$. We want to show that $I$ is invertible. 
We start by showing that $I$ is \textbf{finitely presented}. This means that
there is an exact sequence
\[ R^m \to R^n \to I \to 0,  \]
i.e. $I$ is the cokernel of a map between free modules of finite rank.
To see this, first, we've assumed that $I$ is finitely generated. So there is a
surjection
\[ R^n \twoheadrightarrow I  \]
with a kernel $K \rightarrowtail  R^n$. We must show that $K$ is finitely
generated. Localization is an exact functor, so $K[1/a_i]$ is the kernel of
$R[1/a_i]^n \to I[1/a_i]$. However, we have an exact sequence
\[ K[1/a_i] \rightarrowtail  R[1/a_i]^n \twoheadrightarrow R[1/a_i]  \]
by the assumed isomorphism $I[1/a_i] \simeq R[1/a_i]$. But since a free module
is projective, this sequence splits and we find that $K[1/a_i]$ is finitely
generated. If it's finitely generated, it's generated by finitely many elements
in $K$. 
As a result, we find that there is a map
\[ R^N \to K  \]
such that the localization to $\spec R[1/a_i]$ is surjective. This implies by
the homework that $R^N \to K$ is surjective.\footnote{To check that a map is
surjective, just check at the localizations at any maximal ideal.} Thus $K$ is finitely generated. 

In any case, we have shown that the module $I$ is finitely presented.
\textbf{Define} $J = \hom_R(I, R)$ as the candidate for its dual. This
construction is compatible with localization.
We can choose a finite presentation $R^m \to R^n \to I \to 0$, which leads to a
sequence
\[ 0 \to J \to \hom(R^n, R) \to \hom(R^m, R).  \]
It follows that the formation of $J$ commutes with localization. 
In particular, this argument shows that
\[ J[1/a] = \hom_{R[1/a]}(I[1/a], R[1/a]).  \]
One can check this by using the description of $J$. By construction, there is a
canonical map $I \otimes J \to R$. 
I claim that this map is invertible.

For the proof, we use the fact that one can check for an isomorphism locally.  
It suffices to show that 
\[ I[1/a] \otimes J[1/a] \to R[1/a]  \]
is an isomorphism for some collection of $a$'s that generate the unit ideal.
However, we have $a_1, \dots, a_n$ that generate the unit ideal such that
$I[1/a_i]$ is free of rank 1, hence so is $J[1/a_i]$. It thus follows that
$I[1/a_i] \otimes J[1/a_i]$ is an isomorphism.
\end{proof} 


\begin{definition} 
Let $R$ be a commutative ring. We define the \textbf{Picard group} $\pic(R)$ to
be the set of isomorphism classes of invertible $R$-modules. This is an abelian
group; the addition law is defined so that the sum of the classes represented
by $M, N$ is $M \otimes_R N$.
The identity element is given by $R$. 
\end{definition} 

The Picard group is thus analogous (cf. \cref{linebundleremark}) to the set of
isomorphism classes of line bundles on a topological space (which is also an
abelian group). While the latter can often be easily computed (for a nice space
$X$, the line bundles are classified by elements of $H^2(X, \mathbb{Z})$), the
interpretation in the algebraic setting is more difficult. 
\subsection{Cartier divisors}

Assume furthermore that $R$ is a domain. We now introduce:

\begin{definition} 
A \textbf{Cartier divisor} for $R$ is a submodule $M \subset K(R)$ such that
$M$ is invertible. 
\end{definition} 
In other words, a Cartier divisor is an invertible fractional ideal.
Alternatively, it is an invertible $R$-module $M$ with a nonzero map $M \to
K(R)$. \textbf{ Once this map is nonzero, it is automatically injective,} since
injectivity can be checked at the localizations, and any module-homomorphism from a domain into
its quotient field is either zero or injective (because it is multiplication by
some element). 


We now make this into a group. 
\begin{definition} 
Given $(M, a: M \hookrightarrow K(R))$ and $(N, b: N \hookrightarrow K(R))$, we
define the sum to be 
\[  (M \otimes N, a \otimes b: M \otimes N \hookrightarrow K(R)). \]
The map $a \otimes b$ is nonzero, so by what was said above, it is an injection.
Thus the Cartier divisors from an abelian group $\cart(R)$.
\end{definition} 

By assumption, there is a homomorphism
\[ \cart(R) \to\pic(R)  \]
mapping $(M, M \hookrightarrow K(R)) \to M$. 

\begin{proposition} 
The map $\cart(R) \to \pic(R)$ is surjective. In other words, any invertible
$R$-module can be embedded in $K(R)$.
\end{proposition} 
\begin{proof}  Let $M$ be an invertible $R$-module.
Indeed, we know that $M_{(0)} = M \otimes_R K(R)$ is an invertible
$K(R)$-module, so a one-dimensional vector space over $K(R)$. In particular,
$M_{(0)} \simeq K(R)$. There is a nonzero homomorphic map
\[  M \to M_{(0) } \simeq K(R),  \]
which is automatically injective by the discussion above. 
\end{proof} 

What is the kernel of $\cart(R) \to \pic(R)$? This is the set of Cartier divisors which are
isomorphic to $R$ itself. In other words, it is the set of $(R, R
\hookrightarrow K(R))$. This data is the same thing as the data of a nonzero
element of $K(R)$. 
So the kernel of 
\[  \cart(R) \to \pic(R)  \]
has kernel isomorphic to $K(R)^*$. We have a short exact sequence
\[  K(R)^* \to \cart(R) \to \pic(R) \to 0.  \]

\subsection{Weil divisors and Cartier divisors}

Now, we want to assume $\cart(R)$ if $R$ is ``good.'' The ``goodness'' in
question is to assume that $R$ is locally factorial, i.e. that
$R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is factorial for each $\mathfrak{p}$. This is true, for
instance, if $R$ is the coordinate ring of a smooth algebraic variety.



\begin{proposition} 
If $R$ is locally factorial and noetherian, then the group $\cart(R)$ is a free abelian group.
The generators are in bijection with the height one primes of $R$.
\end{proposition} 
Now assume that $R$ is a locally factorial, noetherian domain. 
We shall produce an isomorphism
\[ \weil(R) \simeq \cart(R)  \]
that sends $[\mathfrak{p}_i]$ to that height one prime $\mathfrak{p}_i$
together with the imbedding $\mathfrak{p}_i \hookrightarrow R \to K(R)$. 

We first check that this is well-defined. Since $\weil(R)$ is free, all we have
to do is check that each $\mathfrak{p}_i$ is a legitimate Cartier divisor. In
other words, we need to show that:

\begin{proposition} 
If $\mathfrak{p} \subset R$ is a height one prime and $R$ locally factorial, then $\mathfrak{p}$ is
invertible. 
\end{proposition} 
\begin{proof} 
In the last lecture, we gave a criterion for invertibility: namely, being
locally trivial. We have to show that for any prime $\mathfrak{q}$, we have
that $\mathfrak{p}_{\mathfrak{q}}$ is isomorphic to $R_{\mathfrak{q}}$. If
$\mathfrak{p} \not\subset \mathfrak{q}$, then $\mathfrak{p}_{\mathfrak{q}}$ is
the entire ring $R_{\mathfrak{q}}$, so this is obvious. Conversely, suppose
$\mathfrak{p} \subset {\mathfrak{q}}$. Then $\mathfrak{p}_{\mathfrak{q}}$ is
a height one prime of $R_{\mathfrak{q}}$: it is minimal over some element in
$R_{\mathfrak{q}}$. 

Thus $\mathfrak{p}_{\mathfrak{q}}$ is principal, in particular free of rank
one, since $R_{\mathfrak{q}}$ is factorial. We saw last time that being
factorial is equivalent to the principalness of height one primes. 
\end{proof} 

We need to define the inverse map
\[ \cart(R) \to \weil(R).  \]
In order to do this, start with a Cartier divisor $(M, M \hookrightarrow
K(R))$. We then have to describe which coefficient to assign a height one
prime. To do this, we use a local criterion. 

Let's first digress a bit.
Consider a locally factorial domain $R$ and a prime $\mathfrak{p}$ of height
one. Then $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is factorial. In particular, its maximal ideal
$\mathfrak{p}R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is height one, so principal. 
It is the principal ideal generated by some $t \in R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. 
Now we show:
\begin{proposition} 
Every nonzero ideal in $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is of the form $(t^n)$ for some unique $n
\geq 0$.
\end{proposition} 
\begin{proof} 
Let $I_0 \subset R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ be nonzero.  If $I_0 = R_{\mathfrak{p}}$, then
we're done---it's generated by $t^0$. Otherwise, $I_0 \subsetneq
R_{\mathfrak{p}}$, so contained in $\mathfrak{p}R_{\mathfrak{p}} = (t)$. So let
$I_1 = \left\{x \in R_{\mathfrak{p}}: tx \in I_0\right\}$. Thus 
\[ I_1 = t^{-1} I_0.  \]
I claim now that $I_1 \neq I_0$, i.e. that there exists $x \in R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ such that $x
\notin I_0$ but $tx \in I_0$. The proof comes from the theory of associated
primes.
Look at $R_{\mathfrak{p}}/I_0$; it has at least one associated prime as it is
nonzero. 

Since it
is a torsion module, this associated prime must be
$\mathfrak{p}R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ since the only primes in $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$
are $(0)$ and $(t)$, \textbf{which we have not yet shown}.  So there exists an
element in the quotient $R/I_0$ whose annihilator is precisely $(t)$. Lifting
this gives an element in $R$ which when multiplied by $(t)$ is in $I_0$ but
which is not in $I_0$. So $I_0 \subsetneq I_1$.

Proceed as before now. Define $I_2 = \left\{x  \in R_{\mathfrak{p}}: tx \in
I_1\right\}$.  This process must halt since we have assumed noetherianness. We
must have $I_m = I_{m+1}$ for some $m$, which would imply that some $I_m =
R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ by the above argument. It then follows that $I_0 = (t^m)$
since each $I_i$ is just $t I_{i+1}$. 
\end{proof} 

We thus have a good structure theory for ideals in $R$ localized at a height one prime.
Let us make a more general claim.

\begin{proposition} 
Every nonzero finitely generated $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$-submodule of the fraction field $K(R)$ is of the
form $(t^n)$ for some $n \in \mathbb{Z}$.
\end{proposition} 
\begin{proof} 
Say that $M \subset K(R)$ is such a submodule. Let $I = \left\{x \in
R_{\mathfrak{p}}, x M \subset R_{\mathfrak{p}}\right\}$. Then $I \neq 0$ as $M$
is finitely generated  $M$ is generated over $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ by a finite number of fractions $a_i/b_i, b_i \in R$.
Then the product $b = \prod b_i$ brings $M$ into $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. 

We know that $I = (t^m) $ for some $m$. In particular, $t^m M$ is an ideal in
$R$. In particular, 
\[ t^m M = t^p R  \]
for some $p$, in particular $M = t^{p-m}R$. 

\end{proof} 

Now let's go back to the main discussion. $R$ is a noetherian locally factorial
domain; we want to construct a map
\[ \cart(R) \to \weil(R).  \]
Given $(M, M \hookrightarrow K(R))$ with $M$ invertible, we want to define a
formal sum $\sum n_i [\mathfrak{p}_i]$. For every height one prime
$\mathfrak{p}$, let us look at the local ring $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ with maximal
ideal generated by some $t_{\mathfrak{p}} \in R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. Now
$M_{\mathfrak{p}} \subset K(R)$ is a finitely generated
$R_{\mathfrak{p}}$-submodule, so generated by some
$t_{\mathfrak{p}}^{n_{\mathfrak{p}}}$. So we map $(M, M \hookrightarrow K(R))$
to 
\[ \sum_{\mathfrak{p}} n_{\mathfrak{p}}[\mathfrak{p}]. \]
First, we have to check that this is well-defined. In particular, we have to
show:

\begin{proposition} 
For almost all height one $\mathfrak{p}$, we have $M_{\mathfrak{p}} =
R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. In other words, the integers $n_{\mathfrak{p}}$ are almost all zero.
\end{proposition} 
\begin{proof} 
We can always assume that $M$ is actually an ideal. Indeed, choose $a \in R$
with $aM = I \subset R$. As Cartier divisors, we have $M  = I  - (a)$. If we
prove the result for $I$ and $(a)$, then we will have proved it for $M$ (note
that the $n_{\mathfrak{p}}$'s are additive invariants\footnote{To see this,
localize at $\mathfrak{p}$---then if $M$ is generated by $t^a$, $N$ generated
by $t^b$, then $M \otimes N$ is generated by $t^{a+b}$.}). So because of this
additivity, it is sufficient to prove the proposition for actual (i.e.
nonfractional) ideals.

Assume thus that $M \subset R$.
All of these $n_{\mathfrak{p}}$ associated to $M$ are at least zero because $M$
is actually an ideal. What we want is that $n_{\mathfrak{p}} \leq 0$ for almost
all $\mathfrak{p}$. In other words, we must show that
\[ M_{\mathfrak{p}} \supset R_{\mathfrak{p}} \quad \mathrm{almost \ all \ }
\mathfrak{p}.  \]
To do this, just choose any $x \in M - 0$. There are finitely many minimal
primes containing $(x)$ (by primary decomposition applied to $R/(x)$). Every
other height one prime $\mathfrak{q}$ does not contain $(x)$.\footnote{Again, we're using
something about height one primes not proved yet.}
This states that $M_{\mathfrak{q}} \supset x/x = 1$, so $M_{\mathfrak{q}}
\supset R_{\mathfrak{q}}$.

The key claim we've used in this proof is the following. If $\mathfrak{q}$ is a 
height one prime in a domain $R$ containing some nonzero element $(x)$, then
$\mathfrak{q}$ is minimal among primes containing $(x)$. In other words, we can
test the height one condition at any nonzero element in that prime.
Alternatively:
\begin{lemma} 
There are no nontrivial containments among height one primes.
\end{lemma} 
\end{proof} 

Anyway, we have constructed maps between $\cart(R) $ and $\weil(R)$. The map
$\cart(R) \to \weil(R)$ takes $M \to \sum n_{\mathfrak{p}}[\mathfrak{p}]$. The
other map $\weil(R) \to \cart(R)$ takes $[\mathfrak{p}] \to \mathfrak{p}
\subset K(R)$. The composition $\weil(R) \to \weil(R)$ is the identity. Why is that? Start with a
prime $\mathfrak{p}$; that goes to the Cartier divisor $\mathfrak{p}$. Then we
need to finitely generatedre the multiplicities at other height one primes. But if
$\mathfrak{p}$ is height one and $\mathfrak{q}$ is a height one prime, then if
$\mathfrak{p} \neq \mathfrak{q}$ the lack of nontrivial containment relations
implies that the multiplicity of $\mathfrak{p}$ at $\mathfrak{q}$ is zero. We
have shown that
\[  \weil(R) \to \cart(R) \to \weil(R)  \]
is the identity.

Now we have to show that $\cart(R) \to \weil(R)$ is injective. Say we have a
Cartier divisor $(M, M \hookrightarrow K(R))$ that maps to zero in $\weil(R)$,
i.e. all its multiplicities
$n_{\mathfrak{p}}$ are zero at height one primes. 
We show that $M  = R$. 

First, assume $M \subset R$. 
It is sufficient to show that at any maximal ideal $\mathfrak{m} \subset R$, we
have
\[ M_{\mathfrak{m}} = R_{\mathfrak{m}}.  \]
What can we say? Well, $M_{\mathfrak{m}}$ is principal as $M$ is invertible,
being a Cartier divisor. Let it be generated by $x \in R_{\mathfrak{m}}$;
suppose $x$ is a nonunit (or we're already done). But
$R_{\mathfrak{m}}$ is factorial, so $x = x_1 \dots x_n$ for each $x_i $ prime.
If $n>0$, then however $M$ has nonzero multiplicity at the prime ideal  $(x_i) \subset
R_{\mathfrak{m}} $. This is a contradiction. 

The general case of $M$ not really a  subset of $R$ can be handled similarly:
then the generating element $x$ might lie in the fraction field. So $x$, if it
is not a unit in $R$, is a
product of some primes in the numerator and some primes in the denominator. 
The nonzero primes that occur lead to nonzero multiplicities. 
\lecture{10/13}

\subsection{Recap and a loose end}

Last time, it was claimed that if $R$ is a locally factorial domain, and
$\mathfrak{p} \subset R$ is of height one, then every prime ideal of
$R_{\mathfrak{p}}$ is either maximal or zero. This follows from general
dimension theory. This is equivalent to the following general claim about
height one primes:

\begin{quote}
There are no nontrivial inclusions among height one primes for $R$ a locally
factorial domain. 
\end{quote}

\begin{proof}  Suppose $\mathfrak{q} \subsetneq \mathfrak{p}$ is an inclusion
of height one primes. 

Replace $R$ by $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$. Then $R$ is local with some maximal ideal
$\mathfrak{m}$, which is principal with some generator $x$.  
Then we have an inclusion 
\[ 0 \subset \mathfrak{q} \subset \mathfrak{m}.  \]
This inclusion is proper. However, $\mathfrak{q}$ is principal since
it is height one in the factorial ring $R_{\mathfrak{p}}$.
This cannot be since every element is a power of $x$ times a unit.
(Alright, this wasn't live \TeX ed well.)
\end{proof} 

Last time, we were talking about $\weil(R)$ and $\cart(R)$ for $R$ a locally
factorial noetherian domain.
\begin{enumerate}
\item $\weil(R)$ is free on the height one primes. 
\item $\cart(R)$ is the group of invertible submodules of $K(R)$.
\end{enumerate}
We produced an isomorphism
\[ \weil(R) \simeq \cart(R).  \]

\begin{remark} 
Geometrically, what is this? Suppose $R = \mathbb{C}[X_1, \dots, X_n]/I$ for
some ideal $I$. Then the maximal ideals, or closed points in $\spec R$, are
certain points in $\mathbb{C}^n$; they form an irreducible variety if $R$ is
a domain. The locally factorial condition is satisfied, for instance, if the
variety is \emph{smooth}. In this case, the Weil divisors correspond to sums of 
irreducible varieties of codimension one---which correspond to the primes of
height one. The Weil divisors are free on the set
of irreducible varieties of codimension one.  

The Cartier divisors can be thought of as ``linear combinations'' of
subvarieties which are locally defined by one equation. It is natural to assume
that the condition of being defined by one equation corresponds to being
codimension one. This is true by the condition of $R$ locally factorial.

In general, we can always construct a map
\[ \cart(R) \to \weil(R),  \]
but it is not necessarily an isomorphism. 


\end{remark} 

\subsection{Further remarks on $\weil(R)$ and $\cart(R)$} Recall that the Cartier group fits in an exact sequence:
\[  K(R)^* \to \cart(R) \to \pic(R) \to 0,   \]
because every element of $\cart(R)$ determines its isomorphism class, and
every element of $K(R)^*$ determines a free module of rank one. Contrary
to what was stated last time, it is \textbf{not true} that exactness holds on
the right. In fact, the kernel is the group $R^*$ of units of $R$. So the exact
sequence runs
\[ 0 \to R^* \to K(R)^* \to  \cart(R) \to \pic(R) \to 0.  \]
This is true for \emph{any} domain $R$. For $R$ locally factorial and
noetherian, we know that $\cart(R) \simeq \weil(R)$, though. 

We can think of this as a generalization of unique factorization. 
\begin{proposition} 
$R$ is factorial if and only if $R$ is locally factorial and $\pic(R) = 0$.
\end{proposition} 
\begin{proof} 
Assume $R$ is locally factorial and $\pic(R)=0$. Then every prime ideal of
height one (an element of $\weil(R)$, hence of $\cart(R)$) is principal, which
implies that $R$ is factorial. And conversely.
\end{proof} 

In general, we can think of the exact sequence above as a form of unique
factorization for a locally factorial domain: any invertible fractional ideal is a product of height one prime
ideals. 

Let us now give an example.
\add{?}