Datasets:
Tasks:
Text Generation
Modalities:
Text
Sub-tasks:
language-modeling
Languages:
English
Size:
100K - 1M
License:
File size: 133,564 Bytes
afd65d6 |
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148 149 150 151 152 153 154 155 156 157 158 159 160 161 162 163 164 165 166 167 168 169 170 171 172 173 174 175 176 177 178 179 180 181 182 183 184 185 186 187 188 189 190 191 192 193 194 195 196 197 198 199 200 201 202 203 204 205 206 207 208 209 210 211 212 213 214 215 216 217 218 219 220 221 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 244 245 246 247 248 249 250 251 252 253 254 255 256 257 258 259 260 261 262 263 264 265 266 267 268 269 270 271 272 273 274 275 276 277 278 279 280 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288 289 290 291 292 293 294 295 296 297 298 299 300 301 302 303 304 305 306 307 308 309 310 311 312 313 314 315 316 317 318 319 320 321 322 323 324 325 326 327 328 329 330 331 332 333 334 335 336 337 338 339 340 341 342 343 344 345 346 347 348 349 350 351 352 353 354 355 356 357 358 359 360 361 362 363 364 365 366 367 368 369 370 371 372 373 374 375 376 377 378 379 380 381 382 383 384 385 386 387 388 389 390 391 392 393 394 395 396 397 398 399 400 401 402 403 404 405 406 407 408 409 410 411 412 413 414 415 416 417 418 419 420 421 422 423 424 425 426 427 428 429 430 431 432 433 434 435 436 437 438 439 440 441 442 443 444 445 446 447 448 449 450 451 452 453 454 455 456 457 458 459 460 461 462 463 464 465 466 467 468 469 470 471 472 473 474 475 476 477 478 479 480 481 482 483 484 485 486 487 488 489 490 491 492 493 494 495 496 497 498 499 500 501 502 503 504 505 506 507 508 509 510 511 512 513 514 515 516 517 518 519 520 521 522 523 524 525 526 527 528 529 530 531 532 533 534 535 536 537 538 539 540 541 542 543 544 545 546 547 548 549 550 551 552 553 554 555 556 557 558 559 560 561 562 563 564 565 566 567 568 569 570 571 572 573 574 575 576 577 578 579 580 581 582 583 584 585 586 587 588 589 590 591 592 593 594 595 596 597 598 599 600 601 602 603 604 605 606 607 608 609 610 611 612 613 614 615 616 617 618 619 620 621 622 623 624 625 626 627 628 629 630 631 632 633 634 635 636 637 638 639 640 641 642 643 644 645 646 647 648 649 650 651 652 653 654 655 656 657 658 659 660 661 662 663 664 665 666 667 668 669 670 671 672 673 674 675 676 677 678 679 680 681 682 683 684 685 686 687 688 689 690 691 692 693 694 695 696 697 698 699 700 701 702 703 704 705 706 707 708 709 710 711 712 713 714 715 716 717 718 719 720 721 722 723 724 725 726 727 728 729 730 731 732 733 734 735 736 737 738 739 740 741 742 743 744 745 746 747 748 749 750 751 752 753 754 755 756 757 758 759 760 761 762 763 764 765 766 767 768 769 770 771 772 773 774 775 776 777 778 779 780 781 782 783 784 785 786 787 788 789 790 791 792 793 794 795 796 797 798 799 800 801 802 803 804 805 806 807 808 809 810 811 812 813 814 815 816 817 818 819 820 821 822 823 824 825 826 827 828 829 830 831 832 833 834 835 836 837 838 839 840 841 842 843 844 845 846 847 848 849 850 851 852 853 854 855 856 857 858 859 860 861 862 863 864 865 866 867 868 869 870 871 872 873 874 875 876 877 878 879 880 881 882 883 884 885 886 887 888 889 890 891 892 893 894 895 896 897 898 899 900 901 902 903 904 905 906 907 908 909 910 911 912 913 914 915 916 917 918 919 920 921 922 923 924 925 926 927 928 929 930 931 932 933 934 935 936 937 938 939 940 941 942 943 944 945 946 947 948 949 950 951 952 953 954 955 956 957 958 959 960 961 962 963 964 965 966 967 968 969 970 971 972 973 974 975 976 977 978 979 980 981 982 983 984 985 986 987 988 989 990 991 992 993 994 995 996 997 998 999 1000 1001 1002 1003 1004 1005 1006 1007 1008 1009 1010 1011 1012 1013 1014 1015 1016 1017 1018 1019 1020 1021 1022 1023 1024 1025 1026 1027 1028 1029 1030 1031 1032 1033 1034 1035 1036 1037 1038 1039 1040 1041 1042 1043 1044 1045 1046 1047 1048 1049 1050 1051 1052 1053 1054 1055 1056 1057 1058 1059 1060 1061 1062 1063 1064 1065 1066 1067 1068 1069 1070 1071 1072 1073 1074 1075 1076 1077 1078 1079 1080 1081 1082 1083 1084 1085 1086 1087 1088 1089 1090 1091 1092 1093 1094 1095 1096 1097 1098 1099 1100 1101 1102 1103 1104 1105 1106 1107 1108 1109 1110 1111 1112 1113 1114 1115 1116 1117 1118 1119 1120 1121 1122 1123 1124 1125 1126 1127 1128 1129 1130 1131 1132 1133 1134 1135 1136 1137 1138 1139 1140 1141 1142 1143 1144 1145 1146 1147 1148 1149 1150 1151 1152 1153 1154 1155 1156 1157 1158 1159 1160 1161 1162 1163 1164 1165 1166 1167 1168 1169 1170 1171 1172 1173 1174 1175 1176 1177 1178 1179 1180 1181 1182 1183 1184 1185 1186 1187 1188 1189 1190 1191 1192 1193 1194 1195 1196 1197 1198 1199 1200 1201 1202 1203 1204 1205 1206 1207 1208 1209 1210 1211 1212 1213 1214 1215 1216 1217 1218 1219 1220 1221 1222 1223 1224 1225 1226 1227 1228 1229 1230 1231 1232 1233 1234 1235 1236 1237 1238 1239 1240 1241 1242 1243 1244 1245 1246 1247 1248 1249 1250 1251 1252 1253 1254 1255 1256 1257 1258 1259 1260 1261 1262 1263 1264 1265 1266 1267 1268 1269 1270 1271 1272 1273 1274 1275 1276 1277 1278 1279 1280 1281 1282 1283 1284 1285 1286 1287 1288 1289 1290 1291 1292 1293 1294 1295 1296 1297 1298 1299 1300 1301 1302 1303 1304 1305 1306 1307 1308 1309 1310 1311 1312 1313 1314 1315 1316 1317 1318 1319 1320 1321 1322 1323 1324 1325 1326 1327 1328 1329 1330 1331 1332 1333 1334 1335 1336 1337 1338 1339 1340 1341 1342 1343 1344 1345 1346 1347 1348 1349 1350 1351 1352 1353 1354 1355 1356 1357 1358 1359 1360 1361 1362 1363 1364 1365 1366 1367 1368 1369 1370 1371 1372 1373 1374 1375 1376 1377 1378 1379 1380 1381 1382 1383 1384 1385 1386 1387 1388 1389 1390 1391 1392 1393 1394 1395 1396 1397 1398 1399 1400 1401 1402 1403 1404 1405 1406 1407 1408 1409 1410 1411 1412 1413 1414 1415 1416 1417 1418 1419 1420 1421 1422 1423 1424 1425 1426 1427 1428 1429 1430 1431 1432 1433 1434 1435 1436 1437 1438 1439 1440 1441 1442 1443 1444 1445 1446 1447 1448 1449 1450 1451 1452 1453 1454 1455 1456 1457 1458 1459 1460 1461 1462 1463 1464 1465 1466 1467 1468 1469 1470 1471 1472 1473 1474 1475 1476 1477 1478 1479 1480 1481 1482 1483 1484 1485 1486 1487 1488 1489 1490 1491 1492 1493 1494 1495 1496 1497 1498 1499 1500 1501 1502 1503 1504 1505 1506 1507 1508 1509 1510 1511 1512 1513 1514 1515 1516 1517 1518 1519 1520 1521 1522 1523 1524 1525 1526 1527 1528 1529 1530 1531 1532 1533 1534 1535 1536 1537 1538 1539 1540 1541 1542 1543 1544 1545 1546 1547 1548 1549 1550 1551 1552 1553 1554 1555 1556 1557 1558 1559 1560 1561 1562 1563 1564 1565 1566 1567 1568 1569 1570 1571 1572 1573 1574 1575 1576 1577 1578 1579 1580 1581 1582 1583 1584 1585 1586 1587 1588 1589 1590 1591 1592 1593 1594 1595 1596 1597 1598 1599 1600 1601 1602 1603 1604 1605 1606 1607 1608 1609 1610 1611 1612 1613 1614 1615 1616 1617 1618 1619 1620 1621 1622 1623 1624 1625 1626 1627 1628 1629 1630 1631 1632 1633 1634 1635 1636 1637 1638 1639 1640 1641 1642 1643 1644 1645 1646 1647 1648 1649 1650 1651 1652 1653 1654 1655 1656 1657 1658 1659 1660 1661 1662 1663 1664 1665 1666 1667 1668 1669 1670 1671 1672 1673 1674 1675 1676 1677 1678 1679 1680 1681 1682 1683 1684 1685 1686 1687 1688 1689 1690 1691 1692 1693 1694 1695 1696 1697 1698 1699 1700 1701 1702 1703 1704 1705 1706 1707 1708 1709 1710 1711 1712 1713 1714 1715 1716 1717 1718 1719 1720 1721 1722 1723 1724 1725 1726 1727 1728 1729 1730 1731 1732 1733 1734 1735 1736 1737 1738 1739 1740 1741 1742 1743 1744 1745 1746 1747 1748 1749 1750 1751 1752 1753 1754 1755 1756 1757 1758 1759 1760 1761 1762 1763 1764 1765 1766 1767 1768 1769 1770 1771 1772 1773 1774 1775 1776 1777 1778 1779 1780 1781 1782 1783 1784 1785 1786 1787 1788 1789 1790 1791 1792 1793 1794 1795 1796 1797 1798 1799 1800 1801 1802 1803 1804 1805 1806 1807 1808 1809 1810 1811 1812 1813 1814 1815 1816 1817 1818 1819 1820 1821 1822 1823 1824 1825 1826 1827 1828 1829 1830 1831 1832 1833 1834 1835 1836 1837 1838 1839 1840 1841 1842 1843 1844 1845 1846 1847 1848 1849 1850 1851 1852 1853 1854 1855 1856 1857 1858 1859 1860 1861 1862 1863 1864 1865 1866 1867 1868 1869 1870 1871 1872 1873 1874 1875 1876 1877 1878 1879 1880 1881 1882 1883 1884 1885 1886 1887 1888 1889 1890 1891 1892 1893 1894 1895 1896 1897 1898 1899 1900 1901 1902 1903 1904 1905 1906 1907 1908 1909 1910 1911 1912 1913 1914 1915 1916 1917 1918 1919 1920 1921 1922 1923 1924 1925 1926 1927 1928 1929 1930 1931 1932 1933 1934 1935 1936 1937 1938 1939 1940 1941 1942 1943 1944 1945 1946 1947 1948 1949 1950 1951 1952 1953 1954 1955 1956 1957 1958 1959 1960 1961 1962 1963 1964 1965 1966 1967 1968 1969 1970 1971 1972 1973 1974 1975 1976 1977 1978 1979 1980 1981 1982 1983 1984 1985 1986 1987 1988 1989 1990 1991 1992 1993 1994 1995 1996 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 2008 2009 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 2018 2019 2020 2021 2022 2023 2024 2025 2026 2027 2028 2029 2030 2031 2032 2033 2034 2035 2036 2037 2038 2039 2040 2041 2042 2043 2044 2045 2046 2047 2048 2049 2050 2051 2052 2053 2054 2055 2056 2057 2058 2059 2060 2061 2062 2063 2064 2065 2066 2067 2068 2069 2070 2071 2072 2073 2074 2075 2076 2077 2078 2079 2080 2081 2082 2083 2084 2085 2086 2087 2088 2089 2090 2091 2092 2093 2094 2095 2096 2097 2098 2099 2100 2101 2102 2103 2104 2105 2106 2107 2108 2109 2110 2111 2112 2113 2114 2115 2116 2117 2118 2119 2120 2121 2122 2123 2124 2125 2126 2127 2128 2129 2130 2131 2132 2133 2134 2135 2136 2137 2138 2139 2140 2141 2142 2143 2144 2145 2146 2147 2148 2149 2150 2151 2152 2153 2154 2155 2156 2157 2158 2159 2160 2161 2162 2163 2164 2165 2166 2167 2168 2169 2170 2171 2172 2173 2174 2175 2176 2177 2178 2179 2180 2181 2182 2183 2184 2185 2186 2187 2188 2189 |
\chapter{Higher inductive types}
\label{cha:hits}
\index{type!higher inductive|(}%
\indexsee{inductive!type!higher}{type, higher inductive}%
\indexsee{higher inductive type}{type, higher inductive}%
\section{Introduction}
\label{sec:intro-hits}
\index{generation!of a type, inductive|(}
Like the general inductive types we discussed in \cref{cha:induction}, \emph{higher inductive types} are a general schema for defining new types generated by some constructors.
But unlike ordinary inductive types, in defining a higher inductive type we may have ``constructors'' which generate not only \emph{points} of that type, but also \emph{paths} and higher paths in that type.
\index{type!circle}%
\indexsee{circle type}{type,circle}%
For instance, we can consider the higher inductive type $\Sn^1$ generated by
\begin{itemize}
\item A point $\base:\Sn^1$, and
\item A path $\lloop : {\id[\Sn^1]\base\base}$.
\end{itemize}
This should be regarded as entirely analogous to the definition of, for instance, $\bool$, as being generated by
\begin{itemize}
\item A point $\bfalse:\bool$ and
\item A point $\btrue:\bool$,
\end{itemize}
or the definition of $\nat$ as generated by
\begin{itemize}
\item A point $0:\nat$ and
\item A function $\suc:\nat\to\nat$.
\end{itemize}
When we think of types as higher groupoids, the more general notion of ``generation'' is very natural:
since a higher groupoid is a ``multi-sorted object'' with paths and higher paths as well as points, we should allow ``generators'' in all dimensions.
We will refer to the ordinary sort of constructors (such as $\base$) as \define{point constructors}
\indexdef{constructor!point}%
\indexdef{point!constructor}%
or \emph{ordinary constructors}, and to the others (such as $\lloop$) as \define{path constructors}
\indexdef{constructor!path}%
\indexdef{path!constructor}%
or \emph{higher constructors}.
Each path constructor must specify the starting and ending point of the path, which we call its \define{source}
\indexdef{source!of a path constructor}%
and \define{target};
\indexdef{target!of a path constructor}%
for $\lloop$, both source and target are $\base$.
Note that a path constructor such as $\lloop$ generates a \emph{new} inhabitant of an identity type, which is not (at least, not \emph{a priori}) equal to any previously existing such inhabitant.
In particular, $\lloop$ is not \emph{a priori} equal to $\refl{\base}$ (although proving that they are definitely unequal takes a little thought; see \cref{thm:loop-nontrivial}).
This is what distinguishes $\Sn^1$ from the ordinary inductive type \unit.
There are some important points to be made regarding this generalization.
\index{free!generation of an inductive type}%
First of all, the word ``generation'' should be taken seriously, in the same sense that a group can be freely generated by some set.
In particular, because a higher groupoid comes with \emph{operations} on paths and higher paths, when such an object is ``generated'' by certain constructors, the operations create more paths that do not come directly from the constructors themselves.
For instance, in the higher inductive type $\Sn^1$, the constructor $\lloop$ is not the only nontrivial path from $\base$ to $\base$; we have also ``$\lloop\ct\lloop$'' and ``$\lloop\ct\lloop\ct\lloop$'' and so on, as well as $\opp{\lloop}$, etc., all of which are different.
This may seem so obvious as to be not worth mentioning, but it is a departure from the behavior of ``ordinary'' inductive types, where one can expect to see nothing in the inductive type except what was ``put in'' directly by the constructors.
Secondly, this generation is really \emph{free} generation: higher inductive types do not technically allow us to impose ``axioms'', such as forcing ``$\lloop\ct\lloop$'' to equal $\refl{\base}$.
However, in the world of $\infty$-groupoids,%
\index{.infinity-groupoid@$\infty$-groupoid}
there is little difference between ``free generation'' and ``presentation'',
\index{presentation!of an infinity-groupoid@of an $\infty$-groupoid}%
\index{generation!of an infinity-groupoid@of an $\infty$-groupoid}%
since we can make two paths equal \emph{up to homotopy} by adding a new 2-di\-men\-sion\-al generator relating them (e.g.\ a path $\lloop\ct\lloop = \refl{\base}$ in $\base=\base$).
We do then, of course, have to worry about whether this new generator should satisfy its own ``axioms'', and so on, but in principle any ``presentation'' can be transformed into a ``free'' one by making axioms into constructors.
As we will see, by adding ``truncation constructors'' we can use higher inductive types to express classical notions such as group presentations as well.
Thirdly, even though a higher inductive type contains ``constructors'' which generate \emph{paths in} that type, it is still an inductive definition of a \emph{single} type.
In particular, as we will see, it is the higher inductive type itself which is given a universal property (expressed, as usual, by an induction principle), and \emph{not} its identity types.
The identity type of a higher inductive type retains the usual induction principle of any identity type (i.e.\ path induction), and does not acquire any new induction principle.
Thus, it may be nontrivial to identify the identity types of a higher inductive type in a concrete way, in contrast to how in \cref{cha:basics} we were able to give explicit descriptions of the behavior of identity types under all the traditional type forming operations.
For instance, are there any paths from $\base$ to $\base$ in $\Sn^1$ which are not simply composites of copies of $\lloop$ and its inverse?
Intuitively, it seems that the answer should be no (and it is), but proving this is not trivial.
Indeed, such questions bring us rapidly to problems such as calculating the homotopy groups of spheres, a long-standing problem in algebraic topology for which no simple formula is known.
Homotopy type theory brings a new and powerful viewpoint to bear on such questions, but it also requires type theory to become as complex as the answers to these questions.
\index{dimension!of path constructors}%
Fourthly, the ``dimension'' of the constructors (i.e.\ whether they output points, paths, paths between paths, etc.)\ does not have a direct connection to which dimensions the resulting type has nontrivial homotopy in.
As a simple example, if an inductive type $B$ has a constructor of type $A\to B$, then any paths and higher paths in $A$ result in paths and higher paths in $B$, even though the constructor is not a ``higher'' constructor at all.
The same thing happens with higher constructors too: having a constructor of type $A\to (\id[B]xy)$ means not only that points of $A$ yield paths from $x$ to $y$ in $B$, but that paths in $A$ yield paths between these paths, and so on.
As we will see, this possibility is responsible for much of the power of higher inductive types.
On the other hand, it is even possible for constructors \emph{without} higher types in their inputs to generate ``unexpected'' higher paths.
For instance, in the 2-dimensional sphere $\Sn^2$ generated by
\symlabel{s2a}
\index{type!2-sphere}%
\begin{itemize}
\item A point $\base:\Sn^2$, and
\item A 2-dimensional path $\surf:\refl{\base} = \refl{\base}$ in ${\base=\base}$,
\end{itemize}
there is a nontrivial \emph{3-dimensional path} from $\refl{\refl{\base}}$ to itself.
Topologists will recognize this path as an incarnation of the \emph{Hopf fibration}.
From a category-theoretic point of view, this is the same sort of phenomenon as the fact mentioned above that $\Sn^1$ contains not only $\lloop$ but also $\lloop\ct\lloop$ and so on: it's just that in a \emph{higher} groupoid, there are \emph{operations} which raise dimension.
Indeed, we saw many of these operations back in \cref{sec:equality}: the associativity and unit laws are not just properties, but operations, whose inputs are 1-paths and whose outputs are 2-paths.
\index{generation!of a type, inductive|)}%
% In US Trade format it wants a page break here but then it stretches the above itemize,
% so we give it some stretchable space to use if it wants to.
\vspace*{0pt plus 20ex}
\section{Induction principles and dependent paths}
\label{sec:dependent-paths}
When we describe a higher inductive type such as the circle as being generated by certain constructors, we have to explain what this means by giving rules analogous to those for the basic type constructors from \cref{cha:typetheory}.
The constructors themselves give the \emph{introduction} rules, but it requires a bit more thought to explain the \emph{elimination} rules, i.e.\ the induction and recursion principles.
In this book we do not attempt to give a general formulation of what constitutes a ``higher inductive definition'' and how to extract the elimination rule from such a definition --- indeed, this is a subtle question and the subject of current research.
Instead we will rely on some general informal discussion and numerous examples.
\index{type!circle}%
\index{recursion principle!for S1@for $\Sn^1$}%
The recursion principle is usually easy to describe: given any type equipped with the same structure with which the constructors equip the higher inductive type in question, there is a function which maps the constructors to that structure.
For instance, in the case of $\Sn^1$, the recursion principle says that given any type $B$ equipped with a point $b:B$ and a path $\ell:b=b$, there is a function $f:\Sn^1\to B$ such that $f(\base)=b$ and $\apfunc f (\lloop) = \ell$.
\index{computation rule!for S1@for $\Sn^1$}%
\index{equality!definitional}%
The latter two equalities are the \emph{computation rules}.
\index{computation rule!for higher inductive types|(}%
\index{computation rule!propositional|(}%
There is, however, a question of whether these computation rules are judgmental\index{judgmental equality} equalities or propositional equalities (paths).
For ordinary inductive types, we had no qualms about making them judgmental, although we saw in \cref{cha:induction} that making them propositional would still yield the same type up to equivalence.
In the ordinary case, one may argue that the computation rules are really \emph{definitional} equalities, in the intuitive sense described in the Introduction.
\index{equality!judgmental}%
For higher inductive types, this is less clear. %, and it is likewise less clear to what extent these equalities can be made judgmental in the known set-theoretic models.
Moreover, since the operation $\apfunc f$ is not really a fundamental part of the type theory, but something that we \emph{defined} using the induction principle of identity types (and which we might have defined in some other, equivalent, way), it seems inappropriate to refer to it explicitly in a \emph{judgmental} equality.
Judgmental equalities are part of the deductive system, which should not depend on particular choices of definitions that we may make \emph{within} that system.
There are also semantic and implementation issues to consider; see the Notes.
It does seem unproblematic to make the computational rules for the \emph{point} constructors of a higher inductive type judgmental.
In the example above, this means we have $f(\base)\jdeq b$, judgmentally.
This choice facilitates a computational view of higher inductive types.
Moreover, it also greatly simplifies our lives, since otherwise the second computation rule $\apfunc f (\lloop) = \ell$ would not even be well-typed as a propositional equality; we would have to compose one side or the other with the specified identification of $f(\base)$ with $b$.
(Such problems do arise eventually, of course, when we come to talk about paths of higher dimension, but that will not be of great concern to us here.
See also \cref{sec:hubs-spokes}.)
Thus, we take the computation rules for point constructors to be judgmental, and those for paths and higher paths to be propositional.%
\footnote{In particular, in the language of \cref{sec:types-vs-sets}, this means that our higher inductive types are a mix of \emph{rules} (specifying how we can introduce such types and their elements, their induction principle, and their computation rules for point constructors) and \emph{axioms} (the computation rules for path constructors, which assert that certain identity types are inhabited by otherwise unspecified terms).
We may hope that eventually, there will be a better type theory in which higher inductive types, like univalence, will be presented using only rules and no axioms.%
\indexfoot{axiom!versus rules}%
\indexfoot{rule!versus axioms}%
}
\begin{rmk}\label{rmk:defid}
Recall that for ordinary inductive types, we regard the computation rules for a recursively defined function as not merely judgmental equalities, but \emph{definitional} ones, and thus we may use the notation $\defeq$ for them.
For instance, the truncated predecessor\index{predecessor!function, truncated} function $p:\nat\to\nat$ is defined by $p(0)\defeq 0$ and $p(\suc(n))\defeq n$.
In the case of higher inductive types, this sort of notation is reasonable for the point constructors (e.g.\ $f(\base)\defeq b$), but for the path constructors it could be misleading, since equalities such as $\ap f \lloop = \ell$ are not judgmental.
Thus, we hybridize the notations, writing instead $\ap f \lloop \defid \ell$ for this sort of ``propositional equality by definition''.
\end{rmk}
\index{computation rule!for higher inductive types|)}%
\index{computation rule!propositional|)}%
\index{type!circle|(}%
\index{induction principle!for S1@for $\Sn^1$}%
Now, what about the induction principle (the dependent eliminator)?
Recall that for an ordinary inductive type $W$, to prove by induction that $\prd{x:W} P(x)$, we must specify, for each constructor of $W$, an operation on $P$ which acts on the ``fibers'' above that constructor in $W$.
For instance, if $W$ is the natural numbers \nat, then to prove by induction that $\prd{x:\nat} P(x)$, we must specify
\begin{itemize}
\item An element $b:P(0)$ in the fiber over the constructor $0:\nat$, and
\item For each $n:\nat$, a function $P(n) \to P(\suc(n))$.
\end{itemize}
The second can be viewed as a function ``$P\to P$'' lying \emph{over} the constructor $\suc:\nat\to\nat$, generalizing how $b:P(0)$ lies over the constructor $0:\nat$.
By analogy, therefore, to prove that $\prd{x:\Sn^1} P(x)$, we should specify
\begin{itemize}
\item An element $b:P(\base)$ in the fiber over the constructor $\base:\Sn^1$, and
\item A path from $b$ to $b$ ``lying over the constructor $\lloop:\base=\base$''.
\end{itemize}
Note that even though $\Sn^1$ contains paths other than $\lloop$ (such as $\refl{\base}$ and $\lloop\ct\lloop$), we only need to specify a path lying over the constructor \emph{itself}.
This expresses the intuition that $\Sn^1$ is ``freely generated'' by its constructors.
The question, however, is what it means to have a path ``lying over'' another path.
It definitely does \emph{not} mean simply a path $b=b$, since that would be a path in the fiber $P(\base)$ (topologically, a path lying over the \emph{constant} path at $\base$).
Actually, however, we have already answered this question in \cref{cha:basics}: in the discussion preceding \cref{lem:mapdep} we concluded that a path from $u:P(x)$ to $v:P(y)$ lying over $p:x=y$ can be represented by a path $\trans p u = v$ in the fiber $P(y)$.
Since we will have a lot of use for such \define{dependent paths}
\index{path!dependent}%
in this chapter, we introduce a special notation for them:
\begin{equation}
(\dpath P p u v) \defeq (\transfib{P} p u = v).\label{eq:dpath}
\end{equation}
\begin{rmk}
There are other possible ways to define dependent paths.
For instance, instead of $\trans p u = v$ we could consider $u = \trans{(\opp p)}{v}$.
We could also obtain it as a special case of a more general ``heterogeneous equality'',
\index{heterogeneous equality}%
\index{equality!heterogeneous}%
or with a direct definition as an inductive type family.
All these definitions result in equivalent types, so in that sense it doesn't much matter which we pick.
However, choosing $\trans p u = v$ as the definition makes it easiest to conclude other things about dependent paths, such as the fact that $\apdfunc{f}$ produces them, or that we can compute them in particular type families using the transport lemmas in \cref{sec:computational}.
\end{rmk}
With the notion of dependent paths in hand, we can now state more precisely the induction principle for $\Sn^1$: given $P:\Sn^1\to\type$ and
\begin{itemize}
\item an element $b:P(\base)$, and
\item a path $\ell : \dpath P \lloop b b$,
\end{itemize}
there is a function $f:\prd{x:\Sn^1} P(x)$ such that $f(\base)\jdeq b$ and $\apd f \lloop = \ell$.
As in the non-dependent case, we speak of defining $f$ by $f(\base)\defeq b$ and $\apd f \lloop \defid \ell$.
\begin{rmk}\label{rmk:varies-along}
When describing an application of this induction principle informally, we regard it as a splitting of the goal ``$P(x)$ for all $x:\Sn^1$'' into two cases, which we will sometimes introduce with phrases such as ``when $x$ is $\base$'' and ``when $x$ varies along $\lloop$'', respectively.
\index{vary along a path constructor}%
There is no specific mathematical meaning assigned to ``varying along a path'': it is just a convenient way to indicate the beginning of the corresponding section of a proof; see \cref{thm:S1-autohtpy} for an example.
\end{rmk}
Topologically, the induction principle for $\Sn^1$ can be visualized as shown in \cref{fig:topS1ind}.
Given a fibration over the circle (which in the picture is a torus), to define a section of this fibration is the same as to give a point $b$ in the fiber over $\base$ along with a path from $b$ to $b$ lying over $\lloop$.
The way we interpret this type-theoretically, using our definition of dependent paths, is shown in \cref{fig:ttS1ind}: the path from $b$ to $b$ over $\lloop$ is represented by a path from $\trans \lloop b$ to $b$ in the fiber over $\base$.
\begin{figure}
\centering
\begin{tikzpicture}
\draw (0,0) ellipse (3 and .5);
\draw (0,3) ellipse (3.5 and 1.5);
\begin{scope}[yshift=4]
\clip (-3,3) -- (-1.8,3) -- (-1.8,3.7) -- (1.8,3.7) -- (1.8,3) -- (3,3) -- (3,0) -- (-3,0) -- cycle;
\draw[clip] (0,3.5) ellipse (2.25 and 1);
\draw (0,2.5) ellipse (1.7 and .7);
\end{scope}
\node (P) at (4.5,3) {$P$};
\node (S1) at (4.5,0) {$\Sn^1$};
\draw[->>,thick] (P) -- (S1);
\node[fill,circle,inner sep=1pt,label={below right:$\base$}] at (0,-.5) {};
\node at (-2.6,.6) {$\lloop$};
\node[fill,circle,\OPTblue,inner sep=1pt] (b) at (0,2.3) {};
\node[\OPTblue] at (-.2,2.1) {$b$};
\begin{scope}
\draw[\OPTblue] (b) to[out=180,in=-150] (-2.7,3.5) to[out=30,in=180] (0,3.35);
\draw[\OPTblue,dotted] (0,3.35) to[out=0,in=175] (1.4,4.35);
\draw[\OPTblue] (1.4,4.35) to[out=-5,in=90] (2.5,3) to[out=-90,in=0,looseness=.8] (b);
\end{scope}
\node[\OPTblue] at (-2.2, 3.3) {$\ell$};
\end{tikzpicture}
\caption{The topological induction principle for $\Sn^1$}
\label{fig:topS1ind}
\end{figure}
\begin{figure}
\centering
\begin{tikzpicture}
\draw (0,0) ellipse (3 and .5);
\draw (0,3) ellipse (3.5 and 1.5);
\begin{scope}[yshift=4]
\clip (-3,3) -- (-1.8,3) -- (-1.8,3.7) -- (1.8,3.7) -- (1.8,3) -- (3,3) -- (3,0) -- (-3,0) -- cycle;
\draw[clip] (0,3.5) ellipse (2.25 and 1);
\draw (0,2.5) ellipse (1.7 and .7);
\end{scope}
\node (P) at (4.5,3) {$P$};
\node (S1) at (4.5,0) {$\Sn^1$};
\draw[->>,thick] (P) -- (S1);
\node[fill,circle,inner sep=1pt,label={below right:$\base$}] at (0,-.5) {};
\node at (-2.6,.6) {$\lloop$};
\node[fill,circle,\OPTblue,inner sep=1pt] (b) at (0,2.3) {};
\node[\OPTblue] at (-.3,2.3) {$b$};
\node[fill,circle,\OPTpurple,inner sep=1pt] (tb) at (0,1.8) {};
% \draw[\OPTpurple,dashed] (b) to[out=0,in=0,looseness=5] (0,4) to[out=180,in=180] (tb);
\draw[\OPTpurple,dashed] (b) arc (-90:90:2.9 and 0.85) arc (90:270:2.8 and 1.1);
\begin{scope}
\clip (b) -- ++(.1,0) -- (.1,1.8) -- ++(-.2,0) -- ++(0,-1) -- ++(3,2) -- ++(-3,0) -- (-.1,2.3) -- cycle;
\draw[\OPTred,dotted,thick] (.2,2.07) ellipse (.2 and .57);
\begin{scope}
% \draw[clip] (b) -- ++(.1,0) |- (tb) -- ++(-.2,0) -- ++(0,-1) -| ++(3,3) -| (b);
\clip (.2,0) rectangle (-2,3);
\draw[\OPTred,thick] (.2,2.07) ellipse (.2 and .57);
\end{scope}
\end{scope}
\node[\OPTred] at (1,1.2) {$\ell: \trans \lloop b=b$};
\end{tikzpicture}
\caption{The type-theoretic induction principle for $\Sn^1$}
\label{fig:ttS1ind}
\end{figure}
Of course, we expect to be able to prove the recursion principle from the induction principle, by taking $P$ to be a constant type family.
This is in fact the case, although deriving the non-dependent computation rule for $\lloop$ (which refers to $\apfunc f$) from the dependent one (which refers to $\apdfunc f$) is surprisingly a little tricky.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:S1rec}
\index{recursion principle!for S1@for $\Sn^1$}%
\index{computation rule!for S1@for $\Sn^1$}%
If $A$ is a type together with $a:A$ and $p:\id[A]aa$, then there is a
function $f:\Sn^1\to{}A$ with
\begin{align*}
f(\base)&\defeq a \\
\apfunc f(\lloop)&\defid p.
\end{align*}
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We would like to apply the induction principle of $\Sn^1$ to the constant type family, $(\lam{x} A): \Sn^1\to \UU$.
The required hypotheses for this are a point of $(\lam{x} A)(\base) \jdeq A$, which we have (namely $a:A$), and a dependent path in $\dpath {x \mapsto A}{\lloop} a a$, or equivalently $\transfib{x \mapsto A}{\lloop} a = a$.
This latter type is not the same as the type $\id[A]aa$ where $p$ lives, but it is equivalent to it, because by \cref{thm:trans-trivial} we have $\transconst{A}{\lloop}{a} : \transfib{x \mapsto A}{\lloop} a= a$.
Thus, given $a:A$ and $p:a=a$, we can consider the composite
\[\transconst{A}{\lloop}{a} \ct p:(\dpath {x \mapsto A}\lloop aa).\]
Applying the induction principle, we obtain $f:\Sn^1\to A$ such that
\begin{align}
f(\base) &\jdeq a \qquad\text{and}\label{eq:S1recindbase}\\
\apdfunc f(\lloop) &= \transconst{A}{\lloop}{a} \ct p.\label{eq:S1recindloop}
\end{align}
It remains to derive the equality $\apfunc f(\lloop)=p$.
However, by \cref{thm:apd-const}, we have
\[\apdfunc f(\lloop) = \transconst{A}{\lloop}{f(\base)} \ct \apfunc f(\lloop).\]
Combining this with~\eqref{eq:S1recindloop} and canceling the occurrences of $\transconstf$ (which are the same by~\eqref{eq:S1recindbase}), we obtain $\apfunc f(\lloop)=p$.
\end{proof}
% Similarly, in this case we speak of defining $f$ by $f(\base)\defeq a$ and $\ap f \lloop \defid p$.
We also have a corresponding uniqueness principle.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:uniqueness-for-functions-on-S1}
\index{uniqueness!principle, propositional!for functions on the circle}%
If $A$ is a type and $f,g:\Sn^1\to{}A$ are two maps together with two
equalities $p,q$:
\begin{align*}
p:f(\base)&=_Ag(\base),\\
q:\map{f}\lloop&=^{\lam{x} x=_Ax}_p\map{g}\lloop.
\end{align*}
Then for all $x:\Sn^1$ we have $f(x)=g(x)$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We apply the induction principle of $\Sn^1$ at the type family $P(x)\defeq(f(x)=g(x))$.
When $x$ is $\base$, $p$ is exactly what we need.
And when $x$ varies along $\lloop$, we need
\(p=^{\lam{x} f(x)=g(x)}_{\lloop} p,\)
which by \cref{thm:transport-path,thm:dpath-path} can be reduced to $q$.
\end{proof}
\index{universal!property!of S1@of $\Sn^1$}%
These two lemmas imply the expected universal property of the circle:
\begin{lem}\label{thm:S1ump}
For any type $A$ we have a natural equivalence
\[ (\Sn^1 \to A) \;\eqvsym\;
\sm{x:A} (x=x).
\]
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We have a canonical function $f:(\Sn^1 \to A) \to \sm{x:A} (x=x)$ defined by $f(g) \defeq (g(\base),\ap g \lloop)$.
The induction principle shows that the fibers of $f$ are inhabited, while the uniqueness principle shows that they are mere propositions.
Hence they are contractible, so $f$ is an equivalence.
\end{proof}
\index{type!circle|)}%
As in \cref{sec:htpy-inductive}, we can show that the conclusion of \cref{thm:S1ump} is equivalent to having an induction principle with propositional computation rules.
Other higher inductive types also satisfy lemmas analogous to \cref{thm:S1rec,thm:S1ump}; we will generally leave their proofs to the reader.
We now proceed to consider many examples.
\section{The interval}
\label{sec:interval}
\index{type!interval|(defstyle}%
\indexsee{interval!type}{type, interval}%
The \define{interval}, which we denote $\interval$, is perhaps an even simpler higher inductive type than the circle.
It is generated by:
\begin{itemize}
\item a point $\izero:\interval$,
\item a point $\ione:\interval$, and
\item a path $\seg : \id[\interval]\izero\ione$.
\end{itemize}
\index{recursion principle!for interval type}%
The recursion principle for the interval says that given a type $B$ along with
\begin{itemize}
\item a point $b_0:B$,
\item a point $b_1:B$, and
\item a path $s:b_0=b_1$,
\end{itemize}
there is a function $f:\interval\to B$ such that $f(\izero)\jdeq b_0$, $f(\ione)\jdeq b_1$, and $\ap f \seg = s$.
\index{induction principle!for interval type}%
The induction principle says that given $P:\interval\to\type$ along with
\begin{itemize}
\item a point $b_0:P(\izero)$,
\item a point $b_1:P(\ione)$, and
\item a path $s:\dpath{P}{\seg}{b_0}{b_1}$,
\end{itemize}
there is a function $f:\prd{x:\interval} P(x)$ such that $f(\izero)\jdeq b_0$, $f(\ione)\jdeq b_1$, and $\apd f \seg = s$.
Regarded purely up to homotopy, the interval is not really interesting:
\begin{lem}\label{thm:contr-interval}
The type $\interval$ is contractible.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We prove that for all $x:\interval$ we have $x=_\interval\ione$. In other words we want a
function $f$ of type $\prd{x:\interval}(x=_\interval\ione)$. We begin to define $f$ in the following way:
\begin{alignat*}{2}
f(\izero)&\defeq \seg &:\izero&=_\interval\ione,\\
f(\ione)&\defeq \refl\ione &:\ione &=_\interval\ione.
\end{alignat*}
It remains to define $\apd{f}\seg$, which must have type $\seg =_\seg^{\lam{x} x=_\interval\ione}\refl \ione$.
By definition this type is $\trans\seg\seg=_{\ione=_\interval\ione}\refl\ione$, which in turn is equivalent to $\rev\seg\ct\seg=\refl\ione$.
But there is a canonical element of that type, namely the proof that path inverses are in fact inverses.
\end{proof}
However, type-theoretically the interval does still have some interesting features, just like the topological interval in classical homotopy theory.
For instance, it enables us to give an easy proof of function extensionality.
(Of course, as in \cref{sec:univalence-implies-funext}, for the duration of the following proof we suspend our overall assumption of the function extensionality axiom.)
\begin{lem}\label{thm:interval-funext}
\index{function extensionality!proof from interval type}%
If $f,g:A\to{}B$ are two functions such that $f(x)=g(x)$ for every $x:A$, then
$f=g$ in the type $A\to{}B$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Let's call the proof we have $p:\prd{x:A}(f(x)=g(x))$. For all $x:A$ we define
a function $\widetilde{p}_x:\interval\to{}B$ by
\begin{align*}
\widetilde{p}_x(\izero) &\defeq f(x), \\
\widetilde{p}_x(\ione) &\defeq g(x), \\
\map{\widetilde{p}_x}\seg &\defid p(x).
\end{align*}
We now define $q:\interval\to(A\to{}B)$ by
\[q(i)\defeq(\lam{x} \widetilde{p}_x(i))\]
Then $q(\izero)$ is the function $\lam{x} \widetilde{p}_x(\izero)$, which is equal to $f$ because $\widetilde{p}_x(\izero)$ is defined by $f(x)$.
Similarly, we have $q(\ione)=g$, and hence
\[\map{q}\seg:f=_{(A\to{}B)}g \qedhere\]
\end{proof}
In \cref{ex:funext-from-interval} we ask the reader to complete the proof of the full function extensionality axiom from \cref{thm:interval-funext}.
\index{type!interval|)}%
\section{Circles and spheres}
\label{sec:circle}
\index{type!circle|(}%
We have already discussed the circle $\Sn^1$ as the higher inductive type generated by
\begin{itemize}
\item A point $\base:\Sn^1$, and
\item A path $\lloop : {\id[\Sn^1]\base\base}$.
\end{itemize}
\index{induction principle!for S1@for $\Sn^1$}%
Its induction principle says that given $P:\Sn^1\to\type$ along with $b:P(\base)$ and $\ell :\dpath P \lloop b b$, we have $f:\prd{x:\Sn^1} P(x)$ with $f(\base)\jdeq b$ and $\apd f \lloop = \ell$.
Its non-dependent recursion principle says that given $B$ with $b:B$ and $\ell:b=b$, we have $f:\Sn^1\to B$ with $f(\base)\jdeq b$ and $\ap f \lloop = \ell$.
We observe that the circle is nontrivial.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:loop-nontrivial}
$\lloop\neq\refl{\base}$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Suppose that $\lloop=\refl{\base}$.
Then since for any type $A$ with $x:A$ and $p:x=x$, there is a function $f:\Sn^1\to A$ defined by $f(\base)\defeq x$ and $\ap f \lloop \defid p$, we have
\[p = f(\lloop) = f(\refl{\base}) = \refl{x}.\]
But this implies that every type is a set, which as we have seen is not the case (see \cref{thm:type-is-not-a-set}).
\end{proof}
The circle also has the following interesting property, which is useful as a source of counterexamples.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:S1-autohtpy}
There exists an element of $\prd{x:\Sn^1} (x=x)$ which is not equal to $x\mapsto \refl{x}$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We define $f:\prd{x:\Sn^1} (x=x)$ by $\Sn^1$-induction.
When $x$ is $\base$, we let $f(\base)\defeq \lloop$.
Now when $x$ varies along $\lloop$ (see \cref{rmk:varies-along}), we must show that $\transfib{x\mapsto x=x}{\lloop}{\lloop} = \lloop$.
However, in \cref{sec:compute-paths} we observed that $\transfib{x\mapsto x=x}{p}{q} = \opp{p} \ct q \ct p$, so what we have to show is that $\opp{\lloop} \ct \lloop \ct \lloop = \lloop$.
But this is clear by canceling an inverse.
To show that $f\neq (x\mapsto \refl{x})$, it suffices to show that $f(\base) \neq \refl{\base}$.
But $f(\base)=\lloop$, so this is just the previous lemma.
\end{proof}
For instance, this enables us to extend \cref{thm:type-is-not-a-set} by showing that any universe which contains the circle cannot be a 1-type.
\begin{cor}
If the type $\Sn^1$ belongs to some universe \type, then \type is not a 1-type.
\end{cor}
\begin{proof}
The type $\Sn^1=\Sn^1$ in \type is, by univalence, equivalent to the type $\eqv{\Sn^1}{\Sn^1}$ of auto\-equivalences of $\Sn^1$, so it suffices to show that $\eqv{\Sn^1}{\Sn^1}$ is not a set.
\index{automorphism!of S1@of $\Sn^1$}%
For this, it suffices to show that its equality type $\id[(\eqv{\Sn^1}{\Sn^1})]{\idfunc[\Sn^1]}{\idfunc[\Sn^1]}$ is not a mere proposition.
Since being an equivalence is a mere proposition, this type is equivalent to $\id[(\Sn^1\to\Sn^1)]{\idfunc[\Sn^1]}{\idfunc[\Sn^1]}$.
But by function extensionality, this is equivalent to $\prd{x:\Sn^1} (x=x)$, which as we have seen in \cref{thm:S1-autohtpy} contains two unequal elements.
\end{proof}
\index{type!circle|)}%
\index{type!2-sphere|(}%
\indexsee{sphere type}{type, sphere}%
We have also mentioned that the 2-sphere $\Sn^2$ should be the higher inductive type generated by
\symlabel{s2b}
\begin{itemize}
\item A point $\base:\Sn^2$, and
\item A 2-dimensional path $\surf:\refl{\base} = \refl{\base}$ in ${\base=\base}$.
\end{itemize}
\index{recursion principle!for S2@for $\Sn^2$}%
The recursion principle for $\Sn^2$ is not hard: it says that given $B$ with $b:B$ and $s:\refl b = \refl b$, we have $f:\Sn^2\to B$ with $f(\base)\jdeq b$ and $\aptwo f \surf = s$.
Here by ``$\aptwo f \surf$'' we mean an extension of the functorial action of $f$ to two-dimensional paths, which can be stated precisely as follows.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:ap2}
Given $f:A\to B$ and $x,y:A$ and $p,q:x=y$, and $r:p=q$, we have a path $\aptwo f r : \ap f p = \ap f q$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
By path induction, we may assume $p\jdeq q$ and $r$ is reflexivity.
But then we may define $\aptwo f {\refl p} \defeq \refl{\ap f p}$.
\end{proof}
In order to state the general induction principle, we need a version of this lemma for dependent functions, which in turn requires a notion of dependent two-dimensional paths.
As before, there are many ways to define such a thing; one is by way of a two-dimensional version of transport.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:transport2}
Given $P:A\to\type$ and $x,y:A$ and $p,q:x=y$ and $r:p=q$, for any $u:P(x)$ we have $\transtwo r u : \trans p u = \trans q u$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
By path induction.
\end{proof}
Now suppose given $x,y:A$ and $p,q:x=y$ and $r:p=q$ and also points $u:P(x)$ and $v:P(y)$ and dependent paths $h:\dpath P p u v$ and $k:\dpath P q u v$.
By our definition of dependent paths, this means $h:\trans p u = v$ and $k:\trans q u = v$.
Thus, it is reasonable to define the type of dependent 2-paths over $r$ to be
\[ (\dpath P r h k )\defeq (h = \transtwo r u \ct k). \]
We can now state the dependent version of \cref{thm:ap2}.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:apd2}
Given $P:A\to\type$ and $x,y:A$ and $p,q:x=y$ and $r:p=q$ and a function $f:\prd{x:A} P(x)$, we have
$\apdtwo f r : \dpath P r {\apd f p}{\apd f q}$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Path induction.
\end{proof}
\index{induction principle!for S2@for $\Sn^2$}%
Now we can state the induction principle for $\Sn^2$: suppose we are given $P:\Sn^2\to\type$ with $b:P(\base)$ and $s:\dpath Q \surf {\refl b}{\refl b}$ where $Q\defeq\lam{p} \dpath P p b b$. Then there is a function $f:\prd{x:\Sn^2} P(x)$ such that $f(\base)\jdeq b$ and $\apdtwo f \surf = s$.
\index{type!2-sphere|)}%
Of course, this explicit approach gets more and more complicated as we go up in dimension.
Thus, if we want to define $n$-spheres for all $n$, we need some more systematic idea.
One approach is to work with $n$-dimensional loops\index{loop!n-@$n$-} directly, rather than general $n$-dimensional paths.\index{path!n-@$n$-}
\index{type!pointed}%
Recall from \cref{sec:equality} the definitions of \emph{pointed types} $\type_*$, and the $n$-fold loop space\index{loop space!iterated} $\Omega^n : \type_* \to \type_*$
(\cref{def:pointedtype,def:loopspace}). Now we can define the
$n$-sphere $\Sn^n$ to be the higher inductive type generated by
\index{type!n-sphere@$n$-sphere}%
\begin{itemize}
\item A point $\base:\Sn^n$, and
\item An $n$-loop $\lloop_n : \Omega^n(\Sn^n,\base)$.
\end{itemize}
In order to write down the induction principle for this presentation, we would need to define a notion of ``dependent $n$-loop\indexdef{loop!dependent n-@dependent $n$-}'', along with the action of dependent functions on $n$-loops.
We leave this to the reader (see \cref{ex:nspheres}); in the next section we will discuss a different way to define the spheres that is sometimes more tractable.
\section{Suspensions}
\label{sec:suspension}
\indexsee{type!suspension of}{suspension}%
\index{suspension|(defstyle}%
The \define{suspension} of a type $A$ is the universal way of making the points of $A$ into paths (and hence the paths in $A$ into 2-paths, and so on).
It is a type $\susp A$ defined by the following generators:\footnote{There is an unfortunate clash of notation with dependent pair types, which of course are also written with a $\Sigma$.
However, context usually disambiguates.}
\begin{itemize}
\item a point $\north:\susp A$,
\item a point $\south:\susp A$, and
\item a function $\merid:A \to (\id[\susp A]\north\south)$.
\end{itemize}
The names are intended to suggest a ``globe'' of sorts, with a north pole, a south pole, and an $A$'s worth of meridians
\indexdef{pole}%
\indexdef{meridian}%
from one to the other.
Indeed, as we will see, if $A=\Sn^1$, then its suspension is equivalent to the surface of an ordinary sphere, $\Sn^2$.
\index{recursion principle!for suspension}%
The recursion principle for $\susp A$ says that given a type $B$ together with
\begin{itemize}
\item points $n,s:B$ and
\item a function $m:A \to (n=s)$,
\end{itemize}
we have a function $f:\susp A \to B$ such that $f(\north)\jdeq n$ and $f(\south)\jdeq s$, and for all $a:A$ we have $\ap f {\merid(a)} = m(a)$.
\index{induction principle!for suspension}%
Similarly, the induction principle says that given $P:\susp A \to \type$ together with
\begin{itemize}
\item a point $n:P(\north)$,
\item a point $s:P(\south)$, and
\item for each $a:A$, a path $m(a):\dpath P{\merid(a)}ns$,
\end{itemize}
there exists a function $f:\prd{x:\susp A} P(x)$ such that $f(\north)\jdeq n$ and $f(\south)\jdeq s$ and for each $a:A$ we have $\apd f {\merid(a)} = m(a)$.
Our first observation about suspension is that it gives another way to define the circle.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:suspbool}
\index{type!circle}%
$\eqv{\susp\bool}{\Sn^1}$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Define $f:\susp\bool\to\Sn^1$ by recursion such that $f(\north)\defeq \base$ and $f(\south)\defeq\base$, while $\ap f{\merid(\bfalse)}\defid\lloop$ but $\ap f{\merid(\btrue)} \defid \refl{\base}$.
Define $g:\Sn^1\to\susp\bool$ by recursion such that $g(\base)\defeq \north$ and $\ap g \lloop \defid \merid(\bfalse) \ct \opp{\merid(\btrue)}$.
We now show that $f$ and $g$ are quasi-inverses.
First we show by induction that $g(f(x))=x$ for all $x:\susp \bool$.
If $x\jdeq\north$, then $g(f(\north)) \jdeq g(\base)\jdeq \north$, so we have $\refl{\north} : g(f(\north))=\north$.
If $x\jdeq\south$, then $g(f(\south)) \jdeq g(\base)\jdeq \north$, and we choose the equality $\merid(\btrue) : g(f(\south)) = \south$.
It remains to show that for any $y:\bool$, these equalities are preserved as $x$ varies along $\merid(y)$, which is to say that when $\refl{\north}$ is transported along $\merid(y)$ it yields $\merid(\btrue)$.
By transport in path spaces and pulled back fibrations, this means we are to show that
\[ \opp{\ap g {\ap f {\merid(y)}}} \ct \refl{\north} \ct \merid(y) = \merid(\btrue). \]
Of course, we may cancel $\refl{\north}$.
Now by \bool-induction, we may assume either $y\jdeq \bfalse$ or $y\jdeq \btrue$.
If $y\jdeq \bfalse$, then we have
\begin{align*}
\opp{\ap g {\ap f {\merid(\bfalse)}}} \ct \merid(\bfalse)
&= \opp{\ap g {\lloop}} \ct \merid(\bfalse)\\
&= \opp{(\merid(\bfalse) \ct \opp{\merid(\btrue)})} \ct \merid(\bfalse)\\
&= \merid(\btrue) \ct \opp{\merid(\bfalse)} \ct \merid(\bfalse)\\
&= \merid(\btrue)
\end{align*}
while if $y\jdeq \btrue$, then we have
\begin{align*}
\opp{\ap g {\ap f {\merid(\btrue)}}} \ct \merid(\btrue)
&= \opp{\ap g {\refl{\base}}} \ct \merid(\btrue)\\
&= \opp{\refl{\north}} \ct \merid(\btrue)\\
&= \merid(\btrue).
\end{align*}
Thus, for all $x:\susp \bool$, we have $g(f(x))=x$.
Now we show by induction that $f(g(x))=x$ for all $x:\Sn^1$.
If $x\jdeq \base$, then $f(g(\base))\jdeq f(\north)\jdeq\base$, so we have $\refl{\base} : f(g(\base))=\base$.
It remains to show that this equality is preserved as $x$ varies along $\lloop$, which is to say that it is transported along $\lloop$ to itself.
Again, by transport in path spaces and pulled back fibrations, this means to show that
\[ \opp{\ap f {\ap g {\lloop}}} \ct \refl{\base} \ct \lloop = \refl{\base}.\]
However, we have
\begin{align*}
\ap f {\ap g {\lloop}} &= \ap f {\merid(\bfalse) \ct \opp{\merid(\btrue)}}\\
&= \ap f {\merid(\bfalse)} \ct \opp{\ap f {\merid(\btrue)}}\\
&= \lloop \ct \refl{\base}
\end{align*}
so this follows easily.
\end{proof}
Topologically, the two-point space \bool is also known as the \emph{0-dimensional sphere}, $\Sn^0$.
(For instance, it is the space of points at distance $1$ from the origin in $\mathbb{R}^1$, just as the topological 1-sphere is the space of points at distance $1$ from the origin in $\mathbb{R}^2$.)
Thus, \cref{thm:suspbool} can be phrased suggestively as $\eqv{\susp\Sn^0}{\Sn^1}$.
\index{type!n-sphere@$n$-sphere|defstyle}%
\indexsee{n-sphere@$n$-sphere}{type, $n$-sphere}%
In fact, this pattern continues: we can define all the spheres inductively by
\begin{equation}\label{eq:Snsusp}
\Sn^0 \defeq \bool
\qquad\text{and}\qquad
\Sn^{n+1} \defeq \susp \Sn^n.
\end{equation}
We can even start one dimension lower by defining $\Sn^{-1}\defeq \emptyt$, and observe that $\eqv{\susp\emptyt}{\bool}$.
To prove carefully that this agrees with the definition of $\Sn^n$ from the previous section would require making the latter more explicit.
However, we can show that the recursive definition has the same universal property that we would expect the other one to have.
If $(A,a_0)$ and $(B,b_0)$ are pointed types (with basepoints often left implicit), let $\Map_*(A,B)$ denote the type of based maps:
\index{based map}
\symlabel{based-maps}
\[ \Map_*(A,B) \defeq \sm{f:A\to B} (f(a_0)=b_0). \]
Note that any type $A$ gives rise to a pointed type $A_+ \defeq A+\unit$ with basepoint $\inr(\ttt)$; this is called \emph{adjoining a disjoint basepoint}.
\indexdef{basepoint!adjoining a disjoint}%
\index{disjoint!basepoint}%
\index{adjoining a disjoint basepoint}%
\begin{lem}
For a type $A$ and a pointed type $(B,b_0)$, we have
\[ \eqv{\Map_*(A_+,B)}{(A\to B)} \]
\end{lem}
Note that on the right we have the ordinary type of \emph{unbased} functions from $A$ to $B$.
\begin{proof}
From left to right, given $f:A_+ \to B$ with $p:f(\inr(\ttt)) = b_0$, we have $f\circ \inl : A \to B$.
And from right to left, given $g:A\to B$ we define $g':A_+ \to B$ by $g'(\inl(a))\defeq g(a)$ and $g'(\inr(u)) \defeq b_0$.
We leave it to the reader to show that these are quasi-inverse operations.
\end{proof}
In particular, note that $\eqv{\bool}{\unit_+}$.
Thus, for any pointed type $B$ we have
\[{\Map_*(\bool,B)} \eqvsym {(\unit \to B)}\eqvsym B.\]
%
Now recall that the loop space\index{loop space} operation $\Omega$ acts on pointed types, with definition $\Omega(A,a_0) \defeq (\id[A]{a_0}{a_0},\refl{a_0})$.
We can also make the suspension $\susp$ act on pointed types, by $\susp(A,a_0)\defeq (\susp A,\north)$.
\begin{lem}\label{lem:susp-loop-adj}
\index{universal!property!of suspension}%
For pointed types $(A,a_0)$ and $(B,b_0)$ we have
\[ \eqv{\Map_*(\susp A, B)}{\Map_*(A,\Omega B)}.\]
\end{lem}
\addtocounter{thm}{1} % Because we removed a numbered equation in commit 8f54d16
\begin{proof}
We first observe the following chain of equivalences:
\begin{align*}
\Map_*(\susp A, B) & \defeq \sm{f:\susp A\to B} (f(\north)=b_0) \\
& \eqvsym \sm{f:\sm{b_n : B}{b_s : B} (A \to (b_n = b_s))} (\fst(f)=b_0) \\
& \eqvsym \sm{b_n : B}{b_s : B} \big(A \to (b_n = b_s)\big) \times (b_n=b_0) \\
& \eqvsym \sm{p : \sm{b_n : B} (b_n=b_0)}{b_s : B} (A \to (\fst(p) = b_s)) \\
& \eqvsym \sm{b_s : B} (A \to (b_0 = b_s))
\end{align*}
The first equivalence is by the universal property of suspensions, which says that
\[ \Parens{\susp A \to B} \eqvsym \Parens{\sm{b_n : B} \sm{b_s : B} (A \to (b_n = b_s)) } \]
with the function from right to left given by the recursor (see \cref{ex:susp-lump}).
The second and third equivalences are by \cref{ex:sigma-assoc}, along with a reordering of components.
Finally, the last equivalence follows from \cref{thm:omit-contr}, since by \cref{thm:contr-paths}, $\sm{b_n : B} (b_n=b_0)$ is contractible with center $(b_0, \refl{b_0})$.
The proof is now completed by the following chain of equivalences:
\begin{align*}
\sm{b_s : B} (A \to (b_0 = b_s))
&\eqvsym \sm{b_s : B}{g:A \to (b_0 = b_s)}{q:b_0 = b_s} (g(a_0) = q)\\
&\eqvsym \sm{r : \sm{b_s : B}(b_0 = b_s)}{g:A \to (b_0 = \proj1(r))} (g(a_0) = \proj2(r))\\
&\eqvsym \sm{g:A \to (b_0 = b_0)} (g(a_0) = \refl{b_0})\\
&\jdeq \Map_*(A,\Omega B).
\end{align*}
Similar to before, the first and last equivalences are by \cref{thm:omit-contr,thm:contr-paths}, and the second is by \cref{ex:sigma-assoc} and reordering of components.
\end{proof}
\index{type!n-sphere@$n$-sphere|defstyle}%
In particular, for the spheres defined as in~\eqref{eq:Snsusp} we have
\index{universal!property!of Sn@of $\Sn^n$}%
\[ \Map_*(\Sn^n,B) \eqvsym \Map_*(\Sn^{n-1}, \Omega B) \eqvsym \cdots \eqvsym \Map_*(\bool,\Omega^n B) \eqvsym \Omega^n B. \]
Thus, these spheres $\Sn^n$ have the universal property that we would expect from the spheres defined directly in terms of $n$-fold loop spaces\index{loop space!iterated} as in \cref{sec:circle}.
\index{suspension|)}%
\section{Cell complexes}
\label{sec:cell-complexes}
\index{cell complex|(defstyle}%
\index{CW complex|(defstyle}%
In classical topology, a \emph{cell complex} is a space obtained by successively attaching discs along their boundaries.
It is called a \emph{CW complex} if the boundary of an $n$-dimensional disc\index{disc} is constrained to lie in the discs of dimension strictly less than $n$ (the $(n-1)$-skeleton).\index{skeleton!of a CW-complex}
Any finite CW complex can be presented as a higher inductive type, by turning $n$-dimensional discs into $n$-dimensional paths and partitioning the image of the attaching\index{attaching map} map into a source\index{source!of a path constructor} and a target\index{target!of a path constructor}, with each written as a composite of lower dimensional paths.
Our explicit definitions of $\Sn^1$ and $\Sn^2$ in \cref{sec:circle} had this form.
\index{torus}%
Another example is the torus $T^2$, which is generated by:
\begin{itemize}
\item a point $b:T^2$,
\item a path $p:b=b$,
\item another path $q:b=b$, and
\item a 2-path $t: p\ct q = q \ct p$.
\end{itemize}
Perhaps the easiest way to see that this is a torus is to start with a rectangle, having four corners $a,b,c,d$, four edges $p,q,r,s$, and an interior which is manifestly a 2-path $t$ from $p\ct q$ to $r\ct s$:
\begin{equation*}
\xymatrix{
a\ar@{=}[r]^p\ar@{=}[d]_r \ar@{}[dr]|{\Downarrow t} &
b\ar@{=}[d]^q\\
c\ar@{=}[r]_s &
d
}
\end{equation*}
Now identify the edge $r$ with $q$ and the edge $s$ with $p$, resulting in also identifying all four corners.
Topologically, this identification can be seen to produce a torus.
\index{induction principle!for torus}%
\index{torus!induction principle for}%
The induction principle for the torus is the trickiest of any we've written out so far.
Given $P:T^2\to\type$, for a section $\prd{x:T^2} P(x)$ we require
\begin{itemize}
\item a point $b':P(b)$,
\item a path $p' : \dpath P p {b'} {b'}$,
\item a path $q' : \dpath P q {b'} {b'}$, and
\item a 2-path $t'$ between the ``composites'' $p'\ct q'$ and $q'\ct p'$, lying over $t$.
\end{itemize}
In order to make sense of this last datum, we need a composition operation for dependent paths, but this is not hard to define.
Then the induction principle gives a function $f:\prd{x:T^2} P(x)$ such that $f(b)\jdeq b'$ and $\apd f {p} = p'$ and $\apd f {q} = q'$ and something like ``$\apdtwo f t = t'$''.
However, this is not well-typed as it stands, firstly because the equalities $\apd f {p} = p'$ and $\apd f {q} = q'$ are not judgmental, and secondly because $\apdfunc f$ only preserves path concatenation up to homotopy.
We leave the details to the reader (see \cref{ex:torus}).
Of course, another definition of the torus is $T^2 \defeq \Sn^1 \times \Sn^1$ (in \cref{ex:torus-s1-times-s1} we ask the reader to verify the equivalence of the two).
\index{Klein bottle}%
\index{projective plane}%
The cell-complex definition, however, generalizes easily to other spaces without such descriptions, such as the Klein bottle, the projective plane, etc.
But it does get increasingly difficult to write down the induction principles, requiring us to define notions of dependent $n$-paths and of $\apdfunc{}$ acting on $n$-paths.
Fortunately, once we have the spheres in hand, there is a way around this.
\section{Hubs and spokes}
\label{sec:hubs-spokes}
\indexsee{spoke}{hub and spoke}%
\index{hub and spoke|(defstyle}%
In topology, one usually speaks of building CW complexes by attaching $n$-dimensional discs along their $(n-1)$-dimensional boundary spheres.
\index{attaching map}%
However, another way to express this is by gluing in the \emph{cone}\index{cone!of a sphere} on an $(n-1)$-dimensional sphere.
That is, we regard a disc\index{disc} as consisting of a cone point (or ``hub''), with meridians
\index{meridian}%
(or ``spokes'') connecting that point to every point on the boundary, continuously, as shown in \cref{fig:hub-and-spokes}.
\begin{figure}
\centering
\begin{tikzpicture}
\draw (0,0) circle (2cm);
\foreach \x in {0,20,...,350}
\draw[\OPTblue] (0,0) -- (\x:2cm);
\node[\OPTblue,circle,fill,inner sep=2pt] (hub) at (0,0) {};
\end{tikzpicture}
\caption{A 2-disc made out of a hub and spokes}
\label{fig:hub-and-spokes}
\end{figure}
We can use this idea to express higher inductive types containing $n$-dimensional path con\-struc\-tors for $n>1$ in terms of ones containing only 1-di\-men\-sion\-al path con\-struc\-tors.
The point is that we can obtain an $n$-dimensional path as a continuous family of 1-dimensional paths parametrized by an $(n-1)$-di\-men\-sion\-al object.
The simplest $(n-1)$-dimensional object to use is the $(n-1)$-sphere, although in some cases a different one may be preferable.
(Recall that we were able to define the spheres in \cref{sec:suspension} inductively using suspensions, which involve only 1-dimensional path constructors.
Indeed, suspension can also be regarded as an instance of this idea, since it involves a family of 1-dimensional paths parametrized by the type being suspended.)
\index{torus}
For instance, the torus $T^2$ from the previous section could be defined instead to be generated by:
\begin{itemize}
\item a point $b:T^2$,
\item a path $p:b=b$,
\item another path $q:b=b$,
\item a point $h:T^2$, and
\item for each $x:\Sn^1$, a path $s(x) : f(x)=h$, where $f:\Sn^1\to T^2$ is defined by $f(\base)\defeq b$ and $\ap f \lloop \defid p \ct q \ct \opp p \ct \opp q$.
\end{itemize}
The induction principle for this version of the torus says that given $P:T^2\to\type$, for a section $\prd{x:T^2} P(x)$ we require
\begin{itemize}
\item a point $b':P(b)$,
\item a path $p' : \dpath P p {b'} {b'}$,
\item a path $q' : \dpath P q {b'} {b'}$,
\item a point $h':P(h)$, and
\item for each $x:\Sn^1$, a path $\dpath {P}{s(x)}{g(x)}{h'}$, where $g:\prd{x:\Sn^1} P(f(x))$ is defined by $g(\base)\defeq b'$ and $\apd g \lloop \defid t(p' \ct q' \ct \opp{(p')} \ct \opp{(q')})$.
In the latter, $\ct$ denotes concatenation of dependent paths, and the definition of $t:\eqv{(\dpath{P}{\ap f \lloop}{b'}{b'})}{(\dpath{P\circ f}{\lloop}{b'}{b'})}$ is left to the reader.
\end{itemize}
Note that there is no need for dependent 2-paths or $\apdtwofunc{}$.
We leave it to the reader to write out the computation rules.
\begin{rmk}\label{rmk:spokes-no-hub}
One might question the need for introducing the hub point $h$; why couldn't we instead simply add paths continuously relating the boundary of the disc to a point \emph{on} that boundary, as shown in \cref{fig:spokes-no-hub}?
However, this does not work without further modification.
For if, given some $f:\Sn^1 \to X$, we give a path constructor connecting each $f(x)$ to $f(\base)$, then what we end up with is more like the picture in \cref{fig:spokes-no-hub-ii} of a cone whose vertex is twisted around and glued to some point on its base.
The problem is that the specified path from $f(\base)$ to itself may not be reflexivity.
We could remedy the problem by adding a 2-dimensional path constructor to ensure this, but using a separate hub avoids the need for any path constructors of dimension above~$1$.
\end{rmk}
\begin{figure}
\centering
\begin{minipage}{2in}
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzpicture}
\draw (0,0) circle (2cm);
\clip (0,0) circle (2cm);
\foreach \x in {0,15,...,165}
\draw[\OPTblue] (0,-2cm) -- (\x:4cm);
\end{tikzpicture}
\end{center}
\caption{Hubless spokes}
\label{fig:spokes-no-hub}
\end{minipage}
\qquad
\begin{minipage}{2in}
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzpicture}[xscale=1.3]
\draw (0,0) arc (-90:90:.7cm and 2cm) ;
\draw[dashed] (0,4cm) arc (90:270:.7cm and 2cm) ;
\draw[\OPTblue] (0,0) to[out=90,in=0] (-1,1) to[out=180,in=180] (0,0);
\draw[\OPTblue] (0,4cm) to[out=180,in=180,looseness=2] (0,0);
\path (0,0) arc (-90:-60:.7cm and 2cm) node (a) {};
\draw[\OPTblue] (a.center) to[out=120,in=10] (-1.2,1.2) to[out=190,in=180] (0,0);
\path (0,0) arc (-90:-30:.7cm and 2cm) node (b) {};
\draw[\OPTblue] (b.center) to[out=150,in=20] (-1.4,1.4) to[out=200,in=180] (0,0);
\path (0,0) arc (-90:0:.7cm and 2cm) node (c) {};
\draw[\OPTblue] (c.center) to[out=180,in=30] (-1.5,1.5) to[out=210,in=180] (0,0);
\path (0,0) arc (-90:30:.7cm and 2cm) node (d) {};
\draw[\OPTblue] (d.center) to[out=190,in=50] (-1.7,1.7) to[out=230,in=180] (0,0);
\path (0,0) arc (-90:60:.7cm and 2cm) node (e) {};
\draw[\OPTblue] (e.center) to[out=200,in=70] (-2,2) to[out=250,in=180] (0,0);
\clip (0,0) to[out=90,in=0] (-1,1) to[out=180,in=180] (0,0);
\draw (0,4cm) arc (90:270:.7cm and 2cm) ;
\end{tikzpicture}
\end{center}
\caption{Hubless spokes, II}
\label{fig:spokes-no-hub-ii}
\end{minipage}
\end{figure}
\begin{rmk}
\index{computation rule!propositional}%
Note also that this ``translation'' of higher paths into 1-paths does not preserve judgmental computation rules for these paths, though it does preserve propositional ones.
\end{rmk}
\index{cell complex|)}%
\index{CW complex|)}%
\index{hub and spoke|)}%
\section{Pushouts}
\label{sec:colimits}
\index{type!limit}%
\index{type!colimit}%
\index{limit!of types}%
\index{colimit!of types}%
From a category-theoretic point of view, one of the important aspects of any foundational system is the ability to construct limits and colimits.
In set-theoretic foundations, these are limits and colimits of sets, whereas in our case they are limits and colimits of \emph{types}.
We have seen in \cref{sec:universal-properties} that cartesian product types have the correct universal property of a categorical product of types, and in \cref{ex:coprod-ump} that coproduct types likewise have their expected universal property.
As remarked in \cref{sec:universal-properties}, more general limits can be constructed using identity types and $\Sigma$-types, e.g.\ the pullback\index{pullback} of $f:A\to C$ and $g:B\to C$ is $\sm{a:A}{b:B} (f(a)=g(b))$ (see \cref{ex:pullback}).
However, more general \emph{colimits} require identifying elements coming from different types, for which higher inductives are well-adapted.
Since all our constructions are homotopy-invariant, all our colimits are necessarily \emph{homotopy colimits}, but we drop the ubiquitous adjective in the interests of concision.
In this section we discuss \emph{pushouts}, as perhaps the simplest and one of the most useful colimits.
Indeed, one expects all finite colimits (for a suitable homotopical definition of ``finite'') to be constructible from pushouts and finite coproducts.
It is also possible to give a direct construction of more general colimits using higher inductive types, but this is somewhat technical, and also not completely satisfactory since we do not yet have a good fully general notion of homotopy coherent diagrams.
\indexsee{type!pushout of}{pushout}%
\index{pushout|(defstyle}%
\index{span}%
Suppose given a span of types and functions:
\[\Ddiag=\;\vcenter{\xymatrix{C \ar^g[r] \ar_f[d] & B \\ A & }}\]
The \define{pushout} of this span is the higher inductive type $A\sqcup^CB$ presented by
\begin{itemize}
\item a function $\inl:A\to A\sqcup^CB$,
\item a function $\inr:B \to A\sqcup^CB$, and
\item for each $c:C$ a path $\glue(c):(\inl(f(c))=\inr(g(c)))$.
\end{itemize}
In other words, $A\sqcup^CB$ is the disjoint union of $A$ and $B$, together with for every $c:C$ a witness that $f(c)$ and $g(c)$ are equal.
The recursion principle says that if $D$ is another type, we can define a map $s:A\sqcup^CB\to{}D$ by defining
\begin{itemize}
\item for each $a:A$, the value of $s(\inl(a)):D$,
\item for each $b:B$, the value of $s(\inr(b)):D$, and
\item for each $c:C$, the value of $\mapfunc{s}(\glue(c)):s(\inl(f(c)))=s(\inr(g(c)))$.
\end{itemize}
We leave it to the reader to formulate the induction principle.
It also implies the uniqueness principle that if $s,s':A\sqcup^CB\to{}D$ are two maps such that
\index{uniqueness!principle, propositional!for functions on a pushout}%
\begin{align*}
s(\inl(a))&=s'(\inl(a))\\
s(\inr(b))&=s'(\inr(b))\\
\mapfunc{s}(\glue(c))&=\mapfunc{s'}(\glue(c))
\qquad\text{(modulo the previous two equalities)}
\end{align*}
for every $a,b,c$, then $s=s'$.
To formulate the universal property of a pushout, we introduce the following.
\begin{defn}\label{defn:cocone}
Given a span $\Ddiag= (A \xleftarrow{f} C \xrightarrow{g} B)$ and a type $D$, a \define{cocone under $\Ddiag$ with vertex $D$}
\indexdef{cocone}%
\index{vertex of a cocone}%
consists of functions $i:A\to{}D$ and $j:B\to{}D$ and a homotopy $h : \prd{c:C} (i(f(c))=j(g(c)))$:
\[\uppercurveobject{{ }}\lowercurveobject{{ }}\twocellhead{{ }}
\xymatrix{C \ar^g[r] \ar_f[d] \drtwocell{^h} & B \ar^j[d] \\ A \ar_i[r] & D
}\]
We denote by $\cocone{\Ddiag}{D}$ the type of all such cocones, i.e.
\[ \cocone{\Ddiag}{D} \defeq
\sm{i:A\to D}{j:B\to D} \prd{c:C} (i(f(c))=j(g(c))).
\]
\end{defn}
Of course, there is a canonical cocone under $\Ddiag$ with vertex $A\sqcup^C B$ consisting of $\inl$, $\inr$, and $\glue$.
\[\uppercurveobject{{ }}\lowercurveobject{{ }}\twocellhead{{ }}
\xymatrix{C \ar^g[r] \ar_f[d] \drtwocell{^\glue\ \ } & B \ar^\inr[d] \\
A \ar_-\inl[r] & A\sqcup^CB }\]
The following lemma says that this is the universal such cocone.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:pushout-ump}
\index{universal!property!of pushout}%
For any type $E$, there is an equivalence
\[ (A\sqcup^C B \to E) \;\eqvsym\; \cocone{\Ddiag}{E}. \]
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Let's consider an arbitrary type $E:\type$.
There is a canonical function $c_\sqcup$ defined by
\[\function{(A\sqcup^CB\to{}E)}{\cocone{\Ddiag}{E}}
{t}{(t\circ{}\inl,t\circ{}\inr,\mapfunc{t}\circ{}\glue)}\]
We write informally $t\mapsto\composecocone{t}c_\sqcup$ for this function.
We show that this is an equivalence.
Firstly, given a $c=(i,j,h):\cocone{\mathscr{D}}{E}$, we need to construct a
map $\mathsf{s}(c)$ from $A\sqcup^CB$ to $E$.
\[\uppercurveobject{{ }}\lowercurveobject{{ }}\twocellhead{{ }}
\xymatrix{C \ar^g[r] \ar_f[d] \drtwocell{^h} & B \ar^{j}[d] \\
A \ar_-{i}[r] & E }\]
The map $\mathsf{s}(c)$ is defined in the following way
\begin{align*}
\mathsf{s}(c)(\inl(a))&\defeq i(a),\\
\mathsf{s}(c)(\inr(b))&\defeq j(b),\\
\mapfunc{\mathsf{s}(c)}(\glue(x))&\defid h(x).
\end{align*}
We have defined a map
\[\function{\cocone{\Ddiag}{E}}{(A\sqcup^CB\to{}E)}{c}{\mathsf{s}(c)}\]
and we need to prove that this map is an inverse to
$t\mapsto{}\composecocone{t}c_\sqcup$.
On the one hand, if $c=(i,j,h):\cocone{\Ddiag}{E}$, we have
\begin{align*}
\composecocone{\mathsf{s}(c)}c_\sqcup & =
(\mathsf{s}(c)\circ\inl,\mathsf{s}(c)\circ\inr,
\mapfunc{\mathsf{s}(c)}\circ\glue) \\
& = (\lamu{a:A} \mathsf{s}(c)(\inl(a)),\;
\lamu{b:B} \mathsf{s}(c)(\inr(b)),\;
\lamu{x:C} \mapfunc{\mathsf{s}(c)}(\glue(x))) \\
& = (\lamu{a:A} i(a),\;
\lamu{b:B} j(b),\;
\lamu{x:C} h(x)) \\
& \jdeq (i, j, h) \\
& = c.
\end{align*}
%
On the other hand, if $t:A\sqcup^CB\to{}E$, we want to prove that
$\mathsf{s}(\composecocone{t}c_\sqcup)=t$.
For $a:A$, we have
\[\mathsf{s}(\composecocone{t}c_\sqcup)(\inl(a))=t(\inl(a))\]
because the first component of $\composecocone{t}c_\sqcup$ is $t\circ\inl$. In
the same way, for $b:B$ we have
\[\mathsf{s}(\composecocone{t}c_\sqcup)(\inr(b))=t(\inr(b))\]
and for $x:C$ we have
\[\mapfunc{\mathsf{s}(\composecocone{t}c_\sqcup)}(\glue(x))
=\mapfunc{t}(\glue(x))\]
hence $\mathsf{s}(\composecocone{t}c_\sqcup)=t$.
This proves that $c\mapsto\mathsf{s}(c)$ is a quasi-inverse to $t\mapsto{}\composecocone{t}c_\sqcup$, as desired.
\end{proof}
A number of standard homotopy-theoretic constructions can be expressed as (homotopy) pushouts.
\begin{itemize}
\item The pushout of the span $\unit \leftarrow A \to \unit$ is the \define{suspension} $\susp A$ (see \cref{sec:suspension}).%
\index{suspension}
\symlabel{join}
\item The pushout of $A \xleftarrow{\proj1} A\times B \xrightarrow{\proj2} B$ is called the \define{join} of $A$ and $B$, written $A*B$.%
\indexdef{join!of types}
\item The pushout of $\unit \leftarrow A \xrightarrow{f} B$ is the \define{cone} or \define{cofiber} of $f$.%
\indexdef{cone!of a function}%
\indexsee{mapping cone}{cone of a function}%
\indexdef{cofiber of a function}%
\symlabel{wedge}
\item If $A$ and $B$ are equipped with basepoints $a_0:A$ and $b_0:B$, then the pushout of $A \xleftarrow{a_0} \unit \xrightarrow{b_0} B$ is the \define{wedge} $A\vee B$.%
\indexdef{wedge}
\symlabel{smash}
\item If $A$ and $B$ are pointed as before, define $f:A\vee B \to A\times B$ by $f(\inl(a))\defeq (a,b_0)$ and $f(\inr(b))\defeq (a_0,b)$, with $\ap f \glue \defid \refl{(a_0,b_0)}$.
Then the cone of $f$ is called the \define{smash product} $A\wedge B$.%
\indexdef{smash product}
\end{itemize}
We will discuss pushouts further in \cref{cha:hlevels,cha:homotopy}.
\begin{rmk}
As remarked in \cref{subsec:prop-trunc}, the notations $\wedge$ and $\vee$ for the smash product and wedge of pointed spaces are also used in logic for ``and'' and ``or'', respectively.
Since types in homotopy type theory can behave either like spaces or like propositions, there is technically a potential for conflict --- but since they rarely do both at once, context generally disambiguates.
Furthermore, the smash product and wedge only apply to \emph{pointed} spaces, while the only pointed mere proposition is $\top\jdeq\unit$ --- and we have $\unit\wedge \unit = \unit$ and $\unit\vee\unit=\unit$ for either meaning of $\wedge$ and $\vee$.
\end{rmk}
\index{pushout|)}%
\begin{rmk}
Note that colimits do not in general preserve truncatedness.
For instance, $\Sn^0$ and \unit are both sets, but the pushout of $\unit \leftarrow \Sn^0 \to \unit$ is $\Sn^1$, which is not a set.
If we are interested in colimits in the category of $n$-types, therefore (and, in particular, in the category of sets), we need to ``truncate'' the colimit somehow.
We will return to this point in \cref{sec:hittruncations,cha:hlevels,cha:set-math}.
\end{rmk}
\section{Truncations}
\label{sec:hittruncations}
\index{truncation!propositional|(}%
In \cref{subsec:prop-trunc} we introduced the propositional truncation as a new type forming operation;
we now observe that it can be obtained as a special case of higher inductive types.
This reduces the problem of understanding truncations to the problem of understanding higher inductives, which at least are amenable to a systematic treatment.
It is also interesting because it provides our first example of a higher inductive type which is truly \emph{recursive}, in that its constructors take inputs from the type being defined (as does the successor $\suc:\nat\to\nat$).
Let $A$ be a type; we define its propositional truncation $\brck A$ to be the higher inductive type generated by:
\begin{itemize}
\item A function $\bprojf : A \to \brck A$, and
\item for each $x,y:\brck A$, a path $x=y$.
\end{itemize}
Note that the second constructor is by definition the assertion that $\brck A$ is a mere proposition.
Thus, the definition of $\brck A$ can be interpreted as saying that $\brck A$ is freely generated by a function $A\to\brck A$ and the fact that it is a mere proposition.
The recursion principle for this higher inductive definition is easy to write down: it says that given any type $B$ together with
\begin{itemize}
\item a function $g:A\to B$, and
\item for any $x,y:B$, a path $x=_B y$,
\end{itemize}
there exists a function $f:\brck A \to B$ such that
\begin{itemize}
\item $f(\bproj a) \jdeq g(a)$ for all $a:A$, and
\item for any $x,y:\brck A$, the function $\apfunc f$ takes the specified path $x=y$ in $\brck A$ to the specified path $f(x) = f(y)$ in $B$ (propositionally).
\end{itemize}
\index{recursion principle!for truncation}%
These are exactly the hypotheses that we stated in \cref{subsec:prop-trunc} for the recursion principle of propositional truncation --- a function $A\to B$ such that $B$ is a mere proposition --- and the first part of the conclusion is exactly what we stated there as well.
The second part (the action of $\apfunc f$) was not mentioned previously, but it turns out to be vacuous in this case, because $B$ is a mere proposition, so \emph{any} two paths in it are automatically equal.
\index{induction principle!for truncation}%
There is also an induction principle for $\brck A$, which says that given any $B:\brck A \to \type$ together with
\begin{itemize}
\item a function $g:\prd{a:A} B(\bproj a)$, and
\item for any $x,y:\brck A$ and $u:B(x)$ and $v:B(y)$, a dependent path $q:\dpath{B}{p(x,y)}{u}{v}$, where $p(x,y)$ is the path coming from the second constructor of $\brck A$,
\end{itemize}
there exists $f:\prd{x:\brck A} B(x)$ such that $f(\bproj a)\jdeq g(a)$ for $a:A$, and also another computation rule.
However, because there can be at most one function between any two mere propositions (up to homotopy), this induction principle is not really useful (see also \cref{ex:prop-trunc-ind}).
\index{truncation!propositional|)}%
\index{truncation!set|(}%
\index{set|(}%
We can, however, extend this idea to construct similar truncations landing in $n$-types, for any $n$.
For instance, we might define the \emph{0-trun\-ca\-tion} $\trunc0A$ to be generated by
\begin{itemize}
\item A function $\tprojf0 : A \to \trunc0 A$, and
\item For each $x,y:\trunc0A$ and each $p,q:x=y$, a path $p=q$.
\end{itemize}
Then $\trunc0A$ would be freely generated by a function $A\to \trunc0A$ together with the assertion that $\trunc0A$ is a set.
A natural induction principle for it would say that given $B:\trunc0 A \to \type$ together with
\begin{itemize}
\item a function $g:\prd{a:A} B(\tproj0a)$, and
\item for any $x,y:\trunc0A$ with $z:B(x)$ and $w:B(y)$, and each $p,q:x=y$ with $r:\dpath{B}{p}{z}{w}$ and $s:\dpath{B}{q}{z}{w}$, a 2-path $v:\dpath{\dpath{B}{-}{z}{w}}{u(x,y,p,q)}{r}{s}$, where $u(x,y,p,q):p=q$ is obtained from the second constructor of $\trunc0A$,
\end{itemize}
there exists $f:\prd{x:\trunc0A} B(x)$ such that $f(\tproj0a)\jdeq g(a)$ for all $a:A$, and also $\apdtwo{f}{u(x,y,p,q)}$ is the 2-path specified above.
(As in the propositional case, the latter condition turns out to be uninteresting.)
From this, however, we can prove a more useful induction principle.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:trunc0-ind}
Suppose given $B:\trunc0 A \to \type$ together with $g:\prd{a:A} B(\tproj0a)$, and assume that each $B(x)$ is a set.
Then there exists $f:\prd{x:\trunc0A} B(x)$ such that $f(\tproj0a)\jdeq g(a)$ for all $a:A$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
It suffices to construct, for any $x,y,z,w,p,q,r,s$ as above, a 2-path $v:\dpath{B}{u(x,y,p,q)}{r}{s}$.
However, by the definition of dependent 2-paths, this is an ordinary 2-path in the fiber $B(y)$.
Since $B(y)$ is a set, a 2-path exists between any two parallel paths.
\end{proof}
This implies the expected universal property.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:trunc0-lump}
\index{universal!property!of truncation}%
For any set $B$ and any type $A$, composition with $\tprojf0:A\to \trunc0A$ determines an equivalence
\[ \eqvspaced{(\trunc0A\to B)}{(A\to B)}. \]
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
The special case of \cref{thm:trunc0-ind} when $B$ is the constant family gives a map from right to left, which is a right inverse to the ``compose with $\tprojf0$'' function from left to right.
To show that it is also a left inverse, let $h:\trunc0A\to B$, and define $h':\trunc0A\to B$ by applying \cref{thm:trunc0-ind} to the composite $a\mapsto h(\tproj0a)$.
Thus, $h'(\tproj0a)=h(\tproj0a)$.
However, since $B$ is a set, for any $x:\trunc0A$ the type $h(x)=h'(x)$ is a mere proposition, and hence also a set.
Therefore, by \cref{thm:trunc0-ind}, the observation that $h'(\tproj0a)=h(\tproj0a)$ for any $a:A$ implies $h(x)=h'(x)$ for any $x:\trunc0A$, and hence $h=h'$.
\end{proof}
\index{limit!of sets}%
\index{colimit!of sets}%
For instance, this enables us to construct colimits of sets.
We have seen that if $A \xleftarrow{f} C \xrightarrow{g} B$ is a span of sets, then the pushout $A\sqcup^C B$ may no longer be a set.
(For instance, if $A$ and $B$ are \unit and $C$ is \bool, then the pushout is $\Sn^1$.)
However, we can construct a pushout that is a set, and has the expected universal property with respect to other sets, by truncating.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:set-pushout}
\index{universal!property!of pushout}%
Let $A \xleftarrow{f} C \xrightarrow{g} B$ be a span\index{span} of sets.
Then for any set $E$, there is a canonical equivalence
\[ \Parens{\trunc0{A\sqcup^C B} \to E} \;\eqvsym\; \cocone{\Ddiag}{E}. \]
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Compose the equivalences in \cref{thm:pushout-ump,thm:trunc0-lump}.
\end{proof}
We refer to $\trunc0{A\sqcup^C B}$ as the \define{set-pushout}
\indexdef{set-pushout}%
\index{pushout!of sets}
of $f$ and $g$, to distinguish it from the (homotopy) pushout $A\sqcup^C B$.
Alternatively, we could modify the definition of the pushout in \cref{sec:colimits} to include the $0$-truncation constructor directly, avoiding the need to truncate afterwards.
Similar remarks apply to any sort of colimit of sets; we will explore this further in \cref{cha:set-math}.
However, while the above definition of the 0-truncation works --- it gives what we want, and is consistent --- it has a couple of issues.
Firstly, it doesn't fit so nicely into the general theory of higher inductive types.
In general, it is tricky to deal directly with constructors such as the second one we have given for $\trunc0A$, whose \emph{inputs} involve not only elements of the type being defined, but paths in it.
This can be gotten round fairly easily, however.
Recall in \cref{sec:bool-nat} we mentioned that we can allow a constructor of an inductive type $W$ to take ``infinitely many arguments'' of type $W$ by having it take a single argument of type $\nat\to W$.
There is a general principle behind this: to model a constructor with funny-looking inputs, use an auxiliary inductive type (such as \nat) to parametrize them, reducing the input to a simple function with inductive domain.
For the 0-truncation, we can consider the auxiliary \emph{higher} inductive type $S$ generated by two points $a,b:S$ and two paths $p,q:a=b$.
Then the fishy-looking constructor of $\trunc 0A$ can be replaced by the unobjectionable
\begin{itemize}
\item For every $f:S\to \trunc 0A$, a path $\apfunc{f}(p) = \apfunc{f}(q)$.
\end{itemize}
Since to give a map out of $S$ is the same as to give two points and two parallel paths between them, this yields the same induction principle.
\index{set|)}%
\index{truncation!set|)}%
\index{truncation!n-truncation@$n$-truncation}%
A more serious problem with our current definition of $0$-truncation, however, is that it doesn't generalize very well.
If we want to describe a notion of definition of ``$n$-truncation'' into $n$-types uniformly for all $n:\nat$, then this approach is unfeasible, since the second constructor would need a number of arguments that increases with $n$.
In \cref{sec:truncations}, therefore, we will use a different idea to construct these, based on the observation that the type $S$ introduced above is equivalent to the circle $\Sn^1$.
This includes the 0-truncation as a special case, and satisfies generalized versions of \cref{thm:trunc0-ind,thm:trunc0-lump}.
\section{Quotients}
\label{sec:set-quotients}
A particularly important sort of colimit of sets is the \emph{quotient} by a relation.
That is, let $A$ be a set and $R:A\times A \to \prop$ a family of mere propositions (a \define{mere relation}).
\indexdef{relation!mere}%
\indexdef{mere relation}%
Its quotient should be the set-coequalizer of the two projections
\[ \tsm{a,b:A} R(a,b) \rightrightarrows A. \]
We can also describe this directly, as the higher inductive type $A/R$ generated by
\index{set-quotient|(defstyle}%
\indexsee{quotient of sets}{set-quotient}%
\indexsee{type!quotient}{set-quotient}%
\begin{itemize}
\item A function $q:A\to A/R$;
\item For each $a,b:A$ such that $R(a,b)$, an equality $q(a)=q(b)$; and
\item The $0$-truncation constructor: for all $x,y:A/R$ and $r,s:x=y$, we have $r=s$.
\end{itemize}
We will sometimes refer to this higher inductive type $A/R$ as the \define{set-quotient} of $A$ by $R$, to emphasize that it produces a set by definition.
(There are more general notions of ``quotient'' in homotopy theory, but they are mostly beyond the scope of this book.
However, in \cref{sec:rezk} we will consider the ``quotient'' of a type by a 1-groupoid, which is the next level up from set-quotients.)
\begin{rmk}\label{rmk:quotient-of-non-set}
It is not actually necessary for the definition of set-quotients, and most of their properties, that $A$ be a set.
However, this is generally the case of most interest.
\end{rmk}
\begin{lem}\label{thm:quotient-surjective}
The function $q:A\to A/R$ is surjective.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We must show that for any $x:A/R$ there merely exists an $a:A$ with $q(a)=x$.
We use the induction principle of $A/R$.
The first case is trivial: if $x$ is $q(a)$, then of course there merely exists an $a$ such that $q(a)=q(a)$.
And since the goal is a mere proposition, it automatically respects all path constructors, so we are done.
\end{proof}
We can now prove that the set-quotient has the expected universal property of a (set-)coequalizer.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:quotient-ump}
For any set $B$, precomposing with $q$ yields an equivalence
\[ \eqvspaced{(A/R \to B)}{\Parens{\sm{f:A\to B} \prd{a,b:A} R(a,b) \to (f(a)=f(b))}}.\]
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
The quasi-inverse of $\blank\circ q$, going from right to left, is just the recursion principle for $A/R$.
That is, given $f:A\to B$ such that
\narrowequation{\prd{a,b:A} R(a,b) \to (f(a)=f(b)),} we define $\bar f:A/R\to B$ by $\bar f(q(a))\defeq f(a)$.
This defining equation says precisely that $(f\mapsto \bar f)$ is a right inverse to $(\blank\circ q)$.
For it to also be a left inverse, we must show that for any $g:A/R\to B$ and $x:A/R$ we have $g(x) = \overline{g\circ q}(x)$.
However, by \cref{thm:quotient-surjective} there merely exists $a$ such that $q(a)=x$.
Since our desired equality is a mere proposition, we may assume there purely exists such an $a$, in which case $g(x) = g(q(a)) = \overline{g\circ q}(q(a)) = \overline{g\circ q}(x)$.
\end{proof}
Of course, classically the usual case to consider is when $R$ is an \define{equivalence relation}, i.e.\ we have
\indexdef{relation!equivalence}%
\indexsee{equivalence!relation}{relation, equivalence}%
%
\begin{itemize}
\item \define{reflexivity}: $\prd{a:A} R(a,a)$,
\indexdef{reflexivity!of a relation}%
\indexdef{relation!reflexive}%
\item \define{symmetry}: $\prd{a,b:A} R(a,b) \to R(b,a)$, and
\indexdef{symmetry!of a relation}%
\indexdef{relation!symmetric}%
\item \define{transitivity}: $\prd{a,b,c:C} R(a,b) \times R(b,c) \to R(a,c)$.
\indexdef{transitivity!of a relation}%
\indexdef{relation!transitive}%
\end{itemize}
%
In this case, the set-quotient $A/R$ has additional good properties, as we will see in \cref{sec:piw-pretopos}: for instance, we have $R(a,b) \eqvsym (\id[A/R]{q(a)}{q(b)})$.
\symlabel{equivalencerelation}
We often write an equivalence relation $R(a,b)$ infix as $a\eqr b$.
The quotient by an equivalence relation can also be constructed in other ways.
The set theoretic approach is to consider the set of equivalence classes, as a subset of the power set\index{power set} of $A$.
We can mimic this ``impredicative'' construction in type theory as well.
\index{impredicative!quotient}
\begin{defn}
A predicate $P:A\to\prop$ is an \define{equivalence class}
\indexdef{equivalence!class}%
of a relation $R : A \times A \to \prop$ if there merely exists an $a:A$ such that for all $b:A$ we have $\eqv{R(a,b)}{P(b)}$.
\end{defn}
As $R$ and $P$ are mere propositions, the equivalence $\eqv{R(a,b)}{P(b)}$ is the same thing as implications $R(a,b) \to P(b)$ and $P(b) \to R(a,b)$.
And of course, for any $a:A$ we have the canonical equivalence class $P_a(b) \defeq R(a,b)$.
\begin{defn}\label{def:VVquotient}
We define
\begin{equation*}
A\sslash R \defeq \setof{ P:A\to\prop | P \text{ is an equivalence class of } R}.
\end{equation*}
The function $q':A\to A\sslash R$ is defined by $q'(a) \defeq P_a$.
\end{defn}
\begin{thm}
For any equivalence relation $R$ on $A$, the type $A\sslash R$ is equivalent to the set-quotient $A/R$.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
First, note that if $R(a,b)$, then since $R$ is an equivalence relation we have $R(a,c) \Leftrightarrow R(b,c)$ for any $c:A$.
Thus, $R(a,c) = R(b,c)$ by univalence, hence $P_a=P_b$ by function extensionality, i.e.\ $q'(a)=q'(b)$.
Therefore, by \cref{thm:quotient-ump} we have an induced map $f:A/R \to A\sslash R$ such that $f\circ q = q'$.
We show that $f$ is injective and surjective, hence an equivalence.
Surjectivity follows immediately from the fact that $q'$ is surjective, which in turn is true essentially by definition of $A\sslash R$.
For injectivity, if $f(x)=f(y)$, then to show the mere proposition $x=y$, by surjectivity of $q$ we may assume $x=q(a)$ and $y=q(b)$ for some $a,b:A$.
Then $R(a,c) = f(q(a))(c) = f(q(b))(c) = R(b,c)$ for any $c:A$, and in particular $R(a,b) = R(b,b)$.
But $R(b,b)$ is inhabited, since $R$ is an equivalence relation, hence so is $R(a,b)$.
Thus $q(a)=q(b)$ and so $x=y$.
\end{proof}
In \cref{subsec:quotients} we will give an alternative proof of this theorem.
Note that unlike $A/R$, the construction $A\sslash R$ raises universe level: if $A:\UU_i$ and $R:A\to A\to \prop_{\UU_i}$, then in the definition of $A\sslash R$ we must also use $\prop_{\UU_i}$ to include all the equivalence classes, so that $A\sslash R : \UU_{i+1}$.
Of course, we can avoid this if we assume the propositional resizing axiom from \cref{subsec:prop-subsets}.
\begin{rmk}\label{defn-Z}
The previous two constructions provide quotients in generality, but in particular cases there may be easier constructions.
For instance, we may define the integers \Z as a set-quotient
\indexdef{integers}%
\indexdef{number!integers}%
%
\[ \Z \defeq (\N \times \N)/{\eqr} \]
%
where $\eqr$ is the equivalence relation defined by
%
\[ (a,b) \eqr (c,d) \defeq (a + d = b + c). \]
%
In other words, a pair $(a,b)$ represents the integer $a - b$.
In this case, however, there are \emph{canonical representatives} of the equivalence classes: those of the form $(n,0)$ or $(0,n)$.
\end{rmk}
The following lemma says that when this sort of thing happens, we don't need either general construction of quotients.
(A function $r:A\to A$ is called \define{idempotent}
\indexdef{function!idempotent}%
\indexdef{idempotent!function}%
if $r\circ r = r$.)
\begin{lem}\label{lem:quotient-when-canonical-representatives}
Suppose $\eqr$ is a relation on a set $A$, and there exists an idempotent $r
: A \to A$ such that $\eqv{(r(x) = r(y))}{(x \eqr y)}$ for all $x, y: A$.
(This implies $\eqr$ is an equivalence relation.)
Then the type
%
\begin{equation*}
(A/{\eqr}) \defeq \Parens{\sm{x : A} r(x) = x}
\end{equation*}
%
satisfies the universal property of the set-quotient of $A$ by~$\eqr$, and hence is equivalent to it.
In other words, there is a map $q : A \to (A/{\eqr})$ such that for every set $B$, precomposition with $q$ induces an equivalence
%
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:quotient-when-canonical}
\Parens{(A/{\eqr}) \to B} \eqvsym \Parens{\sm{g : A \to B} \prd{x, y : A} (x \eqr y) \to (g(x) = g(y))}.
\end{equation}
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Let $i : \prd{x : A} r(r(x)) = r(x)$ witness idempotence of~$r$.
The map $q : A \to (A/{\eqr})$ is defined by $q(x) \defeq (r(x), i(x))$.
Note that since $A$ is a set, we have $q(x)=q(y)$ if and only if $r(x)=r(y)$, hence (by assumption) if and only if $x \eqr y$.
We define a map $e$ from left to right in~\eqref{eq:quotient-when-canonical} by
\[ e(f) \defeq (f \circ q, \nameless), \]
%
where the underscore $\nameless$ denotes the following proof: if $x, y : A$ and $x \eqr y$, then $q(x)=q(y)$ as observed above, hence $f(q(x)) = f(q(y))$.
To see that $e$ is an equivalence, consider the map $e'$ in the opposite direction defined by
%
\[ e'(g, s) (x,p) \defeq g(x). \]
%
Given any $f : (A/{\eqr}) \to B$,
%
\[ e'(e(f))(x, p) \jdeq f(q(x)) \jdeq f(r(x), i(x)) = f(x, p) \]
%
where the last equality holds because $p : r(x) = x$ and so $(x,p) = (r(x), i(x))$
because $A$ is a set. Similarly we compute
%
\[ e(e'(g, s)) \jdeq e(g \circ \proj{1}) \jdeq (g \circ \proj{1} \circ q, {\nameless}). \]
%
Because $B$ is a set we need not worry about the $\nameless$ part, while for the first
component we have
%
\[ g(\proj{1}(q(x))) \jdeq g(r(x)) = g(x), \]
%
where the last equation holds because $r(x) \eqr x$, and $g$ respects $\eqr$ by
the assumption $s$.
\end{proof}
\begin{cor}\label{thm:retraction-quotient}
Suppose $p:A\to B$ is a retraction between sets.
Then $B$ is the quotient of $A$ by the equivalence relation $\eqr$ defined by
\[ (a_1 \eqr a_2) \defeq (p(a_1) = p(a_2)). \]
\end{cor}
\begin{proof}
Suppose $s:B\to A$ is a section of $p$.
Then $s\circ p : A\to A$ is an idempotent which satisfies the condition of \cref{lem:quotient-when-canonical-representatives} for this $\eqr$, and $s$ induces an isomorphism from $B$ to its set of fixed points.
\end{proof}
\begin{rmk}\label{Z-quotient-by-canonical-representatives}
\cref{lem:quotient-when-canonical-representatives} applies to $\Z$ with the idempotent $r : \N \times \N \to \N \times \N$
defined by
%
\begin{equation*}
r(a, b) =
\begin{cases}
(a - b, 0) & \text{if $a \geq b$,} \\
(0, b - a) & \text{otherwise.}
\end{cases}
\end{equation*}
%
(This is a valid definition even constructively, since the relation $\geq$ on $\N$ is decidable.)
Thus a non-negative integer is canonically represented as $(k, 0)$ and a non-positive one by $(0, m)$, for $k,m:\N$.
This division into cases implies the following ``induction principle'' for integers, which will be useful in \cref{cha:homotopy}.
\index{natural numbers}%
(As usual, we identify a natural number $n$ with the corresponding non-negative integer, i.e.\ with the image of $(n,0):\N\times\N$ in $\Z$.)
\end{rmk}
\begin{lem}\label{thm:sign-induction}
\index{integers!induction principle for}%
\index{induction principle!for integers}%
Suppose $P:\Z\to\type$ is a type family and that we have
\begin{itemize}
\item $d_0: P(0)$,
\item $d_+: \prd{n:\N} P(n) \to P(\suc(n))$, and
\item $d_- : \prd{n:\N} P(-n) \to P(-\suc(n))$.
\end{itemize}
Then we have $f:\prd{z:\Z} P(z)$ such that
\begin{itemize}
\item $f(0) = d_0$,
\item $f(\suc(n)) = d_+(n,f(n))$ for all $n:\N$, and
\item $f(-\suc(n)) = d_-(n,f(-n))$ for all $n:\N$.
\end{itemize}
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
For purposes of this proof, let $\Z$ denote $\sm{x:\N\times\N}(r(x)=x)$, where $r$ is the above idempotent.
(We can then transport the result to any equivalent definition of $\Z$.)
Let $q:\N\times\N\to\Z$ be the quotient map, defined by $q(x) = (r(x),i(x))$ as in \cref{lem:quotient-when-canonical-representatives}.
Now define $Q\defeq P\circ q:\N\times \N \to \type$.
By transporting the given data across appropriate equalities, we obtain
\begin{align*}
d'_0 &: Q(0,0)\\
d'_+ &: \prd{n:\N} Q(n,0) \to Q(\suc(n),0)\\
d'_- &: \prd{n:\N} Q(0,n) \to Q(0,\suc(n)).
\end{align*}
Note also that since $q(n,m) = q(\suc(n),\suc(m))$, we have an induced equivalence
\[e_{n,m}:\eqv{Q(n,m)}{Q(\suc(n),\suc(m))}.\]
We can then construct $g:\prd{x:\N\times \N} Q(x)$ by double induction on $x$:
\begin{align*}
g(0,0) &\defeq d'_0,\\
g(\suc(n),0) &\defeq d'_+(n,g(n,0)),\\
g(0,\suc(m)) &\defeq d'_-(m,g(0,m)),\\
g(\suc(n),\suc(m)) &\defeq e_{n,m}(g(n,m)).
\end{align*}
Now we have $\proj1 : \Z \to \N\times\N$, with the property that $q\circ \proj1 = \idfunc$.
In particular, therefore, we have $Q\circ \proj1 = P$, and hence a family of equivalences $s:\prd{z:\Z} \eqv{Q(\proj1(z))}{P(z)}$.
Thus, we can define $f(z) = s(z,g(\proj1(z)))$ to obtain $f:\prd{z:\Z} P(z)$, and verify the desired equalities.
\end{proof}
We will sometimes denote a function $f:\prd{z:\Z} P(z)$ obtained from \cref{thm:sign-induction} with a pattern-matching syntax, involving the three cases $d_0$, $d_+$, and $d_-$:
\begin{align*}
f(0) &\defid d_0\\
f(\suc(n)) &\defid d_+(n,f(n))\\
f(-\suc(n)) &\defid d_-(n,f(-n))
\end{align*}
We use $\defid$ rather than $\defeq$, as we did for the path constructors of higher inductive types, to indicate that the ``computation'' rules implied by \cref{thm:sign-induction} are only propositional equalities.
For example, in this way we can define the $n$-fold concatenation of a loop for any integer $n$.
\begin{cor}\label{thm:looptothe}
\indexdef{path!concatenation!n-fold@$n$-fold}%
Let $A$ be a type with $a:A$ and $p:a=a$.
There is a function $\prd{n:\Z} (a=a)$, denoted $n\mapsto p^n$, defined by
\begin{align*}
p^0 &\defid \refl{a}\\
p^{n+1} &\defid p^n \ct p
& &\text{for $n\ge 0$}\\
p^{n-1} &\defid p^n \ct \opp p
& &\text{for $n\le 0$.}
\end{align*}
\end{cor}
We will discuss the integers further in \cref{sec:free-algebras,sec:field-rati-numb}.
\index{set-quotient|)}%
\section{Algebra}
\label{sec:free-algebras}
In addition to constructing higher-dimensional objects such as spheres and cell complexes, higher inductive types are also very useful even when working only with sets.
We have seen one example already in \cref{thm:set-pushout}: they allow us to construct the colimit of any diagram of sets, which is not possible in the base type theory of \cref{cha:typetheory}.
Higher inductive types are also very useful when we study sets with algebraic structure.
As a running example in this section, we consider \emph{groups}, which are familiar to most mathematicians and exhibit the essential phenomena (and will be needed in later chapters).
However, most of what we say applies equally well to any sort of algebraic structure.
\index{monoid|(}%
\begin{defn}
A \define{monoid}
\indexdef{monoid}%
is a set $G$ together with
\begin{itemize}
\item a \emph{multiplication}
\indexdef{multiplication!in a monoid}%
\indexdef{multiplication!in a group}%
function $G\times G\to G$, written infix as $(x,y) \mapsto x\cdot y$; and
\item a \emph{unit}
\indexdef{unit!of a monoid}%
\indexdef{unit!of a group}%
element $e:G$; such that
\item for any $x:G$, we have $x\cdot e = x$ and $e\cdot x = x$; and
\item for any $x,y,z:G$, we have $x\cdot (y\cdot z) = (x\cdot y)\cdot z$.
\index{associativity!in a monoid}%
\index{associativity!in a group}%
\end{itemize}
A \define{group}
\indexdef{group}%
is a monoid $G$ together with
\begin{itemize}
\item an \emph{inversion} function $i:G\to G$, written $x\mapsto \opp x$; such that
\index{inverse!in a group}%
\item for any $x:G$ we have $x\cdot \opp x = e$ and $\opp x \cdot x = e$.
\end{itemize}
\end{defn}
\begin{rmk}\label{rmk:infty-group}
Note that we require a group to be a set.
We could consider a more general notion of ``$\infty$-group''%
\index{.infinity-group@$\infty$-group}
which is not a set, but this would take us further afield than is appropriate at the moment.
With our current definition, we may expect the resulting ``group theory'' to behave similarly to the way it does in set-theoretic mathematics (with the caveat that, unless we assume \LEM{}, it will be ``constructive'' group theory).\index{mathematics!constructive}
\end{rmk}
\begin{eg}
The natural numbers \N are a monoid under addition, with unit $0$, and also under multiplication, with unit $1$.
If we define the arithmetical operations on the integers \Z in the obvious way, then as usual they are a group under addition and a monoid under multiplication (and, of course, a ring).
For instance, if $u, v \in \Z$ are represented by $(a,b)$ and $(c,d)$, respectively, then $u + v$ is represented by $(a + c, b + d)$, $-u$ is represented by $(b, a)$, and $u v$ is represented by $(a c + b d, a d + b c)$.
\end{eg}
\begin{eg}\label{thm:homotopy-groups}
We essentially observed in \cref{sec:equality} that if $(A,a)$ is a pointed type, then its loop space\index{loop space} $\Omega(A,a)\defeq (\id[A]aa)$ has all the structure of a group, except that it is not in general a set.
It should be an ``$\infty$-group'' in the sense mentioned in \cref{rmk:infty-group}, but we can also make it a group by truncation.
Specifically, we define the \define{fundamental group}
\indexsee{group!fundamental}{fundamental group}%
\indexdef{fundamental!group}%
of $A$ based at $a:A$ to be
\[\pi_1(A,a)\defeq \trunc0{\Omega(A,a)}.\]
This inherits a group structure; for instance, the multiplication $\pi_1(A,a) \times \pi_1(A,a) \to \pi_1(A,a)$ is defined by double induction on truncation from the concatenation of paths.
More generally, the \define{$n^{\mathrm{th}}$ homotopy group}
\index{homotopy!group}%
\indexsee{group!homotopy}{homotopy group}%
of $(A,a)$ is $\pi_n(A,a)\defeq \trunc0{\Omega^n(A,a)}$.
\index{loop space!iterated}%
Then $\pi_n(A,a) = \pi_1(\Omega^{n-1}(A,a))$ for $n\ge 1$, so it is also a group.
(When $n=0$, we have $\pi_0(A) \jdeq \trunc0 A$, which is not a group.)
Moreover, the Eckmann--Hilton argument \index{Eckmann--Hilton argument} (\cref{thm:EckmannHilton}) implies that if $n\ge 2$, then $\pi_n(A,a)$ is an \emph{abelian}\index{group!abelian} group, i.e.\ we have $x\cdot y = y\cdot x$ for all $x,y$.
\cref{cha:homotopy} will be largely the study of these groups.
\end{eg}
\index{algebra!free}%
\index{free!algebraic structure}%
One important notion in group theory is that of the \emph{free group} generated by a set, or more generally of a group \emph{presented} by generators\index{generator!of a group} and relations.
It is well-known in type theory that \emph{some} free algebraic objects can be defined using \emph{ordinary} inductive types.
\symlabel{lst-freemonoid}%
\indexdef{type!of lists}%
\indexsee{list type}{type, of lists}%
\index{monoid!free|(}%
For instance, the free monoid on a set $A$ can be identified with the type $\lst A$ of \emph{finite lists} \index{finite!lists, type of} of elements of $A$, which is inductively generated by
\begin{itemize}
\item a constructor $\nil:\lst A$, and
\item for each $\ell:\lst A$ and $a:A$, an element $\cons(a,\ell):\lst A$.
\end{itemize}
We have an obvious inclusion $\eta : A\to \lst A$ defined by $a\mapsto \cons(a,\nil)$.
The monoid operation on $\lst A$ is concatenation, defined recursively by
\begin{align*}
\nil \cdot \ell &\defeq \ell\\
\cons (a,\ell_1) \cdot \ell_2 &\defeq \cons(a, \ell_1\cdot\ell_2).
\end{align*}
It is straightforward to prove, using the induction principle for $\lst A$, that $\lst A$ is a set and that concatenation of lists is associative
\index{associativity!of list concatenation}%
and has $\nil$ as a unit.
Thus, $\lst A$ is a monoid.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:free-monoid}
\indexsee{free!monoid}{monoid, free}%
For any set $A$, the type $\lst A$ is the free monoid on $A$.
In other words, for any monoid $G$, composition with $\eta$ is an equivalence
\[ \eqv{\hom_{\mathrm{Monoid}}(\lst A,G)}{(A\to G)}, \]
where $\hom_{\mathrm{Monoid}}(\blank,\blank)$ denotes the set of monoid homomorphisms (functions which preserve the multiplication and unit).
\indexdef{homomorphism!monoid}%
\indexdef{monoid!homomorphism}%
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Given $f:A\to G$, we define $\bar{f}:\lst A \to G$ by recursion:
\begin{align*}
\bar{f}(\nil) &\defeq e\\
\bar{f}(\cons(a,\ell)) &\defeq f(a) \cdot \bar{f}(\ell).
\end{align*}
It is straightforward to prove by induction that $\bar{f}$ is a monoid homomorphism, and that $f\mapsto \bar f$ is a quasi-inverse of $(\blank\circ \eta)$; see \cref{ex:free-monoid}.
\end{proof}
\index{monoid!free|)}%
This construction of the free monoid is possible essentially because elements of the free monoid have computable canonical forms (namely, finite lists).
However, elements of other free (and presented) algebraic structures --- such as groups --- do not in general have \emph{computable} canonical forms.
For instance, equality of words in group presentations is algorithmically\index{algorithm} undecidable.
However, we can still describe free algebraic objects as \emph{higher} inductive types, by simply asserting all the axiomatic equations as path constructors.
\indexsee{free!group}{group, free}%
\index{group!free|(}%
For example, let $A$ be a set, and define a higher inductive type $\freegroup{A}$ with the following generators.
\begin{itemize}
\item A function $\eta:A\to \freegroup{A}$.
\item A function $m: \freegroup{A} \times \freegroup{A} \to \freegroup{A}$.
\item An element $e:\freegroup{A}$.
\item A function $i:\freegroup{A} \to \freegroup{A}$.
\item For each $x,y,z:\freegroup{A}$, an equality $m(x,m(y,z)) = m(m(x,y),z)$.
\item For each $x:\freegroup{A}$, equalities $m(x,e) = x$ and $m(e,x) = x$.
\item For each $x:\freegroup{A}$, equalities $m(x,i(x)) = e$ and $m(i(x),x) = e$.
\item The $0$-truncation constructor: for any $x,y:\freegroup{A}$ and $p,q:x=y$, we have $p=q$.
\end{itemize}
The first constructor says that $A$ maps to $\freegroup{A}$.
The next three give $\freegroup{A}$ the operations of a group: multiplication, an identity element, and inversion.
The three constructors after that assert the axioms of a group: associativity\index{associativity}, unitality, and inverses.
Finally, the last constructor asserts that $\freegroup{A}$ is a set.
Therefore, $\freegroup{A}$ is a group.
It is also straightforward to prove:
\begin{thm}
\index{universal!property!of free group}%
$\freegroup{A}$ is the free group on $A$.
In other words, for any (set) group $G$, composition with $\eta:A\to \freegroup{A}$ determines an equivalence
\[ \hom_{\mathrm{Group}}(\freegroup{A},G) \eqvsym (A\to G) \]
where $\hom_{\mathrm{Group}}(\blank,\blank)$ denotes the set of group homomorphisms between two groups.
\indexdef{group!homomorphism}%
\indexdef{homomorphism!group}%
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
The recursion principle of the higher inductive type $\freegroup{A}$ says \emph{precisely} that if $G$ is a group and we have $f:A\to G$, then we have $\bar{f}:\freegroup{A} \to G$.
Its computation rules say that $\bar{f}\circ \eta \jdeq f$, and that $\bar f$ is a group homomorphism.
Thus, $(\blank\circ \eta) : \hom_{\mathrm{Group}}(\freegroup{A},G) \to (A\to G)$ has a right inverse.
It is straightforward to use the induction principle of $\freegroup{A}$ to show that this is also a left inverse.
\end{proof}
\index{acceptance}
It is worth taking a step back to consider what we have just done.
We have proven that the free group on any set exists \emph{without} giving an explicit construction of it.
Essentially all we had to do was write down the universal property that it should satisfy.
In set theory, we could achieve a similar result by appealing to black boxes such as the adjoint functor theorem\index{adjoint!functor theorem}; type theory builds such constructions into the foundations of mathematics.
Of course, it is sometimes also useful to have a concrete description of free algebraic structures.
In the case of free groups, we can provide one, using quotients.
Consider $\lst{A+A}$, where in $A+A$ we write $\inl(a)$ as $a$, and $\inr(a)$ as $\hat{a}$ (intended to stand for the formal inverse of $a$).
The elements of $\lst{A+A}$ are \emph{words} for the free group on $A$.
\begin{thm}
Let $A$ be a set, and let $\freegroupx{A}$ be the set-quotient of $\lst{A+A}$ by the following relations.
\begin{align*}
(\dots,a_1,a_2,\widehat{a_2},a_3,\dots) &=
(\dots,a_1,a_3,\dots)\\
(\dots,a_1,\widehat{a_2},a_2,a_3,\dots) &=
(\dots,a_1,a_3,\dots).
\end{align*}
Then $\freegroupx{A}$ is also the free group on the set $A$.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
First we show that $\freegroupx{A}$ is a group.
We have seen that $\lst{A+A}$ is a monoid; we claim that the monoid structure descends to the quotient.
We define $\freegroupx{A} \times \freegroupx{A} \to \freegroupx{A}$ by double quotient recursion; it suffices to check that the equivalence relation generated by the given relations is preserved by concatenation of lists.
Similarly, we prove the associativity and unit laws by quotient induction.
In order to define inverses in $\freegroupx{A}$, we first define $\mathsf{reverse}:\lst B\to\lst B$ by recursion on lists:
\begin{align*}
\mathsf{reverse}(\nil) &\defeq \nil,\\
\mathsf{reverse}(\cons(b,\ell))&\defeq \mathsf{reverse}(\ell)\cdot \cons(b,\nil).
\end{align*}
Now we define $i:\freegroupx{A}\to \freegroupx{A}$ by quotient recursion, acting on a list $\ell:\lst{A+A}$ by switching the two copies of $A$ and reversing the list.
This preserves the relations, hence descends to the quotient.
And we can prove that $i(x) \cdot x = e$ for $x:\freegroupx{A}$ by induction.
First, quotient induction allows us to assume $x$ comes from $\ell:\lst{A+A}$, and then we can do list induction; if we write $q:\lst{A+A}\to \freegroupx{A}$ for the quotient map, the cases are
\begin{align*}
i(q(\nil)) \ct q(\nil) &= q(\nil) \ct q(\nil)\\
&= q(\nil)\\
i(q(\cons(a,\ell))) \ct q(\cons(a,\ell)) &= i(q(\ell)) \ct q(\cons(\hat{a},\nil)) \ct q(\cons(a,\ell))\\
&= i(q(\ell)) \ct q(\cons(\hat{a},\cons(a,\ell)))\\
&= i(q(\ell)) \ct q(\ell)\\
&= q(\nil). \tag{by the inductive hypothesis}
\end{align*}
(We have omitted a number of fairly evident lemmas about the behavior of concatenation of lists, etc.)
This completes the proof that $\freegroupx{A}$ is a group.
Now if $G$ is any group with a function $f:A\to G$, we can define $A+A\to G$ to be $f$ on the first copy of $A$ and $f$ composed with the inversion map of $G$ on the second copy.
Now the fact that $G$ is a monoid yields a monoid homomorphism $\lst{A+A} \to G$.
And since $G$ is a group, this map respects the relations, hence descends to a map $\freegroupx{A}\to G$.
It is straightforward to prove that this is a group homomorphism, and the unique one which restricts to $f$ on $A$.
\end{proof}
\index{monoid|)}%
If $A$ has decidable equality\index{decidable!equality} (such as if we assume excluded middle), then the quotient defining $\freegroupx{A}$ can be obtained from an idempotent as in \cref{lem:quotient-when-canonical-representatives}.
We define a word, which we recall is just an element of $\lst{A+A}$, to be \define{reduced}
\indexdef{reduced word in a free group}
if it contains no adjacent pairs of the form $(a,\hat a)$ or $(\hat a,a)$.
When $A$ has decidable equality, it is straightforward to define the \define{reduction}
\index{reduction!of a word in a free group}%
of a word, which is an idempotent generating the appropriate quotient; we leave the details to the reader.
If $A\defeq \unit$, which has decidable equality, a reduced word must consist either entirely of $\ttt$'s or entirely of $\hat{\ttt}$'s.
Thus, the free group on $\unit$ is equivalent to the integers \Z, with $0$ corresponding to $\nil$, the positive integer $n$ corresponding to a reduced word of $n$ $\ttt$'s, and the negative integer $(-n)$ corresponding to a reduced word of $n$ $\hat{\ttt}$'s.
One could also, of course, show directly that \Z has the universal property of $\freegroup{\unit}$.
\begin{rmk}\label{thm:freegroup-nonset}
Nowhere in the construction of $\freegroup{A}$ and $\freegroupx{A}$, and the proof of their universal properties, did we use the assumption that $A$ is a set.
Thus, we can actually construct the free group on an arbitrary type.
Comparing universal properties, we conclude that $\eqv{\freegroup{A}}{\freegroup{\trunc0A}}$.
\end{rmk}
\index{group!free|)}%
\index{algebra!colimits of}%
We can also use higher inductive types to construct colimits of algebraic objects.
For instance, suppose $f:G\to H$ and $g:G\to K$ are group homomorphisms.
Their pushout in the category of groups, called the \define{amalgamated free product}
\indexdef{amalgamated free product}%
\indexdef{free!product!amalgamated}%
$H *_G K$, can be constructed as the higher inductive type generated by
\begin{itemize}
\item Functions $h:H\to H *_G K$ and $k:K\to H *_G K$.
\item The operations and axioms of a group, as in the definition of $\freegroup{A}$.
\item Axioms asserting that $h$ and $k$ are group homomorphisms.
\item For $x:G$, we have $h(f(x)) = k(g(x))$.
\item The $0$-truncation constructor.
\end{itemize}
On the other hand, it can also be constructed explicitly, as the set-quotient of $\lst{H+K}$ by the following relations:
\begin{align*}
(\dots, x_1, x_2, \dots) &= (\dots, x_1\cdot x_2, \dots)
& &\text{for $x_1,x_2:H$}\\
(\dots, y_1, y_2, \dots) &= (\dots, y_1\cdot y_2, \dots)
& &\text{for $y_1,y_2:K$}\\
(\dots, 1_G, \dots) &= (\dots, \dots) && \\
(\dots, 1_H, \dots) &= (\dots, \dots) && \\
(\dots, f(x), \dots) &= (\dots, g(x), \dots)
& &\text{for $x:G$.}
\end{align*}
We leave the proofs to the reader.
In the special case that $G$ is the trivial group, the last relation is unnecessary, and we obtain the \define{free product}
\indexdef{free!product}%
$H*K$, the coproduct in the category of groups.
(This notation unfortunately clashes with that for the \emph{join} of types, as in \cref{sec:colimits}, but context generally disambiguates.)
\index{presentation!of a group}%
Note that groups defined by \emph{presentations} can be regarded as a special case of colimits.
Suppose given a set (or more generally a type) $A$, and a pair of functions $R\rightrightarrows \freegroup{A}$.
We regard $R$ as the type of ``relations'', with the two functions assigning to each relation the two words that it sets equal.
For instance, in the presentation $\langle a \mid a^2 = e \rangle$ we would have $A\defeq \unit$ and $R\defeq \unit$, with the two morphisms $R\rightrightarrows \freegroup{A}$ picking out the list $(a,a)$ and the empty list $\nil$, respectively.
Then by the universal property of free groups, we obtain a pair of group homomorphisms $\freegroup{R} \rightrightarrows \freegroup{A}$.
Their coequalizer in the category of groups, which can be built just like the pushout, is the group \emph{presented} by this presentation.
\mentalpause
Note that all these sorts of construction only apply to \emph{algebraic} theories,\index{theory!algebraic} which are theories whose axioms are (universally quantified) equations referring to variables, constants, and operations from a given signature\index{signature!of an algebraic theory}.
They can be modified to apply also to what are called \emph{essentially algebraic theories}:\index{theory!essentially algebraic} those whose operations are partially defined on a domain specified by equalities between previous operations.
They do not apply, for instance, to the theory of fields, in which the ``inversion'' operation is partially defined on a domain $\setof{x | x \mathrel{\#} 0}$ specified by an \emph{apartness} $\#$ between previous operations, see \cref{RD-inverse-apart-0}.
And indeed, it is well-known that the category of fields has no initial object.
\index{initial!field}%
On the other hand, these constructions do apply just as well to \emph{infinitary}\index{infinitary!algebraic theory} algebraic theories, whose ``operations'' can take infinitely many inputs.
In such cases, there may not be any presentation of free algebras or colimits of algebras as a simple quotient, unless we assume the axiom of choice.
This means that higher inductive types represent a significant strengthening of constructive type theory (not necessarily in terms of proof-theoretic strength, but in terms of practical power), and indeed are stronger in some ways than Zermelo--Fraenkel\index{set theory!Zermelo--Fraenkel} set theory (without choice)~\cite{blass:freealg}.
% We will see an example of this in \cref{sec:ordinals}.
\section{The flattening lemma}
\label{sec:flattening}
As we will see in \cref{cha:homotopy}, amazing things happen when we combine higher inductive types with univalence.
The principal way this comes about is that if $W$ is a higher inductive type and \UU is a type universe, then we can define a type family $P:W\to \UU$ by using the recursion principle for $W$.
When we come to the clauses of the recursion principle dealing with the path constructors of $W$, we will need to supply paths in \UU, and this is where univalence comes in.
For example, suppose we have a type $X$ and a self-equivalence $e:\eqv X X$.
Then we can define a type family $P:\Sn^1 \to \UU$ by using $\Sn^1$-recursion:
\begin{equation*}
P(\base) \defeq X
\qquad\text{and}\qquad
\ap P\lloop \defid \ua(e).
\end{equation*}
The type $X$ thus appears as the fiber $P(\base)$ of $P$ over the basepoint.
The self-equivalence $e$ is a little more hidden in $P$, but the following lemma says that it can be extracted by transporting along \lloop.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:transport-is-given}
Given $B:A\to\type$ and $x,y:A$, with a path $p:x=y$ and an equivalence $e:\eqv{B(x)}{B(y)}$ such that $\ap{B}p = \ua(e)$, then for any $u:B(x)$ we have
\begin{align*}
\transfib{B}{p}{u} &= e(u).
\end{align*}
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Applying \cref{thm:transport-is-ap}, we have
\begin{align*}
\transfib{B}{p}{u} &= \idtoeqv(\ap{B}p)(u)\\
&= \idtoeqv(\ua(e))(u)\\
&= e(u).\qedhere
\end{align*}
\end{proof}
We have seen type families defined by recursion before: in \cref{sec:compute-coprod,sec:compute-nat} we used them to characterize the identity types of (ordinary) inductive types.
In \cref{cha:homotopy}, we will use similar ideas to calculate homotopy groups of higher inductive types.
In this section, we describe a general lemma about type families of this sort which will be useful later on.
We call it the \define{flattening lemma}:
\indexdef{flattening lemma}%
\indexdef{lemma!flattening}%
it says that if $P:W\to\UU$ is defined recursively as above, then its total space $\sm{x:W} P(x)$ is equivalent to a ``flattened'' higher inductive type, whose constructors may be deduced from those of $W$ and the definition of $P$.
(From a category-theoretic point of view, $\sm{x:W} P(x)$ is the ``Grothendieck\index{Grothendieck construction} construction'' of $P$, and the flattening lemma expresses its universal property as a ``lax\index{lax colimit} colimit''. Although because types in homotopy type theory (like $W$) correspond categorically to $\infty$-groupoids (since all paths are invertible), in this case the lax colimit is the same as a pseudo colimit.)
We prove here one general case of the flattening lemma, which directly implies many particular cases and suggests the method to prove others.
Suppose we have $A,B:\type$ and $f,g:B\to{}A$, and that the higher inductive type $W$ is generated by
\begin{itemize}
\item $\cc:A\to{}W$ and
\item $\pp:\prd{b:B} (\cc(f(b))=_W\cc(g(b)))$.
\end{itemize}
Thus, $W$ is the \define{(homotopy) coequalizer}
\indexdef{coequalizer}%
\indexdef{type!coequalizer}%
of $f$ and $g$.
Using binary sums (coproducts) and dependent sums ($\Sigma$-types), a lot of interesting nonrecursive higher
inductive types can be represented in this form. All point constructors have to
be bundled in the type $A$ and all path constructors in the type $B$.
For instance:
\begin{itemize}
\item The circle $\Sn^1$ can be represented by taking $A\defeq \unit$ and $B\defeq \unit$, with $f$ and $g$ the identity.
\item The pushout of $j:X\to Y$ and $k:X\to Z$ can be represented by taking $A\defeq Y+Z$ and $B\defeq X$, with $f\defeq \inl \circ j$ and $g\defeq \inr\circ k$.
\end{itemize}
Now suppose in addition that
\begin{itemize}
\item $C:A\to\type$ is a family of types over $A$, and
\item $D:\prd{b:B}\eqv{C(f(b))}{C(g(b))}$ is a family of equivalences over $B$.
\end{itemize}
Define a type family $P : W\to\type$ recursively by
\begin{align*}
P(\cc(a)) &\defeq C(a)\\
\map{P}{\pp(b)} &\defid \ua(D(b)).
\end{align*}
Let \Wtil be the higher inductive type generated by
\begin{itemize}
\item $\cct:\prd{a:A} C(a) \to \Wtil$ and
\item $\ppt:\prd{b:B}{y:C(f(b))} (\cct(f(b),y)=_{\Wtil}\cct(g(b),D(b)(y)))$.
\end{itemize}
The flattening lemma is:
\begin{lem}[Flattening lemma]\label{thm:flattening}
In the above situation, we have
\[ \eqvspaced{\Parens{\sm{x:W} P(x)}}{\widetilde{W}}. \]
\end{lem}
\index{universal!property!of dependent pair type}%
As remarked above, this equivalence can be seen as expressing the universal property of $\sm{x:W} P(x)$ as a ``lax\index{lax colimit} colimit'' of $P$ over $W$.
It can also be seen as part of the \emph{stability and descent} property of colimits, which characterizes higher toposes.%
\index{.infinity1-topos@$(\infty,1)$-topos}%
\index{stability!and descent}%
The proof of \cref{thm:flattening} occupies the rest of this section.
It is somewhat technical and can be skipped on a first reading.
But it is also a good example of ``proof-relevant mathematics'',
\index{mathematics!proof-relevant}%
so we recommend it on a second reading.
The idea is to show that $\sm{x:W} P(x)$ has the same universal property as \Wtil.
We begin by showing that it comes with analogues of the constructors $\cct$ and $\ppt$.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:flattening-cp}
There are functions
\begin{itemize}
\item $\cct':\prd{a:A} C(a) \to \sm{x:W} P(x)$ and
\item $\ppt':\prd{b:B}{y:C(f(b))} \Big(\cct'(f(b),y)=_{\sm{w:W}P(w)}\cct'(g(b),D(b)(y))\Big)$.
\end{itemize}
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
The first is easy; define $\cct'(a,x) \defeq (\cc(a),x)$ and note that by definition $P(\cc(a))\jdeq C(a)$.
For the second, suppose given $b:B$ and $y:C(f(b))$; we must give an equality
\[ (\cc(f(b)),y) = (\cc(g(b)),D(b)(y)). \]
Since we have $\pp(b):\cc(f(b))=\cc(g(b))$, by equalities in $\Sigma$-types it suffices to give an equality $\trans{\pp(b)}{y} = D(b)(y)$.
But this follows from \cref{thm:transport-is-given}, using the definition of $P$.
\end{proof}
Now the following lemma says to define a section of a type family over $\sm{w:W} P(w)$, it suffices to give analogous data as in the case of \Wtil.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:flattening-rect}
Suppose $Q:\big(\sm{x:W} P(x)\big) \to \type$ is a type family and that we have
\begin{itemize}
\item $c : \prd{a:A}{x:C(a)} Q(\cct'(a,x))$ and
\item $p : \prd{b:B}{y:C(f(b))} \Big(\trans{\ppt'(b,y)}{c(f(b),y)} = c(g(b),D(b)(y))\Big)$. %_{Q(\cct'(g(b),D(b)(y)))}
\end{itemize}
Then there exists $k:\prd{z:\sm{w:W} P(w)} Q(z)$ such that $k(\cct'(a,x)) \jdeq c(a,x)$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Suppose given $w:W$ and $x:P(w)$; we must produce an element $k(w,x):Q(w,x)$.
By induction on $w$, it suffices to consider two cases.
When $w\jdeq \cc(a)$, then we have $x:C(a)$, and so $c(a,x):Q(\cc(a),x)$ as desired.
(This part of the definition also ensures that the stated computational rule holds.)
Now we must show that this definition is preserved by transporting along $\pp(b)$ for any $b:B$.
Since what we are defining, for all $w:W$, is a function of type $\prd{x:P(w)} Q(w,x)$, by \cref{thm:dpath-forall} it suffices to show that for any $y:C(f(b))$, we have
\[ \transfib{Q}{\pairpath(\pp(b),\refl{\trans{\pp(b)}{y}})}{c(f(b),y)} = c(g(b),\trans{\pp(b)}{y}). \]
Let $q:\trans{\pp(b)}{y} = D(b)(y)$ be the path obtained from \cref{thm:transport-is-given}.
Then we have
\begin{align}
c(g(b),\trans{\pp(b)}{y})
&= \transfib{x\mapsto Q(\cct'(g(b),x))}{\opp{q}}{c(g(b),D(b)(y))}
\tag{by $\opp{\apdfunc{x\mapsto c(g(b),x)}(\opp q)}$} \\
&= \transfib{Q}{\apfunc{x\mapsto \cct'(g(b),x)}(\opp q)}{c(g(b),D(b)(y))}
\tag{by \cref{thm:transport-compose}}.
\end{align}
Thus, it suffices to show
\begin{multline*}
\Transfib{Q}{\pairpath(\pp(b),\refl{\trans{\pp(b)}{y}})}{c(f(b),y)} = {}\\
\Transfib{Q}{\apfunc{x\mapsto \cct'(g(b),x)}(\opp q)}{c(g(b),D(b)(y))}.
\end{multline*}
Moving the right-hand transport to the other side, and combining two transports, this is equivalent to
%
\begin{narrowmultline*}
\Transfib{Q}{\pairpath(\pp(b),\refl{\trans{\pp(b)}{y}}) \ct
\apfunc{x\mapsto \cct'(g(b),x)}(q)}{c(f(b),y)} =
\narrowbreak
c(g(b),D(b)(y)).
\end{narrowmultline*}
%
However, we have
\begin{multline*}
\pairpath(\pp(b),\refl{\trans{\pp(b)}{y}}) \ct \apfunc{x\mapsto \cct'(g(b),x)}(q)
= {} \\
\pairpath(\pp(b),\refl{\trans{\pp(b)}{y}}) \ct \pairpath(\refl{\cc(g(b))},q)
= \pairpath(\pp(b),q)
= \ppt'(b,y)
\end{multline*}
so the construction is completed by the assumption $p(b,y)$ of type
\[ \transfib{Q}{\ppt'(b,y)}{c(f(b),y)} = c(g(b),D(b)(y)). \qedhere \]
\end{proof}
\cref{thm:flattening-rect} \emph{almost} gives $\sm{w:W}P(w)$ the same induction principle as \Wtil.
The missing bit is the equality $\apdfunc{k}(\ppt'(b,y)) = p(b,y)$.
In order to prove this, we would need to analyze the proof of \cref{thm:flattening-rect}, which of course is the definition of $k$.
It should be possible to do this, but it turns out that we only need the computation rule for the non-dependent recursion principle.
Thus, we now give a somewhat simpler direct construction of the recursor, and a proof of its computation rule.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:flattening-rectnd}
Suppose $Q$ is a type and that we have
\begin{itemize}
\item $c : \prd{a:A} C(a) \to Q$ and
\item $p : \prd{b:B}{y:C(f(b))} \Big(c(f(b),y) =_Q c(g(b),D(b)(y))\Big)$.
\end{itemize}
Then there exists $k:\big(\sm{w:W} P(w)\big) \to Q$ such that $k(\cct'(a,x)) \jdeq c(a,x)$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
As in \cref{thm:flattening-rect}, we define $k(w,x)$ by induction on $w:W$.
When $w\jdeq \cc(a)$, we define $k(\cc(a),x)\defeq c(a,x)$.
Now by \cref{thm:dpath-arrow}, it suffices to consider, for $b:B$ and $y:C(f(b))$, the composite path
\begin{equation}\label{eq:flattening-rectnd}
\transfib{x\mapsto Q}{\pp(b)}{c(f(b),y)}
= c(g(b),\transfib{P}{\pp(b)}{y})
\end{equation}
%
defined as the composition
%
\begin{align}
\transfib{x\mapsto Q}{\pp(b)}{c(f(b),y)}
&= c(f(b),y) \tag{by \cref{thm:trans-trivial}}\\
&= c(g(b),D(b)(y)) \tag{by $p(b,y)$}\\
&= c(g(b),\transfib{P}{\pp(b)}{y}). \tag{by \cref{thm:transport-is-given}}
\end{align}
The computation rule $k(\cct'(a,x)) \jdeq c(a,x)$ follows by definition, as before.
\end{proof}
For the second computation rule, we need the following lemma.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:ap-sigma-rect-path-pair}
Let $Y:X\to\type$ be a type family and let $k:(\sm{x:X}Y(x)) \to Z$ be defined componentwise by $k(x,y) \defeq d(x)(y)$ for a curried function $d:\prd{x:X} Y(x)\to Z$.
Then for any $s:\id[X]{x_1}{x_2}$ and any $y_1:Y(x_1)$ and $y_2:Y(x_2)$ with a path $r:\trans{s}{y_1}=y_2$, the path
\[\apfunc k (\pairpath(s,r)) :k(x_1,y_1) = k(x_2,y_2)\]
is equal to the composite
\begin{align}
k(x_1,y_1)
&\jdeq d(x_1)(y_1) \notag\\
&= \transfib{x\mapsto Z}{s}{d(x_1)(y_1)}
\tag{by $\opp{\text{(\cref{thm:trans-trivial})}}$}\\
&= \transfib{x\mapsto Z}{s}{d(x_1)(\trans{\opp s}{\trans{s}{y_1}})}
\notag\\
&= \big(\transfib{x\mapsto (Y(x)\to Z)}{s}{d(x_1)}\big)(\trans{s}{y_1})
\tag{by~\eqref{eq:transport-arrow}}\\
&= d(x_2)(\trans{s}{y_1})
\tag{by $\happly(\apdfunc{d}(s))(\trans{s}{y_1}$}\\
&= d(x_2)(y_2)
\tag{by $\apfunc{d(x_2)}(r)$}\\
&\jdeq k(x_2,y_2).
\notag
\end{align}
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
After path induction on $s$ and $r$, both equalities reduce to reflexivities.
\end{proof}
At first it may seem surprising that \cref{thm:ap-sigma-rect-path-pair} has such a complicated statement, while it can be proven so simply.
The reason for the complication is to ensure that the statement is well-typed: $\apfunc k (\pairpath(s,r))$ and the composite path it is claimed to be equal to must both have the same start and end points.
Once we have managed this, the proof is easy by path induction.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:flattening-rectnd-beta-ppt}
In the situation of \cref{thm:flattening-rectnd}, we have $\apfunc{k}(\ppt'(b,y)) = p(b,y)$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Recall that $\ppt'(b,y) \defeq \pairpath(\pp(b),q)$ where $q:\trans{\pp(b)}{y} = D(b)(y)$ comes from \cref{thm:transport-is-given}.
Thus, since $k$ is defined componentwise, we may compute $\apfunc{k}(\ppt'(b,y))$ by \cref{thm:ap-sigma-rect-path-pair}, with
\begin{align*}
x_1 &\defeq \cc(f(b)) & y_1 &\defeq y\\
x_2 &\defeq \cc(g(b)) & y_2 &\defeq D(b)(y)\\
s &\defeq \pp(b) & r &\defeq q.
\end{align*}
The curried function $d:\prd{w:W} P(w) \to Q$ was defined by induction on $w:W$;
to apply \cref{thm:ap-sigma-rect-path-pair} we need to understand $\apfunc{d(x_2)}(r)$ and $\happly(\apdfunc{d}(s),\trans s {y_1})$.
For the first, since $d(\cc(a),x)\jdeq c(a,x)$, we have
\[ \apfunc{d(x_2)}(r) \jdeq \apfunc{c(g(b),-)}(q). \]
For the second, the computation rule for the induction principle of $W$ tells us that $\apdfunc{d}(\pp(b))$ is equal to the composite~\eqref{eq:flattening-rectnd}, passed across the equivalence of \cref{thm:dpath-arrow}.
Thus, the computation rule given in \cref{thm:dpath-arrow} implies that $\happly(\apdfunc{d}(\pp(b)),\trans {\pp(b)}{y})$ is equal to the composite
\begin{align}
\big(\trans{\pp(b)}{c(f(b),-)}\big)(\trans {\pp(b)}{y})
&= \trans{\pp(b)}{c(f(b),\trans{\opp {\pp(b)}}{\trans {\pp(b)}{y}})}
\tag{by~\eqref{eq:transport-arrow}}\\
&= \trans{\pp(b)}{c(f(b),y)}
\notag \\
&= c(f(b),y)
\tag{by \cref{thm:trans-trivial}}\\
&= c(f(b),D(b)(y))
\tag{by $p(b,y)$}\\
&= c(f(b),\trans{\pp(b)}{y}).
\tag{by $\opp{\apfunc{c(g(b),-)}(q)}$}
\end{align}
Finally, substituting these values of $\apfunc{d(x_2)}(r)$ and $\happly(\apdfunc{d}(s),\trans s {y_1})$ into \cref{thm:ap-sigma-rect-path-pair}, we see that all the paths cancel out in pairs, leaving only $p(b,y)$.
\end{proof}
Now we are finally ready to prove the flattening lemma.
\begin{proof}[Proof of \cref{thm:flattening}]
We define $h:\Wtil \to \sm{w:W}P(w)$ by using the recursion principle for \Wtil, with $\cct'$ and $\ppt'$ as input data.
Similarly, we define $k:(\sm{w:W}P(w)) \to \Wtil$ by using the recursion principle of \cref{thm:flattening-rectnd}, with $\cct$ and $\ppt$ as input data.
On the one hand, we must show that for any $z:\Wtil$, we have $k(h(z))=z$.
By induction on $z$, it suffices to consider the two constructors of \Wtil.
But we have
\[k(h(\cct(a,x))) \jdeq k(\cct'(a,x)) \jdeq \cct(a,x)\]
by definition, while similarly
\[\ap k{\ap h{\ppt(b,y)}} = \ap k{\ppt'(b,y)} = \ppt(b,y) \]
using the propositional computation rule for $\Wtil$ and \cref{thm:flattening-rectnd-beta-ppt}.
On the other hand, we must show that for any $z:\sm{w:W}P(w)$, we have $h(k(z))=z$.
But this is essentially identical, using \cref{thm:flattening-rect} for ``induction on $\sm{w:W}P(w)$'' and the same computation rules.
\end{proof}
\section{The general syntax of higher inductive definitions}
\label{sec:naturality}
In \cref{sec:strictly-positive}, we discussed the conditions on a putative ``inductive definition'' which make it acceptable, namely that all inductive occurrences of the type in its constructors are ``strictly positive''.\index{strict!positivity}
In this section, we say something about the additional conditions required for \emph{higher} inductive definitions.
Finding a general syntactic description of valid higher inductive definitions is an area of current research, and all of the solutions proposed to date are somewhat technical in nature; thus we only give a general description and not a precise definition.
Fortunately, the corner cases never seem to arise in practice.
Like an ordinary inductive definition, a higher inductive definition is specified by a list of \emph{constructors}, each of which is a (dependent) function.
For simplicity, we may require the inputs of each constructor to satisfy the same condition as the inputs for constructors of ordinary inductive types.
In particular, they may contain the type being defined only strictly positively.
Note that this excludes definitions such as the $0$-truncation as presented in \cref{sec:hittruncations}, where the input of a constructor contains not only the inductive type being defined, but its identity type as well.
It may be possible to extend the syntax to allow such definitions; but also, in \cref{sec:truncations} we will give a different construction of the $0$-truncation whose constructors do satisfy the more restrictive condition.
The only difference between an ordinary inductive definition and a higher one, then, is that the \emph{output} type of a constructor may be, not the type being defined ($W$, say), but some identity type of it, such as $\id[W]uv$, or more generally an iterated identity type such as $\id[({\id[W]uv})]pq$.
Thus, when we give a higher inductive definition, we have to specify not only the inputs of each constructor, but the expressions $u$ and $v$ (or $u$, $v$, $p$, and $q$, etc.)\ which determine the source\index{source!of a path constructor} and target\index{target!of a path constructor} of the path being constructed.
Importantly, these expressions may refer to \emph{other} constructors of $W$.
For instance, in the definition of $\Sn^1$, the constructor $\lloop$ has both $u$ and $v$ being $\base$, the previous constructor.
To make sense of this, we require the constructors of a higher inductive type to be specified \emph{in order}, and we allow the source and target expressions $u$ and $v$ of each constructor to refer to previous constructors, but not later ones.
(Of course, in practice the constructors of any inductive definition are written down in some order, but for ordinary inductive types that order is irrelevant.)
Note that this order is not necessarily the order of ``dimension'': in principle, a 1-dimensional path constructor could refer to a 2-dimensional one and hence need to come after it.
However, we have not given the 0-dimensional constructors (point constructors) any way to refer to previous constructors, so they might as well all come first.
And if we use the hub-and-spoke construction (\cref{sec:hubs-spokes}) to reduce all constructors to points and 1-paths, then we might assume that all point constructors come first, followed by all 1-path constructors --- but the order among the 1-path constructors continues to matter.
The remaining question is, what sort of expressions can $u$ and $v$ be?
We might hope that they could be any expression at all involving the previous constructors.
However, the following example shows that a naive approach to this idea does not work.
\begin{eg}\label{eg:unnatural-hit}
Consider a family of functions $f:\prd{X:\type} (X\to X)$.
Of course, $f_X$ might be just $\idfunc[X]$ for all $X$, but other such $f$s may also exist.
For instance, nothing prevents $f_{\bool}:\bool\to\bool$ from being the nonidentity automorphism\index{automorphism!of 2, nonidentity@of $\bool$, nonidentity} (see \cref{ex:unnatural-endomorphisms}).
Now suppose that we attempt to define a higher inductive type $K$ generated by:
\begin{itemize}
\item two elements $a,b:K$, and
\item a path $\sigma:f_K(a)=f_K(b)$.
\end{itemize}
What would the induction principle for $K$ say?
We would assume a type family $P:K\to\type$, and of course we would need $x:P(a)$ and $y:P(b)$.
The remaining datum should be a dependent path in $P$ living over $\sigma$, which must therefore connect some element of $P(f_K(a))$ to some element of $P(f_K(b))$.
But what could these elements possibly be?
We know that $P(a)$ and $P(b)$ are inhabited by $x$ and $y$, respectively, but this tells us nothing about $P(f_K(a))$ and $P(f_K(b))$.
\end{eg}
Clearly some condition on $u$ and $v$ is required in order for the definition to be sensible.
It seems that, just as the domain of each constructor is required to be (among other things) a \emph{covariant functor}, the appropriate condition on the expressions $u$ and $v$ is that they define \emph{natural transformations}.
Making precise sense of this requirement is beyond the scope of this book, but informally it means that $u$ and $v$ must only involve operations which are preserved by all functions between types.
For instance, it is permissible for $u$ and $v$ to refer to concatenation of paths, as in the case of the final constructor of the torus in \cref{sec:cell-complexes}, since all functions in type theory preserve path concatenation (up to homotopy).
However, it is not permissible for them to refer to an operation like the function $f$ in \cref{eg:unnatural-hit}, which is not necessarily natural: there might be some function $g:X\to Y$ such that $f_Y \circ g \neq g\circ f_X$.
(Univalence implies that $f_X$ must be natural with respect to all \emph{equivalences}, but not necessarily with respect to functions that are not equivalences.)
The intuition of naturality supplies only a rough guide for when a higher inductive definition is permissible.
Even if it were possible to give a precise specification of permissible forms of such definitions in this book, such a specification would probably be out of date quickly, as new extensions to the theory are constantly being explored.
For instance, the presentation of $n$-spheres in terms of ``dependent $n$-loops\index{loop!dependent n-@dependent $n$-}'' referred to in \cref{sec:circle}, and the ``higher inductive-recursive definitions'' used in \cref{cha:real-numbers}, were innovations introduced while this book was being written.
We encourage the reader to experiment --- with caution.
\sectionNotes
The general idea of higher inductive types was conceived in discussions between Andrej Bauer, Peter Lumsdaine, Mike Shulman, and Michael Warren at the Oberwolfach meeting in 2011, although there are some suggestions of some special cases in earlier work. Subsequently, Guillaume Brunerie and Dan Licata contributed substantially to the general theory, especially by finding convenient ways to represent them in computer proof assistants
\index{proof!assistant}
and do homotopy theory with them (see \cref{cha:homotopy}).
A general discussion of the syntax of higher inductive types, and their semantics in higher-categorical models, appears in~\cite{ls:hits}.
As with ordinary inductive types, models of higher inductive types can be constructed by transfinite iterative processes; a slogan is that ordinary inductive types describe \emph{free} monads while higher inductive types describe \emph{presentations} of monads.\index{monad}
The introduction of path constructors also involves the model-category-theoretic equivalence between ``right homotopies'' (defined using path spaces) and ``left homotopies'' (defined using cylinders) --- the fact that this equivalence is generally only up to homotopy provides a semantic reason to prefer propositional computation rules for path constructors.
Another (temporary) reason for this preference comes from the limitations of existing computer implementations.
Proof assistants\index{proof!assistant} like \Coq and \Agda have ordinary inductive types built in, but not yet higher inductive types.
We can of course introduce them by assuming lots of axioms, but this results in only propositional computation rules.
However, there is a trick due to Dan Licata which implements higher inductive types using private data types; this yields judgmental rules for point constructors but not path constructors.
The type-theoretic description of higher spheres using loop spaces and suspensions in \cref{sec:circle,sec:suspension} is largely due to Brunerie and Licata; Hou has given a type-theoretic version of the alternative description that uses $n$-dimensional paths\index{path!n-@$n$-}.
The reduction of higher paths to 1-dimensional paths with hubs and spokes (\cref{sec:hubs-spokes}) is due to Lumsdaine and Shulman.
The description of truncation as a higher inductive type is due to Lumsdaine; the $(-1)$-truncation is closely related to the ``bracket types'' of~\cite{ab:bracket-types}.
The flattening lemma was first formulated in generality by Brunerie.
\index{set-quotient}
Quotient types are unproblematic in extensional type theory, such as \NuPRL~\cite{constable+86nuprl-book}.
They are often added by passing to an extended system of setoids.\index{setoid}
However, quotients are a trickier issue in intensional type theory (the starting point for homotopy type theory), because one cannot simply add new propositional equalities without specifying how they are to behave. Some solutions to this problem have been studied~\cite{hofmann:thesis,Altenkirch1999,altenkirch+07ott}, and several different notions of quotient types have been considered. The construction of set-quotients using higher-inductives provides an argument for our particular approach (which is similar to some that have previously been considered), because it arises as an instance of a general mechanism. Our construction does not yet provide a new solution to all the computational problems related to quotients, since we still lack a good computational understanding of higher inductive types in general---but it does mean that ongoing work on the computational interpretation of higher inductives applies to the quotients as well. The construction of quotients in terms of equivalence classes is, of
course, a standard set-theoretic idea, and a well-known aspect of elementary topos theory; its use in type theory (which depends on the univalence axiom, at least for mere propositions) was proposed by Voevodsky. The fact that quotient types in intensional type theory imply function extensionality was proved by~\cite{hofmann:thesis}, inspired by the work of~\cite{carboni} on exact completions; \cref{thm:interval-funext} is an adaptation of such arguments.
\sectionExercises
\begin{ex}\label{ex:torus}
Define concatenation of dependent paths, prove that application of dependent functions preserves concatenation, and write out the precise induction principle for the torus $T^2$ with its computation rules.\index{torus}
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:suspS1}
Prove that $\eqv{\susp \Sn^1}{\Sn^2}$, using the explicit definition of $\Sn^2$ in terms of $\base$ and $\surf$ given in \cref{sec:circle}.
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:torus-s1-times-s1}
Prove that the torus $T^2$ as defined in \cref{sec:cell-complexes} is equivalent to $\Sn^1\times \Sn^1$.
(Warning: the path algebra for this is rather difficult.)
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:nspheres}
Define dependent $n$-loops\index{loop!dependent n-@dependent $n$-} and the action of dependent functions on $n$-loops, and write down the induction principle for the $n$-spheres as defined at the end of \cref{sec:circle}.
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:susp-spheres-equiv}
Prove that $\eqv{\susp \Sn^n}{\Sn^{n+1}}$, using the definition of $\Sn^n$ in terms of $\Omega^n$ from \cref{sec:circle}.
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:spheres-make-U-not-2-type}
Prove that if the type $\Sn^2$ belongs to some universe \type, then \type is not a 2-type.
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:monoid-eq-prop}
Prove that if $G$ is a monoid and $x:G$, then $\sm{y:G}((x\cdot y = e) \times (y\cdot x =e))$ is a mere proposition.
Conclude, using the principle of unique choice (\cref{cor:UC}), that it would be equivalent to define a group to be a monoid such that for every $x:G$, there merely exists a $y:G$ such that $x\cdot y = e$ and $y\cdot x=e$.
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:free-monoid}
Prove that if $A$ is a set, then $\lst A$ is a monoid.
Then complete the proof of \cref{thm:free-monoid}.\index{monoid!free}
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:unnatural-endomorphisms}
Assuming \LEM{}, construct a family $f:\prd{X:\type}(X\to X)$ such that $f_\bool:\bool\to\bool$ is the nonidentity automorphism.\index{automorphism!of 2, nonidentity@of $\bool$, nonidentity}
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:funext-from-interval}
Show that the map constructed in \cref{thm:interval-funext} is in fact a quasi-inverse to $\happly$, so that an interval type implies the full function extensionality axiom.
(You may have to use \cref{ex:strong-from-weak-funext}.)
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:susp-lump}
Prove the universal property of suspension:
\[ \Parens{\susp A \to B} \eqvsym \Parens{\sm{b_n : B} \sm{b_s : B} (A \to (b_n = b_s)) } \]
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:alt-integers}
Show that $\eqv{\Z}{\N+\unit+\N}$.
Show that if we were to define $\Z$ as $\N+\unit+\N$, then we could obtain \cref{thm:sign-induction} with judgmental computation rules.
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:trunc-bool-interval}
Show that we can also prove \cref{thm:interval-funext} by using $\brck \bool$ instead of $\interval$.
\end{ex}
\index{type!higher inductive|)}%
% Local Variables:
% TeX-master: "hott-online"
% End:
|