Datasets:

Modalities:
Text
Languages:
English
Libraries:
Datasets
License:
File size: 180,637 Bytes
afd65d6
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
1001
1002
1003
1004
1005
1006
1007
1008
1009
1010
1011
1012
1013
1014
1015
1016
1017
1018
1019
1020
1021
1022
1023
1024
1025
1026
1027
1028
1029
1030
1031
1032
1033
1034
1035
1036
1037
1038
1039
1040
1041
1042
1043
1044
1045
1046
1047
1048
1049
1050
1051
1052
1053
1054
1055
1056
1057
1058
1059
1060
1061
1062
1063
1064
1065
1066
1067
1068
1069
1070
1071
1072
1073
1074
1075
1076
1077
1078
1079
1080
1081
1082
1083
1084
1085
1086
1087
1088
1089
1090
1091
1092
1093
1094
1095
1096
1097
1098
1099
1100
1101
1102
1103
1104
1105
1106
1107
1108
1109
1110
1111
1112
1113
1114
1115
1116
1117
1118
1119
1120
1121
1122
1123
1124
1125
1126
1127
1128
1129
1130
1131
1132
1133
1134
1135
1136
1137
1138
1139
1140
1141
1142
1143
1144
1145
1146
1147
1148
1149
1150
1151
1152
1153
1154
1155
1156
1157
1158
1159
1160
1161
1162
1163
1164
1165
1166
1167
1168
1169
1170
1171
1172
1173
1174
1175
1176
1177
1178
1179
1180
1181
1182
1183
1184
1185
1186
1187
1188
1189
1190
1191
1192
1193
1194
1195
1196
1197
1198
1199
1200
1201
1202
1203
1204
1205
1206
1207
1208
1209
1210
1211
1212
1213
1214
1215
1216
1217
1218
1219
1220
1221
1222
1223
1224
1225
1226
1227
1228
1229
1230
1231
1232
1233
1234
1235
1236
1237
1238
1239
1240
1241
1242
1243
1244
1245
1246
1247
1248
1249
1250
1251
1252
1253
1254
1255
1256
1257
1258
1259
1260
1261
1262
1263
1264
1265
1266
1267
1268
1269
1270
1271
1272
1273
1274
1275
1276
1277
1278
1279
1280
1281
1282
1283
1284
1285
1286
1287
1288
1289
1290
1291
1292
1293
1294
1295
1296
1297
1298
1299
1300
1301
1302
1303
1304
1305
1306
1307
1308
1309
1310
1311
1312
1313
1314
1315
1316
1317
1318
1319
1320
1321
1322
1323
1324
1325
1326
1327
1328
1329
1330
1331
1332
1333
1334
1335
1336
1337
1338
1339
1340
1341
1342
1343
1344
1345
1346
1347
1348
1349
1350
1351
1352
1353
1354
1355
1356
1357
1358
1359
1360
1361
1362
1363
1364
1365
1366
1367
1368
1369
1370
1371
1372
1373
1374
1375
1376
1377
1378
1379
1380
1381
1382
1383
1384
1385
1386
1387
1388
1389
1390
1391
1392
1393
1394
1395
1396
1397
1398
1399
1400
1401
1402
1403
1404
1405
1406
1407
1408
1409
1410
1411
1412
1413
1414
1415
1416
1417
1418
1419
1420
1421
1422
1423
1424
1425
1426
1427
1428
1429
1430
1431
1432
1433
1434
1435
1436
1437
1438
1439
1440
1441
1442
1443
1444
1445
1446
1447
1448
1449
1450
1451
1452
1453
1454
1455
1456
1457
1458
1459
1460
1461
1462
1463
1464
1465
1466
1467
1468
1469
1470
1471
1472
1473
1474
1475
1476
1477
1478
1479
1480
1481
1482
1483
1484
1485
1486
1487
1488
1489
1490
1491
1492
1493
1494
1495
1496
1497
1498
1499
1500
1501
1502
1503
1504
1505
1506
1507
1508
1509
1510
1511
1512
1513
1514
1515
1516
1517
1518
1519
1520
1521
1522
1523
1524
1525
1526
1527
1528
1529
1530
1531
1532
1533
1534
1535
1536
1537
1538
1539
1540
1541
1542
1543
1544
1545
1546
1547
1548
1549
1550
1551
1552
1553
1554
1555
1556
1557
1558
1559
1560
1561
1562
1563
1564
1565
1566
1567
1568
1569
1570
1571
1572
1573
1574
1575
1576
1577
1578
1579
1580
1581
1582
1583
1584
1585
1586
1587
1588
1589
1590
1591
1592
1593
1594
1595
1596
1597
1598
1599
1600
1601
1602
1603
1604
1605
1606
1607
1608
1609
1610
1611
1612
1613
1614
1615
1616
1617
1618
1619
1620
1621
1622
1623
1624
1625
1626
1627
1628
1629
1630
1631
1632
1633
1634
1635
1636
1637
1638
1639
1640
1641
1642
1643
1644
1645
1646
1647
1648
1649
1650
1651
1652
1653
1654
1655
1656
1657
1658
1659
1660
1661
1662
1663
1664
1665
1666
1667
1668
1669
1670
1671
1672
1673
1674
1675
1676
1677
1678
1679
1680
1681
1682
1683
1684
1685
1686
1687
1688
1689
1690
1691
1692
1693
1694
1695
1696
1697
1698
1699
1700
1701
1702
1703
1704
1705
1706
1707
1708
1709
1710
1711
1712
1713
1714
1715
1716
1717
1718
1719
1720
1721
1722
1723
1724
1725
1726
1727
1728
1729
1730
1731
1732
1733
1734
1735
1736
1737
1738
1739
1740
1741
1742
1743
1744
1745
1746
1747
1748
1749
1750
1751
1752
1753
1754
1755
1756
1757
1758
1759
1760
1761
1762
1763
1764
1765
1766
1767
1768
1769
1770
1771
1772
1773
1774
1775
1776
1777
1778
1779
1780
1781
1782
1783
1784
1785
1786
1787
1788
1789
1790
1791
1792
1793
1794
1795
1796
1797
1798
1799
1800
1801
1802
1803
1804
1805
1806
1807
1808
1809
1810
1811
1812
1813
1814
1815
1816
1817
1818
1819
1820
1821
1822
1823
1824
1825
1826
1827
1828
1829
1830
1831
1832
1833
1834
1835
1836
1837
1838
1839
1840
1841
1842
1843
1844
1845
1846
1847
1848
1849
1850
1851
1852
1853
1854
1855
1856
1857
1858
1859
1860
1861
1862
1863
1864
1865
1866
1867
1868
1869
1870
1871
1872
1873
1874
1875
1876
1877
1878
1879
1880
1881
1882
1883
1884
1885
1886
1887
1888
1889
1890
1891
1892
1893
1894
1895
1896
1897
1898
1899
1900
1901
1902
1903
1904
1905
1906
1907
1908
1909
1910
1911
1912
1913
1914
1915
1916
1917
1918
1919
1920
1921
1922
1923
1924
1925
1926
1927
1928
1929
1930
1931
1932
1933
1934
1935
1936
1937
1938
1939
1940
1941
1942
1943
1944
1945
1946
1947
1948
1949
1950
1951
1952
1953
1954
1955
1956
1957
1958
1959
1960
1961
1962
1963
1964
1965
1966
1967
1968
1969
1970
1971
1972
1973
1974
1975
1976
1977
1978
1979
1980
1981
1982
1983
1984
1985
1986
1987
1988
1989
1990
1991
1992
1993
1994
1995
1996
1997
1998
1999
2000
2001
2002
2003
2004
2005
2006
2007
2008
2009
2010
2011
2012
2013
2014
2015
2016
2017
2018
2019
2020
2021
2022
2023
2024
2025
2026
2027
2028
2029
2030
2031
2032
2033
2034
2035
2036
2037
2038
2039
2040
2041
2042
2043
2044
2045
2046
2047
2048
2049
2050
2051
2052
2053
2054
2055
2056
2057
2058
2059
2060
2061
2062
2063
2064
2065
2066
2067
2068
2069
2070
2071
2072
2073
2074
2075
2076
2077
2078
2079
2080
2081
2082
2083
2084
2085
2086
2087
2088
2089
2090
2091
2092
2093
2094
2095
2096
2097
2098
2099
2100
2101
2102
2103
2104
2105
2106
2107
2108
2109
2110
2111
2112
2113
2114
2115
2116
2117
2118
2119
2120
2121
2122
2123
2124
2125
2126
2127
2128
2129
2130
2131
2132
2133
2134
2135
2136
2137
2138
2139
2140
2141
2142
2143
2144
2145
2146
2147
2148
2149
2150
2151
2152
2153
2154
2155
2156
2157
2158
2159
2160
2161
2162
2163
2164
2165
2166
2167
2168
2169
2170
2171
2172
2173
2174
2175
2176
2177
2178
2179
2180
2181
2182
2183
2184
2185
2186
2187
2188
2189
2190
2191
2192
2193
2194
2195
2196
2197
2198
2199
2200
2201
2202
2203
2204
2205
2206
2207
2208
2209
2210
2211
2212
2213
2214
2215
2216
2217
2218
2219
2220
2221
2222
2223
2224
2225
2226
2227
2228
2229
2230
2231
2232
2233
2234
2235
2236
2237
2238
2239
2240
2241
2242
2243
2244
2245
2246
2247
2248
2249
2250
2251
2252
2253
2254
2255
2256
2257
2258
2259
2260
2261
2262
2263
2264
2265
2266
2267
2268
2269
2270
2271
2272
2273
2274
2275
2276
2277
2278
2279
2280
2281
2282
2283
2284
2285
2286
2287
2288
2289
2290
2291
2292
2293
2294
2295
2296
2297
2298
2299
2300
2301
2302
2303
2304
2305
2306
2307
2308
2309
2310
2311
2312
2313
2314
2315
2316
2317
2318
2319
2320
2321
2322
2323
2324
2325
2326
2327
2328
2329
2330
2331
2332
2333
2334
2335
2336
2337
2338
2339
2340
2341
2342
2343
2344
2345
2346
2347
2348
2349
2350
2351
2352
2353
2354
2355
2356
2357
2358
2359
2360
2361
2362
2363
2364
2365
2366
2367
2368
2369
2370
2371
2372
2373
2374
2375
2376
2377
2378
2379
2380
2381
2382
2383
2384
2385
2386
2387
2388
2389
2390
2391
2392
2393
2394
2395
2396
2397
2398
2399
2400
2401
2402
2403
2404
2405
2406
2407
2408
2409
2410
2411
2412
2413
2414
2415
2416
2417
2418
2419
2420
2421
2422
2423
2424
2425
2426
2427
2428
2429
2430
2431
2432
2433
2434
2435
2436
2437
2438
2439
2440
2441
2442
2443
2444
2445
2446
2447
2448
2449
2450
2451
2452
2453
2454
2455
2456
2457
2458
2459
2460
2461
2462
2463
2464
2465
2466
2467
2468
2469
2470
2471
2472
2473
2474
2475
2476
2477
2478
2479
2480
2481
2482
2483
2484
2485
2486
2487
2488
2489
2490
2491
2492
2493
2494
2495
2496
2497
2498
2499
2500
2501
2502
2503
2504
2505
2506
2507
2508
2509
2510
2511
2512
2513
2514
2515
2516
2517
2518
2519
2520
2521
2522
2523
2524
2525
2526
2527
2528
2529
2530
2531
2532
2533
2534
2535
2536
2537
2538
2539
2540
2541
2542
2543
2544
2545
2546
2547
2548
2549
2550
2551
2552
2553
2554
2555
2556
2557
2558
2559
2560
2561
2562
2563
2564
2565
2566
2567
2568
2569
2570
2571
2572
2573
2574
2575
2576
2577
2578
2579
2580
2581
2582
2583
2584
2585
2586
2587
2588
2589
2590
2591
2592
2593
2594
2595
2596
2597
2598
2599
2600
2601
2602
2603
2604
2605
2606
2607
2608
2609
2610
2611
2612
2613
2614
2615
2616
2617
2618
2619
2620
2621
2622
2623
2624
2625
2626
2627
2628
2629
2630
2631
2632
2633
2634
2635
2636
2637
2638
2639
2640
2641
2642
2643
2644
2645
2646
2647
2648
2649
2650
2651
2652
2653
2654
2655
2656
2657
2658
2659
2660
2661
2662
2663
2664
2665
2666
2667
2668
2669
2670
2671
2672
2673
2674
2675
2676
2677
2678
2679
2680
2681
2682
2683
2684
2685
2686
2687
2688
2689
2690
2691
2692
2693
2694
2695
2696
2697
2698
2699
2700
2701
2702
2703
2704
2705
2706
2707
2708
2709
2710
2711
2712
2713
2714
2715
2716
2717
2718
2719
2720
2721
2722
2723
2724
2725
2726
2727
2728
2729
2730
2731
2732
2733
2734
2735
2736
2737
2738
2739
2740
2741
2742
2743
2744
2745
2746
2747
2748
2749
2750
2751
2752
2753
2754
2755
2756
2757
2758
2759
2760
2761
2762
2763
2764
2765
2766
2767
2768
2769
2770
2771
2772
2773
2774
2775
2776
2777
2778
2779
2780
2781
2782
2783
2784
2785
2786
2787
2788
2789
2790
2791
2792
2793
2794
2795
2796
2797
2798
2799
2800
2801
2802
2803
2804
2805
2806
2807
2808
2809
2810
2811
2812
2813
2814
2815
2816
2817
2818
2819
2820
2821
2822
2823
2824
2825
2826
2827
2828
2829
2830
2831
2832
2833
2834
2835
2836
2837
2838
2839
2840
2841
2842
2843
2844
2845
2846
2847
2848
2849
2850
2851
2852
2853
2854
2855
2856
2857
2858
2859
2860
2861
2862
2863
2864
2865
2866
2867
2868
2869
2870
2871
2872
2873
2874
2875
2876
2877
2878
2879
2880
2881
2882
2883
2884
2885
2886
2887
2888
2889
2890
2891
2892
2893
2894
2895
2896
2897
2898
2899
2900
2901
2902
2903
2904
2905
2906
2907
2908
2909
2910
2911
2912
2913
2914
2915
2916
2917
2918
2919
2920
2921
2922
2923
2924
2925
2926
2927
2928
2929
2930
2931
2932
2933
2934
2935
2936
2937
2938
2939
2940
2941
2942
2943
2944
2945
2946
2947
2948
2949
2950
2951
2952
2953
2954
2955
2956
2957
2958
2959
2960
2961
2962
2963
2964
2965
2966
2967
2968
2969
2970
2971
2972
2973
2974
2975
2976
2977
2978
2979
2980
2981
2982
2983
2984
2985
2986
2987
2988
2989
2990
2991
2992
2993
2994
2995
2996
2997
2998
2999
3000
3001
3002
3003
3004
3005
3006
3007
3008
3009
3010
3011
3012
3013
3014
3015
3016
3017
3018
3019
3020
3021
3022
3023
3024
3025
3026
3027
\documentclass[a4paper]{article}

\def\npart {II}
\def\nterm {Lent}
\def\nyear {2015}
\def\nlecturer {I.\ B.\ Leader}
\def\ncourse {Logic and Set Theory}

\input{header}

\begin{document}
\maketitle
{\small
\noindent\emph{No specific prerequisites.}
\vspace{10pt}

\noindent\textbf{Ordinals and cardinals}\\
Well-orderings and order-types. Examples of countable ordinals. Uncountable ordinals and Hartogs' lemma. Induction and recursion for ordinals. Ordinal arithmetic. Cardinals; the hierarchy of alephs. Cardinal arithmetic.\hspace*{\fill} [5]

\vspace{10pt}
\noindent\textbf{Posets and Zorn's lemma}\\
Partially ordered sets; Hasse diagrams, chains, maximal elements. Lattices and Boolean algebras. Complete and chain-complete posets; fixed-point theorems. The axiom of choice and Zorn's lemma. Applications of Zorn's lemma in mathematics. The well-ordering principle.\hspace*{\fill} [5]

\vspace{10pt}
\noindent\textbf{Propositional logic}\\
The propositional calculus. Semantic and syntactic entailment. The deduction and completeness theorems. Applications: compactness and decidability.\hspace*{\fill} [3]

\vspace{10pt}
\noindent\textbf{Predicate logic}\\
The predicate calculus with equality. Examples of first-order languages and theories. Statement of the completeness theorem; *sketch of proof*. The compactness theorem and the Lowenheim-Skolem theorems. Limitations of first-order logic. Model theory.\hspace*{\fill} [5]

\vspace{10pt}
\noindent\textbf{Set theory}\\ Set theory as a first-order theory; the axioms of ZF set theory. Transitive closures, epsilon-induction and epsilon-recursion. Well-founded relations. Mostowski's collapsing theorem. The rank function and the von Neumann hierarchy.\hspace*{\fill} [5]

\vspace{10pt}
\noindent\textbf{Consistency}\\
*Problems of consistency and independence*\hspace*{\fill} [1]}

\tableofcontents

\setcounter{section}{-1}
\section{Introduction}
Most people are familiar with the notion of ``sets'' (here ``people'' is defined to be mathematics students). However, most of the time, we only have an intuitive picture of what set theory should look like --- there are sets, we can take intersections, unions, intersections and subsets. We can write down sets like $\{x: \phi(x)\text{ is true}\}$.

Historically, mathematicians were content with this vague notion of sets. However, it turns out that our last statement wasn't really correct. We cannot just arbitrarily write down sets we like. This is evidenced by the famous Russel's paradox, where the set $X$ is defined as $X = \{x: x\not \in x\}$. Then we have $X\in X \Leftrightarrow X\not\in X$, which is a contradiction.

This lead to the formal study of set theory, where set theory is given a formal foundation based on some axioms of set theory. This is known as \emph{axiomatic set theory}. This is similar to Euclid's axioms of geometry, and, in some sense, the group axioms. Unfortunately, while axiomatic set theory appears to avoid paradoxes like Russel's paradox, as G\"odel proved in his incompleteness theorem, we cannot prove that our axioms are free of contradictions.

Closely related to set theory is \emph{formal logic}. Similarly, we want to put logic on a solid foundation. We want to formally define our everyday notions such as propositions, truth and proofs. The main result we will have is that a statement is true if and only if we can prove it. This assures that looking for proofs is a sensible way of showing that a statement is true.

It is important to note that having studied formal logic does \emph{not} mean that we should always reason with formal logic. In fact, this is impossible, as we ultimately need informal logic to reason about formal logic itself!

Throughout the course, we will interleave topics from set theory and formal logic. This is necessary as we need tools from set theory to study formal logic, while we also want to define set theory within the framework of formal logic. One is not allowed to complain that this involves circular reasoning.

As part of the course, we will also side-track to learn about well-orderings and partial orders, as these are very useful tools in the study of logic and set theory. Their importance will become evident as we learn more about them.

\section{Propositional calculus}
\label{sec:propositional}\index{propositional logic}
Propositional calculus is the study of logical statements such $p \Rightarrow p$ and $p \Rightarrow (q\Rightarrow p)$. As opposed to \emph{predicate} calculus, which will be studied in Chapter~\ref{sec:predicate}, the statements will not have quantifier symbols like $\forall$, $\exists$.

When we say ``$p \Rightarrow p$ is a correct'', there are two ways we can interpret this. We can interpret this as ``no matter what truth value $p$ takes, $p \Rightarrow p$ always has the truth value of ``true''.'' Alternatively, we can interpret this as ``there is a proof that $p \Rightarrow p$''.

The first notion is concerned with truth, and does not care about whether we can prove things. The second notion, on the other hand, on talks about proofs. We do not, in any way, assert that $p \Rightarrow p$ is ``true''. One of the main objectives of this chapter is to show that these two notions are consistent with each other. A statement is true (in the sense that it always has the truth value of ``true'') if and only if we can prove it. It turns out that this equivalence has a few rather striking consequences.

Before we start, it is important to understand that there is no ``standard'' logical system. What we present here is just one of the many possible ways of doing formal logic. In particular, do not expect anyone else to know exactly how your system works without first describing it. Fortunately, no one really writes proof with formal logic, and the important theorems we prove (completeness, compactness etc.) do not depend much on the exact implementation details of the systems.

\subsection{Propositions}
We'll start by defining propositions, which are the statements we will consider in propositional calculus.
\begin{defi}[Propositions]\index{propositions}
  Let $P$ be a set of \emph{primitive propositions}. These are a bunch of (meaningless) symbols (e.g.\ $p$, $q$, $r$), which are used as the basic building blocks of our more interesting propositions. These are usually interpreted to take a truth value. Usually, any symbol (composed of alphabets and subscripts) is in the set of primitive propositions.

  The set of \emph{propositions}, written as $L$ or $L(P)$, is defined inductively by
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item If $p\in P$, then $p\in L$.
    \item $\bot\in L$, where $\bot$ is read as ``false'' (also a meaningless symbol).
    \item If $p, q\in L$, then $(p\Rightarrow q)\in L$.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  If our set of primitive propositions is $P = \{p, q, r\}$, then $p\Rightarrow q$, $p\Rightarrow \bot$, $((p\Rightarrow q)\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow r))$ are propositions.
\end{eg}

To define $L$ formally, we let
\begin{align*}
  L_0 &= \{\bot\}\cup P\\
  L_{n + 1} &= L_n\cup \{(p\Rightarrow q): p, q\in L_n\}.
\end{align*}
Then we define $L = L_0 \cup L_1\cup L_2\cup \cdots$.

In formal language terms, $L$ is the set of finite strings of symbols from the alphabet $\bot$ $\Rightarrow $ $($ $)$ $p_1$ $p_2 \cdots$ that satisfy some formal grammar rule (e.g.\ brackets have to match).

Note here that officially, the only relation we have is $\Rightarrow$. The familiar ``not'', ``and'' and ``or'' do not exist. Instead, we define them to be \emph{abbreviations} of certain expressions:
\begin{defi}[Logical symbols]\leavevmode
  \begin{center}
    \begin{tabular}{cccc}
      $\neg p$ & (``not $p$'') & is an abbreviation for & $(p\Rightarrow \bot)$\\
      $p\wedge q$ & (``$p$ and $q$'') & is an abbreviation for & $\neg(p\Rightarrow (\neg q))$\\
      $p\vee q$ & (``$p$ or $q$'') & is an abbreviation for & $(\neg p)\Rightarrow q$
    \end{tabular}
  \end{center}
\end{defi}
The advantage of having just one symbol $\Rightarrow $ is that when we prove something about our theories, we only have to prove it for $\Rightarrow $, instead of all $\Rightarrow , \neg, \wedge$ and $\vee$ individually.
\subsection{Semantic entailment}
The idea of \emph{semantic entailment} is to assign \emph{truth values} to propositions, where we declare each proposition to be ``true'' or ``false''. This assignment is performed by a \emph{valuation}.

\begin{defi}[Valuation]\index{valuation}
  A \emph{valuation} on $L$ is a function $v: L\to \{0, 1\}$ such that:
  \begin{itemize}
  \item $v(\bot) = 0$,
  \item $v(p\Rightarrow q) = \begin{cases} 0 & \text{if }v(p) = 1, v(q) = 0,\\1 & \text{otherwise}\end{cases}$
  \end{itemize}
  We interpret $v(p)$ to be the truth value of $p$, with 0 denoting ``false'' and 1 denoting ``true''.

  Note that we do not impose any restriction of $v(p)$ when $p$ is a primitive proposition.
\end{defi}
For those people who like homomorphisms, we can first give the set $\{0, 1\}$ a binary operation $\Rightarrow $ by
\[
  a\Rightarrow b = \begin{cases}
    0 & \text{if }a = 1, b = 0\\
    1 & \text{otherwise}
  \end{cases}
\]
as well as a constant $\bot = 0$. Then a valuation can be defined as a homomorphism between $L$ and $\{0, 1\}$ that preserves $\bot$ and $\Rightarrow $.

It should be clear that a valuation is uniquely determined by its values on the primitive propositions, as the values on all other propositions follow from the definition of a valuation. In particular, we have
\begin{prop}\leavevmode
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item If $v$ and $v'$ are valuations with $v(p) = v'(p)$ for all $p\in P$, then $v = v'$.
    \item For any function $w: P \to \{0, 1\}$, we can extend it to a valuation $v$ such that $v(p) = w(p)$ for all $p\in L$.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}\leavevmode
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item Recall that $L$ is defined inductively. We are given that $v(p) = v'(p)$ on $L_0$. Then for all $p\in L_1$, $p$ must be in the form $q\Rightarrow r$ for $q, r\in L_0$. Then $v(q\Rightarrow r) = v(p\Rightarrow q)$ since the value of $v$ is uniquely determined by the definition. So for all $p\in L_1$, $v(p) = v'(p)$.

      Continue inductively to show that $v(p) = v'(p)$ for all $p\in L_n$ for any $n$.

    \item Set $v$ to agree with $w$ for all $p\in P$, and set $v(\bot) = 0$. Then define $v$ on $L_n$ inductively according to the definition.\qedhere
  \end{enumerate}
\end{proof}

\begin{eg}
  Suppose $v$ is a valuation with $v(p) = v(q) = 1$, $v(r) = 0$. Then
  \[
    v((p\Rightarrow q)\Rightarrow r) = 0.
  \]
\end{eg}

Often, we are interested in propositions that are always true, such as $p \Rightarrow p$. These are known as \emph{tautologies}.
\begin{defi}[Tautology]\index{tautology}
  $t$ is a \emph{tautology}, written as $\models t$, if $v(t) = 1$ for all valuations $v$.
\end{defi}

To show that a statement is a tautology, we can use a \emph{truth table}, where we simply list out all possible valuations and find the value of $v(t)$.
\begin{eg}\leavevmode
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $\models p\Rightarrow (q\Rightarrow p)$ ``A true statement is implied by anything''
      \begin{center}
        \begin{tabular}{cccc}
          \toprule
          $v(p)$ & $v(q)$ & $v(q\Rightarrow p)$ & $v(p\Rightarrow (q\Rightarrow p))$\\
          \midrule
          1 & 1 & 1 & 1\\
          1 & 0 & 1 & 1\\
          0 & 1 & 0 & 1\\
          0 & 0 & 1 & 1\\
          \bottomrule
        \end{tabular}
      \end{center}
    \item $\models (\neg \neg p)\Rightarrow p$. Recall that $\neg\neg p$ is defined as $((p\Rightarrow \bot)\Rightarrow \bot)$.
      \begin{center}
        \begin{tabular}{cccc}
          \toprule
          $v(p)$ & $v(p\Rightarrow \bot)$ & $v((p\Rightarrow \bot)\Rightarrow \bot)$ & $v(((p\Rightarrow \bot)\Rightarrow \bot)\Rightarrow p)$\\
          \midrule
          1 & 0 & 1 & 1\\
          0 & 1 & 0 & 1\\
          \bottomrule
        \end{tabular}
      \end{center}
  \item $\models [p\Rightarrow (q\Rightarrow r)]\Rightarrow [(p\Rightarrow q)\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow r)]$.

    Instead of creating a truth table, which would be horribly long, we show this by reasoning: Suppose it is not a tautology. So there is a $v$ such that $v(p\Rightarrow (q\Rightarrow r)) = 1$ and $v((p\Rightarrow q)\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow r)) =0 $. For the second equality to hold, we must have $v(p\Rightarrow q) = 1$ and $v(p\Rightarrow r) = 0$. So $v(p) = 1, v(r) = 0, v(q) = 1$. But then $v(p\Rightarrow (q \Rightarrow r)) = 0$.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{eg}

Sometimes, we don't want to make statements as strong as ``$t$ is always true''. Instead, we might want to say ``$t$ is true whenever $S$ is true''. This is known as \emph{semantic entailment}.
\begin{defi}[Semantic entailment]\index{semantic entailment}
  For $S\subseteq L$, $t\in L$, we say $S$ \emph{entails} $t$, $S$ \emph{semantically implies t} or $S\models t$ if, for any $v$ such that $v(s) = 1$ for all $s\in S$, we have $v(t) = 1$.
\end{defi}
Here we are using the symbol $\models$ again. This is not an attempt to confuse students. $\models t$ is equivalent to the statement $\emptyset \models t$.

\begin{eg}
  $\{p\Rightarrow q, q\Rightarrow r\}\models (p\Rightarrow r).$

  We want to show that for any valuation $v$ with $v(p\Rightarrow q) = v(q\Rightarrow r) = 1$, we have $v(p\Rightarrow r) = 1$. We prove the contrapositive.

  If $v(p\Rightarrow r) = 0$, then $v(p) = 1$ and $v(r) = 0$. If $v(q) = 0$, then $v(p\Rightarrow q) = 0$. If $v(q) = 1$, then $v(q\Rightarrow r) = 0$. So $v(p\Rightarrow r) = 0$ only if one of $v(p\Rightarrow q)$ or $v(q\Rightarrow r)$ is zero.
\end{eg}

Note that $\{p\}\models q$ and $p \Rightarrow q$ both intuitively mean ``if $p$ is true, then $q$ is true''. However, these are very distinct notions. $p\Rightarrow q$ is a proposition \emph{within} our theory. It is true (or false) in the sense that valuations take the value 0 (or 1).

On the other hand, when we say $\{p\} \models q$, this is a statement in the \emph{meta-theory}. It is true (or false) in the sense that we decided it is true (or false) based on some arguments and (informal) proofs, performed in the real world instead of inside propositional calculus.

The same distinction should be made when we define syntactic implication later.

Before we dive into syntactic implication, we will define a few convenient terms for later use.
\begin{defi}[Truth and model]
  If $v(t) = 1$, then we say that $t$ is \emph{true} in $v$, or $v$ is a \emph{model} of $t$. For $S\subseteq L$, a valuation $v$ is a \emph{model} of $S$ if $v(s) = 1$ for all $s\in S$.
\end{defi}
\subsection{Syntactic implication}
While semantic implication captures the idea of truthfulness, syntactic implication captures the idea of proofs. We want to say $S$ \emph{syntactically implies} $t$ if there we can prove $t$ from $S$.

To prove propositions, we need two things. Firstly, we need \emph{axioms}, which are statements we can assume to be true in a proof. These are the basic building blocks from which we will prove our theorems.

Other than axioms, we also need \emph{deduction rules}. This allows as to make deduce statements from other statements.

Our system of deduction composes of the following three axioms:
\begin{enumerate}[label=\arabic{*}.]
  \item $p\Rightarrow(q\Rightarrow p)$
  \item $[p\Rightarrow(q\Rightarrow r)]\Rightarrow[(p\Rightarrow q)\Rightarrow(p \Rightarrow r)]$
  \item $(\neg\neg p)\Rightarrow p$
\end{enumerate}
and the deduction rule of \emph{modus ponens}\index{modus ponens}: from $p$ and $p\Rightarrow q$, we can deduce $q$.

At first sight, our axioms look a bit weird, especially the second one. We will later see that how this particular choice of axioms allows us to prove certain theorems more easily. This choice of axioms can also be motivated by combinatory logic, but we shall not go into details of these.

\begin{defi}[Proof and syntactic entailment]\index{proof}\index{syntactic entailment}
  For any $S\subseteq L$, a \emph{proof} of $t$ from $S$ is a finite sequence $t_1, t_2, \cdots t_n$ of propositions, with $t_n = t$, such that each $t_i$ is one of the following:
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item An axiom
    \item A member of $S$
    \item A proposition $t_i$ such that there exist $j, k < i$ with $t_j$ being $t_k\Rightarrow t_i$.
  \end{enumerate}
  If there is a proof of $t$ from $S$, we say that $S$ \emph{proves} or \emph{syntactically entails} $t$, written $S\vdash t$.

  If $\emptyset \vdash t$, we say $t$ is a \emph{theorem}\index{theorem} and write $\vdash t$.

  In a proof of $t$ from $S$, $t$ is the \emph{conclusion} and $S$ is the set of \emph{hypothesis} or \emph{premises}.
\end{defi}
\begin{eg}
  $\{p\Rightarrow q, q\Rightarrow r\} \vdash p\Rightarrow r$

  We go for $(p\Rightarrow q)\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow r)$ via Axiom 2.
  \begin{enumerate}[label=\arabic{*}.]
    \item $[p\Rightarrow (q\Rightarrow r)]\Rightarrow [(p\Rightarrow q) \Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow r)]$ \hfill Axiom 2
    \item $q\Rightarrow r$ \hfill Hypothesis
    \item $(q\Rightarrow r)\Rightarrow [p\Rightarrow (q\Rightarrow r)]$\hfill Axiom 1
    \item $p\Rightarrow (q\Rightarrow r)$ \hfill MP on 2, 3
    \item $(p\Rightarrow q)\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow r)$\hfill MP on 1, 4
    \item $p\Rightarrow q$\hfill Hypothesis
    \item $p\Rightarrow r$\hfill MP on 5, 6
  \end{enumerate}
\end{eg}

\begin{eg}
  $\vdash (p\Rightarrow p)$

  We go for $[p\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow p)]\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow p)$.
  \begin{enumerate}[label=\arabic{*}.]
    \item $[p\Rightarrow ((p\Rightarrow p)\Rightarrow p)]\Rightarrow [(p\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow p))\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow p)]$ \hfill Axiom 2
    \item $p\Rightarrow ( (p\Rightarrow p)\Rightarrow p)$\hfill Axiom 1
    \item $[p\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow p)]\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow p)$ \hfill MP on 1, 2
    \item $p\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow p)$\hfill Axiom 1
    \item $p\Rightarrow p$ \hfill MP on 3, 4
  \end{enumerate}
\end{eg}

This seems like a really tedious way to prove things. We now prove that the \emph{deduction theorem}, which allows as to find proofs much more easily.

\begin{prop}[Deduction theorem]\index{deduction theorem}
  Let $S\subset L$ and $p, q\in L$. Then we have
  \[
    S\vdash (p\Rightarrow q)\quad \Leftrightarrow\quad S\cup \{p\} \vdash q.
  \]
  This says that $\vdash$ behaves like the connective $\Rightarrow $ in the language.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}
  ($\Rightarrow $) Given a proof of $p\Rightarrow q$ from $S$, append the lines
  \begin{itemize}
    \item $p$\hfill Hypothesis
    \item $q$\hfill MP
  \end{itemize}
  to obtain a proof of $q$ from $S\cup \{p\}$.

  ($\Leftarrow$) Let $t_1, t_2, \cdots, t_n = q$ be a proof of $q$ from $S\cup \{p\}$. We'll show that $S\vdash p\Rightarrow t_i$ for all $i$.

  We consider different possibilities of $t_i$:
  \begin{itemize}
    \item $t_i$ is an axiom: Write down
      \begin{itemize}
        \item $t_i\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow t_i)$\hfill Axiom 1
        \item $t_i$\hfill Axiom
        \item $p\Rightarrow t_i$ \hfill MP
      \end{itemize}
    \item $t_i\in S$: Write down
      \begin{itemize}
        \item $t_i\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow t_i)$\hfill Axiom 1
        \item $t_i$\hfill Hypothesis
        \item $p\Rightarrow t_i$ \hfill MP
      \end{itemize}
    \item $t_i = p$: Write down our proof of $p\Rightarrow p$ from our example above.
    \item $t_i$ is obtained by MP: we have some $j, k< i$ such that $t_k = (t_j\Rightarrow t_i)$. We can assume that $S\vdash (p\Rightarrow t_j)$ and $S\vdash (p\Rightarrow t_k)$ by induction on $i$. Now we can write down
      \begin{itemize}
        \item $[p\Rightarrow (t_j\Rightarrow t_i)]\Rightarrow [(p\Rightarrow t_j)\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow t_i)]$\hfill Axiom 2
        \item $p\Rightarrow (t_j\Rightarrow t_i)$\hfill Known already
        \item $(p\Rightarrow t_j)\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow t_i)$\hfill MP
        \item $p\Rightarrow t_j$\hfill Known already
        \item $p\Rightarrow t_i$\hfill MP
      \end{itemize}
      to get $S\vdash (p\Rightarrow t_i)$.
  \end{itemize}
  This is the reason why we have this weird-looking Axiom 2 --- it enables us to easily prove the deduction theorem.
\end{proof}

This theorem has a ``converse''. Suppose we have a deduction system system that admits \emph{modus ponens}, and the deduction theorem holds for this system. Then axioms (1) and (2) must hold in the system, since we can prove them using the deduction theorem and \emph{modus ponens}. However, we are not able to deduce axiom (3) from just \emph{modus ponens} and the deduction theorem.

\begin{eg}
  We want to show $\{p\Rightarrow q, q\Rightarrow r\} \vdash (p\Rightarrow r)$. By the deduction theorem, it is enough to show that $\{p\Rightarrow q, q\Rightarrow r, p\}\vdash r$, which is trivial by applying MP twice.
\end{eg}

Now we have two notions: $\models$ and $\vdash$. How are they related? We want to show that they are equal: if something is true, we can prove it; if we can prove something, it must be true.

\begin{aim}
 Show that $S\vdash t$ if and only if $S\models t$.
 \end{aim}
This is known as the \emph{completeness theorem}, which is made up of two directions:
\begin{enumerate}
  \item Soundness: If $S\vdash t$, then $S\models t$. ``Our axioms aren't absurd''
  \item Adequacy: If $S\models t$, $S\vdash t$. ``Our axioms are strong enough to be able to deduce, from $S$, \emph{all} semantic consequences of $S$.''
\end{enumerate}

We first prove the easy bit:
\begin{prop}[Soundness theorem]\index{soundness theorem}
  If $S\vdash t$, then $S\models t$.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}
  Given valuation $v$ with $v(s) = 1$ for all $s\in S$, we need to show that $v(t) = 1$. We will show that every line $t_i$ in the proof has $v(t_i) = 1$.

  If $t_i$ is an axiom, then $v(t_i) = 1$ since axioms are tautologies. If $t_i$ is a hypothesis, then by assumption $v(s) = 1$. If $t_i$ is obtained by modus ponens, say from $t_j \Rightarrow t_i$, since $v(t_j) = 1$ and $v(t_j \Rightarrow t_i) = 1$, we must have $v(t_i) = 1$.
\end{proof}
Note that soundness holds whenever our axioms are all tautologies. Even if we had silly axioms that are able to prove almost nothing, as long as they are all tautologies, it will be sound.

Now we have to prove adequacy. It seems like a big and scary thing to prove. Given that a statement is true, we have to find a proof for it, but we all know that finding proofs is hard!

We first prove a special case. To do so, we first define \emph{consistency}.
\begin{defi}[Consistent]\index{consistent}\index{inconsistent}
  $S$ is \emph{inconsistent} if $S\vdash \bot$. $S$ is \emph{consistent} if it is not inconsistent.
\end{defi}

The special case we will prove is the following:
\begin{thm}[Model existence theorem]\index{model existence theorem}
  If $S\models \bot$, then $S\vdash \bot$. i.e.\ if $S$ has no model, then $S$ is inconsistent. Equivalently, if $S$ is consistent, then $S$ has a model.
\end{thm}

While we called this a ``special case'', it is in fact all we need to know to prove adequacy. If we are given $S\models t$, then $S\cup \{\neg t\} \models \bot$. Hence using the model existence theorem, we know that $S\cup \{\neg t\} \vdash \bot$. Hence by the deduction theorem, we know that $S\vdash \neg \neg t$. But $\vdash (\neg\neg t)\Rightarrow t$ by Axiom 3. So $S\vdash t$.

As a result, some books call this the ``completeness theorem'' instead, because the rest of the completeness theorem follows trivially from this.

The idea of the proof is that we'd like to define $v: L \to \{0, 1\}$ by
\[
  p\mapsto
  \begin{cases}
    1 & \text{if } p\in S\\
    0 & \text{if } p\not\in S
  \end{cases}
\]
However, this is obviously going to fail, because we could have some $p$ such that $S\vdash p$ but $p\not\in S$, i.e.\ $S$ is not \emph{deductively closed}. Yet this is not a serious problem --- we take the deductive closure first, i.e.\ add all the statements that $S$ can prove.

But there is a more serious problem. There might be a $p$ with $S\not\vdash p$ and $S\not\vdash \neg p$. This is the case if, say, $p$ never appears in $S$. The idea here is to arbitrarily declare that $p$ is true or false, and add $p$ or $\neg p$ to $S$. What we have to prove is that we can do so without making $S$ consistent.

We'll prove this in the following lemma:
\begin{lemma}
  For consistent $S\subset L$ and $p\in L$, at least one of $S\cup \{p\}$ and $S\cup \{\neg p\}$ is consistent.
\end{lemma}

\begin{proof}
  Suppose instead that both $S\cup \{p\} \vdash \bot$ and $S\cup \{\neg p\}\vdash \bot$. Then by the deduction theorem, $S\vdash p$ and $S\vdash \neg p$. So $S\vdash \bot$, contradicting consistency of $S$.
\end{proof}

Now we can prove the completeness theorem. Here we'll assume that the primitives $P$, and hence the language $L$ is countable. This is a reasonable thing to assume, since we can only talk about finitely many primitives (we only have a finite life), so uncountably many primitives would be of no use.

However, this is not a good enough excuse to not prove our things properly. To prove the whole completeness theorem, we will need to use Zorn's lemma, which we will discuss in Chapter~\ref{sec:poset}. For now, we will just prove the countable case.

\begin{proof}
  Assuming that $L$ is countable, list $L$ as $\{t_1, t_2, \cdots\}$.

  Let $S_0 = S$. Then at least one of $S\cup \{t_1\}$ and $S\cup \{\neg t_1\}$ is consistent. Pick $S_1$ to be the consistent one. Then let $S_2 = S_1 \cup \{t_2\}$ or $S_1\cup \{\neg t_2\}$ such that $S_2$ is consistent. Continue inductively.

  Set $\bar{S} = S_0\cup S_1\cup S_2\cdots$. Then $p\in \bar{S}$ or $\neg p\in \bar{S}$ for each $p\in L$ by construction. Also, we know that $\bar S$ is consistent. If we had $\bar S\vdash \bot$, then since proofs are finite, there is some $S_n$ that contains all assumptions used in the proof of $\bar S \vdash \bot$. Hence $S_n \vdash \bot$, but we know that all $S_n$ are consistent.

  Finally, we check that $\bar S$ is deductively closed: if $\bar S\vdash p$, we must have $p \in \bar S$. Otherwise, $\neg p\in \bar S$. But this implies that $\bar S$ is inconsistent.

  Define $v: L\to \{0, 1\}$ by
  \[
    p \mapsto
    \begin{cases}
      1 & \text{if }p\in \bar S\\
      0 & \text{if not}
    \end{cases}.
  \]
  All that is left to show is that this is indeed a valuation.

  First of all, we have $v(\bot) = 0$ as $\bot \not\in \bar S$ (since $\bar S$ is consistent).

  For $p\Rightarrow q$, we check all possible cases.
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item If $v(p) = 1, v(q) = 0$, we have $p\in \bar S$, $q\not\in \bar S$. We want to show $p\Rightarrow q\not\in \bar S$. Suppose instead that $p\Rightarrow q\in \bar S$. Then $\bar S \vdash q$ by modus ponens. Hence $q\in \bar S$ since $\bar S$ is deductively closed. This is a contradiction. Hence we must have $v(p\Rightarrow q) = 0$.
    \item If $v(q) = 1$, then $q\in \bar S$. We want to show $p\Rightarrow q\in \bar S$. By our first axiom, we know that $\vdash q\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow q)$. So $\bar S \vdash p\Rightarrow q$. So $p\Rightarrow q \in \bar S$ by deductive closure. Hence we have $v(p \Rightarrow q) = 1$.
    \item If $v(p) = 0$, then $p\not\in \bar S$. So $\neg p\in \bar S$. We want to show $p\Rightarrow q\in \bar S$.
      \begin{itemize}
        \item
          This is equivalent to showing $\neg p \vdash p\Rightarrow q$.
        \item By the deduction theorem, this is equivalent to proving $\{p, \neg p\} \vdash q$.
        \item We know that $\{p, \neg p\} \vdash \bot$. So it is sufficient to show $\bot \vdash q$.
        \item By axiom 3, this is equivalent to showing $\bot \vdash \neg \neg q$.
        \item By the deduction theorem, this is again equivalent to showing $\vdash \bot \Rightarrow \neg \neg q$.
        \item By definition of $\neg$, this is equivalent to showing $\vdash \bot \Rightarrow (\neg q\Rightarrow \bot)$.
      \end{itemize}
      But this is just an instance of the first axiom. So we know that $\bar S\vdash p\Rightarrow q$. So $v(p\Rightarrow q) = 1$.\qedhere
  \end{enumerate}
\end{proof}
Note that the last case is the first time we really use Axiom 3.

By remark before the proof, we have
\begin{cor}[Adequacy theorem]\index{adequacy theorem}
  Let $S\subset L$, $t\in L$. Then $S\models t$ implies $S\vdash t$.
\end{cor}

\begin{thm}[Completeness theorem]\index{completeness theorem}
  Le $S\subset L$ and $t\in L$. Then $S\models t$ if and only if $S\vdash t$.
\end{thm}

This theorem has two nice consequences.
\begin{cor}[Compactness theorem]\index{compactness theorem}
  Let $S\subset L$ and $t\in L$ with $S\models t$. Then there is some finite $S'\subset S$ has $S'\models t$.
\end{cor}

\begin{proof}
  Trivial with $\models$ replaced by $\vdash$, because proofs are finite.
\end{proof}
Sometimes when people say compactness theorem, they mean the special case where $t = \bot$. This says that if every finite subset of $S$ has a model, then $S$ has a model. This result can be used to prove some rather unexpected result in other fields such as graph theory, but we will not go into details.

\begin{cor}[Decidability theorem]\index{decidability theorem}
  Let $S\subset L$ be a finite set and $t\in L$. Then there exists an algorithm that determines, in finite and bounded time, whether or not $S\vdash t$.
\end{cor}
\begin{proof}
  Trivial with $\vdash$ replaced by $\models$, by making a truth table.
\end{proof}
This is a rather nice result, because we know that proofs are hard to find in general. However, this theorem only tells you whether a proof exists, without giving you the proof itself!

\section{Well-orderings and ordinals}
In the coming two sections, we will study different orderings. The focus of this chapter is \emph{well-orders}, while the focus of the next is \emph{partial orders}.

A well-order on a set $S$ is a special type of total order where every non-empty subset of $S$ has a least element. Among the many nice properties of well-orders, it is possible to do induction and recursion on well-orders.

Our interest, however, does not lie in well-orders itself. Instead, we are interested in the ``lengths'' of well-orders. Officially, we call them them the \emph{order types} of the well-orders. Each order type is known as an \emph{ordinal}.

There are many things we can do with ordinals. We can add and multiply them to form ``longer'' well-orders. While we will not make much use of them in this chapter, in later chapters, we will use ordinals to count ``beyond infinity'', similar to how we count finite things using natural numbers.

\subsection{Well-orderings}
We start with a few definitions.
\begin{defi}[(Strict) total order]\index{total order}
  A \emph{(strict) total order} or \emph{linear order} is a pair $(X, <)$, where $X$ is a set and $<$ is a relation on $X$ that satisfies
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $x \not< x$ for all $x$ \hfill (irreflexivity)
    \item If $x < y$, $y < z$, then $x < z$ \hfill (transitivity)
    \item $x < y$ or $x = y$ or $y < x$ \hfill (trichotomy)
  \end{enumerate}
\end{defi}

We have the usual shorthands for total orders. For example, $x > y$ means $y < x$ and $x \leq y$ means ($x < y$ or $x = y$).

It is also possible for a total order to be defined in terms of $\leq$ instead of $<$.
\begin{defi}[(Non-strict) total order]
  A \emph{(non-strict) total order} is a pair $(X, \leq)$, where $X$ is a set and $\leq$ is a relation on $X$ that satisfies
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $x \leq x$ \hfill (reflexivity)
    \item $x\leq y$ and $y \leq z$ implies $x\leq z$ \hfill (transitivity)
    \item $x\leq y$ and $y\leq x$ implies $x = y$ \hfill (antisymmetry)
    \item $x\leq y$ or $y\leq x$ \hfill (trichotomy)
  \end{enumerate}
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}\leavevmode
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $\N, \Z, \Q, \R$ with usual the usual orders are total orders.
    \item On $\N^+$ (the positive integers), `$x < y$ if $x\mid y$ and $x \not=y$' is not trichotomous, and so not a total order.
    \item On $\P(S)$, define `$x\leq y$' if $x\subseteq y$. This is not a total order since it is not trichotomous (for $|X| > 1$).
  \end{enumerate}
\end{eg}

While there can be different total orders, the particular kind we are interested in is well-orders.
\begin{defi}[Well order]\index{well order}
  A total order $(X, <)$ is a \emph{well-ordering} if every (non-empty) subset has a least element, i.e.
  \[
    (\forall S\subseteq X)[S\not= \emptyset \Rightarrow (\exists x\in S)(\forall y\in S)\, y \geq x].
  \]
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}\leavevmode
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $\N$ with usual ordering is a well-order.
    \item $\Z, \Q, \R$ are not well-ordered because the whole set itself does not have a least element.
    \item $\{x\in \Q: x\geq 0\}$ is not well-ordered. For example, $\{x\in X: x> 0\}$ has no least element.
    \item In $\R$, $\{1 - 1/n: n = 2, 3, 4, \cdots\}$ is well-ordered because it is isomorphic to the naturals.
    \item $\{1 - 1/n: n = 2, 3, 4, \cdots\} \cup \{1\}$ is also well-ordered, If the subset is only $1$, then $1$ is the least element. Otherwise take the least element of the remaining set.
    \item Similarly, $\{1 - 1/n: n = 2, 3, 4, \cdots\}\cup \{2\}$ is well-ordered.
    \item $\{1 - 1/n: n = 2, 3, 4, \cdots\} \cup \{2 - 1/n: n = 2, 3, 4, \cdots\}$ is also well-ordered. This is a good example to keep in mind.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{eg}

There is another way to characterize total orders in terms of infinite decreasing sequences.
\begin{prop}
  A total order is a well-ordering if and only if it has no infinite strictly decreasing sequence.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}
  If $x_1 > x_2 > x_3 > \cdots$, then $\{x_i: i\in \N\}$ has no least element.

  Conversely, if non-empty $S\subset X$ has no least element, then each $x\in S$ have $x'\in S$ with $x' < x$. Similarly, we can find some $x'' < x'$ \emph{ad infinitum}. So
  \[
    x > x' > x'' > x''' > \cdots
  \]
  is an infinite decreasing sequence.
\end{proof}

Like all other axiomatic theories we study, we identify two total orders to be \emph{isomorphic} if they are ``the same up to renaming of elements''.
\begin{defi}[Order isomorphism]\index{order isomorphism}
  Say the total orders $X, Y$ are \emph{isomorphic} if there exists a bijection $f: X\to Y$ that is order-preserving, i.e.\ $x < y \Rightarrow f(x) < f(y)$.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}\leavevmode
\begin{enumerate}
  \item $\N$ and $\{1 - 1/n: n = 2, 3, 4, \cdots\}$ are isomorphic.
  \item $\{1 - 1/n:n = 2, 3, 4, \cdots\}\cup \{1\}$ is isomorphic to $\{1 - 1/n: n = 2, 3, 4, \cdots\} \cup \{2\}$.
  \item $\{1 - 1/n: n = 2, 3, 4, \cdots\}$ and $\{1 - 1/n: n = 2, 3, 4, \cdots\}\cup \{1\}$ are not isomorphic because the second has a greatest element but the first doesn't.
\end{enumerate}
\end{eg}

Recall from IA Numbers and Sets that in $\N$, the well-ordering principle is equivalent to the principle induction. We proved that we can do induction simply by assuming that $\N$ is well-ordered. Using the same proof, we should be able to prove that we can do induction on \emph{any} well-ordered set.

Of course, a general well-ordered set does not have the concept of ``$+1$'', so we won't be able to formulate weak induction. Instead, our principle of induction is the form taken by strong induction.
\begin{prop}[Principle by induction]\index{induction}
  Let $X$ be a well-ordered set. Suppose $S \subseteq X$ has the property:
  \[
    (\forall x)\Big(\big((\forall y)\, y < x \Rightarrow y\in S\big) \Rightarrow x\in S\Big),
  \]
  then $S = X$.

  In particular, if a property $P(x)$ satisfies
  \[
    (\forall x)\Big(\big((\forall y)\, y < x \Rightarrow P(y)\big)\Rightarrow P(x)\Big),
  \]
  then $P(x)$ for all $x$.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}
  Suppose $S\not=X$. Let $x$ be the least element of $X\setminus S$. Then by minimality of $x$, for all $y$, $y < x \Rightarrow y\in S$. Hence $x\in S$. Contradiction.
\end{proof}

Using proof by induction, we can prove the following property of well-orders:
\begin{prop}
  Let $X$ and $Y$ be isomorphic well-orderings. Then there is a unique isomorphism between $X$ and $Y$.
\end{prop}
This is something special to well-orders. This is not true for general total orderings. For example, $x\mapsto x$ and $x\mapsto x - 13$ are both isomorphisms $\Z\to \Z$. It is also not true for, say, groups. For example, there are two possible isomorphisms from $\Z_3$ to itself.

\begin{proof}
  Let $f$ and $g$ be two isomorphisms $X\to Y$. To show that $f = g$, it is enough, by induction, to show $f(x) = g(x)$ given $f(y) = g(y)$ for all $y < x$.

  Given a fixed $x$, let $S = \{f(y): y < x\}$. We know that $Y\setminus S$ is non-empty since $f(x) \not\in S$. So let $a$ be the least member of $Y\setminus S$. Then we must have $f(x) = a$. Otherwise, we will have $a < f(x)$ by minimality of $a$, which implies that $f^{-1}(a) < x$ since $f$ is order-preserving. However, by definition of $S$, this implies that $a = f(f^{-1}(a)) \in S$. This is a contradiction since $a \in Y\setminus S$.

  By the induction hypothesis, for $y < x$, we have $f(y) = g(y)$. So we have $S = \{g(y): y < x\}$ as well. Hence $g(x) = \min(Y\setminus S) = f(x)$.
\end{proof}

If we have an ordered set, we can decide to cut off the top of the set and keep the bottom part. What is left is an initial segment.
\begin{defi}[Initial segment]\index{initial segment}
  A subset $Y$ of a totally ordered $X$ is an \emph{initial segment} if
  \[
    x\in Y, y< x \Rightarrow y\in Y,
  \]
  \begin{center}
    \begin{tikzpicture}
      \fill [gray!50!white] (-0.5, 0) arc (180:360:0.5 and 1.3) -- cycle;
      \draw (0, 0) ellipse (0.5 and 1.3);
      \draw (-0.5, 0) -- (0.5, 0);
      \node at (0, -0.5) {$Y$};
      \node at (0.7, 1) {$X$};
    \end{tikzpicture}
  \end{center}
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  For any $x\in X$, the set $I_x = \{y\in X: y < x\}$ is an initial segment. However, not every initial segment of $X$ need to be in this form. For example, $\{x: x\leq 3\}\subseteq \R$ and $\{x: x < 0\text{ or }x^2 < 2\}\subseteq \Q$ are both initial segments not of this form.
\end{eg}

The next nice property of well-orders we have is that every proper initial segment is of this form.
\begin{prop}
  Every initial segment $Y$ of a well-ordered set $X$ is of the form $I_x = \{y\in X: y < x\}$.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}
  Take $x = \min X\setminus Y$. Then for any $y\in I_x$, we have $y < x$. So $y \in Y$ by definition of $x$. So $I_x \subseteq Y$.

  On the other hand, if $y \in Y$, then definitely $y \not= x$. We also cannot have $y > x$ since this implies $x \in Y$. Hence we must have $y < x$. So $y \in I_x$. Hence $Y \subseteq I_x$. So $Y = I_x$.
\end{proof}

The next nice property we want to show is that in a well-ordering $X$, \emph{every} subset $S$ is isomorphic to an initial segment.

Note that this is \emph{very} false for a general total order. For example, in $\Z$, no initial segment is isomorphic to the subset $\{1, 2, 3\}$ since every initial segment of $\Z$ is either infinite or empty. Alternatively, in $\R$, $\Q$ is not isomorphic to an initial segment.

It is intuitively obvious how we can prove this. We simply send the minimum element of $S$ to the minimum of $X$, and the continue recursively. However, how can we justify recursion? If we have the well-order $\{\frac{1}{2}, \frac{2}{3}, \frac{3}{4}, \cdots, 1\}$, then we will never reach $1$ if we attempt to write down each step of the recursion, since we can only get there after infinitely many steps. We will need to define some sort of ``infinite recursion'' to justify our recursion on general well-orders.

We first define the restriction of a function:
\begin{defi}[Restriction of function]
  For $f: A\to B$ and $C\subseteq A$, the \emph{restriction} of $f$ to $C$ is
  \[
    f|_C = \{(x, f(x)): x\in C\}.
  \]
\end{defi}
In this theorem (and the subsequent proof), we are treating functions as explicitly a set of ordered pairs $(x, f(x))$. We will perform set operations on functions and use unions to ``stitch together'' functions.

\begin{thm}[Definition by recursion]\index{recursion}
  Let $X$ be a well-ordered set and $Y$ be any set. Then for any function $G: \P(X\times Y)\to Y$, there exists a function $f:X\to Y$ such that
  \[
    f(x) = G(f|_{I_x})
  \]
  for all $x$.

  This is a rather weird definition. Intuitively, it means that $G$ takes previous values of $f(x)$ and returns the desired output. This means that in defining $f$ at $x$, we are allowed to make use of values of $f$ on $I_x$. For example, we define $f(n) = n f(n - 1)$ for the factorial function, with $f(0) = 1$.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  We might want to jump into the proof and define $f(0) = G(\emptyset)$, where $0$ is the minimum element. Then we define $f(1) = G(f(0))$ etc. But doing so is simply recursion, which is the thing we want to prove that works!

  Instead, we use the following clever trick: We define an ``$h$ is an attempt'' to mean
  \begin{center}
    $h: I \to Y$ for some initial segment $I$ of $X$, and $h(x) = G(h|_{I_x})$ for $x\in I$.
  \end{center}
  The idea is to show that for any $x$, there is an attempt $h$ that is defined at $x$. Then take the value $f(x)$ to be $h(x)$. However, we must show this is well-defined first:

  \begin{claim}
    If attempts $h$ and $h'$ are defined at $x$, then $h(x) = h'(x)$.
  \end{claim}
  By induction on $x$, it is enough to show that $h(x) = h'(x)$ assuming $h(y) = h'(y)$ for all $y < x$. But then $h(x) = G(h|_{I_x}) = G(h'|_{I_x}) = h'(x)$. So done.

  \begin{claim}
    For any $x$, there must exist an attempt $h$ that is defined at $x$.
  \end{claim}
  Again, we may assume (by induction) that for each $y < x$, there exists an attempt $h_y$ defined at $y$. Then we put all these functions together, and take $h' = \bigcup_{y < x} h_y$. This is defined for all $y < x$, and is well-defined since the $h_y$ never disagree.

  Finally, add to it $(x, G(h'|_{I_x}))$. Then $h = h'\cup (x, G(h'|_{I_x}))$ is an attempt defined at $x$.

  Now define $f:X\to Y$ by $f(x) = y$ if there exists an attempt $h$, defined at $x$, with $h(x) = y$.

  \begin{claim}
    There is a unique such $f$.
  \end{claim}
  Suppose $f$ and $f'$ both work. Then if $f(y) = f'(y)$ for all $y < x$, then $f(x) = f'(x)$ by definition. So by induction, we know for all $x$, we have $f'(x) = f(x)$.
\end{proof}
With the tool of recursion, we can prove that every subset of a well-order.

\begin{lemma}[Subset collapse]\index{subset collapse lemma}
  Let $X$ be a well-ordering and let $Y\subseteq X$. Then $Y$ is isomorphic to an initial segment of $X$. Moreover, this initial segment is unique.
\end{lemma}

\begin{proof}
  For $f: Y\to X$ to be an order-preserving bijection with an initial segment of $X$, we need to map $x$ to the smallest thing not yet mapped to, i.e.
  \[
    f(x) = \min (X\setminus \{f(y): y < x\}).
  \]
  To be able to take the minimum, we have to make sure the set is non-empty, i.e.\ $\{f(y): y < x\} \not= X$. We can show this by proving that $f(z) < x$ for all $z < x$ by induction, and hence $x \not\in \{f(y): y < x\}$.

  Then by the recursion theorem, this function exists and is unique.
\end{proof}
This implies that a well-ordered $X$ can \emph{never} be isomorphic to a proper initial segment of itself. This is since $X$ is isomorphic to itself by the identity function, and uniqueness shows that it cannot be isomorphic to another initial segment.

Using the idea of initial segments, we can define an order comparing different well-orders themselves.
\begin{notation}
  Write $X\leq Y$ if $X$ is isomorphic to an initial segment of $Y$.

  We write $X < Y$ if $X\leq Y$ but $X$ is not isomorphic to $Y$, i.e.\ $X$ is isomorphic to a proper initial segment of $Y$.
\end{notation}

\begin{eg}
  If $X = \N$, $Y = \{\frac{1}{2}, \frac{2}{3}, \frac{3}{4},\cdots\}\cup \{1\}$, then $X \leq Y$.
\end{eg}

We will show that this is a total order. Of course, we identify two well-orders as ``equal'' when they are isomorphic.

Reflexivity and transitivity are straightforward. So we prove trichotomy and antisymmetry:
\begin{thm}
  Let $X, Y$ be well-orderings. Then $X\leq Y$ or $Y \leq X$.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  We attempt to define $f: X\to Y$ by
  \[
    f(x) = \min (Y\setminus \{f(y): y < x\}).
  \]
  By the law of excluded middle, this function is either well-defined or not.

  If it is well-defined, then it is an isomorphism from $X$ to an initial segment of $Y$.

  If it is not, then there is some $x$ such that $\{f(y): y < x\} = Y$ and we cannot take the minimum. Then $f$ is a bijection between $I_x = \{y: y < x\}$ and $Y$. So $f$ is an isomorphism between $Y$ and an initial segment of $X$.

  Hence either $X \leq Y$ or $Y \leq X$.
\end{proof}

\begin{thm}
  Let $X, Y$ be well-orderings with $X\leq Y$ and $Y \leq X$. Then $X$ and $Y$ are isomorphic.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  Since $X \leq Y$, there is an order-preserving function $f: X\to Y$ that bijects $X$ with an initial segment of $Y$. Similarly, since $Y \leq X$, we get an analogous $g: Y\to X$. Then $g\circ f: X\to X$ defines a bijection between $X$ and an initial segment of $X$.

  Since there is no bijection between $X$ and a \emph{proper} initial segment of itself, the image of $g\circ f$ must be $X$ itself. Hence $g\circ f$ is a bijection.

  Similarly, $f\circ g$ is a bijection. Hence $f$ and $g$ are both bijections, and $X$ and $Y$ are isomorphic.
\end{proof}

\subsection{New well-orderings from old}
Given a well-ordering $X$, we want to create more well-orderings. We've previously shown that we can create a shorter one by taking an initial segment. In this section, we will explore two ways to make \emph{longer} well-orderings.

\subsubsection*{Add one element}
We can extend a well-ordering by exactly one element. This is known as the \emph{successor}.
\begin{defi}[Successor]\index{successor}
  Given $X$, choose some $x\not\in X$ and define a well-ordering on $X\cup \{x\}$ by setting $y < x$ for all $y \in X$. This is the \emph{successor} of $X$, written $X^+$.
\end{defi}
We clearly have $X < X^+$.
\subsubsection*{Put some together}
More interestingly, we want to ``stitch together'' many well-orderings. However, we cannot just arbitrarily stitch well-orderings together. The well-orderings must satisfy certain nice conditions for this to be well-defined.

\begin{defi}[Extension]\index{extension}\index{extension}
  For well-orderings $(X, <_X)$ and $(Y, <_Y)$, we say $Y$ \emph{extends} $X$ if $X$ is a proper initial segment of $Y$ and $<_X$ and $<_Y$ agree when defined.
\end{defi}
Note that we explicitly require $X$ to be an initial segment of $Y$. $X$ simply being a \emph{subset} of $Y$ will not work, for reasons that will become clear shortly.

\begin{defi}[Nested family]\index{nested family}
  We say well-orderings $\{X_i: i\in I\}$ form a \emph{nested} family if for any $i, j\in I$, either $X_i$ extends $X_j$, or $X_j$ extends $X_i$.
\end{defi}

\begin{prop}
  Let $\{X_i: i\in I\}$ be a nested set of well-orderings. Then there exists a well-ordering $X$ with $X_i\leq X$ for all $i$.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}
  Let $X = \bigcup_{i\in I}X_i$ with $<$ defined on $X$ as $\bigcup_{i\in I} <_i$ (where $<_i$ is the ordering of $X_i$), i.e.\ we inherit the orders from the $X_i$'s. This is clearly a total ordering. Since $\{X_i: i \in I\}$ is a nested family, each $X_i$ is an initial segment of $X$.

  To show that it is a well-ordering, let $S\subseteq X$ be a non-empty subset of $X$. Then $S\cap X_i$ is non-empty for some $i$. Let $x$ be the minimum element (in $X_i$) of $S\cap X_i$. Then also for any $y\in S$, we must have $x \leq y$, as $X_i$ is an initial segment of $X$.
\end{proof}
Note that if we didn't require $X$ to be an initial segment of $Y$ when defining 'extension', then the above proof will not work. For example, we can take the collection of all subsets $X_n = \{x \geq -n: x\in \Z\}$, and their union would be $\Z$, which is not well-ordered.

\subsection{Ordinals}
We have already shown that the collection of all well-orderings is a total order. But is it a well-ordering itself? To investigate this issue further, we first define ourselves a convenient way of talking about well-orderings.

\begin{defi}[Ordinal]\index{ordinal}
  An \emph{ordinal} is a well-ordered set, with two regarded as the same if they are isomorphic. We write ordinals as Greek letters $\alpha, \beta$ etc.
\end{defi}
We would want to define ordinals as equivalence classes of well-orders under isomorphism, but we cannot, because they do not form a set. We will provide a formal definition of ordinals later when we study set theory.

\begin{defi}[Order type]\index{order type}
  If a well-ordering $X$ has corresponding ordinal $\alpha$, we say $X$ has \emph{order type} $\alpha$, and write $\otp(X) = \alpha$.
\end{defi}

\begin{notation}
  For each $k\in \N$, we write $k$ for the order type of the (unique) well-ordering of size $k$. We write $\omega$ for the order type of $\N$.
\end{notation}

\begin{eg}
  In $\R$, $\{2, 3, 5 ,6\}$ has order type 4. $\{\frac{1}{2}, \frac{2}{3}, \frac{3}{4}, \cdots\}$ has order type $\omega$.
\end{eg}

\begin{notation}
  For ordinals $\alpha, \beta$, write $\alpha \leq \beta$ if $X\leq Y$ for some $X$ of order type $\alpha$, $Y$ of order type $\beta$. This does not depend on the choice of $X$ and $Y$ (since any two choices must be isomorphic).
\end{notation}

\begin{prop}
  Let $\alpha$ be an ordinal. Then the ordinals $<\alpha$ form a well-ordering of order type $\alpha$.
\end{prop}

\begin{notation}
  Write $I_\alpha = \{\beta: \beta < \alpha\}$.
\end{notation}

\begin{proof}
  Let $X$ have order type $\alpha$. The well-orderings $< X$ are precisely (up to isomorphism) the proper initial segments of $X$ (by uniqueness of subset collapse). But these are the $I_x$ for all $x\in X$. So we can biject $X$ with the well-orderings $< X$ by $x\mapsto I_x$.
\end{proof}

Finally, we can prove that the ordinals are well-ordered.
\begin{prop}
  Let $S$ be a non-empty set of ordinals. Then $S$ has a least element.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}
  Choose $\alpha\in S$. If it is minimal, done.

  If not, then $S\cap I_\alpha$ is non-empty. But $I_\alpha$ is well-ordered. So $S\cap I_\alpha$ has a least element, $\beta$. Then this is a minimal element of $S$.
\end{proof}

However, it would be wrong to say that the ordinals form a well-ordered \emph{set}, for the very reason that they don't form a set.
\begin{thm}[Burali-Forti paradox]\index{Burali-Forti paradox}
  The ordinals do not form a set.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  Suppose not. Let $X$ be the set of ordinals. Then $X$ is a well-ordering. Let its order-type be $\alpha$. Then $X$ is isomorphic to $I_\alpha$, a proper initial subset of $X$. Contradiction.
\end{proof}

Recall that we could create new well-orderings from old via adding one element and taking unions. We can translate these into ordinal language.

Given an ordinal $\alpha$, suppose that $X$ is the corresponding well-order. Then we define $\alpha^+$ to be the order type of $X^+$.

If we have a set $\{\alpha_i: i \in I\}$ of ordinals, we can stitch them together to form a new well-order. In particular, we apply ``nested well-orders'' to the initial segments $\{I_{\alpha_i}: i \in I\}$. This produces an upper bound of the ordinals $\alpha_i$. Since the ordinals are well-ordered, we know that there is a \emph{least} upper bound. We call this the \emph{supremum} of the set $\{\alpha_i: i \in I\}$, written $\sup\{\alpha_i: i \in I\}$. In fact, the upper bound created by nesting well-orders is the least upper bound.

\begin{eg}
  $\{2, 4, 6, 8, \cdots\}$ has supremum $\omega$.
\end{eg}

Now we have two ways of producing ordinals: $+1$ and supremum.

We can generate a lot of ordinals now:
\begin{center}
  \begin{tabular}{ccccccc}
    0 & $\omega\cdot 2 + 1$ & $\omega^2 + 1$ & $\omega^2\cdot 3$ & $\omega^{\omega + 2}$ & $\varepsilon_0 + 1$ \\
    1 & $\omega\cdot 2 + 2$ & $\omega^2 + 2$ & $\omega^2\cdot 4$ & $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ \\
    2 & $\omega\cdot 2 + 3$ & $\omega^2 + 3$ & $\omega^2\cdot 5$ & $\omega^{\omega \cdot 2}$ & $\varepsilon_0 \cdot 2$ \\
    $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ \\
    $\omega$ & $\omega\cdot 3$ & $\omega^2 + \omega$ & $\omega^3$ & $\omega^{\omega^2}$ & $\varepsilon_0^2$ \\
    $\omega + 1$ & $\omega\cdot 4$ & $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ \\
    $\omega + 2$ & $\omega\cdot 5$ & $\omega^2 + \omega \cdot 2$ & $\omega^\omega$ & $\omega^{\omega^{\omega}}$ & $\varepsilon_0^{\varepsilon_0}$ \\
    $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ & $\vdots$ \\
    $\omega + \omega = \omega\cdot 2$ & $\omega\cdot \omega = \omega^2$ & $\omega^2 \cdot 2$ & $\omega^{\omega + 1}$ & $\omega^{\omega^{.^{.^.}}} = \varepsilon_0$ & $\varepsilon_0^{\varepsilon_0^{.^{.^.}}} = \varepsilon_1$ \\
  \end{tabular}
\end{center}
Here we introduced a lot of different notations. For example, we wrote $\omega + 1$ to mean $\omega^+$, and $\omega\cdot 2 = \sup\{\omega, \omega + 1, \omega + 2, \cdots\}$. We will formally define these notations later.

We have written a lot of ordinals above, some of which are really huge. However, all the ordinals above are countable. The operations we have done so far is adding one element and taking countable unions. So the results are all countable. So is there an uncountable ordinal?

\begin{thm}
  There is an uncountable ordinal.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  This is easy by looking at the supremum of the set of all countable ordinals. However, this works only if the collection of countable ordinals is a set.

  Let $A = \{R\in \P(\N\times \N): R \text{ is a well-ordering of a subset of }\N\}$. So $A \subseteq \P(\N\times \N)$. Then $B = \{\text{order type of }R: R\in A\}$ is the set of all countable ordinals.

  Let $\omega_1 = \sup B$. Then $\omega_1$ is uncountable. Indeed, if $\omega_1$ were countable, then it would be the greatest countable ordinal, but $\omega_1 + 1$ is greater and is also countable.
\end{proof}

By definition, $\omega_1$ is the \emph{least} uncountable ordinal, and everything in our previous big list of ordinals is less than $\omega_1$.

There are two strange properties of $\omega_1$:
\begin{enumerate}
  \item $\omega_1$ is an uncountable ordering, yet for every $x\in \omega_1$, the set $\{y: y< x\}$ is countable.
  \item Every sequence in $\omega_1$ is bounded, since its supremum is a countable union of countable sets, which is countable.
\end{enumerate}

In general, we have the following theorem:
\begin{thm}[Hartogs' lemma]\index{Hartogs' lemma}
  For any set $X$, there is an ordinal that does not inject into $X$.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  As before, with $B = \{\alpha: \alpha\text{ injects into }X\}$.
\end{proof}

\begin{notation}
  Write $\gamma(X)$ for the least ordinal that does not inject into $X$. e.g.\ $\gamma(\omega) = \omega_1$.
\end{notation}

\subsection{Successors and limits}
In general, we can divide ordinals into two categories. The criteria is as follows:

Given an ordinal $\alpha$, is there a greatest element of $\alpha$? i.e.\ does $I_\alpha = \{\beta: \beta < \alpha\}$ have a greatest element?

If yes, say $\beta$ is the greatest element. Then $\gamma\in I_\alpha \Leftrightarrow \gamma \leq \beta$. So $I_\alpha = \{\beta\}\cup I_\beta$. In other words, $\alpha = \beta^+$.

\begin{defi}[Successor ordinal]\index{successor ordinal}
  An ordinal $\alpha$ is a \emph{successor ordinal} if there is a greatest element $\beta$ below it. Then $\alpha = \beta^+$.
\end{defi}

On the other hand, if no, then for any $\gamma < \alpha$, there exists $\beta < \alpha$ such that $\beta > \gamma$. So $\alpha = \sup \{\beta: \beta < \alpha\}$.
\begin{defi}[Limit ordinal]\index{limit ordinal}
  An ordinal $\alpha$ is a limit if it has no greatest element below it. We usually write $\lambda$ for limit ordinals.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  $5$ and $\omega^+$ are successors. $\omega$ and $0$ are limits ($0$ is a limit because it has no element below it, let alone a greatest one!).
\end{eg}

\subsection{Ordinal arithmetic}
We want to define ordinals arithmetic such as $+$ and $\times$, so that we can make formal sense out of our notations such as $\omega + \omega$ in our huge list of ordinals.

We first start with addition.
\begin{defi}[Ordinal addition (inductive)]\index{ordinal addition}
  Define $\alpha + \beta$ by recursion on $\beta$ ($\alpha$ is fixed):
  \begin{itemize}
    \item $\alpha + 0 = \alpha$.
    \item $\alpha + \beta^+ = (\alpha + \beta)^+$.
    \item $\alpha + \lambda = \sup \{\alpha + \gamma: \gamma < \lambda\}$ for non-zero limit $\lambda$.
  \end{itemize}
\end{defi}
Note that officially, we cannot do ``recursion on the ordinals'', since the ordinals don't form a set. So what we officially do is that we define $\alpha + \gamma$ on $\{\gamma: \gamma < \beta\}$ recursively for each ordinal $\beta$. Then by uniqueness of recursions, we can show that this addition is well-defined.

\begin{eg}
  $\omega + 1 = (\omega + 0)^+ = \omega^+$.

  $\omega + 2 = (\omega + 1)^+ = \omega^{++}$.

  $1 + \omega = \sup\{ 1 + n: n \leq \omega\} = \sup\{1, 2, 3, \cdots\} = \omega$.
\end{eg}
It is very important to note that addition is not commutative! This asymmetry arises from our decision to perform recursion on $\beta$ instead of $\alpha$.

On the other hand, addition \emph{is} associative.
\begin{prop}
  Addition is associative, i.e.\ $(\alpha + \beta) + \gamma = \alpha + (\beta + \gamma)$.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}
  Since we define addition by recursion, it makes sense to prove this by induction. Since we recursed on the right-hand term in the definition, it only makes sense to induct on $\gamma$ (and fix $\alpha + \beta$).

  \begin{enumerate}
    \item If $\gamma = 0$, then $\alpha + (\beta + 0) = \alpha + \beta = (\alpha + \beta) + 0$.
    \item If $\gamma = \delta^+$ is a successor, then
      \begin{align*}
        \alpha + (\beta + \delta^+) &= \alpha + (\beta + \delta)^+\\
        &= [\alpha + (\beta + \delta)]^+\\
        &= [(\alpha + \beta) + \delta]^+\\
        &= (\alpha + \beta) + \delta^+\\
        &= (\alpha + \beta) + \gamma.
      \end{align*}
    \item If $\gamma$ is a limit ordinal, we have
      \begin{align*}
        (\alpha + \beta) + \lambda &= \sup\{(\alpha + \beta) + \gamma: \gamma < \lambda\}\\
        &= \sup\{\alpha + (\beta + \gamma): \gamma < \lambda\}
      \end{align*}
      If we want to evaluate $\alpha + (\beta + \lambda)$, we have to first know whether $\beta + \lambda$ is a successor or a limit. We now claim it is a limit:

      $\beta + \lambda = \sup\{\beta + \gamma: \gamma < \lambda\}$. We show that this cannot have a greatest element: for any $\beta + \gamma$, since $\lambda$ is a limit ordinal, we can find a $\gamma'$ such that $\gamma < \gamma' < \lambda$. So $\beta + \gamma' > \beta + \gamma$. So $\beta + \gamma$ cannot be the greatest element.

      So
      \[
        \alpha + (\beta + \lambda) = \sup\{\alpha + \delta: \delta < \beta + \lambda\}.
      \]
      We need to show that
      \[
        \sup\{\alpha + \delta: \delta < \beta + \lambda\} = \sup\{\alpha + (\beta + \gamma): \gamma < \lambda\}.
      \]
      Note that the two sets are not equal. For example, if $\beta = 3$ and $\lambda = \omega$, then the left contains $\alpha + 2$ but the right does not.

      So we show that the left is both $\geq$ and $\leq$ the right.

      $\geq$: Each element of the right hand set is an element of the left.

      $\leq$: For $\delta < \beta + \lambda$, we have $\delta < \sup \{\beta + \gamma: \gamma < \lambda\}$. So $\delta < \beta + \gamma$ for some $\gamma < \lambda$. Hence $\alpha + \delta < \alpha + (\beta + \gamma)$.\qedhere
  \end{enumerate}
\end{proof}
Note that it is easy to prove that $\beta < \gamma \Rightarrow \alpha + \beta < \alpha + \gamma$ by induction on $\gamma$ (which we implicitly assumed above). But it is not true if we add on the right: $1 < 2$ but $1 + \omega = 2 + \omega$.

The definition we had above is called the \emph{inductive} definition. There is an alternative definition of $+$ based on actual well-orders. This is known as the \emph{synthetic} definition.

Intuitively, we first write out all the elements of $\alpha$, then write out all the elements of $\beta$ after it. The $\alpha + \beta$ is the order type of the combined mess.

\begin{defi}[Ordinal addition (synthetic)]\index{ordinal addition}
  $\alpha + \beta$ is the order type of $\alpha \sqcup \beta$ ($\alpha$ disjoint union $\beta$, e.g.\ $\alpha\times \{0\}\cup \beta\times \{1\}$), with all $\alpha$ before all of $\beta$
  \[
    \alpha + \beta = \underbracket{\quad\quad\vphantom{\beta}\alpha\vphantom{\beta}\quad\quad}\underbracket{\quad\;\beta\;\quad}
  \]
\end{defi}
\begin{eg}
  $\omega + 1 = \omega^+$.

  $1 + \omega = \omega$.
\end{eg}

With this definition, associativity is trivial:.
\[
  \alpha + (\beta + \gamma) = \underbracket{\quad\quad\vphantom{\beta}\alpha\vphantom{\beta}\quad\quad}\underbracket{\quad\;\beta\;\quad}\underbracket{\quad\gamma\quad} = (\alpha + \beta) + \gamma.
\]
Now that we have given two definitions, we must show that they are the same:
\begin{prop}
  The inductive and synthetic definition of $+$ coincide.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}
  Write $+$ for inductive definition, and $+'$ for synthetic. We want to show that $\alpha + \beta = \alpha +' \beta$. We induct on $\beta$.

  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $\alpha + 0 = \alpha = \alpha +' 0$.
    \item $\alpha + \beta^+ = (\alpha + \beta)^+ = (\alpha +' \beta)^+ = \otp\underbracket{\quad\vphantom\beta\alpha\vphantom\beta\quad}\underbracket{\quad\beta\quad}\underbracket{\vphantom\beta\cdot\vphantom\beta} = \alpha +' \beta^+$
    \item $\alpha + \lambda = \sup\{\alpha + \gamma: \gamma < \lambda\} = \sup \{\alpha +' \gamma: \gamma < \lambda\} = \alpha +' \lambda$. This works because taking the supremum is the same as taking the union.
      \[
        \underbracket{\quad\vphantom\gamma\alpha\vphantom\gamma\quad}\underbracket{\gamma\quad\gamma'\;\gamma''\cdots \lambda}\qedhere
      \]%\qedhere
  \end{enumerate}
\end{proof}
The synthetic definition is usually easier to work with, if possible. For example, it was very easy to show associativity using the synthetic definition. It is also easier to see why addition is not commutative. However, if we want to do induction, the inductive definition is usually easier.

After addition, we can define multiplication. Again, we first give an inductive definition, and then a synthetic one.
\begin{defi}[Ordinal multiplication (inductive)]\index{ordinal multiplication}
  We define $\alpha\cdot \beta$ by induction on $\beta$ by:
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $\alpha\cdot 0 = 0$.
    \item $\alpha\cdot (\beta^+) = \alpha\cdot \beta + \alpha$.
    \item $\alpha\cdot \lambda = \sup\{\alpha\cdot \gamma: \gamma < \lambda\}$ for $\lambda$ a non-zero limit.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}\leavevmode
  \begin{itemize}
    \item $\omega \cdot 1 = \omega\cdot 0 + \omega = 0 + \omega = \omega$.
    \item $\omega \cdot 2 = \omega \cdot 1 + \omega = \omega + \omega$.
    \item $2\cdot \omega = \sup\{2\cdot n: n < \omega\} = \omega$.
    \item $\omega\cdot \omega = \sup \{\omega\cdot n: n < \omega\} = \sup\{\omega, \omega^2, \omega^3, \cdots\}$.
  \end{itemize}
\end{eg}

We also have a synthetic definition.
\begin{defi}[Ordinal multiplication (synthetic)]\index{ordinal multiplication}
  \[
    \beta\left\{
      \begin{array}{c}
        \underbracket{\quad\alpha\quad} \\
        \vdots \\
        \underbracket{\quad\alpha\quad} \\
        \underbracket{\quad\alpha\quad}
      \end{array}\right.
    \]
  Formally, $\alpha\cdot \beta$ is the order type of $\alpha\times \beta$, with $(x, y) < (x', y')$ if $y < y'$ or ($y = y'$ and $x < x'$).
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  $\displaystyle\omega\cdot 2 =
  \begin{array}{c}
    \underbracket{\quad\omega\quad}\\
    \underbracket{\quad\omega\quad}
  \end{array} = \omega + \omega$.

  Also $2\cdot \omega = \omega\left\{
  \begin{array}{c}
    \underbracket{\,\cdot\,\cdot\,} \\
    \vdots \\
    \underbracket{\,\cdot\,\cdot\,} \\
    \underbracket{\,\cdot\,\cdot\,} \\
  \end{array}\right. = \omega$
\end{eg}
We can check that the definitions coincide, prove associativity etc. similar to what we did for addition.

We can define ordinal exponentiation, towers etc. similarly:
\begin{defi}[Ordinal exponentiation (inductive)]\index{ordinal exponentiation}
  $\alpha^\beta$ is defined as
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $\alpha^0 = 1$
    \item $\alpha^{\beta^+} = \alpha^\beta \cdot \alpha$
    \item $\alpha^{\lambda} = \sup \{\alpha^\gamma: \gamma< \lambda\}$.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  $\omega^1 = \omega^0\cdot \omega = 1\cdot \omega = \omega$.

  $\omega^2 = \omega^1\cdot \omega = \omega\cdot \omega$.

  $2^{\omega} = \sup \{2^n: n < \omega\} = \omega$.
\end{eg}

\subsection{Normal functions*}
\begin{own}
  \emph{Note: These content were not lectured during the year.}

  When we have ordinals, we would like to consider functions $\mathrm{On} \to \mathrm{On}$. Since the ordinals are totally ordered, it would make sense to consider the order-preserving functions, i.e.\ the increasing ones. However, ordinals have an additional property --- we could take suprema of ordinals. If we want our function to preserve this as well, we are lead to the following definition:

  \begin{defi}[Normal function]\index{normal function}
    A function $f: \mathrm{On} \to \mathrm{On}$ is \emph{normal} if
    \begin{enumerate}
      \item For any ordinal $\alpha$, we have $f(\alpha) < f(\alpha^+)$.
      \item If $\lambda$ is a non-zero limit ordinal, then $f(\lambda) = \sup \{f(\gamma): \gamma < \lambda\}$.
    \end{enumerate}
  \end{defi}
  Some replace the increasing condition by $f(\alpha) < f(\alpha^+)$. These are easily seen to be equivalent by transfinite induction.

  \begin{eg}
    By definition, we see that for each $\beta > 1$, the function $\alpha \mapsto \beta^\alpha$ is normal.
  \end{eg}

  We start by a few technical lemmas.
  \begin{lemma}
    Let $f$ be a normal function. Then $f$ is strictly increasing.
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof}
    Let $\alpha$ be a fixed ordinal. We induct on all $\beta > \alpha$ that $f(\alpha) < f(\beta)$.

    If $\beta = \alpha^+$, then the result is obvious.

    If $\beta = \gamma^+$ with $\gamma \not= \alpha$, then $\alpha < \gamma$. So $f(\alpha) < f(\gamma) < f(\gamma^+) = f(\beta)$ by induction.

    If $\beta$ is a limit and is greater than $\alpha$, then
    \[
      f(\beta) = \sup\{f(\gamma): \gamma < \beta\} \geq f(\alpha^+) > f(\alpha),
    \]
    since $\alpha^+ < \beta$. So the result follows.
  \end{proof}

  \begin{lemma}
    Let $f$ be a normal function, and $\alpha$ an ordinal. Then $f(\alpha) \geq \alpha$.
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof}
    We prove by induction. It is trivial for zero. For successors, we have $f(\alpha^+) > f(\alpha) \geq \alpha$, so $f(\alpha^+) \geq \alpha^+$. For limits, we have
    \[
      f(\lambda) = \sup \{f(\gamma): \gamma < \lambda\} \geq \sup\{\gamma: \gamma < \lambda\} = \lambda.\qedhere
    \]
  \end{proof}

  The following is a convenient refinement of the continuity result:
  \begin{lemma}
    If $f$ is a normal function, then for any non-empty set $\{\alpha_i\}_{i \in I}$, we have
    \[
      f(\sup\{\alpha_i: i \in I\}) = \sup\{f(\alpha_i): i \in I\}.
    \]
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof}
    If $\{\alpha_i\}$ has a maximal element, then the result is obvious, as $f$ is increasing, and the supremum is a maximum.

    Otherwise, let
    \[
      \alpha = \sup\{\alpha_i: i \in I\}
    \]
    Since the $\alpha_i$ has no maximal element, we know $\alpha$ must be a limit ordinal. So we have
    \[
      f(\alpha) = \sup \{f(\beta): \beta < \alpha\}.
    \]
    So it suffices to prove that
    \[
      \sup \{f(\beta): \beta < \alpha\} = \sup\{f(\alpha_i): i \in I\}.
    \]
    Since all $\alpha_i < \alpha$, we have $\sup \{f(\beta): \beta < \alpha\} \geq \sup\{f(\alpha_i): i \in I\}$.

    For the other direction, it suffices, by definition, to show that
    \[
      f(\beta) \leq \sup \{f(\alpha_\gamma): i \in I\}
    \]
    for all $\beta < \alpha$.

    Given such a $\beta$, since $\alpha$ is the supremum of the $\alpha_i$, we can find some particular $\alpha_i$ such that $\beta < \alpha_i$. So $f(\beta) < f(\alpha_i) \leq \sup \{f(\alpha_i): i \in I\}$. So we are done.
  \end{proof}
  Because of these results, some define normal functions to be functions that are strictly increasing and preserve all suprema.

  We now proceed to prove two important properties of normal functions (with easy proofs!):

  \begin{lemma}[Fixed-point lemma]\index{ordinal!fixed point lemma}\index{normal function!fixed point lemma}\index{fixed point}\index{fixed point lemma for normal functions}
    Let $f$ be a normal function. Then for each ordinal $\alpha$, there is some $\beta \geq \alpha$ such that $f(\beta) = \beta$.
  \end{lemma}
  Since the supremum of fixed points is also a fixed point (by normality), it follows that we can define a function $g: \mathrm{On} \to \mathrm{On}$ that enumerates the fixed points. Now this function itself is again normal, so it has fixed points as well\ldots

  \begin{proof}
    We thus define
    \[
      \beta = \sup \{f(\alpha), f(f(\alpha)), f(f(f(\alpha))), \cdots\}.
    \]
    If the sequence eventually stops, then we have found a fixed point. Otherwise, $\beta$ is a limit ordinal, and thus normality gives
    \[
      f(\beta) = \sup\{f(f(\alpha)), f(f(f(\alpha))), f(f(f(f(\alpha)))), \cdots\} = \beta.
    \]
    So $\beta$ is a fixed point, and $\beta \geq f(\alpha) \geq \alpha$.
  \end{proof}

  \begin{lemma}[Division algorithm for normal functions]
    Let $f$ be a normal function. Then for all $\alpha$, there is some maximal $\gamma$ such that $\alpha \geq f(\gamma)$.
  \end{lemma}

  \begin{proof}
    Let $\gamma = \sup\{\beta: f(\beta) \leq \alpha\}$. Then we have
    \[
      f(\gamma) = \sup\{f(\beta): f(b) \leq \alpha\} \leq \alpha.
    \]
    This is clearly maximal.
  \end{proof}
\end{own}
\section{Posets and Zorn's lemma}
\label{sec:poset}
In this chapter, we study \emph{partial orders}. While there are many examples of partial orders, the most important example is the power set $\P(X)$ for any set $X$, ordered under inclusion. We will also consider subsets of the power set.

The two main theorems of this chapter are Knaster-Tarski fixed point theorem and Zorn's lemma. We will use Zorn's lemma to prove a lot of useful results in different fields, including the completeness theorem in propositional calculus. Finally, we will investigate the relationship between Zorn's lemma and Axiom of Choice.

\subsection{Partial orders}
\begin{defi}[Partial ordering (poset)]\index{partial order}\index{poset}
  A \emph{partially ordered set} or \emph{poset} is a pair $(X, \leq)$, where $X$ is a set and $\leq$ is a relation on $X$ that satisfies
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $x\leq x$ for all $x\in X$ \hfill (reflexivity)
    \item $x \leq y$ and $y \leq z \Rightarrow x \leq z$ \hfill (transitivity)
    \item $x \leq y$ and $y \leq x \Rightarrow x = y$ \hfill (antisymmetry)
  \end{enumerate}
  We write $x < y$ to mean $ x\leq y$ and $x\not= y$. We can also define posets in terms of~$<$:
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $x \not< x$ for all $x\in X$ \hfill (irreflexive)
    \item $x < y$ and $y < z\Rightarrow x < z$ \hfill (transitive)
  \end{enumerate}
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}\leavevmode
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item Any total order is (trivially) a partial order.
    \item $\N$ with ``$x\leq y$'' if $x \mid y$ is a partial order.
    \item $\P(S)$ with $\subseteq$ for any set $S$ is a partial order.
    \item Any subset of $\P(S)$ with inclusion is a partial order.
    \item We can use a diagram
      \begin{center}
        \begin{tikzpicture}[grow=up]
          \node {a}
          child {
            node {b} edge from parent
            child {
              node {c} edge from parent
            }
          }
          child {
            node {d} edge from parent
            child {
              node {e} edge from parent
            }
          };
        \end{tikzpicture}
      \end{center}
      Where ``above'' means ``greater''. So $a \leq b\leq c$, $a \leq d\leq e$, and what follows by transitivity. This is a Hasse diagram.

      \begin{defi}[Hasse diagram]
        A \emph{Hasse diagram} for a poset $X$ consists of a drawing of the points of $X$ in the plane with an upwards line from $x$ to $y$ if $y$ \emph{covers} $x$:
      \end{defi}
      \begin{defi}[Cover]
        In a poset, $y$ \emph{covers} $x$ if $y > x$ and no $z$ has $y > z > x$.
      \end{defi}
      Hasse diagrams can be useful --- e.g.\ $\N$, or useless, e.g.\ $\Q$.
    \item The following example shows that we cannot assign ``heights'' or ``ranks'' to posets:
      \begin{center}
        \begin{tikzpicture}
          \node (a) {$a$};
          \node[above=0.5 of a] (dummy1) {};
          \node[above=0.5 of dummy1] (dummy2) {};
          \node[above=0.5 of dummy2] (dummy3) {};

          \node[right=of dummy1] (d) {$d$} edge (a);
          \node[left=of dummy2] (b) {$b$} edge (a);
          \node[right=of dummy3] (e) {$e$} edge (d);
          \node [above=0.5 of dummy3] {$c$} edge (b) edge (e);
        \end{tikzpicture}
      \end{center}
    \item We can also have complicated structures:
      \begin{center}
        \begin{tikzpicture}[node distance=1]
          \node at (-1, 0) (a) {$a$};
          \node at (1, 0) (b) {$b$};
          \node at (-1, 1) (c) {$c$} edge (a) edge (b);
          \node at (1, 1) (d) {$d$} edge (a) edge (b);
          \node at (0, 2) {$e$} edge (c) edge (d);
        \end{tikzpicture}
      \end{center}
    \item Or the empty poset (let $X$ be any set and nothing is less than anything else).
  \end{enumerate}
\end{eg}
While there are many examples of posets, all we care about are actually power sets and their subsets only.

Often, we want to study subsets of posets. For example, we might want to know if a subset has a least element. All subsets are equal, but some subsets are more equal than others. A particular interesting class of subsets is a \emph{chain}.
\begin{defi}[Chain and antichain]\index{chain}\index{antichain}
  In a poset, a subset $S$ is a \emph{chain} if it is totally ordered, i.e.\ for all $x$, $y$, $x\leq y$ or $y\leq x$. An \emph{antichain} is a subset in which no two things are related.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  In $(\N, \mid )$, $1, 2, 4, 8, 16, \cdots$ is a chain.

  In (v), $\{a, b, c\}$ or $\{a, c\}$ are chains.

  $\R$ is a chain in $\R$.
\end{eg}

\begin{defi}[Upper bound and supremum]\index{upper bound}\index{supremum}
  For $S\subset X$, an \emph{upper bound} for $S$ is an $x\in X$ such that $\forall y\in S: x \geq y$.

  $x\in X$ is a \emph{least upper bound}, \emph{supremum} or \emph{join} of $S$, written $x = \sup S$ or $x = \bigvee S$, if $x$ is an upper bound for $S$, and for all $y \in X$, if $y$ is an upper bound, then $y \geq x$.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}\leavevmode
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item In $\R$, $\{x: x < \sqrt{2}\}$ has an upper bound $7$, and has a supremum $\sqrt{2}$.

    \item In (v) above, consider $\{a, b\}$. Upper bounds are $b$ and $c$. So $\sup = b$. However, $\{b, d\}$ has no upper bound!
    \item In (vii), $\{a, b\}$ has upper bounds $c, d, e$, but has no \emph{least} upper bound.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{eg}

\begin{defi}[Complete poset]\index{complete poset}
  A poset $X$ is \emph{complete} if every $S\subseteq X$ has a supremum. In particular, it has a greatest element (i.e.\ $x$ such that $\forall y: x \geq y$), namely $\sup X$, and least element (i.e.\ $x$ such that $\forall y: x \leq y$), namely $\sup \emptyset$.
\end{defi}
It is very important to remember that this definition does \emph{not} require that the subset $S$ is bounded above or non-empty. This is different from the definition of metric space completeness.

\begin{eg}\leavevmode
  \begin{itemize}
    \item $\R$ is not complete because $\R$ itself has no supremum.
    \item $[0, 1]$ is complete because every subset is bounded above, and so has a least upper bound. Also, $\emptyset$ has a supremum of $0$.
    \item $(0, 1)$ is not complete because $(0, 1)$ has no upper bound.
    \item $\P(S)$ for any $S$ is \emph{always} complete, because given any $\{A_i: i\in A\}$, where each $A_i\subseteq S$, $\bigcup A_i$ is its supremum.
  \end{itemize}
\end{eg}

Now we are going to derive fixed-point theorems for complete posets. We start with a few definitions:

\begin{defi}[Fixed point]\index{fixed point}
  A \emph{fixed point} of a function $f:X\to X$ is an $x$ such that $f(x) = x$.
\end{defi}

\begin{defi}[Order-preserving function]\index{order-preserving function}
  For a poset $X$, $f: X\to X$ is \emph{order-preserving} of $x \leq y \Rightarrow f(x) \leq f(y)$.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}\leavevmode
  \begin{itemize}
    \item On $\N$, $x\mapsto x + 1$ is order-preserving
    \item On $\Z$, $x\mapsto x - 1$ is order-preserving
    \item On $(0, 1)$, $x\mapsto \frac{1 + x}{2}$ is order-preserving (this function halves the distance from $x$ to $1$).
    \item On $\P(S)$, let some fixed $i\in S$. Then $A\mapsto A\cup \{i\}$ is order-preserving.
  \end{itemize}
\end{eg}
Not every order-preserving $f$ has a fixed point (e.g.\ first two above). However, we have
\begin{thm}[Knaster-Tarski fixed point theorem]
  Let $X$ be a complete poset, and $f: X\to X$ be a order-preserving function. Then $f$ has a fixed point.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  To show that $f(x) = x$, we need $f(x) \leq x$ and $f(x) \geq x$. Let's not be too greedy and just want half of it:

  Let $E = \{x: x \leq f(x)\}$. Let $s = \sup E$. We claim that this is a fixed point, by showing $f(s) \leq s$ and $s \leq f(s)$.

  To show $s \leq f(s)$, we use the fact that $s$ is the least upper bound. So if we can show that $f(s)$ is also an upper bound, then $s \leq f(s)$. Now let $x \in E$. So $x\leq s$. Therefore $f(x) \leq f(s)$ by order-preservingness. Since $x \leq f(x)$ (by definition of $E$) $x \leq f(x) \leq f(s)$. So $f(s)$ is an upper bound.

  To show $f(s) \leq s$, we simply have to show $f(s) \in E$, since $s$ is an upper bound. But we already know $s \leq f(s)$. By order-preservingness, $f(s) \leq f(f(s))$. So $f(s)\in E$ by definition.
\end{proof}
While this proof looks rather straightforward, we need to first establish that $s \leq f(s)$, then use this fact to show $f(s) \leq s$. If we decided to show $f(s) \leq s$ first, then we would fail!

The very typical application of Knaster-Tarski is the quick, magic proof of Cantor-Shr\"oder-Bernstein theorem.
\begin{cor}[Cantor-Schr\"oder-Bernstein theorem]\index{Cantor-Schr\"oder-Bernstein}
  Let $A, B$ be sets. Let $f: A\to B$ and $g: B\to A$ be injections. Then there is a bijection $h: A\to B$.
\end{cor}

\begin{proof}
  We try to partition $A$ into $P$ and $Q$, and $B$ into $R$ and $S$, such that $f(P) = R$ and $g(S) = Q$. Then we let $h = f$ on $R$ and $g^{-1}$ on $Q$.
  \begin{center}
    \begin{tikzpicture}
      \draw (-1, 0) ellipse (0.5 and 1.3);
      \draw (-1.5, 0) -- (-0.5, 0);
      \node at (-1, -0.5) {$Q$};
      \node at (-1, 0.5) {$P$};
      \draw (1, 0) ellipse (0.5 and 1.3);
      \draw (0.5, 0) -- (1.5, 0);
      \node at (1, -0.5) {$S$};
      \node at (1, 0.5) {$R$};
      \draw [->] (-0.4, 0.7) -- (0.4, 0.7) node [pos = 0.5, above] {$f$};
      \draw [->] (0.4, -0.7) -- (-0.4, -0.7) node [pos = 0.5, above] {$g$};
    \end{tikzpicture}
  \end{center}
  Since $S = B\setminus R$ and $Q = A \setminus P$, so we want
  \[
    P = A\setminus g(B\setminus f(P))
  \]
  Since the function $P \mapsto A\setminus g(B\setminus f(P))$ from $\P(A)$ to $\P(A)$ is order-preserving (and $\P(a)$ is complete), the result follows.
\end{proof}

The next result we have is Zorn's lemma. The main focus of Zorn's lemma is on \emph{maximal elements}.
\begin{defi}[Maximal element]\index{maximal}
  In a poset $X$, $x\in X$ is maximal if no $y\in X$ has $y > x$.
\end{defi}
Caution! Under no circumstances confuse a maximal element with a maximum element, except under confusing circumstances! A maximum element is defined as an $x$ such that all $y\in X$ satisfies $y \leq x$. These two notions are the same in totally ordered sets, but are very different in posets.

\begin{eg}
  In the poset
  \begin{center}
    \begin{tikzpicture}[grow=up]
      \node {a}
      child {
        node {b} edge from parent
        child {
          node {c} edge from parent
        }
      }
      child {
        node {d} edge from parent
        child {
          node {e} edge from parent
        }
      };
    \end{tikzpicture}
  \end{center}
  $c$ and $e$ are maximal.
\end{eg}

Not every poset has a maximal element, e.g.\ $\N, \Q, \R$. In each of these, not only are they incomplete. They have chains that are not bounded above.

\begin{thm}[Zorn's lemma]\index{Zorn's lemma}
  Assuming Axiom of Choice, let $X$ be a (non-empty) poset in which every chain has an upper bound. Then it has a maximal element.
\end{thm}
Note that ``non-empty'' is not a strictly necessary condition, because if $X$ is an empty poset, then the empty chain has no upper bound. So the conditions can never be satisfied.

The actual proof of Zorn's lemma is rather simple, given what we've had so far. We ``hunt'' for the maximal element. We start with $x_0$. If it is maximal, done. If not, we find a bigger $x_1$. If $x_1$ is maximal, done. Otherwise, keep go on.

If we never meet a maximal element, then we have an infinite chain. This has an upper bound $x_\omega$. If this is maximal, done. If not, find $x_{\omega + 1} > x_\omega$. Keep going on.

We have not yet reached a contradiction. But suppose we never meet a maximal element. If $X$ is countable, and we can reach $x_{\omega_1}$, then we have found uncountably many elements in a countable set, which is clearly nonsense!

Since the ordinals can be arbitrarily large (Hartogs' lemma), if we never reach a maximal element, then we can get find more elements that $X$ has.

\begin{proof}
  Suppose not. So for each $x\in X$, we have $x'\in X$ with $x' > x$. We denote the-element-larger-than-$x$ by $x'$.

  We know that each chain $C$ has an upper bound, say $u(C)$.

  Let $\gamma = \gamma(X)$, the ordinal-larger-than-$X$ by Hartogs' lemma.

  We pick $x\in X$, and define $x_\alpha$ for $\alpha < \gamma$ recursively by
  \begin{itemize}
    \item $x_0 = x$
    \item $x_{\alpha^+} = x_\alpha'$
    \item $x_{\lambda} = u(\{x_\alpha: \alpha < \lambda\})'$ for non-zero limit $\lambda$
  \end{itemize}
  Of course, we have to show that $\{x_\alpha: \alpha < \lambda\}$ is a chain. This is trivial by induction.

  Then $\alpha \mapsto x_\alpha$ is an injection from $\gamma\to X$. Contradiction.
\end{proof}
Note that we could as well have defined $x_\lambda = u(\{x_\alpha : \alpha < \lambda\})$, and we can easily prove it is still an injection. However, we are lazy and put the ``prime'' just to save a few lines of proof.

This proof was rather easy. However, this is only because we are given ordinals, definition by recursion, and Hartogs' lemma. Without these tools, it is rather difficult to prove Zorn's lemma.

A typical application of Zorn's lemma is: Does every vector space have a basis? Recall that a \emph{basis} of $V$ is a subset of $V$ that is linearly independent (no finite linear combination $= 0$) and spanning (ie every $x\in V$ is a finite linear combination from it).

\begin{eg}\leavevmode
  \begin{itemize}
    \item Let $V$ be the space of all real polynomials. A basis is $\{1, x, x^2, x^3, \cdots\}$.
    \item Let $V$ be the space of all real sequences. Let $\mathbf{e}_i$ be the sequence with all $0$ except $1$ in the $i$th place. However, $\{\mathbf{e}_i\}$ is not a basis, since $1, 1, \cdots$ cannot be written as a finite linear combination of them. In fact, there is no countable basis (easy exercise). It turns out that there is no ``explicit'' basis.
    \item Take $\R$ as a vector space over $\Q$. A basis here, if exists, is called a Hamel basis.
  \end{itemize}
\end{eg}

Using Zorn's lemma, we can prove that the answer is positive.
\begin{thm}
  Every vector space $V$ has a basis.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  We go for a maximal linearly independent subset.

  Let $X$ be the set of all linearly independent subsets of $V$, ordered by inclusion. We want to find a maximal $B\in X$. Then $B$ is a basis. Otherwise, if $B$ does not span $V$, choose $x\not\in \spn B$. Then $B\cup \{x\}$ is independent, contradicting maximality.

  So we have to find such a maximal $B$. By Zorn's lemma, we simply have to show that every chain has an upper bound.

  Given a chain $\{A_i: i\in I\}$ in $X$, a reasonable guess is to try the union. Let $A = \bigcup A_i$. Then $A\subseteq A_i$ for all $i$, by definition. So it is enough to check that $A\in X$, i.e.\ is linearly independent.

  Suppose not. Say $\lambda_1x_1 + \cdots + \lambda_nx_n = 0$ for some $\lambda_1 \cdots \lambda_n$ scalars (not all $0$). Suppose $x_1 \in A_{i_1}, \cdots x_n \in A_{i_n}$ for some $i_1, \cdots i_n \in I$. Then there is some $A_{i_m}$ that contains all $A_{i_k}$, since they form a finite chain. So $A_{i_m}$ contains all $x_i$. This contradicts the independence of $A_{i_m}$.

  Hence by Zorn's lemma, $X$ has a maximal element. Done.
\end{proof}

Another application is the completeness theorem for propositional logic when $P$, the primitives, can be uncountable.

\begin{thm}[Model existence theorem (uncountable case)]\index{model existence theorem}
  Let $S\subseteq L(P)$ for any set of primitive propositions $P$. Then if $S$ is consistent, $S$ has a model.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  We need a consistent $\bar S \subseteq S$ such that $\forall t\in L$, $t\in \bar S$ or $\neg t\in \bar S$. Then we have a valuation $v(t) = \begin{cases} 1 & t\in \bar S \\ 0 & t\not\in \bar S\end{cases}$, as in our original proof for the countable case.

  So we seek a \emph{maximal} consistent $\bar S\supseteq S$. If $\bar S$ is maximal, then if $t\not\in \bar S$, then we must have $\bar S \cup \{t\}$ inconsistent, i.e.\ $\bar S \cup \{t\}\vdash \bot$. By deduction theorem, this means that $\bar S \vdash \neg t$. By maximality, we must have $\neg t \in \bar S$. So either $t$ or $\neg t$ is in $\bar S$.

  Now we show that there is such a maximal $\bar S$. Let $X = \{ T\subseteq L: T\text{ is consistent }, T\supseteq S\}$. Then $X\not=\emptyset$ since $S\in X$. We show that any non-empty chain has an upper bound. An obvious choice is, again the union.

  Let $\{T_i: i\in I\}$ be a non-empty chain. Let $T = \bigcup T_i$. Then $T\supseteq T_i$ for all $i$. So to show that $T$ is an upper bound, we have to show $T\in X$.

  Certainly, $T\supseteq S$, as any $T_i$ contains $S$ (and the chain is non-empty). So we want to show $T$ is consistent. Suppose $T\vdash \bot$. So we have $t_1, \cdots, t_n \in T$ with $\{t_1, \cdots, t_n\} \vdash \bot$, since proofs are finite. Then some $T_k$ contains all $t_i$ since $T_i$ are nested. So $T_k$ is inconsistent. This is a contradiction. Therefore $T$ must be consistent.

  Hence by Zorn's lemma, there is a maximal element of $X$.
\end{proof}
This proof is basically the same proof that every vector space has a basis! In fact, most proofs involving Zorn's lemma are similar.

\subsection{Zorn's lemma and axiom of choice}
Recall that in the proof of Zorn's, we picked $x$, then picked $x'$, then picked $x''$, \emph{ad infinitum}. Here we are making arbitrary choices of $x'$. In particular, we have made infinitely many arbitrary choices.

We did the same in IA Numbers and Sets, when proving a countable union of countable sets is countable, because we chose, for each $A_n$, a listing of $A_n$, and then count them diagonally. We needed to make a choice because each $A_n$ has a lot of possible listings, and we have to pick exactly one.

In terms of ``rules for producing sets'', we are appealing to the axiom of choice, which states that you can pick an element of each $A_i$ whenever $\{A_i: i\in I\}$ is a family of non-empty sets. Formally,
\begin{axiom}[Axiom of choice]\index{axiom!of choice}
  Given any family $\{A_i: i\in I\}$ of non-empty sets, there is a \emph{choice function} $f: i \to \bigcup A_i$ such that $f(i)\in A_i$.
\end{axiom}
This is of a different character from the other set-building rules (e.g.\ unions and power sets exist). The difference is that the other rules are concrete. We know exactly what $A\cup B$ is, and there is only one possible candidate for what $A\cup B$ might be. ``Union'' uniquely specifies what it produces. However, the choice function is not. $\{A_i:i\in I\}$ can have many choice functions, and the axiom of choice does not give us a solid, explicit choice function. We say the axiom of choice is \emph{non-constructive}.

We are not saying that it's wrong, but it's \emph{weird}. For this reason, it is often of interest to ask ``Did I use AC?'' and ``Do I need AC?''.

(It is important to note that the Axiom of Choice is needed only to make \emph{infinite} choices. It is trivially true if $|I| = 1$, since $A\not=\emptyset$ by definition means $\exists x\in A$. We can also do it for two sets. Similarly, for $|I|$ finite, we can do it by induction. However, in general, AC is required to make infinite choices, i.e.\ it cannot be deduced from the other axioms of set theory)

In the proof of Zorn's we used Choice. However, do we \emph{need} it? Is it possible to prove it without Choice?

The answer is it is necessary, since we can deduce AC from Zorn's. In other words, we can write down a proof of AC from Zorn's, using only the other set-building rules.

\begin{thm}
  Zorn's Lemma $\Leftrightarrow$ Axiom of choice.
\end{thm}

As in the past uses of Zorn's lemma, we have a big scary choice function to produce. We know that we can do it for small cases, such as when $|I| = 1$. So we start with small attempts and show that the maximal attempt is what we want.
\begin{proof}
  We have already proved that AC $\Rightarrow $ Zorn. We now proved the other way round.

  Given a family $\{A_i: i\in I\}$ of non-empty sets. We say a \emph{partial choice function} is a function $f: J\to \bigcup_{i\in I}A_i$ (for some $J\subseteq I$) such that $f(j)\in A$ for all $j\in J$.

  Let $X = \{(J, f): f\text{ is a partial choice function with domain }J\}$. We order by extension, i.e.\ $(J, f) \leq (J', f')$ iff $J\subseteq J'$ and $f'$ agrees with $f$ when both are defined.

  Given a chain $\{(J_k, f_k): k\in K\}$, we have an upper bound $\left(\bigcup J_k, \bigcup f_k\right)$, ie the function obtained by combining all functions in the chain. So by Zorn's, it has a maximal element $(J, f)$.

  Suppose $J \not = I$. Then pick $i\in I\setminus J$. Then pick $x\in A_i$. Set $J' = J\cup \{i\}$ and $f' = f\cup\{(i, x)\}$. Then this is greater than $(J, f)$. This contradicts the maximality of $(J, f)$. So we must have $J = I$, i.e.\ $f$ is a full choice function.
\end{proof}

We have shown that Zorn's lemma is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice. There is a \emph{third} statement that is also equivalent to both of these:
\begin{thm}[Well-ordering theorem]\index{well-ordering theorem}
  Axiom of choice $\Rightarrow$ every set $X$ can be well-ordered.
\end{thm}
This might be very surprising at first for, say $X = \R$, since there is no obvious way we can well-order $\R$. However, it is much less surprising given Hartogs' lemma, since Hartogs' lemma says that there is a (well-ordered) ordinal even bigger than $\R$. So well-ordering $\R$ shouldn't be hard.

\begin{proof}
  The idea is to pick an element from $X$ and call it the first; pick another element and call it the second, and continue transfinitely until we pick everything.

  For each $A\subseteq X$ with $A\not= X$, we let $y_A$ be an element of $X\setminus A$. Here we are using Choice to pick out $y_A$.

  Define $x_\alpha$ recursively: Having defined $x_{\beta}$ for all $\beta < \alpha$, if $\{x_\beta: \beta < \alpha\} = X$, then stop. Otherwise, set $x_\alpha = y_{\{x_\beta: \beta< \alpha\}}$, ie pick $x_\alpha$ to be something not yet chosen.

  We must stop at some time. Otherwise, we have injected $\gamma(X)$ (ie the ordinal larger than $X$) into $X$, which is a contradiction. So when stop, we have bijected $X$ with an well-ordered set (i.e.\ $I_\alpha$, where $\alpha$ is when you've stopped). Hence we have well-ordered $X$.
\end{proof}

Did we need AC? Yes, trivially.
\begin{thm}
  Well-ordering theorem $\Rightarrow $ Axiom of Choice.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  Given non-empty sets $\{A_i: i\in I\}$, well-order $\bigcup A_i$. Then define $f(i)$ to be the least element of $A_i$.
\end{proof}
Our conclusion is:
\begin{center}
  Axiom of Choice $\Leftrightarrow$ Zorn's lemma $\Leftrightarrow$ Well-ordering theorem.
\end{center}
Before we end, we need to do a small sanity check: we showed that these three statements are equivalents using a lot of ordinal theory. Our proofs above make sense only if we did not use AC when building our ordinal theory. Fortunately, we did not, apart from the remark that $\omega_1$ is not a countable supremum --- which used the fact that a countable union of countable sets is countable.

\subsection{Bourbaki-Witt theorem*}
Finally, we'll quickly present a second (non-examinable) fixed-point theorem. This time, we are concerned about \emph{chain-complete} posets and \emph{inflationary} functions.

\begin{defi}[Chain-complete poset]\index{chain-complete}
  We say a poset $X$ is \emph{chain-complete} if $X \not=\emptyset$ and every non-empty chain has a supremum.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}\leavevmode
  \begin{itemize}
    \item Every complete poset is chain-complete.
    \item Any finite (non-empty) poset is chain complete, since every chain is finite and has a greatest element.
    \item $\{A\subseteq V: A\text{ is linearly independent}\}$ for any vector space $V$ is chain-complete, as shown in the proof that every vector space has a basis.
  \end{itemize}
\end{eg}

\begin{defi}[Inflationary function]\index{inflationary function}
  A function $f: X\to X$ is \emph{inflationary} if $f(x) \geq x$ for all $x$.
\end{defi}

\begin{thm}[Bourbaki-Witt theorem]\index{Bourbaki-Witt theorem}
  If $X$ is chain-complete and $f: X\to X$ is inflationary, then $f$ has a fixed point.
\end{thm}
This is follows instantly from Zorn's, since $X$ has a maximal element $x$, and since $f(x) \geq x$, we must have $f(x) = x$. However, we can prove Bourbaki-Witt without choice. In the proof of Zorn's, we had to ``pick'' and $x_1 > x_0$. Here, we can simply let
\[
  x_0 \xmapsto{\,f\,} x_1 \xmapsto{\,f\,} x_2 \xmapsto{\,f\,} x_3 \cdots
\]
Since each chain has a \emph{supremum} instead of an upper bound, we also don't need Choice to pick our favorite upper bound of each chain.

Then we can do the same proof as Zorn's to find a fixed point.

We can view this as the ``AC-free'' part of Zorn's. It can be used to prove Zorn's lemma, but the proof is totally magic.

\section{Predicate logic}
\label{sec:predicate}\index{predicate logic}
In the first chapter, we studied propositional logic. However, it isn't sufficient for most mathematics we do.

In, say, group theory, we have a set of objects, operations and constants. For example, in group theory, we have the operations multiplication $m: A^2 \to A$, inverse $i: A\to A$, and a constant $e\in A$. For each of these, we assign a number known as the \emph{arity}, which specifies how many inputs each operation takes. For example, multiplication has arity 2, inverse has arity 1 and $e$ has arity $0$ (we can view $e$ as a function $A^0 \to A$, that takes no inputs and gives a single output).

The study of these objects is known as \emph{predicate logic}. Compared to propositional logic, we have a much richer language, which includes all the operations and possibly relations. For example, with group theory, we have $m, i, e$ in our language, as well as things like $\forall$, $\Rightarrow$ etc. Note that unlike propositional logic, different theories give rise to different languages.

Instead of a valuation, now we have a \emph{structure}, which is a solid object plus the operations and relations required. For example, a structure of group theory will be an actual concrete group with the group operations.

Similar to what we did in propositional logic, we will take $S\models t$ to mean ``for any structure in which $S$ is true, $t$ is true''. For example, ``Axioms of group theory'' $\models m(e, e) = e$, i.e.\ in any set that satisfies the group axioms, $m(e, e) = e$. We also have $S\vdash t$ meaning we can prove $t$ from $S$.

\subsection{Language of predicate logic}
We start with the definition of the language. This is substantially more complicated than what we've got in propositional logic.
\begin{defi}[Language]\index{language}
  Let $\Omega$ (function symbols) and $\Pi$ (relation symbols) be disjoint sets, and $\alpha : \Omega\cup\Pi \to \N$ a function ('arity').

  The \emph{language} $L = L(\Omega, \Pi, \alpha)$ is the set of formulae, defined as follows:

  \begin{itemize}
    \item \emph{Variables}\index{variable}: we have some variables $x_1, x_2, \cdots$. Sometimes (i.e.\ always), we write $x, y, z, \cdots$ instead.
    \item \emph{Terms}\index{term}: these are defined inductively by
      \begin{enumerate}
        \item Every variable is a term
        \item If $f\in \Omega$, $\alpha(f) = n$, and $t_1, \cdots, t_n$ are terms, then $ft_1\cdots t_n$ is a term. We often write $f(t_1, \cdots, t_n)$ instead.
      \end{enumerate}
      \begin{eg}
        In the language of groups $\Omega = \{m, i, e\}$, $\Pi = \emptyset$, and $\alpha (m) = 2, \alpha(i) = 1, \alpha(e) = 0$. Then $e, x_1, m(x_1, x_2), i(m(x_1, x_1))$ are terms.
      \end{eg}
    \item \emph{Atomic formulae}\index{atomic formulae}: there are three sorts:
      \begin{enumerate}
        \item $\bot$
        \item $(s = t)$ for any terms $s, t$.
        \item $(\phi t_1 \cdots t_n)$ for any $\phi\in \Pi$ with $\alpha(\phi) = n$ and $t_1, \cdots, t_n$ terms.
      \end{enumerate}
      \begin{eg}
        In the language of posets, $\Omega = \emptyset$, $\Pi=\{\leq\}$ and $\alpha(\leq) = 2$. Then $(x_1 = x_1)$, $x_1\leq x_2$ (really means $(\leq x_1x_2)$) are atomic formulae.
      \end{eg}
    \item \emph{Formulae}\index{formulae}: defined inductively by
      \begin{enumerate}
        \item Atomic formulae are formulae
        \item $(p \Rightarrow q)$ is a formula for any formulae $p, q$.
        \item $(\forall x) p$ is a formula for any formula $p$ and variable $x$.
      \end{enumerate}
      \begin{eg}
        In the language of groups, $e = e$, $x_1 = e$, $m(e, e) = e$, $(\forall x) m(x, i(x)) = e$, $(\forall x)(m(x, x) = e \Rightarrow (\exists y) (m(y, y) = x))$ are formulae.
      \end{eg}
  \end{itemize}
\end{defi}
It is important to note that a formula is a string of meaningless symbol. It doesn't make sense to ask whether it is true or false. In particular, the function and relation symbols are not assigned any meaning. The only thing the language cares is the arity of the symbol.

Again, we have the usual abbreviations $\neg p$, $p\wedge q$, $p\vee q$ etc. Also, we have $(\exists x)p$ for $\neg(\forall x)(\neg p)$.

\begin{defi}[Closed term]\index{closed term}
  A term is \emph{closed} if it has no variables.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  In the language of groups, $e, m(e, e)$ are closed terms. However, $m(x, i(x))$ is not closed even though we think it is always $e$. Apart from the fact that it is by definition not closed (it has a variable $x$), we do not have the groups axioms stating that $m(x, i(x)) = e$.
\end{eg}

\begin{defi}[Free and bound variables]\index{free variable}\index{bound variable}
  An occurrence of a variable $x$ in a formula $p$ is \emph{bound} if it is inside brackets of a $(\forall x)$ quantifier. It is \emph{free} otherwise.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  In $(\forall x)(m(x, x) = e)$, $x$ is a bound variable.

  In $(\forall y)(m(y, y) = x \Rightarrow m(x, y) = m(y, x))$, $y$ is bound while $x$ is free.

  We are technically allowed to have a formula with $x$ both bound and free, but \emph{DO NOT DO IT}. For example, $m(x, x) = e \Rightarrow (\forall x)(\forall y)(m(x, y) = m(y, x))$ is a valid formula (first two $x$ are free, while the others are bound).
\end{eg}

\begin{defi}[Sentence]\index{sentence}
  A \emph{sentence} is a formula with no free variables.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  $m(e, e) = e$ and $(\forall x)(m(x, x) = e)$ are sentences, while $m(x, i(x)) = e$ is not.
\end{eg}

\begin{defi}[Substitution]\index{substitution}
  For a formula $p$, a variable $x$ and a term $t$, the \emph{substitution} $p[t/x]$ is obtained by replacing each free occurrence of $x$ with $t$.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  If $p$ is the statement $(\exists y)(m(y, y) = x)$, then $p[e/x]$ is $(\exists y)(m(y, y) = e$.
\end{eg}
\subsection{Semantic entailment}
In propositional logic, we can't say whether a proposition is true or false unless we have a valuation. What would be a ``valuation'' in the case of predicate logic? It is a set with the operations of the right arity. We call this a structure.

For example, in the language of groups, a structure is a set $G$ with the correct operations. Note that it does not have to satisfy the group axioms in order to qualify as a structure.

\begin{defi}[Structure]\index{structure}
  An $L$-\emph{structure} is a non-empty set $A$ with a function $f_A: A^n \to A$ for each $f\in \Omega, \alpha(f) = n$, and a relation $\phi_A\subseteq A^n$, for each $\phi\in \Pi$, $\alpha(\phi) = n$.
\end{defi}
Note that we explicitly forbid $A$ from being empty. It is possible to formulate predicate logic that allows empty structures, but we will have to make many exceptions when defining our axioms, as we will see later. Since empty structures are mostly uninteresting (and don't exist if there is at least one constant), it isn't a huge problem if we ignore it. (There is a small caveat here --- we are working with single-sorted logic here, so everything is of the same ``type''. If we want to work with multi-sorted logic, where there can be things of different types, it would then be interesting to consider the case where some of the types could be empty).

\begin{eg}
  In the language of posets $A$, a structure is a set $A$ with a relation $\leq_A \subseteq A\times A$.

  In the language of groups, a structure is a set $A$ with functions $m_A: A\times A\to A$, $i_A: A\to A$ and $e_A\in A$.
\end{eg}
Again, these need not be genuine posets/groups since we do not have the axioms yet.

Now we want to define ``$p$ holds in $A$'' for a sentence $p\in L$ and a $L$-structure $A$.

For example, we want $(\forall x)(m(x, x) = e)$ to be true in $A$ iff for each $a\in A$, we have $m_A(a, a) = e_A$. So to translate $p$ into something about $A$, you ``add subscript $_A$ to each function-symbol and relation-symbol, insert $\in A$ after the quantifiers, and say it aloud''. We call this the interpretation of the sentence $p$.

This is not great as a definition. So we define it formally, and then quickly forget about it.

\begin{defi}[Interpretation]\index{interpretation}
  To define the \emph{interpretation} $p_A\in {0, 1}$ for each sentence $p$ and $L$-structure $A$, we define inductively:
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item Closed terms: define $t_A\in A$ for each closed term $t$ by
      \[
        (ft_1, \cdots, t_n)_A = f_A(t_{1_A}, t_{2_A}\cdots, t_{n_A})
      \]
      for any $f\in \Omega$, $\alpha(f) = n$, and closed terms $t_1, \cdots, t_n$.

      \begin{eg}
        $(m(m(e,e),e))_A = m_A(m_A(e_A, e_A),e_A)$.
      \end{eg}
    \item Atomic formulae:
      \begin{align*}
        \bot_A &= 0\\
        (s = t)_A &=
        \begin{cases}
          1 & s_A = t_A\\
          0 & s_A \not= t_A
        \end{cases}\\
        (\phi t_1 \cdots t_n)_A &=
        \begin{cases}
          1 & (t_{1_A}, \cdots, t_{n_A})\in \phi_A \\
          0 & \text{otherwise}
        \end{cases}.
      \end{align*}
    \item Sentences:
      \begin{align*}
        (p\Rightarrow q)_A &=
        \begin{cases}
          0 & p_A = 1, q_A = 0\\
          1 & \text{otherwise}
        \end{cases}\\
        ((\forall x)p)_A &=
        \begin{cases}
          1 & p[\bar a/x]_{\bar A} \text{ for all }a\in A\\
          0 & \text{otherwise}
        \end{cases}
      \end{align*}
      where for any $a\in A$, we define a new language $L'$ by adding a constant $\bar a$ and make $A$ into an $L'$ structure $\bar A$ by setting $\bar a_{\bar A} = a$.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{defi}
Now that we have formally defined truth, just forget about it!

Note that we have only defined the interpretation only for sentences. We can also define it for functions with free variables. For any formula $p$ with $n$ free variables, we can define the interpretation as the set of all things that satisfy $p$. For example, if $p$ is $(\exists y)(m(y, y) = a)$, then
\[
  p_A = \{a\in A: \exists b\in A\text{ such that } m(b, b) = a\}.
\]
However, we are mostly interested in sentences, and don't have to worry about these.

Now we can define models and entailment as in propositional logic.
\begin{defi}[Theory]\index{theory}
  A \emph{theory} is a set of sentences.
\end{defi}

\begin{defi}[Model]\index{model}
  If a sentence $p$ has $p_A = 1$, we say that $p$ \emph{holds} in $A$, or $p$ is \emph{true} in $A$, or $A$ is a model of $p$.

  For a theory $S$, a \emph{model} of $S$ is a structure that is a model for each $s\in S$.
\end{defi}

\begin{defi}[Semantic entailment]\index{semantic entailment}
  For a theory $S$ and a sentence $t$, $S$ \emph{entails} $t$, written as $S\models t$, if every model of $S$ is a model of $t$.

  ``Whenever $S$ is true, $t$ is also true''.
\end{defi}

\begin{defi}[Tautology]\index{tautology}
  $t$ is a \emph{tautology}, written $\models t$, if $\emptyset\models t$, i.e.\ it is true everywhere.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  $(\forall x)(x = x)$ is a tautology.
\end{eg}

\begin{eg}\leavevmode
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item Groups:
      \begin{itemize}
        \item The language $L$ is $\Omega = (m, i, e)$ and $\Pi = \emptyset$, with arities 2, 1, 0 respectively.
        \item Let $T$ be
          \begin{align*}
            \{&(\forall x)(\forall y)(\forall z) m(x,m(y, z)) = m(m(x, y), z),\\
              &(\forall x)(m(x, e) = x \wedge m(e, x) = x),\\
            & (\forall x)(m(x, i(x)) = e \wedge m(i(x), x) = e)\}.
          \end{align*}
      \end{itemize}
      Then an $L$-structure $A$ is a model for $T$ iff $A$ is a group. We say $T$ \emph{axiomatizes} the theory of groups/class of groups. Sometimes we call the members of $T$ the \emph{axioms} of $T$.

     Note that we could use a different language and theory to axiomatize group theory. For example, we can have $\Omega = (m, e)$ and change the last axiom to $(\forall x)(\exists y)(m(x, y) = e\wedge m(y, x) = e)\}$.
  \item Fields:
    \begin{itemize}
      \item The language $L$ is $\Omega = (+, \times, -, 0, 1)$ and $\Pi = \emptyset$, with arities 2, 2, 1, 0, 0.
      \item The theory $T$ consists of:
        \begin{itemize}
          \item Abelian group under $+$
          \item $\times$ is commutative, associative, and distributes over $+$
          \item $\neg (0 = 1)$
          \item $(\forall x)((\neg(x = 0)) \Rightarrow (\exists y)(y\times x = 1)$.
        \end{itemize}
        Then an $L$-structure is a model of $T$ iff it is a field. Then we have $T\models$ "inverses are unique", i.e.
        \[
          T\models (\forall x)\Big(\big(\neg(x = 0)\big) \Rightarrow (\forall y)(\forall z)\big((xy = 1 \wedge xz = 1)\Rightarrow (y = z)\big)\Big)
        \]
    \end{itemize}
  \item Posets:
    \begin{itemize}
      \item The language is $\Omega = \emptyset$, and $\Pi=\{\leq\}$ with arity 2.
      \item The theory $T$ is
        \begin{align*}
          \{& (\forall x)(x \leq x),\\
            & (\forall x)(\forall y)(\forall z)\big((x \leq y)\wedge(y \leq z) \Rightarrow x \leq z\big),\\
          & (\forall x)(\forall y)\big(x \leq y \wedge y \leq z \Rightarrow x = y\big)\}
        \end{align*}
        Then $T$ axiomatizes the theory of posets.
    \end{itemize}
  \item Graphs:
    \begin{itemize}
      \item The language $L$ is $\Omega = \emptyset$ and $\Pi = \{a\}$ with arity 2. This relation is ``adjacent to''. So $a(x, y)$ means there is an edge between $x$ and $y$.
      \item The theory is
        \begin{align*}
          \{& (\forall x)(\neg a(x, x)),\\
            & (\forall x)(\forall y)(a(x, y)\Leftrightarrow a(y, x)\}
          \end{align*}
    \end{itemize}
\end{enumerate}
Predicate logic is also called ``first-order logic''. It is ``first-order'' because our quantifiers range over \emph{elements} of the structure only, and not subsets. It would be difficult (and in fact impossible) to axiomatize, say, a complete ordered field, since the definition requires says every bounded \emph{subset} has a least upper bound.
\end{eg}

\subsection{Syntactic implication}
Again, to define syntactic implication, we need axioms and deduction rules.
\begin{defi}[Axioms of predicate logic]
  The \emph{axioms of predicate logic} consists of the 3 usual axioms, 2 to explain how $=$ works, and 2 to explain how $\forall$ works. They are
  \begin{enumerate}[label=\arabic{*}.]
    \item $p\Rightarrow (q\Rightarrow p)$ for any formulae $p, q$.
    \item $[p\Rightarrow (q\Rightarrow r)] \Rightarrow [(p\Rightarrow q)\Rightarrow (p\Rightarrow r)]$ for any formulae $p, q, r$.
    \item $(\neg \neg p\Rightarrow p)$ for any formula $p$.
    \item $(\forall x)(x = x)$ for any variable $x$.
    \item $(\forall x)(\forall y)\big((x = y)\Rightarrow (p \Rightarrow p[y/x])\big)$ for any variable $x, y$ and formula $p$, with $y$ not occurring bound in $p$.
    \item $[(\forall x)p] \Rightarrow p[t/x]$ for any formula $p$, variable $x$, term $t$ with no free variable of $t$ occurring bound in $p$.
    \item $[(\forall x)(p\Rightarrow q)]\Rightarrow [p\Rightarrow (\forall x)q]$ for any formulae $p, q$ with variable $x$ not occurring free in $p$.
  \end{enumerate}
  The \emph{deduction rules} are
  \begin{enumerate}[label=\arabic{*}.]
    \item Modus ponens\index{modus ponens}: From $p$ and $p\Rightarrow q$, we can deduce $q$.
    \item Generalization\index{generalization}: From $r$, we can deduce $(\forall x)r$, provided that no premise used in the proof so far had $x$ as a free variable.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{defi}
Again, we can define proofs, theorems etc.

\begin{defi}[Proof]\index{proof}
  A \emph{proof} of $p$ from $S$ is a sequence of statements, in which each statement is either an axiom, a statement in $S$, or obtained via modus ponens or generalization.
\end{defi}
\begin{defi}[Syntactic implication]\index{syntactic entailment}
  If there exists a proof a formula $p$ form a set of formulae $S$, we write $S\vdash p$ ``$S$ proves $t$''.
\end{defi}

\begin{defi}[Theorem]\index{theorem}
  If $S\vdash p$, we say $p$ is a \emph{theorem} of $S$. (e.g.\ a theorem of group theory)
\end{defi}

Note that these definitions are exactly the same as those we had in propositional logic. The only thing that changed is the set of axioms and deduction rules.

\begin{eg}
  $\{x = y, x = z\}\vdash y = z$.

  We go for $x = z$ giving $y = z$ using Axiom 5.

  \begin{enumerate}[label=\arabic{*}.]
    \item $(\forall x)(\forall y)((x = y)\Rightarrow (x = z\Rightarrow y=z))$\hfill Axiom 5
    \item $[(\forall x)(\forall y)((x = y)\Rightarrow (x = z\Rightarrow y=z))]\Rightarrow (\forall y)(x = y\Rightarrow y = z)$ \hfill Axiom 6
    \item $(\forall y)((x = y) \Rightarrow x = z \Rightarrow y = z)$\hfill MP on 1, 2
    \item $[(\forall y)((x = y) \Rightarrow x = z \Rightarrow y = z)]\Rightarrow [(x = y)\Rightarrow (x = z\Rightarrow y = z)$\hfill Axiom 6
    \item $(x = y) \Rightarrow [(x = z) \Rightarrow (y = z)]$\hfill MP on 3, 4
    \item $x = y$\hfill Premise
    \item $(x = z) \Rightarrow (y = z)$\hfill MP 6, 7
    \item $x = z$ \hfill Premise
    \item $y = z$ \hfill MP on 7, 8
  \end{enumerate}

  Note that in the first 5 rows, we are merely doing tricks to get rid of the $\forall$ signs.
\end{eg}

We can now revisit why we forbid $\emptyset$ from being a structure. If we allowed $\emptyset$, then $(\forall x)\bot$ holds in $\emptyset$. However, axioms 6 states that $((\forall x)\bot )\Rightarrow \bot$. So we can deduce $\bot$ in the empty structure! To fix this, we will have to add some weird clauses to our axioms, or simply forbid the empty structure!

Now we will prove the theorems we had for propositional logic.
\begin{prop}[Deduction theorem]\index{deduction theorem}
  Let $S\subseteq L$, and $p, q\in L$. Then $S\cup \{p\}\vdash q$ if and only if $S\vdash p\Rightarrow q$.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}
  The proof is exactly the same as the one for propositional logic, except in the $\Rightarrow $ case, we have to check Gen.

  Suppose we have lines
  \begin{itemize}
    \item $r$
    \item $(\forall x) r$\hfill Gen
  \end{itemize}
  and we have a proof of $S\vdash p\Rightarrow r$ (by induction). We want to seek a proof of $p\Rightarrow (\forall x)r$ from $S$.

  We know that no premise used in the proof of $r$ from $S\cup \{p\}$ had $x$ as a free variable, as required by the conditions of the use of Gen. Hence no premise used in the proof of $p\Rightarrow r$ from $S$ had $x$ as a free variable.

  Hence $S\vdash (\forall x)(p\Rightarrow r)$.

  If $x$ is not free in $p$, then we get $S\vdash p\Rightarrow (\forall x)r$ by Axiom 7 (and MP).

  If $x$ \emph{is} free in $p$, then we did not use premise $p$ in our proof $r$ from $S\cup \{p\}$ (by the conditions of the use of Gen). So $S\vdash r$, and hence $S\vdash (\forall x)r$ by Gen. So $S\vdash p\Rightarrow (\forall x)r$.
\end{proof}

Now we want to show $S\vdash p$ iff $S\models p$. For example, a sentence that holds in all groups should be deducible from the axioms of group theory.

\begin{prop}[Soundness theorem]\index{soundness theorem}
  Let $S$ be a set of sentences, $p$ a sentence. Then $S\vdash p$ implies $S\models p$.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}(non-examinable)
  We have a proof of $p$ from $S$, and want to show that for every model of $S$, $p$ holds.

  This is an easy induction on the lines of the proof, since our axioms are tautologies and our rules of deduction are sane.
\end{proof}

The hard part is proving
\[
  S\models p \Rightarrow S\vdash p.
\]
This is, by the deduction theorem,
\[
  S\cup \{\neg p\}\models \bot \Rightarrow S\cup \{\neg p\}\vdash \bot.
\]
This is equivalent to the contrapositive:
\[
  S\cup \{\neg p\} \not\vdash \bot \Rightarrow S\cup \{\neg p\}\not\models \bot.
\]

\begin{thm}[Model existence lemma]\index{model existence theorem}
  Let $S$ be a consistent set of sentences. Then $S$ has a model.
\end{thm}

We need several ideas to prove the lemma:
\begin{enumerate}
  \item We need to find a structure. Where can we start from? The only thing we have is the language. So we start form the language. Let $A =$ set of all closed terms, with the obvious operations.

    For example, in the theory of fields, we have ``$1 + 1$'', ``$0 + 1$`` etc in the structure. Then $(1 + 1) +_A (0 + 1) = (1 + 1) + (0 + 1)$.
  \item However, we have a problem. In, say, the language of fields, and $S$ our field axioms, our $A$ has distinct elements ``$1 + 0$'', ``$0 + 1$'', ``$0 + 1 + 0$'' etc. However, $S\vdash 1 + 0 = 0 + 1$ etc. So we can't have them as distinct elements. The solution is to quotient out by the equivalence relation $s\sim t$ if $S\vdash (s = t)$, i.e.\ our structure is the set of equivalence classes. It is trivial check to check that the $+$, $\times$ operations are well-defined for the equivalence classes.
  \item We have the next problem: If $S$ is ''field of characteristic 2 or 3``, i.e.\ $S$ has a field axiom plus $1 + 1 = 0 \vee 1 + 1 + 1 = 0$. Then $S\not\vdash 1 + 1 = 0$. Also $S\not\vdash 1 + 1 + 1 = 0$. So $[1 + 1] \not = [0]$, and $[1 + 1 + 1] \not= [0]$. But then our $S$ has neither characteristic $2$ or $3$.

    This is similar to the problem we had in the propositional logic case, where we didn't know what to do with $p_3$ if $S$ only talks about $p_1$ and $p_2$. So we first extend $S$ to a maximal consistent (or \emph{complete}) $\bar S$.

  \item Next problem: Let $S =$ ``fields with a square root of 2'', i.e.\ $S$ is the field axioms plus $(\exists x)(xx = 1 + 1)$. However, there is no closed term $t$ which is equivalent to $\sqrt{2}$. We say we lack \emph{witnesses} to the statement $(\exists x)(xx = 1 + 1)$. So we add a witness. We add a constant $c$ to the language, and add the axiom ``$cc = 1 + 1$'' to $S$. We do this for each such existential statement.

  \item Now what? We have added new symbols to $S$, so our new $S$ is no longer complete! Of course, we go back to (iii), and take the completion again. Then we have new existential statements to take care of, and we do (iv) again. Then we're back to (iii) again! It won't terminate!

      So we keep on going, and finally take the union of all stages.
  \end{enumerate}

\begin{proof}(non-examinable)
  Suppose we have a consistent $S$ in the language $L = L(\Omega, \Pi)$. Extend $S$ to a consistent $S_1$ such that $p\in S_1$ or $(\neg p)\in S$ for each sentence $p\in L$ (by applying Zorn's lemma to get a maximal consistent $S_1$). In particular, $S_1$ is \emph{complete}, meaning $S_1\vdash p$ or $S_1 \vdash \neg p$ for all $p$.

  Then for each sentence of the form $(\exists x)p$ in $S_1$, add a new constant $c$ to $L$ and add $p[c/x]$ to $S_1$ --- obtaining $T_1$ in language $L_1 = L(\Omega \cup C_1, \Pi)$. It is easy to check that $T_1$ is consistent.

  Extend $T_1$ to a complete theory $S_2\subseteq L_1$, and add witnesses to form $T_2 \subseteq L_2 = L(\Omega \cup C_1 \cup C_2, \Pi)$. Continue inductively.

  Let $\bar S = S_1 \cup S_2 \cup \cdots$ in language $\bar L = L_1\cup L_2\cup \cdots$ (i.e.\ $\bar L = L(\Omega\cup C_1\cup C_2\cup\cdots, \Pi)$).

  \begin{claim}
    $\bar S$ is consistent, complete, and has witnesses, i.e.\ if $(\exists x)p \in \bar S$, then $p[t/x]\in \bar S$ For some term $t$.
  \end{claim}

  It is consistent since if $\bar S \vdash \bot$, then some $S_n \vdash \bot$ since proofs are finite. But all $S_n$ are consistent. So $\bar S$ is consistent.

  To show completeness, for sentence $p\in \bar L$, we have $p\in L_n$ for some $n$, as $p$ has only finitely many symbols. So $S_{n + 1} \vdash p$ or $S_{n + 1}\vdash \neg p$. Hence $\bar S \vdash p$ or $\bar S \vdash \neg p$.

  To show existence of witnesses, if $(\exists x)p \in \bar S$, then $(\exists x) p\in S_n$ for some $n$. Hence (by construction of $T_n$), we have $p[c/x] \in T_n$ for some constant $c$.

  Now define an equivalence relation $\sim$ on closed term of $\bar L$ by $s\sim t$ if $\bar S\vdash (s = t)$. It is easy to check that this is indeed an equivalence relation. Let $A$ be the set of equivalence classes. Define
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $f_A([t_1],\cdots, [t_n]) = [f t_1, \cdots, t_n]$ for each formula $f\in \Omega$, $\alpha(f) = n$.
    \item $\phi_A = \{([t_1], \cdots, [t_n]): \bar S \vdash \phi(t_1, \cdots, t_n)\}$ for each relation $\phi \in \Pi$ and $\alpha (\phi) = n$.
  \end{enumerate}
  It is easy to check that this is well-defined.

  \begin{claim}
    For each sentence $p$, $\bar S\vdash p$ (i.e.\ $p\in \bar S$) if and only if $p$ holds in $A$, i.e.\ $p_A = 1$.
  \end{claim}
  We prove this by an easy induction.
  \begin{itemize}
    \item Atomic sentences:
      \begin{itemize}
        \item $\bot$: $\bar S \not\vdash \bot$, and $\bot_A = 0$. So good.
        \item $s = t$: $\bar S \vdash s = t$ iff $[s] = [t]$ (by definition) iff $s_A = t_A$ (by definition of $s_A$) iff $(s = t)_A$. So done.
        \item $\phi t_1, \cdots, t_n$ is the same.
      \end{itemize}
    \item Induction step:
      \begin{itemize}
        \item $p\Rightarrow q$: $\bar S\vdash (p \Rightarrow q)$ iff $\bar S \vdash (\neg p)$ or $\bar S\vdash q$ (justification: if $\bar S \not\vdash \neg p$ and $\bar S\not\vdash q$, then $\bar S\vdash p$ and $\bar S \vdash \neg q$ by completeness, hence $\bar S\vdash \neg(p\Rightarrow q)$, contradiction). This is true iff $p_A = 0$ or $q_A = 1$ iff $(p\Rightarrow q)_A = 1$.
        \item $(\exists x)p$: $\bar S \vdash (\exists x)p$ iff $\bar S\vdash p[t/x]$ for some closed term $t$. This is true since $\bar S$ has witnesses. Now this holds iff $p[t/x]_A = 1$ for some closed term $t$ (by induction). This is the same as saying $(\exists x)p$ holds in $A$, because $A$ is the set of (equivalence classes of) closed terms.
      \end{itemize}
      Here it is convenient to pretend $\exists$ is the primitive symbol instead of $\forall$. Then we can define $(\forall x) p$ to be $\neg (\exists x)\neg p$, instead of the other way round. It is clear that the two approaches are equivalent, but using $\exists $ as primitive makes the proof look clearer here.
  \end{itemize}
  Hence $A$ is a model of $\bar S$. Hence it is also a model of $S$. So $S$ has a model.
\end{proof}
Again, if $L$ is countable (i.e.\ $\Omega, \Pi$ are countable), then Zorn's Lemma is not needed.

From the Model Existence lemma, we obtain:
\begin{cor}[Adequacy theorem]\index{adequacy theorem}
  Let $S$ be a theory, and $p$ a sentence. Then $S\models p$ implies $S\vdash p$.
\end{cor}

\begin{thm}[G\"odel's completeness theorem (for first order logic)]\index{completeness theorem}\index{G\"odel's completeness theorem}
  Let $S$ be a theory, $p$ a sentence. Then $S\vdash p$ if and only if $S \models p$.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  $(\Rightarrow)$ Soundness, $(\Leftarrow)$ Adequacy.
\end{proof}

\begin{cor}[Compactness theorem]\index{compactness theorem}
  Let $S$ be a theory such that every finite subset of $S$ has a model. Then so does $S$.
\end{cor}

\begin{proof}
  Trivial if we replace ``has a model'' with ``is consistent'', because proofs are finite.
\end{proof}

We can look at some applications of this:

Can we axiomatize the theory of finite groups (in the language of groups)? i.e.\ is there a set of sentences $T$ such that models of $T$ are finite groups.

\begin{cor}
  The theory of finite groups cannot be axiomatized (in the language of groups).
\end{cor}
It is extraordinary that we can \emph{prove} this, as opposed to just ``believing it should be true''.

\begin{proof}
  Suppose theory $T$ has models all finite groups and nothing else. Let $T'$ be $T$ together with
  \begin{itemize}
    \item $(\exists x_1)(\exists x_2)(x_1 \not = x_2)$ (intuitively, $|G| \geq 2$)
    \item $(\exists x_1)(\exists x_2)(\exists x_3)(x_1 \not= x_2 \not= x_3)$ (intuitively, $|G| \geq 3$)
    \item $\cdots$
  \end{itemize}
  Then $T'$ has no model, since each model has to be simultaneously arbitrarily large and finite. But every finite subset of $T'$ does have a model (e.g.\ $\Z_n$ for some $n$). Contradiction.
\end{proof}
This proof looks rather simple, but it is not ``easy'' in any sense. We are using the full power of completeness (via compactness), and this is not easy to prove!

\begin{cor}
  Let $S$ be a theory with arbitrarily large models. Then $S$ has an infinite model.

  ``Finiteness is not a first-order property''
\end{cor}

\begin{proof}
  Same as above.
\end{proof}

Similarly, we have
\begin{cor}[Upward L\"owenheim-Skolem theorem]\index{L\"owenheim-Skolem theorem}\index{upward L\"owenheim-Skolem theorem}
  Let $S$ be a theory with an infinite model. Then $S$ has an uncountable model.
\end{cor}

\begin{proof}
  Add constants $\{c_i: i\in I\}$ to $L$ for some uncountable $I$.

  Let $T = S\bigcup\{\text{``}c_i \not= c_j\text{''}: i, j\in I, i \not = j\}$.

  Then any finite $T' \subseteq T$ has a model, since it can only mention finitely many of the $C_i$. So any infinite model of $S$ will do. Hence by compactness, $T$ has a model
\end{proof}
Similarly, we have a model for $S$ that does not inject into $X$, for any chosen set $X$. For example, we can add $\gamma(X)$ constants, or $\P(X)$ constants.

\begin{eg}
  There exists an infinite field ($\Q$). So there exists an uncountable field (e.g.\ $\R$). Also, there is a field that does not inject into $\P(\P(\R))$, say,
\end{eg}

\begin{thm}[Downward L\"owenheim-Skolem theorem]\index{L\"owenheim-Skolem theorem}\index{downward L\"owenheim-Skolem theorem}
  Let $L$ be a countable language (i.e.\ $\Omega$ and $\Pi$ are countable). Then if $S$ has a model, then it has a countable model.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  The model constructed in the proof of model existence theorem is countable.
\end{proof}
Note that the proof of the model existence theorem is non-examinable, but the proof of this is examinable! So we are supposed to magically know that the model constructed in the proof is countable without knowing what the proof itself is!

\subsection{Peano Arithmetic}
As an example, we will make the usual axioms for $\N$ into a first-order theory. We take $\Omega = \{0, s, +, \times\}$, and $\Pi = \emptyset$. The arities are $\alpha(0) = 0, \alpha(s) = 1, \alpha(+) = \alpha(\times) = 2$.

The operation $s$ is the \emph{successor}\index{successor} operation, which should be thought of as ``+1''.

Our axioms are
\begin{defi}[Peano's axioms]\index{Peano's axioms}\index{PA}
  The axioms of \emph{Peano's arithmetic} (PA) are
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $(\forall x)\neg(s(x) = 0)$.
    \item $(\forall x)(\forall y)((s(x) = s(y)) \Rightarrow (x = y))$.
    \item ${\color{gray}(\forall y_1)\cdots (\forall y_n)}[p[0/x] \wedge (\forall x)(p \Rightarrow p[s(x)/x])]\Rightarrow (\forall x)p$. This is actually infinitely many axioms --- one for each formula $p$, free variables $y_1, \cdots, y_n, x$, i.e.\ it is an axiom scheme.
    \item $(\forall x)(x + 0 = x)$.
    \item $(\forall x)(\forall y)(x + s(y) = s(x + y))$.
    \item $(\forall x)(x \times 0 = 0)$.
    \item $(\forall x)(\forall y)(x\times s(y) = (x + y) + x)$.
  \end{enumerate}
  Note that our third axiom looks rather funny with all the $(\forall y_i)$ in front. Our first guess at writing it would be
  \[
    [p[0/x] \wedge (\forall x)(p\Rightarrow p[s(x)/x])] \Rightarrow (\forall x)p.
  \]
  However, this is in fact not sufficient. Suppose we want to prove that for all $x$ and $y$, $x + y = y + x$. The natural thing to do would be to fix a $y$ and induct on $x$ (or the other way round). We want to be able to fix \emph{any} $y$ to do so. So we need a $(\forall y)$ in front of our induction axiom, so that we can prove it for all values of $y$ all at once, instead of proving it once for $y = 0$, once for $y = 1$ , once for $y = 1 + 1$ etc. This is important, since we might have an uncountable model of PA, and we cannot name all $y$. When we actually think about it, we can just forget about the $(\forall y_i)$s. But just remember that formally we need them.
\end{defi}
We know that PA has a model $\N$ that is infinite. So it has an uncountable model by Upward L\"owenheim-Skolem. Then clearly this model is not isomorphic to $\N$. However, we are also told that the axioms of arithmetic characterize $\N$ completely. Why is this so?

This is since Axiom 3 is not \emph{full} induction, but a ``first-order'' version. The proper induction axiom talks about \emph{subsets} of $\N$, i.e.
\[
  (\forall S\subseteq \N )((0 \in S \wedge x\in S \Rightarrow s(x)\in S)\Rightarrow S=\N).
\]
However, there are uncountably many subsets of $\N$, and countably many formulae $p$. So our Axiom 3 only talks about \emph{some} subsets of $\N$, not all.

Now the important question is: is PA complete?

G\"odel's \emph{in}completeness theorem says: no! There exists some $p$ with PA $\not\vdash p$ and PA $\not\vdash \neg p$.

Hence, there is a $p$ that is true in $\N$, but PA $\not\vdash p$.

Note that this does not contradict G\"odel's completeness theorem. The completeness theorem tells us that if $p$ holds in \emph{every} model of PA (not just in $\N$), then $PA\vdash p$.

\subsection{Completeness and categoricity*}
\begin{own}
  We now study some ``completeness'' property of theories. For convenience, we will assume that the language is countable.

  \begin{defi}[Complete theory]\index{complete theory}\index{theory!complete}
    A theory $T$ is \emph{complete} if for all propositions $p$ in the language, either $T \vdash p$ or $T \vdash \neg p$.
  \end{defi}
  Complete theories are rather hard to find. So for the moment, we will content ourselves by just looking at theories that are not complete.
  \begin{eg}
    The theory of groups is not complete, since the proposition
    \[
      (\forall g)(\forall h)(gh = hg)
    \]
    can neither be proven or disproven (there are abelian groups and non-abelian groups).
  \end{eg}
  Another ``completeness'' notion we might be interested in is \emph{categoricity}. We will need to use the notion of a cardinal, which will be introduced later in the course. Roughly, a cardinal is a mathematical object that denotes the sizes of sets, and a set ``has cardinality $\kappa$'' if it bijects with $\kappa$.
  \begin{defi}[$\kappa$-categorical]\index{$\kappa$-categorical}
    Let $\kappa$ be an infinite cardinal. Then a theory $T$ is \emph{$\kappa$-categorical} if there is a unique model of the theory of cardinality $\kappa$ up to isomorphism.
  \end{defi}

  Here the notion of ``isomorphism'' is the obvious one --- a homomorphism of models is a function between the structures that preserves everything, and an isomorphism is a homomorphism with an inverse (that is also a homomorphism).

  \begin{eg}[Pure identity theory]\index{pure identity theory}
    The \emph{pure identity theory} has an empty language and no axioms. Then this theory is $\kappa$-categorical for any $\kappa$, since if two models have the same cardinality, then by definition there is a bijection between them, and any such bijection is an isomorphism because there are no properties to be preserve.
  \end{eg}

  One nice thing about categorical theories is that they are complete!
  \begin{prop}
    Let $T$ be a theory that is $\kappa$ categorical for some $\kappa$, and suppose $T$ has no finite models. Then $T$ is complete.
  \end{prop}
  Note that the requirement that $T$ has no finite models is necessary. For example, pure identity theory is $\kappa$-categorical for all $\kappa$ but is not complete, since the statement $(\exists x)(\exists y)(\neg (x = y))$ is neither provable nor disprovable.
  \begin{proof}
    Let $p$ be a proposition. Suppose $T \not\vdash p$ and $T \not\vdash \neg p$. Then there are infinite models of $T \cup \{p\}$ and $T \cup \{\neg p\}$ (since the models cannot be finite), and so by the L\"owenhein--Skolem theorems, we can find such models of cardinality $\kappa$. But since one satisfies $p$ and the other does not, they cannot be isomorphic. This contradicts $\kappa$-categoricity.
  \end{proof}

  We are now going to use this idea to prove the \term{Ax-Grothendieck theorem}
  \begin{thm}[Ax-Grothendieck theorem]
    Let $f: \C^n \to \C^n$ be a complex polynomial. If $f$ is injective, then it is in fact a bijection.
  \end{thm}

  We will use the following result from field theory without proof:
  \begin{lemma}
    Any two uncountable algebraically closed fields with the same dimension and same characteristic are isomorphic. In other words, the theory of algebraically closed fields of characteristic $p$ (for $p$ a prime or $0$) is $\kappa$-categorical for all uncountable cardinals $\kappa$, and in particular complete.
  \end{lemma}
  The rough idea (for the field theorists) is that an algebraically closed field is uniquely determined by its transcendence degree over the base field $\Q$ or $\F_p$.

  In the following proof, we will also use some (very) elementary results about field theory that can be found in IID Galois Theory.

  \begin{proof}[Proof of Ax-Grothendieck]
    We will use compactness and completeness to show that we only have to prove this for fields of positive characteristic, and the result can be easily proven since we end up dealing with finite fields.

    Let $\mathrm{ACF}$ be the theory of algebraically closed fields. The language is the language of rings, and the axioms are the usual axioms of a field, plus the following axiom for each $n > 0$:
    \[
      (\forall a_0, a_1, \cdots, a_{n - 1})(\exists x)(x^n + a_{n - 1}x^{n - 1} + \cdots + a_1 x + a_0 = 0).
    \]
    Let $\mathrm{ACF}_0$ denote the theory of algebraically closed fields of characteristic $0$, where we add the axiom
    \[
      \underbrace{1 + 1 + \cdots + 1}_{n\text{ times}} \not= 0\tag{$*$}
    \]
    for all $n$ to $\mathrm{ACF}_n$.

    Let $\mathrm{ACF}_p$ denote the theory of algebraically closed fields of characteristic $p$, where we add the axiom
    \[
      \underbrace{1 + 1 + \cdots + 1}_{p\text{ times}} = 0
    \]
    to $\mathrm{ACF}$.

    We now notice the following fact: if $r$ is a proposition that is a theorem of $\mathrm{ACF}_p$ for all $p$, then it is true of $\mathrm{ACF}_0$. Indeed, we know that $\mathrm{ACF}_0$ is complete. So if $r$ is not a theorem in $\mathrm{ACF}_0$, then $\neg r$ is a theorem. But the proof is finite, so it can only use finitely many instances of $(*)$. So there is some large $p$ where $\neg r$ can be proven in $\mathrm{ACF}_p$, which is a contradiction.

    Now the statement ``If $f$ is a polynomial of degree $d$ and $f$ is injective, then $f$ is surjective'' can be expressed as a first-order statement. So we just have to prove it for all fields of characteristic $p > 0$. Moreover, by completeness, for each $p$, we only need to prove it for \emph{some} algebraically complete field of characteristic $p$.

    Fix a prime $p$, and consider $F = \bar{\F}_p$, the algebraic closure of $\F_p$. This is an algebraically closed field with the property that every element is algebraic over $\F_p$, i.e.\ the field generated by any finite subset of elements is finite.

    Let $f: F^n \to F^n$ be a polynomial function involving coefficients $a_1, \cdots, a_K$. Let $b = (b_1, \cdots, b_n) \in F^n$ be a point. Then $F$ restricts to a function from the field $\tilde{F}$ generated by $\{b_1, \cdots, b_n, a_1, \cdots, a_K\}$ to itself. But $\tilde{F}$ is finite, so any function $f|_{\tilde{F}}: \tilde{F} \to \tilde{F}$ that is injective must also be surjective. So $b$ is in the image of $f$. So $f$ is surjective. So done.
  \end{proof}

  We conclude the section by stating, without proof, a theorem by Morely:
  \begin{thm}[Morley's categoricity theorem]\index{Morley's categoricity theorem}
    Let $T$ be a theory with a countable language. If $T$ is $\kappa$-categorical for \emph{some} uncountable cardinal $\kappa$, then it is $\mu$-categorical for \emph{all} uncountable cardinals $\mu$.
  \end{thm}
  Hence we often just say a theory is uncountably categorical when the theory is categorical for some (hence all) uncountable cardinals.
\end{own}
\section{Set theory}
Here we'll axiomatize set theory as ``just another first-order theory'', with signatures, structures etc. There are many possible formulations, but the most common one is \emph{Zermelo Fraenkel set theory} (with the axiom of choice), which is what we will study.

\subsection{Axioms of set theory}
\begin{defi}[Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory]\index{Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory}\index{ZF}
  \emph{Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory} (ZF) has language $\Omega = \emptyset$, $\Pi = \{\in\}$, with arity 2.
\end{defi}
Then a ``universe of sets'' will simply mean a model of these axioms, a pair $(V, \in)$, where $V$ is a set and $\in$ is a binary relation on $V$ in which the axioms are true (officially, we should write $\in_V$, but it's so \emph{weird} that we don't do it). Each model $(V, \in)$ will (hopefully) contain a copy of all of maths, and so will look very complicated!

ZF will have 2 axioms to get started with, 4 to build things, and 3 more weird ones one might not realize are needed.

\begin{axiom}[Axiom of extension]\index{axiom!of extension}
  ``If two sets have the same elements, they are the same set''.
  \[
    (\forall x)(\forall y)((\forall z)(z\in x\Leftrightarrow z\in y) \Rightarrow x = y).
  \]
\end{axiom}
We could replace the $\Rightarrow $ with an $\Leftrightarrow$, but the converse statement $x = y \Rightarrow (z\in x \Leftrightarrow z\in y)$ is an instance of a logical axiom, and we don't have to explicitly state it.

\begin{axiom}[Axiom of separation]\index{axiom!of separation}
  ``Can form subsets of sets''. More precisely, for any set $x$ and a formula $p$, we can form $\{z\in x: p(z)\}$.
  \[
    {\color{gray}{(\forall t_1)\cdots(\forall t_n)}}(\forall x)(\exists y)(\forall z)(z\in y \Leftrightarrow (z\in x\wedge p)).
  \]
  This is an axiom scheme, with one instance for each formula $p$ with free variables $t_1, \cdots, t_n, z$.

  Note again that we have those funny $(\forall t_i)$. We do need them to form, e.g.\ $\{z\in x: t\in z\}$, where $t$ is a parameter.

  This is sometimes known as Axiom of comprehension.
\end{axiom}
\begin{axiom}[Axiom of empty set]\index{axiom!of empty set}
  ``The empty-set exists''
  \[
    (\exists x)(\forall y)(y\not\in x).
  \]
  We write $\emptyset$ for the (unique, by extension) set with no members. This is an abbreviation: $p(\emptyset)$ means $(\exists x)(x\text{ has no members}\wedge p(x))$. Similarly, we tend to write $\{z\in x: p(z)\}$ for the set given by separation.
\end{axiom}
\begin{axiom}[Axiom of pair set]\index{axiom!of pair set}
  ``Can form $\{x, y\}$''.
  \[
    (\forall x)(\forall y)(\exists z)(\forall t)(t\in z \Leftrightarrow (t= x\vee t = y)).
  \]
  We write $\{x, y\}$ for this set. We write $\{x\}$ for $\{x, x\}$.
\end{axiom}

We can now define ordered pairs:
\begin{defi}[Ordered pair]\index{ordered pair}
  An \emph{ordered pair} $(x, y)$ is $\{\{x\}, \{x, y\}\}$.

  We define ``$x$ is an ordered pair'' to mean $(\exists y)(\exists z)(x = (y, z))$.
\end{defi}
We can show that $(a, b) = (c, d) \Leftrightarrow (a = c) \wedge (b = d)$.

\begin{defi}[Function]\index{function}
  We define ``$f$ is a \emph{function}'' to mean
  \begin{align*}
    & (\forall x)(x\in f\Rightarrow x\text{ is an ordered pair})\wedge\\
    & (\forall x)(\forall y)(\forall z)[(x, y)\in f \wedge (x, z)\in f]\Rightarrow y = z.
  \end{align*}
  We define $x = \dom f$ to mean $f$ is a function and $(\forall y)(y\in x \Leftrightarrow (\exists z)((y, z)\in f))$.

  We define $f: x\to y$ to mean $f$ is a function and $\dom f = x$ and
  \[
    (\forall z)[(\exists t)((t, z)\in f)\Rightarrow z\in y].
  \]
\end{defi}
Once we've defined them formally, let's totally forget about the definition and move on with life.

\begin{axiom}[Axiom of union]\index{axiom!of union}
  ``We can form unions'' Intuitively, we have $a\cup b\cup c = \{x: x\in a \text{ or }x\in b\text{ or }x\in c\}$. but instead of $a\cup b\cup c$, we write $\bigcup\{a, b, c\}$ so that we can express infinite unions as well.
  \[
    (\forall x)(\exists y)(\forall z)(z\in y \Leftrightarrow (\exists t)(t\in x \wedge z\in t)).
  \]
  We tend to write $\bigcup x$ for the set given above. We also write $x\cup y$ for $\bigcup\{x, y\}$.
\end{axiom}

Note that we can define intersection $\bigcap x$ as a subset of $y$ (for any $y\in x$) by separation, so we don't need an axiom for that.
\begin{axiom}[Axiom of power set]\index{axiom!of power set}
  ``Can form power sets''.
  \[
    (\forall x)(\exists y)(\forall z)(z\in y \Leftrightarrow z\subseteq x),
  \]
  where $z\subseteq x$ means $(\forall t)(t\in z \Rightarrow t\in x)$.

  We tend to write $\P(x)$ for the set generated above.
\end{axiom}
We can now form $x\times y$, as a subset of $\P(\P(x\cup y))$, because for $t\in x, s\in y$, we have $(t, s) = \{\{t\},\{t, s\}\}\in \P(\P(x\cup y))$.

Similarly, we can form the set of all functions from $x$ to $y$ as a subset of $\P(x\times y)$ (or $\P(\P(\P(x\cup y)))$!).

Now we've got the easy axioms. Time for the weird ones.

\subsubsection*{Axiom of infinity}\index{axiom!of infinity}
From the axioms so far, we cannot prove that there is an infinite set! We start from the empty set, and all the operations above can only produce finite sets. So we need an axiom to say that the natural numbers exists.

But how could we do so in finitely many words? So far, we do have infinitely many sets. For example, if we write $x^+$ for $x\cup \{x\}$, it is easy to check that $\empty, \emptyset^+, \emptyset^{++}, \cdots$ are all distinct.

(Writing them out explicitly, we have $\emptyset^+ = \{\emptyset\}$, $\emptyset^{++} = \{\emptyset, \{\emptyset\}\}$, $\emptyset^{+++} = \{\emptyset, \{\emptyset\}, \{\emptyset, \{\emptyset\}\}\}$. We can also write $0$ for $\emptyset$, $1$ for $\emptyset^{+}$, $2$ for $\emptyset^{++}$. So $0 = \emptyset$, $1 = \{0\}$, $2 = \{0, 1\}, \cdots$)

Note that all of these are individually sets, and so $V$ is definitely infinite. However, inside $V$, $V$ is not a set, or else we can apply separation to obtain Russell's paradox.

So the collection of all $0, 1, \cdots, $ need not be a set. Therefore we want an axiom that declares this is a set. So we want an axiom stating $\exists x$ such that $\emptyset\in x, \emptyset^+\in x, \emptyset^{++}\in x, \cdots$. But this is an infinite statement, and we need a smarter way of formulating this.

\begin{axiom}[Axiom of infinity]
  ``There is an infinite set''.
  \[
    (\exists x)(\emptyset\in x \wedge (\forall y)(y\in x \Rightarrow y^+ \in x)).
  \]
  We say any set that satisfies the above axiom is a successor set.
\end{axiom}
A successor set can contain a lot of nonsense elements. How do we want to obtain $\N$, without nonsense?

We know that the intersection of successors is also a successor set. So there is a \emph{least} successor set, i.e.\ the intersection of all successor sets. Call this $\omega$. This will be our copy of $\N$ in $V$. So
\[
  (\forall x)(x\in \omega \Leftrightarrow (\forall y)(y\text{ is a successor set} \Rightarrow x \in y)).
\]
Therefore, if we have
\[
  (\forall x)[(x \subseteq \omega\wedge x\text{ is a successor set}) \Rightarrow x = \omega],
\]
by definition of $\omega$. By the definition of ``is a successor set'', we can write this as
\[
  (\forall x)[(x\subseteq \omega \wedge \emptyset\in x \wedge (\forall y)(y\in x \Rightarrow y^+ \in x))\Rightarrow x = \omega].
\]
This is genuine induction (in $V$)! It is not just our weak first-order axiom in Peano's axioms.

Also, we have
\[
  (\forall x)(x\in \omega \Rightarrow x^+ \not = \emptyset)\text{ and }(\forall x)(\forall y)((x\in \omega \wedge y\in \omega \wedge x^+ = y^+) \Rightarrow x = y)
\]
by $\omega$-induction (i.e.\ induction on $\omega$). Hence $\omega$ satisfies the axioms of natural numbers.

We can now write, e.g.\ ``$x$ is finite'' for $(\exists y)(\exists f)(y\in x \wedge f\text{ bijects }x\text{ with }y)$.

Similarly, we define ``$x$ is countable'' to mean ``$x$ is finite or $x$ bijects with $\omega$''.

That's about it for this axiom. Time for the next one:
\subsubsection*{Axiom of foundation}\index{axiom!of foundation}
``Sets are built out of simpler sets''. We want to ban weird things like $x\in x$, or $x\in y\wedge y\in x$, or similarly for longer chains. We also don't want infinite descending chains like $\cdots x_3 \in x_2 \in x_1 \in x_0$.

How can we capture the ``wrongness'' of these weird things all together? In the first case $x\in x$, we see that $\{x\}$ has no $\in$-minimal element (we say $y$ is $\in$-minimal in $x$ if $(\forall z\in x)(z\not\in y)$). In the second case, $\{x, y\}$ has no minimal element. In the last case, $\{x_0, x_1, x_2, \cdots\}$ has no $\in$-minimal element.


\begin{axiom}[Axiom of foundation]
  ``Every (non-empty) set has an $\in$-minimal member''
  \[
    (\forall x)(x\not= \emptyset \Rightarrow (\exists y)(y\in x\wedge (\forall z)(z\in x \Rightarrow z\not\in y))).
  \]
  This is sometimes known as the Axiom of regularity.
\end{axiom}
Note that most of the time, we don't actually use the Axiom of Foundation. It's here just so that our universe ``looks nice''. Most results in set theory don't rely on foundation.

We will later show that this entails that all sets in $V$ can be ``built out of'' the empty set, but that's left for a later time.

\subsubsection*{Axiom of replacement}
In ordinary mathematics, we often say things like ``for each $x\in I$, we have some $A_i$. Now take $\{A_i: i\in I\}$''. For example, (after defining ordinals), we want to have the set $\{\omega + i: i\in \omega\}$.

How do we know that $\{A_i: i\in I\}$ is a set? How do we know that $i\mapsto A_i$ is a function, i.e.\ that $\{(i, A_i): i\in I\}$ is a set? It feels like it should be. We want an axiom that says something along the line of ``the image of a set under a function is a set''. However, we do not know that the thing is a function yet. So we will have ``the image of a set under something that looks like a function is a set''.

To formally talk about ``something that looks like a function'', we need a digression on classes:

\subsubsection*{Digression on classes}
$x\mapsto \{x\}$ for all $x$ looks like a function, but isn't it, since every function $f$ has a (set) domain, defined as a suitable subset of $\bigcup \bigcup f$, but our function here has domain $V$.

So what is this $x\mapsto \{x\}$? We call it a class.
\begin{defi}[Class]\index{class}
  Let $(V, \in)$ be an $L$-structure. A \emph{class} is a collection $C$ of points of $V$ such that, for some formula $p$ with free variable $x$ (and maybe more funny parameters), we have
  \[
    x\in C\Leftrightarrow p\text{ holds}.
  \]
  Intuitively, everything of the form $\{x\in V: p(x)\}$ is a class.
\end{defi}
Note that here we are abusing notation. When we say $x\in C$, the symbol $\in$ does not mean the membership relation in $V$. Inside the theory, we should view $x\in C$ as a shorthand of ``$p(x)$ holds''.

\begin{eg}\leavevmode
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $V$ is a class, by letting $p$ be ``$x = x$''.
    \item For any $t$, $\{x\in V: t\in x\}$ is a class, with $p$ being $t\in x$. Here $t$ is a parameter.
    \item For any set $y\in V$, $y$ is a class --- let $p$ be ``$x\in y$''.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{eg}

\begin{defi}[Proper class]\index{proper class}
  We say $C$ is a \emph{proper class} if $C$ is not a set (in $V$), ie
  \[
    \neg (\exists y)(\forall x)(x\in y\Leftrightarrow p).
  \]
\end{defi}

Similarly, we can have
\begin{defi}[Function-class]\index{function class}
  A \emph{function-class} $F$ is a collection of ordered pairs such that there is a formula $p$ with free variables $x, y$ (and maybe more) such that
  \[
    (x, y) \in F \Leftrightarrow p\text{ holds, and } (x, y)\in F\wedge (x, z)\in F \Rightarrow y = z.
  \]
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  $x\mapsto \{x\}$ is a function-class: take $p$ to be $y = \{x\}$.
\end{eg}

\subsubsection*{Back to replacement}\index{axiom!of replacement}
How do we talk about function-classes? We cannot refer to classes inside $V$. Instead, we must refer to the first-order formula $p$.

\begin{axiom}[Axiom of replacement]
  ``The image of a set under a function-class is a set''. This is an axiom scheme, with an instance for each first-order formula $p$:
  \begin{align*}
   \underbrace{{\color{gray}{(\forall t_1)\cdots(\forall t_n)}}}_{\text{parameters }}\big(&\underbrace{[(\forall x)(\forall y)(\forall z)((p\wedge p[z/y])\Rightarrow y=z)]}_{p\text{ defines a function-class}}\\
   & \Rightarrow \underbrace{[(\forall x)(\exists y)(z\in y \Leftrightarrow (\exists t)(t\in x\wedge p[t/x, z/y]))]}_{\text{image of }x\text{ under }F\text{ is a set}}\big).
  \end{align*}
\end{axiom}

\begin{eg}
  For any set $x$, we can form $\{\{t\}: t\in x\}$ by $p$ being ``$y = \{x\}$''. However, this is a \emph{bad} use of replacement, because we can already obtain that by power set (and separation).

  We will give a good example later.
\end{eg}

So that's all the axioms of ZF. Note that we did not include the Axiom of choice!

\subsubsection*{Axiom of choice}\index{axiom!of choice}
\begin{defi}[ZFC]\index{ZFC}
  ZFC is the axioms ZF + AC, where AC is the axiom of choice, ``every family of non-empty sets has a choice function''.
  \begin{align*}
    (\forall f)[&(\forall x)(x\in \dom f \Rightarrow f(x)\not= \emptyset) \Rightarrow \\
    &(\exists g)(\dom g = \dom f) \wedge (\forall x)(x\in \dom g \Rightarrow g(x) \in f(x))]
  \end{align*}
  Here we define a family of sets $\{A_i: i \in I\}$ to be a function $f: I \to V$ such that $i \mapsto A_i$.
\end{defi}

\subsection{Properties of ZF}
Now, what does $V$ look like? We start with the following definition:
\begin{defi}[Transitive set]\index{transitive}
  A set $x$ is \emph{transitive} if every member of a member of $x$ is a member of $x$:
  \[
    (\forall y)((\exists z)(y\in z\wedge z\in x)\Rightarrow y \in x).
  \]
  This can be more concisely written as $\bigcup x \subseteq x$, but is very confusing and impossible to understand!
\end{defi}
This notion seems absurd --- and it is. It is only of importance in the context of set theory and understanding what $V$ looks like. It is an utterly useless notion in, say, group theory.

\begin{eg}
  $\{\emptyset, \{\emptyset\}\}$ is transitive. In general, for any $n\in \omega$, $n$ is transitive. $\omega$ is also transitive.
\end{eg}

\begin{lemma}
  Every $x$ is contained in a transitive set.
\end{lemma}
Note that this is a theorem of $ZF$, i.e.\ it officially means: let $(V, \in)$ be a model of ZF. Then in $V$, $<$stuff above$>$. Equivalently, ZF $\vdash$ $<$stuff above$>$.

We know that any intersection of transitive sets is transitive. So this lemma will tell us that $x$ is contained in a \emph{least} transitive set, called the \emph{transitive closure} of $x$, or $TC(x)$.

\begin{proof}
  We'd like to form ``$x\cup (\bigcup x)\cup (\bigcup\bigcup x)\cup (\bigcup\bigcup\bigcup x)\cup \cdots$''. If this makes sense, then we are done, since the final product is clearly transitive. This will be a set by the union axiom applied to $\{x, \bigcup x, \bigcup\bigcup x, \cdots\}$, which itself is a set by replacement applied to $\omega$, for the function-class $0\mapsto x$, $1\mapsto \bigcup x$, $2\mapsto \bigcup\bigcup x$ etc.

  Of course we have to show that the above is a function class, i.e.\ can be expressed as a first order relation. We might want to write the sentence as:
  \[
    p(s, t)\text{ is }(s = 0\wedge t = x)\vee (\exists u)(\exists v)(s = u + 1\wedge t = \textstyle{\bigcup} v \wedge p(u, v)),
  \]
  but this is complete nonsense! We are defining $p$ in terms of itself!

  The solution would be to use attempts, as we did previously for recursion. We define ``$f$ is an attempt'' to mean ``$f$ is a function and $\dom f\in \omega$ and $\dom f\not=\emptyset$ and $f(0) = x$ and $(\forall n)(n\in \omega \wedge n\in \dom f)\Rightarrow f(n) = \bigcup f(n - 1)$, i.e.\ $f$ is defined for some natural numbers and meet our requirements when it is defined.

  Then it is easy to show that two attempts $f$ and $f'$ agree whenever both are defined. Also, $\forall n\in \omega$, there is an attempt $f$ defined for $n$ (both by $\omega$-induction).

  Note that the definition of an attempt is a first-order formula. So our function class is
  \[
    p(s, t)\text{ is } (\exists f)(f\text{ is an attempt}\wedge y\in \dom f \wedge f(y) = z).\qedhere
  \]
\end{proof}
This is a good use of replacement, unlike our example above.

We previously said that Foundation captures the notion ``every set is built out of simpler sets''. What does that exactly mean? If this is true, we should be able to do induction on it: if $p(y)$ for all $y\in x$, then $p(x)$.

If this sounds weird, think about the natural numbers: everything is built from $0$ using $+1$. So we can do induction on $\omega$.

\begin{thm}[Principle of $\in$-induction]\index{$\in$-induction}
  For each formula $p$, with free variables $t_1, \cdots, t_n, x$,
  \[
    {\color{gray}{(\forall t_1)\cdots(\forall t_n)}}\big([(\forall x)((\forall y)(y\in x \Rightarrow p(y))) \Rightarrow p(x)] \Rightarrow (\forall x)(p(x))\big)
  \]
  Note that officially, $p(y)$ means $p[y/x]$ and $p(x)$ is simply $x$.
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  Given $t_1, \cdots, t_n$, suppose $\neg (\forall x)p(x)$. So we have some $x$ with $\neg p(x)$. Similar to how we proved regular induction on naturals from the well-ordering principle (in IA Numbers and Sets), we find a minimal $x$ such that $p(x)$ does not hold.

  While foundation allows us to take the minimal element of a \emph{set}, $\{y: \neg p(y)\}$ need not be a set --- e.g.\ if $p(y)$ is $y \not= y$.

  Instead, we pick a single $x$ such that $\neg p(x)$. Let $u = TC(\{x\})$. Then $\{y\in u: \neg p(y)\} \not= \emptyset$, since $x\in u$. So it has an $\in$-minimal element, say $y$, by Foundation. Then each $z\in y$ has $z\in u$ since $u$ is transitive. Hence $p(z)$ by minimality of $y$. But this implies $p(y)$. Contradiction.
\end{proof}
Note that here we used the transitive closure to reduce from reasoning about the whole scary $V$, to an actual set $TC(x)$. This technique is rather useful.

We have now used Foundation to prove $\in$-induction. It turns out that the two are in fact equivalent.

\begin{prop}
  $\in$-induction $\Rightarrow $ Foundation.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}
  To deduce foundation from $\in$-induction, the obvious $p(x)$ --- $x$ has an $\in$-minimal member, doesn't work.

  Instead, consider $p(x)$ given by
  \[
    (\forall y)\,x\in y \Rightarrow y\text{ has an }\in\text{-minimal member}.
  \]
  If $p(x)$ is true, we say $x$ is \emph{regular}. To show that $(\forall x)p(x)$, it is enough to show that: if every $y\in x$ is regular, then $x$ is regular.

  Given any $z$ with $x\in z$, we want to show that $z$ has an $\in$-minimal member.

  If $x$ is itself minimal in $z$, then done. Otherwise, then $y\in z$ for some $y\in x$. But since $y\in x$, $y$ is regular. So $z$ has a minimal element.

  Hence all $x$ is regular. Since all non-empty sets contain at least one element (by definition), all sets have $\in$-minimal member.
\end{proof}
This looked rather simple to prove. However, it is because we had the clever idea of regularity. If we didn't we would be stuck for a long time!

Now what about recursion? Can we define $f(x)$ using $f(y)$ for all $y\in x$?

\begin{thm}[$\in$-recursion theorem]\index{$\in$-recursion}
  Let $G$ be a function-class, everywhere defined. Then there is a function-class $F$ such that $F(x) = G(F|_x)$ for all $x$. Moreover, $F$ is unique (cf.\ definition of recursion on well-orderings).
\end{thm}
Note that $F|_x = \{(y, F(y)): y\in x\}$ is a set, by replacement.

\begin{proof}
  We first show existence. Again, we prove this with attempts. Define ``$f$ is an attempt'' to mean ``$f$ is a function and $\dom f$ is transitive and $(\forall x)(x\in \dom f \Rightarrow f(x) = G(f|_x))$''.

  Then by simple $\in$-induction, we have
  \begin{align*}
    (\forall x)(\forall f')[(&f\text{ an attempt defined at }x\wedge\\
    & f'\text{ an attempt defined at $x$}) \Rightarrow f(x) = f'(x)].
  \end{align*}
  Also, $(\forall x)(\exists f)(f\text{ an attempt defined at }x)$, again by $\in$-induction: suppose for each $y\in x$, there exists an attempt defined at $y$. So there exists a unique attempt $f_y$ with domain $TC(\{y\})$. Set $f = \bigcup_{y\in x}f_y$, and let $f' = f\bigcup \{(x, G(f|_x)\}$. Then this is an attempt defined at $x$.

  So we take $q(x, y)$ to be
  \[
    (\exists f)(f\text{ is an attempt defined at }x\text{ with }f(x) = y).
  \]
  Uniqueness follows form $\in$-induction.
\end{proof}
Note that this is exactly the same as the proof of recursion on well-orderings. It is just that we have some extra mumbling about transitive closures.

So we proved recursion and induction for $\in$. What property of the relation-class $\in$ (with $p(x, y)$ defined as $x\in y$) did we use? We most importantly used the Axiom of foundation, which says that
\begin{enumerate}
  \item $p$ is \emph{well-founded}: every set has a $p$-minimal element.
  \item $p$ is \emph{local}: ie, $\{x: p(x, y)\}$ is a set for each $y$. We needed this to form the transitive closure.
\end{enumerate}

\begin{defi}[Well-founded relation]\index{well-founded relation}
  A relation-class $R$ is \emph{well-founded} if every set has a $R$-minimal element.
\end{defi}

\begin{defi}[Local relation]\index{local relation}
  A relation-class $R$ is \emph{local} if $\{x: p(x, y)\}$ is a set for each $y$.
\end{defi}

So we will have
\begin{prop}
  $p$-induction and $p$-recursion are well-defined and valid for any $p(x, y)$ that is well-founded and local.
\end{prop}

\begin{proof}
  Same as above.
\end{proof}
Note that if $r$ is a relation on a set $a$, then $r$ is trivially local. So we just need $r$ to be well-founded. In particular, our induction and recursion theorems for well-orderings are special cases of this.

We have almost replicated everything we proved for well-orderings, except for subset collapse. We will now do that.

This is motivated by the following question: can we model a given relation on a set by $\in$?

For example, let $a = \{b, c, d\}$, with $b\,r\,c$ and $c\;r\;d$. Can we find a set $\{b', c', d'\}$ such that $b'\in c'$ and $c'\in d'$? Yes. We can put $b' = \emptyset$, $c' = \{\emptyset\}$, $d' = \{\{\emptyset\}\}$. Moreover, $a' = \{b', c', d'\}$ is transitive.

\begin{defi}[Extensional relation]\index{extension relation}
  We say a relation $r$ on set $a$ is \emph{extensional} if
  \[
    (\forall x\in a)(\forall y\in a)((\forall z\in a)(z\,r\,x \Leftrightarrow z\,r\,y)\Rightarrow x = y).
  \]
  i.e.\ it obeys the axiom of extension.
\end{defi}

\begin{thm}[Mostowski collapse theorem]\index{Mostowski collapse theorem}
  Let $r$ be a relation on a set $a$ that is well-founded and extensional. Then there exists a transitive $b$ and a bijection $f: a \to b$ such that $(\forall x, y\in a)(x\, r\, y\Leftrightarrow f(x) \in f(y))$. Moreover, $b$ and $f$ are unique.
\end{thm}
Note that the two conditions ``well-founded'' and ``extensional'' are trivially necessary, since $\in$ is both well-founded and extensional.

\begin{proof}
  Existence: define $f$ on $a$ the obvious way --- $f(x) = \{f(y): y\,r\,x\}$. This is well-defined by $r$-recursion, and is a genuine function, not just of a function class by replacement --- it is an image of $a$.

  Let $b = \{f(x): x\in a\}$ (this is a set by replacement). We need to show that it is transitive and bijective.

  By definition of $f$, $b$ is transitive, and $f$ is surjective as $b$ is \emph{defined} to be the image of $f$. So we have to show that $f$ is injective.

  We'll show that $(\forall x\in a)(f(y) = f(x) \Rightarrow y = x)$ for each $x\in a$, by $r$-induction. Given $y\in a$, with $f(y) = f(x)$, we have $\{f(t): t\,r\, y\} = \{f(s): s\,r\,y\}$ by definition of $f$. So $\{t: t\,r \, y\}=\{s: s\,r \, x\}$ by the induction hypothesis. Hence $x = y$ since $r$ is extensional.

  So we have constructed such an $b$ and $f$. Now we show it is unique: for any suitable $f, f'$, we have $f(x) = f'(x)$ for all $x\in a$ by $r$-induction.
\end{proof}

Recall that we defined the ordinals to be the ``equivalence class'' of all well-orderings. But this is not a good definition since the ordinals won't be sets. Hence we define them (formally) as follows:
\begin{defi}[Ordinal]\index{ordinal}
  An \emph{ordinal} is a transitive set, totally ordered by $\in$.
\end{defi}
This is automatically well-ordered by $\in$, by foundation.

\begin{eg}
  $\emptyset$, $\{\emptyset\}$, $\{\emptyset, \{\emptyset\}\}$ are ordinals. Any $n\in \omega$ as $n = \{0, 1, \cdots, n - 1\}$, as well as $\omega$ itself, are ordinals.
\end{eg}

Why is this a good definition? Mostowski says that each well-ordering is order-isomorphic to a unique ordinal (using our definition of ordinal above) --- this is its order-type. So here, instead of saying that the ordinals is the equivalence class of well-orderings, we simply choose one representative of each equivalence class (given by Mostowski collapse), and call that the ordinal.

For any ordinal $\alpha$, $I_\alpha = \{\beta: \beta < \alpha \}$ is a well-ordering of order-type $\alpha$. Applying Mostowski collapse, we get $\alpha = \{\beta: \beta < \alpha\}$. So $\beta < \alpha$ iff $\beta \in \alpha$.

So, for example, $\alpha^+ = \alpha \cup \{\alpha\}$, and $\sup \{\alpha_k: k\in I\} = \bigcup\{\alpha_i: i\in I\}$, Set theorists are often write suprema as unions, but this is a totally unhelpful notation!

\subsection{Picture of the universe}
What does the universe look like? We start with the empty set, and take the power set, repeatedly, transfinitely.

\begin{defi}[von Neumann hierarchy]\index{von Neumann hierarchy}
  Define sets $V_\alpha$ for $\alpha \in \mathrm{On}$ (where $\mathrm{On}$ is the class of ordinals) by $\in$-recursion:
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $V_0 = \emptyset$.
    \item $V_{\alpha + 1} = \P(V_\alpha)$.
    \item $V_\lambda = \bigcup\{V_\gamma: \gamma < \lambda\}$ for $\lambda$ a non-zero limit ordinal.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{defi}
\begin{center}
  \begin{tikzpicture}
    \draw [->] (0, 0) -- (0, 6) node [above] {On};
    \draw (-3, 6) -- (0, 0) -- (3, 6);
    \draw (-0.15, 0.3) -- (0.15, 0.3) node [right] {$V_0 = \emptyset$};
    \draw (-0.375, 0.75) -- (0.375, 0.75) node [right] {$V_1 = \{\emptyset\}$};
    \draw (-1, 2) -- (1, 2) node [right] {$V_7$};
    \node at (-0.75, 2.6) {$\vdots$};
    \node at (0.75, 2.6) {$\vdots$};
    \draw (-1.5, 3) -- (1.5, 3) node [right] {$V_\omega$};
    \draw (-1.75, 3.5) -- (1.75, 3.5) node [right] {$V_{\omega + 1}$};
    \node at (-0.75, 4.1) {$\vdots$};
    \node at (0.75, 4.1) {$\vdots$};
    \draw (-2.3, 4.6) -- (2.3, 4.6) node [right] {$V_{\omega + \omega}$};
    \node at (-0.75, 5.3) {$\vdots$};
    \node at (0.75, 5.3) {$\vdots$};
  \end{tikzpicture}
\end{center}
Note that by definition, we have $x\subseteq V_\alpha \Leftrightarrow x\in V_{\alpha + 1}$.

We would like every $x$ to be in some $V_\alpha$, and that is indeed true. We prove this though a series of lemmas:

\begin{lemma}
  Each $V_\alpha$ is transitive.
\end{lemma}

\begin{proof}
  Since we define $V_\alpha$ by recursion, it is sensible to prove this by induction:

  By induction on $\alpha$:
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item Zero: $V_0 = \emptyset$ is transitive.
    \item Successors: If $x$ is transitive, then so is $\P(x)$: given $y\in z\in \P(x)$, we want to show that $y\in \P(x)$. Since $y$ is in a member of $\P(x)$, i.e.\ a subset of $x$, we must have $y\in x$. So $y\subseteq x$ since $x$ is transitive. So $y\in \P(x)$.
    \item Limits: Any union of transitive sets is transitive.\qedhere
  \end{enumerate}
\end{proof}

\begin{lemma}
  If $\alpha \leq \beta$, then $V_\alpha \subseteq V_\beta$.
\end{lemma}

\begin{proof}
  Fix $\alpha$, and induct on $\beta$.
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $\beta = \alpha$: trivial
    \item Successors: $V_{\beta^+}\subseteq V_\beta$ since $x\subseteq \P(x)$ for transitive $x$. So $V_\alpha \subseteq V_\beta \Rightarrow V_\alpha \subseteq V_{\beta^+}$.
    \item Limits: Trivial by definition\qedhere
  \end{enumerate}
\end{proof}

Finally we are ready for:
\begin{thm}
  Every $x$ belongs to some $V_\alpha$. Intuitively, we want to say
  \[
    V = \bigcup_{\alpha \in \mathrm{On}} V_\alpha,
  \]
\end{thm}
We'll need some terminology to start with. If $x\subseteq V_\alpha$ for some $\alpha$, then there is a least $\alpha$ with $x\subseteq V_\alpha$. We call this the \emph{rank} of $x$.

For example, $\rank(\emptyset) = 0$, $\rank(\{\emptyset\}) = 1$. Also $\rank(\omega) = \omega$. In fact, $\rank(\alpha) = \alpha$ for all $\alpha\in \mathrm{On}$.

Note that we want the least $\alpha$ such that $x\subseteq V_\alpha$, \emph{not} $x\in V_\alpha$.

\begin{proof}
  We'll show that $(\forall x)(\exists \alpha)(x\in V_\alpha)$ by $\in$-induction on $x$.

  So we are allowed to assume that for each $y\in x$, we have $y\subseteq V_\alpha$ for some $\alpha$. So $y\subseteq V_{\rank(y)}$, or $y\in V_{\rank(y) + 1}$.

  Let $\alpha = \sup\{(\rank(y)^+: y\in x\}$. Then $y\in V_\alpha$ for every $y\in x$. So $x\subseteq V_\alpha$.
\end{proof}

Our definition of rank is easy to get wrong --- it is easy to be off by of 1. So the official definition is
\begin{defi}[Rank]\index{rank}
  The \emph{rank} of a set $x$ is defined recursively by
  \[
    \rank(x) = \sup\{(\rank y)^+ : y\in x\}.
  \]
\end{defi}

Then the initial definition we had is now a proposition.
\begin{prop}
  $\rank(x)$ is the first $\alpha$ such that $x\subseteq V_\alpha$.
\end{prop}

\section{Cardinals}
In this chapter, we will look at the ``sizes'' of (infinite) sets (finite sets are boring!). We work in ZFC, since things become really weird without Choice.

Since we will talk about bijections a lot, we will have the following notation:
\begin{notation}
  Write $x\leftrightarrow y$ for $\exists f: f$ is a bijection from $x$ to $y$.
\end{notation}

\subsection{Definitions}
We want to define $\card(x)$ (the \emph{cardinality}, or \emph{size} of $x$) in such a way that $\card(x) = \card(y) \Leftrightarrow x\leftrightarrow y$. We can't define $\card(x) = \{y: y\leftrightarrow x\}$ as it may not be a set. So we want to pick a ``representative'' of the sets that biject with $x$, like how we defined the ordinals.

So why not use the ordinals? By Choice, we know that all $x$ is well-orderable. So $x\leftrightarrow \alpha$ for some $\alpha$. So we define:
\begin{defi}[Cardinality]\index{cardinality}
  The \emph{cardinality} of a set $x$, written $\card(x)$, is the least ordinal $\alpha$ such that $x\leftrightarrow \alpha$.
\end{defi}
Then we have (trivially) $\card(x) = \card(y) \Leftrightarrow x\leftrightarrow y$.

(What if we don't have Choice, i.e.\ if we are in ZF? This will need a really clever trick, called the \emph{Scott trick}. In our universe of ZF, there is a huge of blob of things that biject with $x$. We cannot take the whole blob (it won't be a set), or pick one of them (requires Choice). So we ``chop off'' the blob at fixed, determined point, so we are left with a set.

Define the essential rank of $x$ to be the least rank of all $y$ such that $y\leftrightarrow x$. Then set $\card (x) = \{y\in V_{\mathrm{essrank}(x)^+}: y\leftrightarrow x\}$.)

So what cardinals are there? Clearly we have $1, 2, 3, \cdots$. What else?

\begin{defi}[Initial ordinal]\index{initial ordinal}
  We say an ordinal $\alpha$ is \emph{initial} if
  \[
    (\forall \beta < \alpha)(\neg \beta \leftrightarrow \alpha),
  \]
  i.e.\ it is the smallest ordinal of that cardinality.
\end{defi}

Then $0, 1, 2, 3, \cdots, \omega, \omega_1, \gamma(X)$ for any $X$ are all initial. However, $\omega^\omega$ is not initial, as it bijects with $\omega$ (both are countable).

Can we find them all? Yes!
\begin{defi}[Omega ordinals]\index{$\omega_\alpha$}
  We define $\omega_\alpha$ for each $\alpha \in \mathrm{On}$ by
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $\omega_0 = \omega$;
    \item $\omega_{\alpha + 1} = \gamma(\omega_\alpha)$;
    \item $\omega_\lambda = \sup\{\omega_\alpha: \alpha < \lambda\}$ for non-zero limit $\lambda$.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{defi}
It is easy induction to show that each $\omega_\alpha$ is initial. We can also show that every initial $\delta$ (for $\delta \geq \omega$) is an $\omega_\alpha$. We know that the $\omega_\alpha$ are unbounded since, say $\omega_\alpha \geq \alpha$ for all $\alpha$. So there is a least $\alpha$ with $\omega_\alpha \geq \delta$.

If $\alpha$ is a successor, then let $\alpha = \beta^+$. Then $\omega_\beta < \delta \leq \omega_\alpha$. But there is no initial ordinal between $\omega_\beta$ and $\omega_\alpha = \gamma(\omega_\beta)$, since $\gamma(X)$ is defined as the \emph{least} ordinal that does not biject with $X$. So we must have $\delta = \omega_\alpha$.

If $\alpha$ is a limit, then since $\omega_\alpha$ is defined as a supremum, by definition we cannot have $\delta < \omega_\alpha$, or else there is some $\beta < \alpha$ with $\delta < \omega_\beta$. So $\omega_\alpha = \delta$ as well.

\begin{defi}[Aleph number]\index{$\aleph_\alpha$}
  Write $\aleph_\alpha$ (``aleph-$\alpha$'') for $\card(\omega_\alpha)$.
\end{defi}

Then from the argument above, we have
\begin{thm}
  The $\aleph_\alpha$ are the cardinals of all infinite sets (or, in ZF, the cardinals of all infinite well-orderable sets). For example, $\card(\omega) = \aleph_0$, $\card \omega_1 = \aleph_1$.
\end{thm}

We will use lower case letters to denote cardinalities and upper case for the sets with that cardinality. e.g.\ $\card(N) = n$.

\begin{defi}[Cardinal (in)equality]\index{cardinal inequality}
  For cardinals $n$ and $m$, write $m \leq n$ if $M$ injects into $N$, where $\card M = m, \card N = n$. This clearly does not depend on $M$ and $N$.

  So $m \leq n$ and $n\leq m$ implies $n = m$ by Schr\"oder-Bernstein. Write $m < n$ if $m \leq n$ by $m\not = n$.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  $\card(\P(\omega)) > \card(\omega)$.
\end{eg}

This $\leq$ is a partial order. Moreover, it is a total order (assuming AC).

\subsection{Cardinal arithmetic}
\begin{defi}[Cardinal addition, multiplication and exponentiation]\index{cardinal addition}\index{cardinal multiplication}\index{cardinal exponentiation}
  For cardinals $m, n$, write $m + n$ for $\card(M\sqcup N)$; $mn$ for $\card(M\times N)$; and $m^n$ for $\card(M^N)$, where $M^N = \{f: f\text{ is a function }N\to M\}$. Note that this coincides with our usual definition of $X^n$ for finite $n$.
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  $\R \leftrightarrow \P(\omega) \leftrightarrow 2^\omega$. So $\card(\R) = \card(\P_\omega) = 2^{\aleph_0}$.
\end{eg}

Similarly, define
\[
  \sum_{i \in I} m_i = \card\left(\bigsqcup_{i\in I} M_i\right).
\]

\begin{eg}
  How many sequences of reals are there? A real sequence is a function from $\omega \to \R$. We have
  \[
    \card(\R^\omega) = (2^{\aleph_0})^{\aleph_0} = 2^{\aleph_0 \times \aleph_0} = 2^{\aleph_0} = \card(\R)
  \]
\end{eg}
Note that we used facts like
\begin{prop}\leavevmode
  \begin{enumerate}
    \item $m + n = n + m$ since $N\sqcup M \leftrightarrow N\sqcup N$ with the obvious bijection.
    \item $mn = nm$ using the obvious bijection
    \item $(m^n)^p = m^{np}$ as $(M^N)^P \leftrightarrow M^{N\times P}$ since both objects take in a $P$ and an $N$ and returns an $M$.
  \end{enumerate}
\end{prop}
It is important to note that cardinal exponentiation is different from ordinal exponentiation. For example, $\omega^\omega$ (ordinal exponentiation) is countable, but $\aleph_0^{\aleph_0} \geq 2^{\aleph_0} > \aleph_0$ (cardinal exponentiation).

From IA Numbers and sets, we know that $\aleph_0 \aleph_0 = \aleph_0$. What about $\aleph_1 \aleph_1$? Or $\aleph_3 \aleph_0$?

It turns out that cardinal sums and multiplications are utterly boring:
\begin{thm}
  For every ordinal $\alpha$,
  \[
    \aleph_\alpha \aleph_\alpha = \aleph_\alpha.
  \]
  This is the best we could ever ask for. What can be simpler?
\end{thm}

\begin{proof}
  Since the Alephs are defined by induction, it makes sense to prove it by induction.

  In the following proof, there is a small part that doesn't work nicely with $\alpha = 0$. But $\alpha = 0$ case (ie $\aleph_0\aleph_0 = \aleph_0$) is already done. So assume $\alpha \not= 0$.

  Induct on $\alpha$. We want $\omega_\alpha \times \omega_\alpha$ to biject with $\omega_\alpha$, i.e.\ well-order $\omega_\alpha \times \omega_\alpha$ to an ordering of length $\omega_\alpha$.

  Using the ordinal product clearly doesn't work. The ordinal product counts the product in rows, so we have many copies of $\omega_\alpha$. When we proved $\aleph_0\aleph_0 = \aleph_0$, we counted them diagonally. But counting diagonally here doesn't look very nice, since we will have to ``jump over'' infinities. Instead, we count in squares
  \begin{center}
    \begin{tikzpicture}
      \draw rectangle (3, 3);
      \node at (1.5, 3) [above] {$\omega_\alpha$};
      \node at (3, 1.5) [right] {$\omega_\alpha$};
      \draw (0, 1) -- (1, 1) -- (1, 0);
      \draw (0, 1.5) -- (1.5, 1.5) -- (1.5, 0);
      \draw (0, 1.8) -- (1.8, 1.8) -- (1.8, 0);
    \end{tikzpicture}
  \end{center}
  We set $(x, y) < (x', y')$ if \emph{either} $\max(x, y) < \max(x', y')$ (this says that $(x', y')$ is in a bigger square), \emph{or}, (say $\max(x, y) = \max(x', y') = \beta$ and $y' = \beta, y < \beta$ or $x = x' = \beta, y < y'$ or $y = y' = \beta, x < x'$) (nonsense used to order things in the same square --- utterly unimportant).

  How do we show that this has order type $\omega_\alpha$? We show that any initial segment has order type $ < \omega_\alpha$.

  For any proper initial segment $I_{(x, y)}$, we have
  \[
    I_{(x, y)} \subseteq \beta\times \beta
  \]
  for some $\beta < \omega_\alpha$, since $\omega_\alpha$ is a limit, with wlog $\beta$ infinite. So
  \[
    \beta\times \beta \leftrightarrow \beta
  \]
  by induction hypothesis (their cardinality is less that $\omega_\alpha$). So
  \[
    \card(\beta\times \beta) < \card(\omega_\alpha).
  \]
  Hence $I_{(x, y)}$ has order type $ < \omega_\alpha$. Thus the order type of our well-order is $\leq \omega_\alpha$. So $\omega_\alpha \times \omega_\alpha$ injects into $\omega_\alpha$. Since trivially $\omega_\alpha$ injects into $\omega_\alpha \times \omega_\alpha$, we have $\omega_\alpha \times \omega_\alpha \leftrightarrow \omega_\alpha$.
\end{proof}
So why did we say cardinal arithmetic is boring? We have
\begin{cor}
  Let $\alpha \leq \beta$. Then
  \[
    \aleph_\alpha + \aleph_\beta = \aleph_\alpha\aleph_\beta = \aleph_\beta.
  \]
\end{cor}

\begin{proof}
  \[
    \aleph_\beta \leq \aleph_\alpha + \aleph_\beta \leq \aleph_\beta + \aleph_\beta = 2\aleph_\beta \leq \aleph_\beta\times \aleph_\beta = \aleph_\beta,
  \]
  So done
\end{proof}

\begin{eg}
  $X\sqcup X$ bijects with $X$, for infinite $X$ (in ZFC).
\end{eg}

However, cardinal exponentiation is \emph{very hard}. For example, is $2^{\aleph_0} = \aleph_1$? This is the continuum hypothesis, and cannot be proved or disproved in ZFC!

Even today, not all implications among values of $\aleph_\alpha^{\aleph_\beta}$ are known, i.e.\ we don't know whether they are true, false or independent!
\section{Incompleteness*}
The big goal of this (non-examinable) chapter is to show that PA is incomplete, i.e.\ there is a sentence $p$ such that $\mathrm{PA}\not\vdash p$ and $\mathrm{PA}\not\vdash \neg p$.

The strategy is to find a $p$ that is true in $\N$, but $\mathrm{PA}\not\vdash p$.

Here we say ``true'' to mean ``true in $\N$'', and ``provable'' to mean ``PA proves it''.

The idea is to find a $p$ that says ``I am not provable''. More precisely, we want a $p$ such that $p$ is true if and only if $p$ is not provable. We are then done: $p$ must be true, since if $p$ were false, then it is provable, i.e.\ $\mathrm{PA}\vdash p$. So $p$ holds in every model of PA, and in particular, $p$ holds in $\N$. Contradiction. So $p$ is true. So $p$ is not provable.

We'll have to ``code'' formulae, proofs etc. inside PA, i.e.\ as numbers. But this doesn't seem possible --- it seems like, in any format, ``$p$ is not provable'' must be longer than $p$. So $p$ cannot say ``$p$ is not provable``!

So be prepared for some magic to come up in the middle for the proof!

\subsection*{Definability}
We first start with some notions of definability.

\begin{defi}[Definability]\index{definability}
  A subset $S\subseteq \N$ is \emph{definable} if there is a formula $p$ with one free variable such that
  \[
    \forall m\in \N:\; m\in S \Leftrightarrow p(m)\text{ holds}.
  \]
  Similarly, $f: \N \to \N$ is \emph{definable} if there exists a formula $p(x, y)$ such that
  \[
    \forall m, n\in \N:\; f(m) = n \Leftrightarrow p(m, n)\text{ holds}.
  \]
\end{defi}

\begin{eg}
  The set of primes is definable: $p(x)$ is
  \[
    x\not = 1 \wedge (\forall y)(\forall z)(yz = x \Rightarrow (y = 1\vee z = 1)).
  \]
  We can say ``$m$ is prime'' is definable.

  How about powers of $2$? We don't have exponentiation here. What can we do? We can take $p(x)$ to be
  \[
    (\forall y)((y\text{ is prime}\wedge y \mid x) \Rightarrow y = 2),
  \]
  where $2$ is a shorthand for $s(s(0))$, and $y\mid x$ is a shorthand for $(\exists z)(yz = x)$. So this is also definable.

  The function $m\mapsto m^2$ is also definable: take $p(x, y)$ to be $yy = x$.
\end{eg}

Here we will assume:
\begin{fact}
  Any function given by an algorithm is definable.
\end{fact}
Proof will not be given here. See, eg, PTJ's book for detailed proof.

\begin{eg}
  $m\mapsto 2^m$ is definable.
\end{eg}

\subsection*{Coding}
Our language has 12 symbols: $s, 0, \times, +, \bot, \Rightarrow, (, ), =, x, ', \forall$ (where the variables are now called $x, x', x'', x'''$.

We assign values to them, say $v(s) = 1, v(0) = 2, \cdots, v(\forall) = 12$. To code a formula, we can take
\[
  2^{v(\text{first symbol})}\cdot 3^{v(\text{second symbol})}\cdots (n\text{th prime})^{v(n\text{th symbol})}.
\]
For example, $(\forall x)(x = x)$ is coded as
\[
  2^7 3^{12}5^{10}7^8 11^7 13^{10}17^9 23^8.
\]
Not every $m$ codes a formula, e.g.\ $2^7 3^{12}5^{10}$ is translated to $(\forall x$, which is clearly nonsense. Similarly, $2^7 7^3$ or $2^{100}$ can't even be translated at all.

However, ``$m$ codes a formula'' is definable, as there is an algorithm that checks that.

Write $S_m$ for the formula coded by $m$ (and set $S_m$ to be ``$\bot$'' if $m$ does not code a formula). Similarly, write $c(p)$ for the code of $p$.

Given a finite sequence $p_1, \cdots p_n$ for formulae, code it as
\[
  2^{c(p_1)}3^{c(p_2)}\cdots (n\text{th prime})^{c(p_n)}.
\]
Alternatively, we can add a separator character to our 12 symbols and concatenate the sequence of formulae with the separator character.

Now, ``$m$ codes an axiom (either logical or axiom of PA)'' is definable, as there exists an algorithm to check it. For example, an instance of the first logical axiom can be validated by the following regex:
\[
  \verb/^\([s0()=x'\+/\mathtt{\times\bot\Rightarrow\forall}\verb/]+\)/\mathtt{\Rightarrow}\verb/([s0()=x'\+/\mathtt{\times\bot\Rightarrow\forall}\verb/]+/\Rightarrow\verb/\1)$/
\]
(after translating to a sentence and verifying it is a valid logical formula)

Also,
\begin{center}
  $\phi(\ell, m, n) = $``$S_n$ obtained from $S_\ell$, $S_m$ via MP''
\end{center}
is definable, and similarly for generalization.

So
\[
  \Theta(m, n) =\text{``}n\text{ codes a proof of }S_m\text{''}
\]
is definable.

Thus
\[
  \Psi(m) = \text{``}S_m\text{ is provable''}
\]
is definable as
\[
  \Psi(m) \Leftrightarrow (\exists n)\Theta(m, n).
\]
So far, everything is rather boring. We all \emph{know} that strings of symbols can be coded into numbers --- that's what computers do!

\subsection*{Clever bit}
Consider the statement $\chi(m)$ that states
\begin{center}
  ``$m$ codes a formula $S_m$ with one free variable, and $S_m(m)$ is not provable.''
\end{center}
This is clearly definable. Suppose this is defined by $p$. So
\[
  \chi(n) \Leftrightarrow p[n/x]
\]
Suppose $c(p) = N$. Then $\chi(N)$ asserts
\begin{center}
  ``$N$ codes a formula $S_N$ with one free variable and $S_N(N)$ is not provable.''
\end{center}
But we already know that $N$ codes the formula $\chi$. So $\chi(N)$ asserts that $\chi(N)$ is not provable.

So
\begin{thm}[G\"odel's incompleteness theorem]\index{G\"odel's incompleteness theorem}
  PA is incomplete.
\end{thm}

Maybe that's because PA is rubbish. Could we add some clever axiom $t$ (true in $\N$) to PA, so that PA$\cup \{t\}$ is complete? No! Just run the same proof with ``PA'' replaced by ``PA$\cup \{t\}$'' to show that PA$\cup\{t\}$ is incomplete.

But we can certainly extend PA to a complete theory --- let $T = \{p: p\text{ holds in }\N\}$. What will go wrong in our proof? It can only be because
\begin{thm}
  ``Truth is not definable''

  $T= \{p: p\text{ holds in }\N\}$ is not definable. This officially means
  \[
    \{m: m\text{ codes a member of }T\}
  \]
  is not a definable set.
\end{thm}

Next question: we proved that our clever statement $p$ is true but not provable. Why doesn't this formalize into PA? The answer is, in the proof, we also used the fact that PA has a model, $\N$. By completeness, this means that we used the statement con(PA), i.e.\ the statement that PA is consistent, or
\[
  (\forall m)(m\text{ does not code a proof of }\bot).
\]
With this statement, the proof does formalize to PA. So PA$\cup \{\text{con(PA)}\}\vdash p$. Hence
\begin{thm}
  PA $\not \vdash$ con(PA).
\end{thm}

The same proof works in ZF. So ZF is incomplete and ZF does not prove its own consistency.

\printindex
\end{document}