Datasets:
Tasks:
Text Generation
Modalities:
Text
Sub-tasks:
language-modeling
Languages:
English
Size:
100K - 1M
License:
\input{preamble} | |
% OK, start here. | |
% | |
\begin{document} | |
\title{Examples of Stacks} | |
\maketitle | |
\phantomsection | |
\label{section-phantom} | |
\tableofcontents | |
\section{Introduction} | |
\label{section-introduction} | |
\noindent | |
This is a discussion of examples of stacks in algebraic geometry. | |
Some of them are algebraic stacks, some are not. | |
We will discuss which are algebraic stacks in a later chapter. | |
This means that in this chapter we mainly worry about the descent | |
conditions. See \cite{Vis2} for example. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
Some of the notation, conventions and terminology in this chapter is awkward | |
and may seem backwards to the more experienced reader. This is intentional. | |
Please see Quot, Section \ref{quot-section-conventions} for an | |
explanation. | |
\section{Notation} | |
\label{section-notation} | |
\noindent | |
In this chapter we fix a suitable big fppf site $\Sch_{fppf}$ | |
as in Topologies, Definition \ref{topologies-definition-big-fppf-site}. | |
So, if not explicitly stated otherwise all schemes will be objects | |
of $\Sch_{fppf}$. | |
We will always work relative to a base $S$ contained in $\Sch_{fppf}$. | |
And we will then work with the big fppf site $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$, | |
see Topologies, Definition \ref{topologies-definition-big-small-fppf}. | |
The absolute case can be recovered by taking | |
$S = \Spec(\mathbf{Z})$. | |
\section{Examples of stacks} | |
\label{section-examples-stacks} | |
\noindent | |
We first give some important examples of stacks over | |
$(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\section{Quasi-coherent sheaves} | |
\label{section-stack-of-quasi-coherent-sheaves} | |
\noindent | |
We define a category $\QCohstack$ as follows: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item An object of $\QCohstack$ is a pair $(X, \mathcal{F})$, | |
where $X/S$ is an object of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$, and $\mathcal{F}$ | |
is a quasi-coherent $\mathcal{O}_X$-module, and | |
\item a morphism $(f, \varphi) : (Y, \mathcal{G}) \to (X, \mathcal{F})$ | |
is a pair consisting of a morphism $f : Y \to X$ of schemes over $S$ | |
and an $f$-map (see | |
Sheaves, Section \ref{sheaves-section-ringed-spaces-functoriality-modules}) | |
$\varphi : \mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{G}$. | |
\item The composition of morphisms | |
$$ | |
(Z, \mathcal{H}) \xrightarrow{(g, \psi)} | |
(Y, \mathcal{G}) \xrightarrow{(f, \phi)} (X, \mathcal{F}) | |
$$ | |
is $(f \circ g, \psi \circ \phi)$ where $\psi \circ \phi$ is | |
the composition of $f$-maps. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
Thus $\QCohstack$ is a category and | |
$$ | |
p : \QCohstack \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}, | |
\quad | |
(X, \mathcal{F}) \mapsto X | |
$$ | |
is a functor. Note that the fibre category of $\QCohstack$ over | |
a scheme $X$ is the opposite of the category $\QCoh(\mathcal{O}_X)$ | |
of quasi-coherent $\mathcal{O}_X$-modules. | |
We remark for later use that given | |
$(X, \mathcal{F}), (Y, \mathcal{G}) \in \Ob(\QCohstack)$ | |
we have | |
\begin{equation} | |
\label{equation-morphisms-qcoh} | |
\Mor_{\QCohstack}((Y, \mathcal{G}), (X, \mathcal{F})) | |
= | |
\coprod\nolimits_{f \in \Mor_S(Y, X)} | |
\Mor_{\QCoh(\mathcal{O}_Y)}(f^*\mathcal{F}, \mathcal{G}) | |
\end{equation} | |
See the discussion on $f$-maps of modules in | |
Sheaves, Section \ref{sheaves-section-ringed-spaces-functoriality-modules}. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
The category $\QCohstack$ is not a stack over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
because its collection of objects is a proper class. On the other hand | |
we will see that it does satisfy all the axioms of a stack. We will | |
get around the set theoretical issue in | |
Section \ref{section-stack-of-finitely-generated-quasi-coherent-sheaves}. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-quasi-coherent-strongly-cartesian} | |
A morphism $(f, \varphi) : (Y, \mathcal{G}) \to (X, \mathcal{F})$ | |
of $\QCohstack$ is strongly cartesian if and only if the | |
map $\varphi$ induces an isomorphism $f^*\mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{G}$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Let $(X, \mathcal{F}) \in \Ob(\QCohstack)$. | |
Let $f : Y \to X$ be a morphism of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
Note that there is a canonical $f$-map $c : \mathcal{F} \to f^*\mathcal{F}$ | |
and hence we get a morphism | |
$(f, c) : (Y, f^*\mathcal{F}) \to (X, \mathcal{F})$. | |
We claim that $(f, c)$ is strongly cartesian. | |
Namely, for any object $(Z, \mathcal{H})$ of $\QCohstack$ we have | |
\begin{align*} | |
\Mor_{\QCohstack}((Z, \mathcal{H}), (Y, f^*\mathcal{F})) | |
& = | |
\coprod\nolimits_{g \in \Mor_S(Z, Y)} | |
\Mor_{\QCoh(\mathcal{O}_Z)}(g^*f^*\mathcal{F}, \mathcal{H}) \\ | |
& = | |
\coprod\nolimits_{g \in \Mor_S(Z, Y)} | |
\Mor_{\QCoh(\mathcal{O}_Z)}((f \circ g)^*\mathcal{F}, \mathcal{H}) \\ | |
& = | |
\Mor_{\QCohstack}((Z, \mathcal{H}), (X, \mathcal{F})) | |
\times_{\Mor_S(Z, X)} \Mor_S(Z, Y) | |
\end{align*} | |
where we have used Equation (\ref{equation-morphisms-qcoh}) twice. | |
This proves that the condition of | |
Categories, Definition \ref{categories-definition-cartesian-over-C} | |
holds for $(f, c)$, and hence our claim is true. Now by | |
Categories, Lemma \ref{categories-lemma-composition-cartesian} | |
we see that isomorphisms are strongly cartesian and | |
compositions of strongly cartesian morphisms are strongly cartesian | |
which proves the ``if'' part of the lemma. For the converse, note | |
that given $(X, \mathcal{F})$ and $f : Y \to X$, if there exists a | |
strongly cartesian morphism lifting $f$ with target $(X, \mathcal{F})$ | |
then it has to be isomorphic to $(f, c)$ (see discussion following | |
Categories, Definition \ref{categories-definition-cartesian-over-C}). | |
Hence the "only if" part of the lemma holds. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-stack-of-quasi-coherent-sheaves} | |
The functor $p : \QCohstack \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
satisfies conditions (1), (2) and (3) of | |
Stacks, Definition \ref{stacks-definition-stack}. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
It is clear from | |
Lemma \ref{lemma-quasi-coherent-strongly-cartesian} | |
that $\QCohstack$ is a fibred category over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
Given covering $\mathcal{U} = \{X_i \to X\}_{i \in I}$ of | |
$(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ the functor | |
$$ | |
\QCoh(\mathcal{O}_X) \longrightarrow DD(\mathcal{U}) | |
$$ | |
is fully faithful and essentially surjective, see | |
Descent, Proposition \ref{descent-proposition-fpqc-descent-quasi-coherent}. | |
Hence | |
Stacks, Lemma \ref{stacks-lemma-stack-equivalences} | |
applies to show that $\QCohstack$ satisfies all the | |
axioms of a stack. | |
\end{proof} | |
\section{The stack of finitely generated quasi-coherent sheaves} | |
\label{section-stack-of-finitely-generated-quasi-coherent-sheaves} | |
\noindent | |
It turns out that we can get a stack of quasi-coherent sheaves | |
if we only consider finite type quasi-coherent modules. | |
Let us denote | |
$$ | |
p_{fg} : \QCohstack_{fg} \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
the full subcategory of $\QCohstack$ over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
consisting of pairs $(T, \mathcal{F})$ such that $\mathcal{F}$ | |
is a quasi-coherent $\mathcal{O}_T$-module of finite type. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-stack-of-finite-type-quasi-coherent-sheaves} | |
The functor $p_{fg} : \QCohstack_{fg} \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
satisfies conditions (1), (2) and (3) of | |
Stacks, Definition \ref{stacks-definition-stack}. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
We will verify assumptions (1), (2), (3) of | |
Stacks, Lemma \ref{stacks-lemma-substack} | |
to prove this. By | |
Lemma \ref{lemma-quasi-coherent-strongly-cartesian} | |
a morphism $(Y, \mathcal{G}) \to (X, \mathcal{F})$ is | |
strongly cartesian if and only if it induces an isomorphism | |
$f^*\mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{G}$. By | |
Modules, Lemma \ref{modules-lemma-pullback-finite-type} | |
the pullback of a finite type $\mathcal{O}_X$-module is of finite | |
type. Hence assumption (1) of | |
Stacks, Lemma \ref{stacks-lemma-substack} | |
holds. Assumption (2) holds trivially. | |
Finally, to prove assumption (3) we have to show: | |
If $\mathcal{F}$ is a quasi-coherent $\mathcal{O}_X$-module | |
and $\{f_i : X_i \to X\}$ is an fppf covering such that each | |
$f_i^*\mathcal{F}$ is of finite type, then $\mathcal{F}$ is of | |
finite type. Considering the restriction of $\mathcal{F}$ to | |
an affine open of $X$ this reduces to the following algebra statement: | |
Suppose that $R \to S$ is a finitely presented, faithfully flat ring map | |
and $M$ an $R$-module. If $M \otimes_R S$ is a finitely generated | |
$S$-module, then $M$ is a finitely generated $R$-module. | |
A stronger form of the algebra fact can be found in | |
Algebra, Lemma \ref{algebra-lemma-descend-properties-modules}. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-finite-type} | |
Let $(X, \mathcal{O}_X)$ be a ringed space. | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item The category of finite type $\mathcal{O}_X$-modules has a | |
set of isomorphism classes. | |
\item The category of finite type quasi-coherent | |
$\mathcal{O}_X$-modules has a set of isomorphism classes. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Part (2) follows from part (1) as the category in (2) is a full subcategory | |
of the category in (1). Consider any open covering | |
$\mathcal{U} : X = \bigcup_{i \in I} U_i$. Denote $j_i : U_i \to X$ | |
the inclusion maps. Consider any map $r : I \to \mathbf{N}$. | |
If $\mathcal{F}$ is an $\mathcal{O}_X$-module whose restriction to | |
$U_i$ is generated by at most $r(i)$ sections from $\mathcal{F}(U_i)$, | |
then $\mathcal{F}$ is a quotient of the sheaf | |
$$ | |
\mathcal{H}_{\mathcal{U}, r} = | |
\bigoplus\nolimits_{i \in I} j_{i, !}\mathcal{O}_{U_i}^{\oplus r(i)} | |
$$ | |
By definition, if $\mathcal{F}$ is of finite type, then there exists | |
some open covering with $\mathcal{U}$ whose index set is $I = X$ | |
such that this condition is true. Hence it suffices to show that | |
there is a set of possible choices for $\mathcal{U}$ (obvious), | |
a set of possible choices for $r : I \to \mathbf{N}$ (obvious), and | |
a set of possible quotient modules of $\mathcal{H}_{\mathcal{U}, r}$ | |
for each $\mathcal{U}$ and $r$. In other words, it suffices to show | |
that given an $\mathcal{O}_X$-module $\mathcal{H}$ there is at most | |
a set of isomorphism classes of quotients. | |
This last assertion becomes obvious | |
by thinking of the kernels of a quotient map | |
$\mathcal{H} \to \mathcal{F}$ | |
as being parametrized by a subset of the power set of | |
$\prod_{U \subset X\text{ open}} \mathcal{H}(U)$. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-stack-fg-quasi-coherent} | |
There exists a subcategory | |
$\QCohstack_{fg, small} \subset \QCohstack_{fg}$ | |
with the following properties: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item the inclusion functor | |
$\QCohstack_{fg, small} \to \QCohstack_{fg}$ is | |
fully faithful and essentially surjective, and | |
\item the functor | |
$p_{fg, small} : \QCohstack_{fg, small} \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
turns $\QCohstack_{fg, small}$ into a stack over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
We have seen in | |
Lemmas \ref{lemma-stack-of-finite-type-quasi-coherent-sheaves} and | |
\ref{lemma-finite-type} | |
that $p_{fg} : \QCohstack_{fg} \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
satisfies (1), (2) and (3) of | |
Stacks, Definition \ref{stacks-definition-stack} | |
as well as the additional condition (4) of | |
Stacks, Remark \ref{stacks-remark-stack-make-small}. | |
Hence we obtain $\QCohstack_{fg, small}$ from the discussion | |
in that remark. | |
\end{proof} | |
\noindent | |
We will often perform the replacement | |
$$ | |
\QCohstack_{fg} \leadsto \QCohstack_{fg, small} | |
$$ | |
without further remarking on it, and by abuse of notation we will | |
simply denote $\QCohstack_{fg}$ this replacement. | |
\begin{remark} | |
\label{remark-higher-rank} | |
Note that the whole discussion in this section works | |
if we want to consider those | |
quasi-coherent sheaves which are locally generated by at most $\kappa$ | |
sections, for some infinite cardinal $\kappa$, e.g., $\kappa = \aleph_0$. | |
\end{remark} | |
\section{Finite \'etale covers} | |
\label{section-finite-etale} | |
\noindent | |
We define a category $\textit{F\'Et}$ as follows: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item An object of $\textit{F\'Et}$ is a finite \'etale morphism $Y \to X$ | |
of schemes (by our conventions this means a finite \'etale morphism | |
in $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$), | |
\item A morphism $(b, a) : (Y \to X) \to (Y' \to X')$ of $\textit{F\'Et}$ | |
is a commutative diagram | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
Y \ar[d] \ar[r]_b & Y' \ar[d] \\ | |
X \ar[r]_a & X' | |
} | |
$$ | |
in the category of schemes. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
Thus $\textit{F\'Et}$ is a category and | |
$$ | |
p : \textit{F\'Et} \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}, | |
\quad | |
(Y \to X) \mapsto X | |
$$ | |
is a functor. Note that the fibre category of $\textit{F\'Et}$ over | |
a scheme $X$ is just the category $\textit{F\'Et}_X$ studied in | |
Fundamental Groups, Section \ref{pione-section-finite-etale}. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-finite-etale-stack} | |
The functor | |
$$ | |
p : \textit{F\'Et} \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
defines a stack over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Fppf descent for finite \'etale morphisms follows from | |
Descent, Lemmas \ref{descent-lemma-affine}, | |
\ref{descent-lemma-descending-property-finite}, and | |
\ref{descent-lemma-descending-property-etale}. | |
Details omitted. | |
\end{proof} | |
\section{Algebraic spaces} | |
\label{section-stack-of-spaces} | |
\noindent | |
We define a category $\Spacesstack$ as follows: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item An object of $\Spacesstack$ is a morphism $X \to U$ | |
of algebraic spaces over $S$, where $U$ is representable by an object of | |
$(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$, and | |
\item a morphism $(f, g) : (X \to U) \to (Y \to V)$ | |
is a commutative diagram | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
X \ar[d] \ar[r]_f & Y \ar[d] \\ | |
U \ar[r]^g & V | |
} | |
$$ | |
of morphisms of algebraic spaces over $S$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
Thus $\Spacesstack$ is a category and | |
$$ | |
p : \Spacesstack \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}, | |
\quad | |
(X \to U) \mapsto U | |
$$ | |
is a functor. Note that the fibre category of $\Spacesstack$ over | |
a scheme $U$ is just the category $\textit{Spaces}/U$ of | |
algebraic spaces over $U$ (see | |
Topologies on Spaces, Section \ref{spaces-topologies-section-procedure}). | |
Hence we sometimes think of an object of $\Spacesstack$ as a | |
pair $X/U$ consisting of a scheme $U$ and an algebraic space $X$ over $U$. | |
We remark for later use that given | |
$(X/U), (Y/V) \in \Ob(\Spacesstack)$ | |
we have | |
\begin{equation} | |
\label{equation-morphisms-spaces} | |
\Mor_{\Spacesstack}(X/U, Y/V) | |
= | |
\coprod\nolimits_{g \in \Mor_S(U, V)} | |
\Mor_{\textit{Spaces}/U}(X, U \times_{g, V} Y) | |
\end{equation} | |
The category $\Spacesstack$ is almost, but not quite a stack | |
over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. The problem is a set theoretical | |
issue as we will explain below. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-spaces-strongly-cartesian} | |
A morphism $(f, g) : X/U \to Y/V$ | |
of $\Spacesstack$ is strongly cartesian if and only if the | |
map $f$ induces an isomorphism $X \to U \times_{g, V} Y$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Let $Y/V \in \Ob(\Spacesstack)$. | |
Let $g : U \to V$ be a morphism of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
Note that the projection $p : U \times_{g, V} Y \to Y$ | |
gives rise a morphism | |
$(p, g) : U \times_{g, V} Y/U \to Y/V$ of $\Spacesstack$. | |
We claim that $(p, g)$ is strongly cartesian. | |
Namely, for any object $Z/W$ of $\Spacesstack$ we have | |
\begin{align*} | |
\Mor_{\Spacesstack}(Z/W, U \times_{g, V} Y/U) | |
& = | |
\coprod\nolimits_{h \in \Mor_S(W, U)} | |
\Mor_{\textit{Spaces}/W}(Z, W \times_{h, U} U \times_{g, V} Y) \\ | |
& = | |
\coprod\nolimits_{h \in \Mor_S(W, U)} | |
\Mor_{\textit{Spaces}/W}(Z, W \times_{g \circ h, V} Y) \\ | |
& = | |
\Mor_{\Spacesstack}(Z/W, Y/V) | |
\times_{\Mor_S(W, V)} \Mor_S(W, U) | |
\end{align*} | |
where we have used Equation (\ref{equation-morphisms-spaces}) twice. | |
This proves that the condition of | |
Categories, Definition \ref{categories-definition-cartesian-over-C} | |
holds for $(p, g)$, and hence our claim is true. Now by | |
Categories, Lemma \ref{categories-lemma-composition-cartesian} | |
we see that isomorphisms are strongly cartesian and | |
compositions of strongly cartesian morphisms are strongly cartesian | |
which proves the ``if'' part of the lemma. For the converse, note | |
that given $Y/V$ and $g : U \to V$, if there exists a | |
strongly cartesian morphism lifting $g$ with target $Y/V$ | |
then it has to be isomorphic to $(p, g)$ (see discussion following | |
Categories, Definition \ref{categories-definition-cartesian-over-C}). | |
Hence the "only if" part of the lemma holds. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-pre-stack-of-spaces} | |
The functor $p : \Spacesstack \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
satisfies conditions (1) and (2) of | |
Stacks, Definition \ref{stacks-definition-stack}. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
It is follows from | |
Lemma \ref{lemma-spaces-strongly-cartesian} | |
that $\Spacesstack$ is a fibred category over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
which proves (1). | |
Suppose that $\{U_i \to U\}_{i \in I}$ is a covering of | |
$(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. Suppose that $X, Y$ are algebraic spaces over | |
$U$. Finally, suppose that $\varphi_i : X_{U_i} \to Y_{U_i}$ are morphisms | |
of $\textit{Spaces}/U_i$ such that $\varphi_i$ and $\varphi_j$ restrict | |
to the same morphisms $X_{U_i \times_U U_j} \to Y_{U_i \times_U U_j}$ | |
of algebraic spaces over $U_i \times_U U_j$. | |
To prove (2) we have to show that there exists a unique morphism | |
$\varphi : X \to Y$ over $U$ whose base change to $U_i$ is | |
equal to $\varphi_i$. As a morphism from $X$ to $Y$ is the same thing | |
as a map of sheaves this follows directly from | |
Sites, Lemma \ref{sites-lemma-glue-maps}. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{remark} | |
\label{remark-stack-spaces} | |
Ignoring set theoretical difficulties\footnote{The difficulty is not | |
that $\Spacesstack$ is a proper class, since by our definition of | |
an algebraic space over $S$ there is only a set worth of isomorphism | |
classes of algebraic spaces over $S$. It is rather that arbitrary disjoint | |
unions of algebraic spaces may end up being too large, hence lie outside | |
of our chosen ``partial universe'' of sets.} | |
$\Spacesstack$ also satisfies | |
descent for objects and hence is a stack. Namely, we have to show that | |
given | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item an fppf covering $\{U_i \to U\}_{i \in I}$, | |
\item for each $i \in I$ an algebraic space $X_i/U_i$, and | |
\item for each $i, j \in I$ an isomorphism | |
$\varphi_{ij} : X_i \times_U U_j \to U_i \times_U X_j$ of algebraic spaces | |
over $U_i \times_U U_j$ satisfying the cocycle condition over | |
$U_i \times_U U_j \times_U U_k$, | |
\end{enumerate} | |
there exists an algebraic space $X/U$ and isomorphisms | |
$X_{U_i} \cong X_i$ over $U_i$ recovering the isomorphisms $\varphi_{ij}$. | |
First, note that by | |
Sites, Lemma \ref{sites-lemma-glue-sheaves} | |
there exists a sheaf $X$ on $(\Sch/U)_{fppf}$ recovering | |
the $X_i$ and the $\varphi_{ij}$. Then by | |
Bootstrap, Lemma \ref{bootstrap-lemma-locally-algebraic-space} | |
we see that $X$ is an algebraic space (if we ignore the set theoretic | |
condition of that lemma). | |
We will use this argument in the next section to show that | |
if we consider only algebraic spaces of finite type, then we obtain | |
a stack. | |
\end{remark} | |
\section{The stack of finite type algebraic spaces} | |
\label{section-stack-of-finite-type-spaces} | |
\noindent | |
It turns out that we can get a stack of spaces | |
if we only consider spaces of finite type. | |
Let us denote | |
$$ | |
p_{ft} : \Spacesstack_{ft} \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
the full subcategory of $\Spacesstack$ over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
consisting of pairs $X/U$ such that $X \to U$ | |
is a morphism of finite type. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-stack-of-finite-type-spaces} | |
The functor | |
$p_{ft} : \Spacesstack_{ft} \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
satisfies the conditions (1), (2) and (3) of | |
Stacks, Definition \ref{stacks-definition-stack}. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
We are going to write this out in ridiculous detail (which may make | |
it hard to see what is going on). | |
\medskip\noindent | |
We have seen in | |
Lemma \ref{lemma-spaces-strongly-cartesian} | |
that a morphism $(f, g) : X/U \to Y/V$ of $\Spacesstack$ is | |
strongly cartesian if the induced morphism $f : X \to U \times_V Y$ | |
is an isomorphism. Note that if $Y \to V$ is of finite type | |
then also $U \times_V Y \to U$ is of finite type, see | |
Morphisms of Spaces, | |
Lemma \ref{spaces-morphisms-lemma-base-change-finite-type}. | |
So if $(f, g) : X/U \to Y/V$ of $\Spacesstack$ is | |
strongly cartesian in $\Spacesstack$ and $Y/V$ is an object | |
of $\Spacesstack_{ft}$ then automatically also $X/U$ is an | |
object of $\Spacesstack_{ft}$, and of course $(f, g)$ is | |
also strongly cartesian in $\Spacesstack_{ft}$. In this way | |
we conclude that $\Spacesstack_{ft}$ is a fibred category over | |
$(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. This proves (1). | |
\medskip\noindent | |
The argument above also shows that the inclusion | |
functor $\Spacesstack_{ft} \to \Spacesstack$ transforms | |
strongly cartesian morphisms into strongly cartesian morphisms. | |
In other words $\Spacesstack_{ft} \to \Spacesstack$ is | |
a $1$-morphism of fibred categories over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
Let $U \in \Ob((\Sch/S)_{fppf})$. | |
Let $X, Y$ be algebraic spaces of finite type over $U$. By | |
Stacks, Lemma \ref{stacks-lemma-presheaf-mor-map-fibred-categories} | |
we obtain a map of presheaves | |
$$ | |
\mathit{Mor}_{\Spacesstack_{ft}}(X, Y) | |
\longrightarrow | |
\mathit{Mor}_{\Spacesstack}(X, Y) | |
$$ | |
which is an isomorphism as $\Spacesstack_{ft}$ is a full subcategory of | |
$\Spacesstack$. Hence the left hand side is a sheaf, because in | |
Lemma \ref{lemma-pre-stack-of-spaces} | |
we showed the right hand side is a sheaf. This proves (2). | |
\medskip\noindent | |
To prove condition (3) of | |
Stacks, Definition \ref{stacks-definition-stack} | |
we have to show the following: Given | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item a covering $\{U_i \to U\}_{i \in I}$ of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$, | |
\item for each $i \in I$ an algebraic space $X_i$ of finite type over $U_i$, | |
and | |
\item for each $i, j \in I$ an isomorphism | |
$\varphi_{ij} : X_i \times_U U_j \to U_i \times_U X_j$ of algebraic spaces | |
over $U_i \times_U U_j$ satisfying the cocycle condition over | |
$U_i \times_U U_j \times_U U_k$, | |
\end{enumerate} | |
there exists an algebraic space $X$ of finite type over $U$ and isomorphisms | |
$X_{U_i} \cong X_i$ over $U_i$ recovering the isomorphisms $\varphi_{ij}$. | |
This follows from | |
Bootstrap, Lemma \ref{bootstrap-lemma-descend-algebraic-space} part (2). By | |
Descent on Spaces, Lemma | |
\ref{spaces-descent-lemma-descending-property-locally-finite-presentation} | |
we see that $X \to U$ is of finite type which concludes the proof. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-stack-ft-spaces} | |
There exists a subcategory | |
$\Spacesstack_{ft, small} \subset \Spacesstack_{ft}$ | |
with the following properties: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item the inclusion functor | |
$\Spacesstack_{ft, small} \to \Spacesstack_{ft}$ is | |
fully faithful and essentially surjective, and | |
\item the functor | |
$p_{ft, small} : \Spacesstack_{ft, small} \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
turns $\Spacesstack_{ft, small}$ into a stack over | |
$(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
We have seen in | |
Lemmas \ref{lemma-stack-of-finite-type-spaces} | |
that $p_{ft} : \Spacesstack_{ft} \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
satisfies (1), (2) and (3) of | |
Stacks, Definition \ref{stacks-definition-stack}. | |
The additional condition (4) of | |
Stacks, Remark \ref{stacks-remark-stack-make-small} | |
holds because every algebraic space $X$ over $S$ is of the | |
form $U/R$ for $U, R \in \Ob((\Sch/S)_{fppf})$, see | |
Spaces, Lemma \ref{spaces-lemma-space-presentation}. | |
Thus there is only a set worth of isomorphism classes of objects. | |
Hence we obtain $\Spacesstack_{ft, small}$ from the discussion | |
in that remark. | |
\end{proof} | |
\noindent | |
We will often perform the replacement | |
$$ | |
\Spacesstack_{ft} \leadsto \Spacesstack_{ft, small} | |
$$ | |
without further remarking on it, and by abuse of notation we will | |
simply denote $\Spacesstack_{ft}$ this replacement. | |
\begin{remark} | |
\label{remark-higher-cardinality-spaces} | |
Note that the whole discussion in this section works | |
if we want to consider those algebraic spaces $X/U$ which are | |
locally of finite type such that the inverse image in $X$ of an affine open | |
of $U$ can be covered by countably many affines. | |
If needed we can also introduce the notion of a morphism of | |
$\kappa$-type (meaning some bound on the number of generators of | |
ring extensions and some bound on the cardinality of the affines over | |
a given affine in the base) where $\kappa$ is a cardinal, and then | |
we can produce a stack | |
$$ | |
\Spacesstack_\kappa \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
in exactly the same manner as above (provided we make sure that | |
$\Sch$ is large enough depending on $\kappa$). | |
\end{remark} | |
\section{Examples of stacks in groupoids} | |
\label{section-examples-stacks-in-groupoids} | |
\noindent | |
The examples above are examples of stacks which are not stacks in | |
groupoids. In the rest of this chapter we give | |
algebraic geometric examples of stacks in groupoids. | |
\section{The stack associated to a sheaf} | |
\label{section-stack-associated-to-sheaf} | |
\noindent | |
Let $F : (\Sch/S)_{fppf}^{opp} \to \textit{Sets}$ be a presheaf. | |
We obtain a category fibred in sets | |
$$ | |
p_F : \mathcal{S}_F \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}, | |
$$ | |
see | |
Categories, Example \ref{categories-example-presheaf}. | |
This is a stack in sets if and only if $F$ is a sheaf, see | |
Stacks, Lemma \ref{stacks-lemma-stack-in-setoids-characterize}. | |
\section{The stack in groupoids of finitely generated quasi-coherent sheaves} | |
\label{section-stack-in-groupoids-of-quasi-coherent-sheaves} | |
\noindent | |
Let $p : \QCohstack_{fg} \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ be the stack | |
introduced in | |
Section \ref{section-stack-of-finitely-generated-quasi-coherent-sheaves} | |
(using the abuse of notation introduced there). | |
We can turn this into a stack in groupoids | |
$p' : \QCohstack_{fg}' \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ by | |
the procedure of | |
Categories, Lemma \ref{categories-lemma-fibred-gives-fibred-groupoids}, | |
see | |
Stacks, Lemma \ref{stacks-lemma-stack-gives-stack-groupoids}. | |
In this particular case this simply means $\QCohstack_{fg}'$ has | |
the same objects as $\QCohstack_{fg}$ but the morphisms are | |
pairs $(f, g) : (U, \mathcal{F}) \to (U', \mathcal{F}')$ | |
where $g$ is an isomorphism $g : f^*\mathcal{F}' \to \mathcal{F}$. | |
\section{The stack in groupoids of finite type algebraic spaces} | |
\label{section-stack-in-groupoids-of-finite-type-spaces} | |
\noindent | |
Let $p : \Spacesstack_{ft} \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ be the stack | |
introduced in | |
Section \ref{section-stack-of-finite-type-spaces} | |
(using the abuse of notation introduced there). | |
We can turn this into a stack in groupoids | |
$p' : \Spacesstack_{ft}' \to (\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ by | |
the procedure of | |
Categories, Lemma \ref{categories-lemma-fibred-gives-fibred-groupoids}, | |
see | |
Stacks, Lemma \ref{stacks-lemma-stack-gives-stack-groupoids}. | |
In this particular case this simply means $\Spacesstack_{ft}'$ | |
has the same objects as $\Spacesstack_{ft}$, i.e., finite type morphisms | |
$X \to U$ where $X$ is an algebraic space over $S$ and $U$ is a scheme | |
over $S$. But the morphisms $(f, g) : X/U \to Y/V$ are now | |
commutative diagrams | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
X \ar[d] \ar[r]_f & Y \ar[d] \\ | |
U \ar[r]^g & V | |
} | |
$$ | |
which are cartesian. | |
\section{Quotient stacks} | |
\label{section-quotient-stacks} | |
\noindent | |
Let $(U, R, s, t, c)$ be a groupoid in algebraic spaces over $S$. | |
In this case the quotient stack | |
$$ | |
[U/R] \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
is a stack in groupoids by construction, see | |
Groupoids in Spaces, | |
Definition \ref{spaces-groupoids-definition-quotient-stack}. | |
It is even the case that the $\mathit{Isom}$-sheaves are | |
representable by algebraic spaces, see | |
Bootstrap, Lemma \ref{bootstrap-lemma-quotient-stack-isom}. | |
These quotient stacks are of fundamental importance to the theory of | |
algebraic stacks. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
A special case of the construction above is the quotient stack | |
$$ | |
[X/G] \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
associated to a datum $(B, G/B, m, X/B, a)$. Here | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $B$ is an algebraic space over $S$, | |
\item $(G, m)$ is a group algebraic space over $B$, | |
\item $X$ is an algebraic space over $B$, and | |
\item $a : G \times_B X \to X$ is an action of $G$ on $X$ over $B$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
Namely, by | |
Groupoids in Spaces, | |
Definition \ref{spaces-groupoids-definition-quotient-stack} | |
the stack in groupoids $[X/G]$ is the | |
quotient stack $[X/G \times_B X]$ given above. It behooves us to | |
spell out what the category $[X/G]$ really looks like. We will do this in | |
Section \ref{section-group-quotient-stacks}. | |
\section{Classifying torsors} | |
\label{section-torsors} | |
\noindent | |
We want to carefuly explain a number of variants of what it could | |
mean to study the stack of torsors for a group algebraic space $G$ | |
or a sheaf of groups $\mathcal{G}$. | |
\subsection{Torsors for a sheaf of groups} | |
\label{subsection-torsors-sheaf} | |
\noindent | |
Let $\mathcal{G}$ be a sheaf of groups on $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
For $U \in \Ob((\Sch/S)_{fppf})$ we denote | |
$\mathcal{G}|_U$ the restriction of $\mathcal{G}$ to $(\Sch/U)_{fppf}$. | |
We define a category $\mathcal{G}\textit{-Torsors}$ as follows: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item An object of $\mathcal{G}\textit{-Torsors}$ is a pair | |
$(U, \mathcal{F})$ where $U$ is an object of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
and $\mathcal{F}$ is a $\mathcal{G}|_U$-torsor, see | |
Cohomology on Sites, Definition \ref{sites-cohomology-definition-torsor}. | |
\item A morphism $(U, \mathcal{F}) \to (V, \mathcal{H})$ is given | |
by a pair $(f, \alpha)$, where $f : U \to V$ is a morphism of schemes | |
over $S$, and $\alpha : f^{-1}\mathcal{H} \to \mathcal{F}$ is an | |
isomorphism of $\mathcal{G}|_U$-torsors. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
Thus $\mathcal{G}\textit{-Torsors}$ is a category and | |
$$ | |
p : \mathcal{G}\textit{-Torsors} \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf}, | |
\quad | |
(U, \mathcal{F}) \longmapsto U | |
$$ | |
is a functor. Note that the fibre category of $\mathcal{G}\textit{-Torsors}$ | |
over $U$ is the category of $\mathcal{G}|_U$-torsors which is a groupoid. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-torsors-sheaf-stack-in-groupoids} | |
Up to a replacement as in | |
Stacks, Remark \ref{stacks-remark-stack-make-small} | |
the functor | |
$$ | |
p : \mathcal{G}\textit{-Torsors} \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
defines a stack in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
The most difficult part of the proof is to show that | |
we have descent for objects. | |
Let $\{U_i \to U\}_{i \in I}$ be a covering of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
Suppose that for each $i$ we are given a $\mathcal{G}|_{U_i}$-torsor | |
$\mathcal{F}_i$, and for each $i, j \in I$ an isomorphism | |
$\varphi_{ij} : | |
\mathcal{F}_i|_{U_i \times_U U_j} \to \mathcal{F}_j|_{U_i \times_U U_j}$ | |
of $\mathcal{G}|_{U_i \times_U U_j}$-torsors | |
satisfying a suitable cocycle condition on $U_i \times_U U_j \times_U U_k$. | |
Then by | |
Sites, Section \ref{sites-section-glueing-sheaves} | |
we obtain a sheaf $\mathcal{F}$ on $(\Sch/U)_{fppf}$ | |
whose restriction to each $U_i$ recovers $\mathcal{F}_i$ as well | |
as recovering the descent data. By the equivalence of categories in | |
Sites, Lemma \ref{sites-lemma-mapping-property-glue} | |
the action maps $\mathcal{G}|_{U_i} \times \mathcal{F}_i \to \mathcal{F}_i$ | |
glue to give a map $a : \mathcal{G}|_U \times \mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{F}$. | |
Now we have to show that $a$ is an action and that $\mathcal{F}$ becomes | |
a $\mathcal{G}|_U$-torsor. Both properties may be checked locally, and | |
hence follow from the corresponding properties of the actions | |
$\mathcal{G}|_{U_i} \times \mathcal{F}_i \to \mathcal{F}_i$. | |
This proves that descent for objects holds in | |
$\mathcal{G}\textit{-Torsors}$. | |
Some details omitted. | |
\end{proof} | |
\subsection{Variant on torsors for a sheaf} | |
\label{subsection-variant-torsor-sheaf} | |
\noindent | |
The construction of | |
Subsection \ref{subsection-torsors-sheaf} | |
can be generalized slightly. | |
Namely, let $\mathcal{G} \to \mathcal{B}$ be a map of sheaves | |
on $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ and let | |
$$ | |
m : | |
\mathcal{G} \times_\mathcal{B} \mathcal{G} | |
\longrightarrow | |
\mathcal{G} | |
$$ | |
be a group law on $\mathcal{G}/\mathcal{B}$. In other words, the pair | |
$(\mathcal{G}, m)$ is a group object of the topos | |
$\Sh((\Sch/S)_{fppf})/\mathcal{B}$. See | |
Sites, Section \ref{sites-section-localize-topoi} | |
for information regarding localizations of topoi. | |
In this setting we can define a category | |
$\mathcal{G}/\mathcal{B}\textit{-Torsors}$ as follows | |
(where we use the Yoneda embedding to think of schemes as sheaves): | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item An object of $\mathcal{G}/\mathcal{B}\textit{-Torsors}$ is a triple | |
$(U, b, \mathcal{F})$ where | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $U$ is an object of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$, | |
\item $b : U \to \mathcal{B}$ is a section of $\mathcal{B}$ over $U$, and | |
\item $\mathcal{F}$ is a $U \times_{b, \mathcal{B}}\mathcal{G}$-torsor | |
over $U$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\item A morphism $(U, b, \mathcal{F}) \to (U', b', \mathcal{F}')$ is given | |
by a pair $(f, g)$, where $f : U \to U'$ is a morphism of schemes | |
over $S$ such that $b = b' \circ f$, and | |
$g : f^{-1}\mathcal{F}' \to \mathcal{F}$ is an | |
isomorphism of $U \times_{b, \mathcal{B}} \mathcal{G}$-torsors. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
Thus $\mathcal{G}/\mathcal{B}\textit{-Torsors}$ is a category and | |
$$ | |
p : | |
\mathcal{G}/\mathcal{B}\textit{-Torsors} | |
\longrightarrow | |
(\Sch/S)_{fppf}, | |
\quad | |
(U, b, \mathcal{F}) \longmapsto U | |
$$ | |
is a functor. Note that the fibre category of | |
$\mathcal{G}/\mathcal{B}\textit{-Torsors}$ | |
over $U$ is the disjoint union over $b : U \to \mathcal{B}$ | |
of the categories of $U \times_{b, \mathcal{B}} \mathcal{G}$-torsors, | |
hence is a groupoid. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
In the special case $\mathcal{B} = S$ we recover the category | |
$\mathcal{G}\textit{-Torsors}$ introduced in | |
Subsection \ref{subsection-torsors-sheaf}. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-variant-torsors-sheaf-stack-in-groupoids} | |
Up to a replacement as in | |
Stacks, Remark \ref{stacks-remark-stack-make-small} | |
the functor | |
$$ | |
p : | |
\mathcal{G}/\mathcal{B}\textit{-Torsors} | |
\longrightarrow | |
(\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
defines a stack in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
This proof is a repeat of the proof of | |
Lemma \ref{lemma-torsors-sheaf-stack-in-groupoids}. | |
The reader is encouraged to read that proof first since | |
the notation is less cumbersome. | |
The most difficult part of the proof is to show that | |
we have descent for objects. Let $\{U_i \to U\}_{i \in I}$ | |
be a covering of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
Suppose that for each $i$ we are given a pair $(b_i, \mathcal{F}_i)$ | |
consisting of a morphism $b_i : U_i \to \mathcal{B}$ and a | |
$U_i \times_{b_i, \mathcal{B}} \mathcal{G}$-torsor | |
$\mathcal{F}_i$, and for each $i, j \in I$ | |
we have $b_i|_{U_i \times_U U_j} = b_j|_{U_i \times_U U_j}$ and | |
we are given an isomorphism | |
$\varphi_{ij} : | |
\mathcal{F}_i|_{U_i \times_U U_j} \to \mathcal{F}_j|_{U_i \times_U U_j}$ | |
of $(U_i \times_U U_j) \times_\mathcal{B} \mathcal{G}$-torsors | |
satisfying a suitable cocycle condition on $U_i \times_U U_j \times_U U_k$. | |
Then by | |
Sites, Section \ref{sites-section-glueing-sheaves} | |
we obtain a sheaf $\mathcal{F}$ on $(\Sch/U)_{fppf}$ | |
whose restriction to each $U_i$ recovers $\mathcal{F}_i$ as well | |
as recovering the descent data. By the sheaf axiom for $\mathcal{B}$ | |
the morphisms $b_i$ come from a unique morphism $b : U \to \mathcal{B}$. | |
By the equivalence of categories in | |
Sites, Lemma \ref{sites-lemma-mapping-property-glue} | |
the action maps | |
$(U_i \times_{b_i, \mathcal{B}} \mathcal{G}) \times_{U_i} \mathcal{F}_i | |
\to \mathcal{F}_i$ | |
glue to give a map | |
$(U \times_{b, \mathcal{B}} \mathcal{G}) \times \mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{F}$. | |
Now we have to show that this is an action and that $\mathcal{F}$ becomes | |
a $U \times_{b, \mathcal{B}} \mathcal{G}$-torsor. | |
Both properties may be checked locally, and | |
hence follow from the corresponding properties of the actions | |
on the $\mathcal{F}_i$. | |
This proves that descent for objects holds in | |
$\mathcal{G}/\mathcal{B}\textit{-Torsors}$. | |
Some details omitted. | |
\end{proof} | |
\subsection{Principal homogeneous spaces} | |
\label{subsection-principal-homogeneous-spaces} | |
\noindent | |
Let $B$ be an algebraic space over $S$. | |
Let $G$ be a group algebraic space over $B$. | |
We define a category $G\textit{-Principal}$ as follows: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item An object of $G\textit{-Principal}$ is a triple $(U, b, X)$ where | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $U$ is an object of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$, | |
\item $b : U \to B$ is a morphism over $S$, and | |
\item $X$ is a principal homogeneous $G_U$-space over $U$ where | |
$G_U = U \times_{b, B} G$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
See | |
Groupoids in Spaces, | |
Definition \ref{spaces-groupoids-definition-principal-homogeneous-space}. | |
\item A morphism $(U, b, X) \to (U', b', X')$ is given | |
by a pair $(f, g)$, where $f : U \to U'$ is a morphism of schemes | |
over $B$, and $g : X \to U \times_{f, U'} X'$ is an | |
isomorphism of principal homogeneous $G_U$-spaces. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
Thus $G\textit{-Principal}$ is a category and | |
$$ | |
p : G\textit{-Principal} \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf}, | |
\quad | |
(U, b, X) \longmapsto U | |
$$ | |
is a functor. Note that the fibre category of $G\textit{-Principal}$ | |
over $U$ is the disjoint union over $b : U \to B$ | |
of the categories of principal homogeneous $U \times_{b, B} G$-spaces, | |
hence is a groupoid. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
In the special case $S = B$ the objects are simply pairs | |
$(U, X)$ where $U$ is a scheme over $S$, and $X$ is a principal homogeneous | |
$G_U$-space over $U$. Moreover, morphisms are simply cartesian | |
diagrams | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
X \ar[d] \ar[r]_g & X' \ar[d] \\ | |
U \ar[r]^f & U' | |
} | |
$$ | |
where $g$ is $G$-equivariant. | |
\begin{remark} | |
\label{remark-principal-stack-in-groupoids} | |
We conjecture that up to a replacement as in | |
Stacks, Remark \ref{stacks-remark-stack-make-small} | |
the functor | |
$$ | |
p : G\textit{-Principal} \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
defines a stack in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. This would | |
follow if one could show that given | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item a covering $\{U_i \to U\}_{i \in I}$ of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$, | |
\item an group algebraic space $H$ over $U$, | |
\item for every $i$ a principal homogeneous $H_{U_i}$-space $X_i$ | |
over $U_i$, and | |
\item $H$-equivariant isomorphisms | |
$\varphi_{ij} : X_{i, U_i \times_U U_j} \to X_{j, U_i \times_U U_j}$ | |
satisfying the cocycle condition, | |
\end{enumerate} | |
there exists a principal homogeneous $H$-space $X$ over $U$ | |
which recovers $(X_i, \varphi_{ij})$. The technique of the proof of | |
Bootstrap, Lemma \ref{bootstrap-lemma-descent-torsor} | |
reduces this to a set theoretical question, so the reader who ignores | |
set theoretical questions will ``know'' that the result is true. In | |
\url{https://math.columbia.edu/~dejong/wordpress/?p=591} | |
there is a suggestion as to how to approach this problem. | |
\end{remark} | |
\subsection{Variant on principal homogeneous spaces} | |
\label{subsection-variant-principal-homogeneous-spaces} | |
\noindent | |
Let $S$ be a scheme. Let $B = S$. | |
Let $G$ be a group scheme over $B = S$. | |
In this setting we can define a full subcategory | |
$G\textit{-Principal-Schemes} \subset G\textit{-Principal}$ | |
whose objects are pairs $(U, X)$ where $U$ is an object of | |
$(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ and $X \to U$ is a principal homogeneous | |
$G$-space over $U$ which is representable, i.e., a scheme. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
It is in general not the case that $G\textit{-Principal-Schemes}$ is | |
a stack in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. The reason is | |
that in general there really do exist principal homogeneous spaces | |
which are not schemes, hence descent for objects will not be satisfied | |
in general. | |
\subsection{Torsors in fppf topology} | |
\label{subsection-fppf-torsors} | |
\noindent | |
Let $B$ be an algebraic space over $S$. | |
Let $G$ be a group algebraic space over $B$. | |
We define a category $G\textit{-Torsors}$ as follows: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item An object of $G\textit{-Torsors}$ is a triple $(U, b, X)$ where | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $U$ is an object of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$, | |
\item $b : U \to B$ is a morphism, and | |
\item $X$ is an fppf $G_U$-torsor over $U$ where $G_U = U \times_{b, B} G$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
See | |
Groupoids in Spaces, | |
Definition \ref{spaces-groupoids-definition-principal-homogeneous-space}. | |
\item A morphism $(U, b, X) \to (U', b', X')$ is given | |
by a pair $(f, g)$, where $f : U \to U'$ is a morphism of schemes | |
over $B$, and $g : X \to U \times_{f, U'} X'$ is an | |
isomorphism of $G_U$-torsors. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
Thus $G\textit{-Torsors}$ is a category and | |
$$ | |
p : G\textit{-Torsors} \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf}, | |
\quad | |
(U, a, X) \longmapsto U | |
$$ | |
is a functor. Note that the fibre category of $G\textit{-Torsors}$ | |
over $U$ is the disjoint union over $b : U \to B$ | |
of the categories of fppf $U \times_{b, B} G$-torsors, | |
hence is a groupoid. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
In the special case $S = B$ the objects are simply pairs | |
$(U, X)$ where $U$ is a scheme over $S$, and $X$ is an fppf | |
$G_U$-torsor over $U$. Moreover, morphisms are simply cartesian | |
diagrams | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
X \ar[d] \ar[r]_g & X' \ar[d] \\ | |
U \ar[r]^f & U' | |
} | |
$$ | |
where $g$ is $G$-equivariant. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-torsors-stack-in-groupoids} | |
Up to a replacement as in | |
Stacks, Remark \ref{stacks-remark-stack-make-small} | |
the functor | |
$$ | |
p : G\textit{-Torsors} \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
defines a stack in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
The most difficult part of the proof is to show that we have descent for | |
objects, which is | |
Bootstrap, Lemma \ref{bootstrap-lemma-descent-torsor}. | |
We omit the proof of axioms (1) and (2) of | |
Stacks, Definition \ref{stacks-definition-stack-in-groupoids}. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-compare-torsors} | |
Let $B$ be an algebraic space over $S$. Let $G$ be a group algebraic | |
space over $B$. Denote $\mathcal{G}$, resp.\ $\mathcal{B}$ the algebraic | |
space $G$, resp.\ $B$ seen as a sheaf on $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
The functor | |
$$ | |
G\textit{-Torsors} \longrightarrow \mathcal{G}/\mathcal{B}\textit{-Torsors} | |
$$ | |
which associates to a triple $(U, b, X)$ the triple | |
$(U, b, \mathcal{X})$ where $\mathcal{X}$ is $X$ viewed as a sheaf | |
is an equivalence of stacks in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
We will use the result of | |
Stacks, Lemma \ref{stacks-lemma-characterize-essentially-surjective-when-ff} | |
to prove this. The functor is fully faithful since the category of | |
algebraic spaces over $S$ is a full subcategory of the category of | |
sheaves on $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
Moreover, all objects (on both sides) are locally trivial torsors | |
so condition (2) of the lemma referenced above holds. | |
Hence the functor is an equivalence. | |
\end{proof} | |
\subsection{Variant on torsors in fppf topology} | |
\label{subsection-variant-fppf-torsors} | |
\noindent | |
Let $S$ be a scheme. Let $B = S$. | |
Let $G$ be a group scheme over $B = S$. | |
In this setting we can define a full subcategory | |
$G\textit{-Torsors-Schemes} \subset G\textit{-Torsors}$ | |
whose objects are pairs $(U, X)$ where $U$ is an object of | |
$(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ and $X \to U$ is an fppf | |
$G$-torsor over $U$ which is representable, i.e., a scheme. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
It is in general not the case that $G\textit{-Torsors-Schemes}$ is | |
a stack in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. The reason is | |
that in general there really do exist fppf $G$-torsors | |
which are not schemes, hence descent for objects will not be satisfied | |
in general. | |
\section{Quotients by group actions} | |
\label{section-group-quotient-stacks} | |
\noindent | |
At this point we have introduced enough notation that we can work out | |
in more detail what the stacks $[X/G]$ of | |
Section \ref{section-quotient-stacks} | |
look like. | |
\begin{situation} | |
\label{situation-quotient-stack} | |
Here | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $S$ is a scheme contained in $\Sch_{fppf}$, | |
\item $B$ is an algebraic space over $S$, | |
\item $(G, m)$ is a group algebraic space over $B$, | |
\item $\pi : X \to B$ is an algebraic space over $B$, and | |
\item $a : G \times_B X \to X$ is an action of $G$ on $X$ over $B$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{situation} | |
\noindent | |
In this situation we construct a category $[[X/G]]$\footnote{The notation | |
$[[X/G]]$ with double brackets serves to distinguish this category from | |
the stack $[X/G]$ introduced earlier. In | |
Proposition \ref{proposition-equal-quotient-stacks} | |
we show that the two are canonically equivalent. | |
Afterwards we will use the notation $[X/G]$ to indicate either.} as follows: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item An object of $[[X/G]]$ consists of a quadruple | |
$(U, b, P, \varphi : P \to X)$ where | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $U$ is an object of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$, | |
\item $b : U \to B$ is a morphism over $S$, | |
\item $P$ is an fppf $G_U$-torsor over $U$ where $G_U = U \times_{b, B} G$, and | |
\item $\varphi : P \to X$ is a $G$-equivariant morphism fitting | |
into the commutative diagram | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
P \ar[d] \ar[r]_{\varphi} & X \ar[d] \\ | |
U \ar[r]^b & B | |
} | |
$$ | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\item A morphism of $[[X/G]]$ is a pair | |
$(f, g) : (U, b, P, \varphi) \to (U', b', P', \varphi')$ | |
where $f : U \to U'$ is a morphism of schemes over $B$ | |
and $g : P \to P'$ is a $G$-equivariant morphism over $f$ | |
which induces an isomorphism $P \cong U \times_{f, U'} P'$, and has | |
the property that $\varphi = \varphi' \circ g$. | |
In other words $(f, g)$ fits into the following commutative | |
diagram | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
P \ar[d] \ar[rrrd]_\varphi \ar[r]^g & P' \ar[d] \ar[rrd]^{\varphi'} \\ | |
U \ar[rrrd]_b \ar[r]^f & U' \ar[rrd]^{b'} & & X \ar[d] \\ | |
& & & B | |
} | |
$$ | |
\end{enumerate} | |
Thus $[[X/G]]$ is a category and | |
$$ | |
p : [[X/G]] \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf}, | |
\quad | |
(U, b, P, \varphi) \longmapsto U | |
$$ | |
is a functor. Note that the fibre category of $[[X/G]]$ | |
over $U$ is the disjoint union over $b \in \Mor_S(U, B)$ | |
of fppf $U \times_{b, B} G$-torsors $P$ endowed with a $G$-equivariant | |
morphism to $X$. Hence the fibre categories of $[[X/G]]$ are groupoids. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
Note that the functor | |
$$ | |
[[X/G]] \longrightarrow G\textit{-Torsors}, | |
\quad | |
(U, b, P, \varphi) \longmapsto (U, b, P) | |
$$ | |
is a $1$-morphism of categories over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-group-quotient-stack-in-groupoids} | |
Up to a replacement as in | |
Stacks, Remark \ref{stacks-remark-stack-make-small} | |
the functor | |
$$ | |
p : [[X/G]] \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
defines a stack in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
The most difficult part of the proof is to show that we have descent for | |
objects. Suppose that $\{U_i \to U\}_{i \in I}$ is a covering in | |
$(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. Let | |
$\xi_i = (U_i, b_i, P_i, \varphi_i)$ be objects of $[[X/G]]$ over $U_i$, | |
and let $\varphi_{ij} : \text{pr}_0^*\xi_i \to \text{pr}_1^*\xi_j$ | |
be a descent datum. This in particular implies that we get a descent | |
datum on the triples $(U_i, b_i, P_i)$ for the stack in groupoids | |
$G\textit{-Torsors}$ by applying the functor | |
$[[X/G]] \to G\textit{-Torsors}$ above. We have seen that | |
$G\textit{-Torsors}$ is a stack in groupoids | |
(Lemma \ref{lemma-torsors-stack-in-groupoids}). | |
Hence we may assume that $b_i = b|_{U_i}$ for some morphism $b : U \to B$, and | |
that $P_i = U_i \times_U P$ for some fppf $G_U = U \times_{b, B} G$-torsor | |
$P$ over $U$. The morphisms $\varphi_i$ are compatible | |
with the canonical descent datum on the restrictions $U_i \times_U P$ | |
and hence define a morphism $\varphi : P \to X$. (For example you | |
can use | |
Sites, Lemma \ref{sites-lemma-mapping-property-glue} | |
or you can use | |
Descent on Spaces, | |
Lemma \ref{spaces-descent-lemma-fpqc-universal-effective-epimorphisms} | |
to get $\varphi$.) | |
This proves descent for objects. | |
We omit the proof of axioms (1) and (2) of | |
Stacks, Definition \ref{stacks-definition-stack-in-groupoids}. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{proposition} | |
\label{proposition-equal-quotient-stacks} | |
In | |
Situation \ref{situation-quotient-stack} | |
there exists a canonical equivalence | |
$$ | |
[X/G] \longrightarrow [[X/G]] | |
$$ | |
of stacks in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
We write this out in detail, to make sure that all the definitions | |
work out in exactly the correct manner. | |
Recall that $[X/G]$ is the quotient stack | |
associated to the groupoid in algebraic spaces | |
$(X, G \times_B X, s, t, c)$, see | |
Groupoids in Spaces, | |
Definition \ref{spaces-groupoids-definition-quotient-stack}. | |
This means that $[X/G]$ is the stackification of the | |
category fibred in groupoids $[X/_{\!p}G]$ associated to the functor | |
$$ | |
(\Sch/S)_{fppf} \longrightarrow \textit{Groupoids}, | |
\quad | |
U \longmapsto (X(U), G(U) \times_{B(U)} X(U), s, t, c) | |
$$ | |
where $s(g, x) = x$, $t(g, x) = a(g, x)$, and | |
$c((g, x), (g', x')) = (m(g, g'), x')$. By the construction of | |
Categories, Example \ref{categories-example-functor-groupoids} | |
an object of $[X/_{\!p}G]$ is a pair $(U, x)$ with $x \in X(U)$ | |
and a morphism $(f, g) : (U, x) \to (U', x')$ of $[X/_{\!p}G]$ | |
is given by a morphism of schemes $f : U \to U'$ and an element | |
$g \in G(U)$ such that $a(g, x) = x' \circ f$. | |
Hence we can define a $1$-morphism of stacks in groupoids | |
$$ | |
F_p : [X/_{\!p}G] \longrightarrow [[X/G]] | |
$$ | |
by the following rules: On objects we set | |
$$ | |
F_p(U, x) = | |
(U, \pi \circ x, G \times_{B, \pi \circ x} U, a \circ (\text{id}_G \times x)) | |
$$ | |
This makes sense because the diagram | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
G \times_{B, \pi \circ x} U \ar[d] \ar[r]_{\text{id}_G \times x} & | |
G \times_{B, \pi} X \ar[r]_-a & | |
X \ar[d]^\pi \\ | |
U \ar[rr]^{\pi \circ x} & & B | |
} | |
$$ | |
commutes, and the two horizontal arrows are $G$-equivariant if we think | |
of the fibre products as trivial $G$-torsors over $U$, resp.\ $X$. | |
On morphisms $(f, g) : (U, x) \to (U', x')$ we set | |
$F_p(f, g) = (f, R_{g^{-1}})$ where $R_{g^{-1}}$ denotes right translation | |
by the inverse of $g$. More precisely, the morphism | |
$F_p(f, g) : F_p(U, x) \to F_p(U', x')$ is given by the cartesian diagram | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
G \times_{B, \pi \circ x} U \ar[d] \ar[r]_{R_{g^{-1}}} & | |
G \times_{B, \pi \circ x'} U' \ar[d] \\ | |
U \ar[r]^f & U' | |
} | |
$$ | |
where $R_{g^{-1}}$ on $T$-valued points is given by | |
$$ | |
R_{g^{-1}}(g', u) = (m(g', i(g(u))), f(u)) | |
$$ | |
To see that this works we have to verify that | |
$$ | |
a \circ (\text{id}_G \times x) | |
= | |
a \circ (\text{id}_G \times x') \circ R_{g^{-1}} | |
$$ | |
which is true because the right hand side applied to the $T$-valued point | |
$(g', u)$ gives the desired equality | |
\begin{align*} | |
a((\text{id}_G \times x')(m(g', i(g(u))), f(u))) | |
& = | |
a(m(g', i(g(u))), x'(f(u))) \\ | |
& = | |
a(g', a(i(g(u)), x'(f(u)))) \\ | |
& = | |
a(g', x(u)) | |
\end{align*} | |
because $a(g, x) = x' \circ f$ and hence $a(i(g), x' \circ f) = x$. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
By the universal property of stackification from | |
Stacks, Lemma \ref{stacks-lemma-stackify-groupoids-universal-property} | |
we obtain a canonical extension $F : [X/G] \to [[X/G]]$ of the $1$-morphism | |
$F_p$ above. We first prove that $F$ is fully faithful. | |
To do this, since both source and target are stacks in groupoids, | |
it suffices to prove that the $\mathit{Isom}$-sheaves are identified | |
under $F$. Pick a scheme $U$ and objects $\xi, \xi'$ of | |
$[X/G]$ over $U$. We want to show that | |
$$ | |
F : | |
\mathit{Isom}_{[X/G]}(\xi, \xi') | |
\longrightarrow | |
\mathit{Isom}_{[[X/G]]}(F(\xi), F(\xi')) | |
$$ | |
is an isomorphism of sheaves. To do this it suffices to work locally | |
on $U$, and hence we may assume that $\xi, \xi'$ come from objects | |
$(U, x)$, $(U, x')$ of $[X/_{\!p}G]$ over $U$; this follows directly | |
from the construction of the stackification, and it is also worked | |
out in detail in | |
Groupoids in Spaces, | |
Section \ref{spaces-groupoids-section-explicit-quotient-stacks}. | |
Either by directly using the description of morphisms in | |
$[X/_{\!p}G]$ above, or using | |
Groupoids in Spaces, | |
Lemma \ref{spaces-groupoids-lemma-quotient-stack-morphisms} | |
we see that in this case | |
$$ | |
\mathit{Isom}_{[X/G]}(\xi, \xi') = | |
U \times_{(x, x'), X \times_S X, (s, t)} (G \times_B X) | |
$$ | |
A $T$-valued point of this fibre product corresponds to a pair | |
$(u, g)$ with $u \in U(T)$, and $g \in G(T)$ such that | |
$a(g, x \circ u) = x' \circ u$. (Note that this implies | |
$\pi \circ x \circ u = \pi \circ x' \circ u$.) | |
On the other hand, a $T$-valued | |
point of $\mathit{Isom}_{[[X/G]]}(F(\xi), F(\xi'))$ by definition | |
corresponds to a morphism $u : T \to U$ such that | |
$\pi \circ x \circ u = \pi \circ x' \circ u : T \to B$ and an isomorphism | |
$$ | |
R : | |
G \times_{B, \pi \circ x \circ u} T | |
\longrightarrow | |
G \times_{B, \pi \circ x' \circ u} T | |
$$ | |
of trivial $G_T$-torsors compatible with the given maps to $X$. | |
Since the torsors are trivial we see that $R = R_{g^{-1}}$ | |
(right multiplication) by some $g \in G(T)$. Compatibility with the maps | |
$a \circ (1_G, x \circ u), a \circ (1_G, x' \circ u) : G \times_B T \to X$ | |
is equivalent to the condition that $a(g, x \circ u) = x' \circ u$. | |
Hence we obtain the desired equality of $\mathit{Isom}$-sheaves. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
Now that we know that $F$ is fully faithful we see that | |
Stacks, Lemma \ref{stacks-lemma-characterize-essentially-surjective-when-ff} | |
applies. Thus to show that $F$ is an equivalence it suffices | |
to show that objects of $[[X/G]]$ are fppf locally in the essential image | |
of $F$. This is clear as fppf torsors are fppf locally trivial, and hence | |
we win. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-classifying-stacks} | |
\begin{slogan} | |
The classifying stack of a group scheme or group algebraic space. | |
\end{slogan} | |
Let $S$ be a scheme. Let $B$ be an algebraic space over $S$. | |
Let $G$ be a group algebraic space over $B$. Then the stacks | |
in groupoids | |
$$ | |
[B/G],\quad | |
[[B/G]],\quad | |
G\textit{-Torsors},\quad | |
\mathcal{G}/\mathcal{B}\textit{-Torsors} | |
$$ | |
are all canonically equivalent. | |
If $G \to B$ is flat and locally | |
of finite presentation, then these are also equivalent to | |
$G\textit{-Principal}$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
The equivalence | |
$G\textit{-Torsors} \to \mathcal{G}/\mathcal{B}\textit{-Torsors}$ | |
is given in Lemma \ref{lemma-compare-torsors}. | |
The equivalence $[B/G] \to [[B/G]]$ is given in | |
Proposition \ref{proposition-equal-quotient-stacks}. | |
Unwinding the definition of $[[B/G]]$ given in | |
Section \ref{section-group-quotient-stacks} | |
we see that $[[B//G]] = G\textit{-Torsors}$. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
Finally, assume $G \to B$ is flat and locally of finite presentation. | |
To show that the natural functor | |
$G\textit{-Torsors} \to G\textit{-Principal}$ is an equivalence | |
it suffices to show that for a scheme $U$ over $B$ | |
a principal homogeneous $G_U$-space $X \to U$ | |
is fppf locally trivial. By our definition of principal homogeneous spaces | |
(Groupoids in Spaces, | |
Definition \ref{spaces-groupoids-definition-principal-homogeneous-space}) | |
there exists an fpqc covering $\{U_i \to U\}$ such that | |
$U_i \times_U X \cong G \times_B U_i$ as algebraic spaces over $U_i$. | |
This implies that $X \to U$ is surjective, flat, and locally of finite | |
presentation, see | |
Descent on Spaces, Lemmas | |
\ref{spaces-descent-lemma-descending-property-surjective}, | |
\ref{spaces-descent-lemma-descending-property-flat}, and | |
\ref{spaces-descent-lemma-descending-property-locally-finite-presentation}. | |
Choose a scheme $W$ and a surjective \'etale morphism $W \to X$. | |
Then it follows from what we just said that $\{W \to U\}$ is an fppf covering | |
such that $X_W \to W$ has a section. Hence $X$ is an fppf $G_U$-torsor. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{remark} | |
\label{remark-X-mod-G-group} | |
Let $S$ be a scheme. | |
Let $G$ be an abstract group. | |
Let $X$ be an algebraic space over $S$. | |
Let $G \to \text{Aut}_S(X)$ be a group homomorphism. | |
In this setting we can define $[[X/G]]$ similarly | |
to the above as follows: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item An object of $[[X/G]]$ consists of a triple | |
$(U, P, \varphi : P \to X)$ where | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $U$ is an object of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$, | |
\item $P$ is a sheaf on $(\Sch/U)_{fppf}$ which comes | |
with an action of $G$ that turns it into a torsor under the constant | |
sheaf with value $G$, and | |
\item $\varphi : P \to X$ is a $G$-equivariant map of sheaves. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\item A morphism | |
$(f, g) : (U, P, \varphi) \to (U', P', \varphi')$ | |
is given by a morphism of schemes $f : T \to T'$ | |
and a $G$-equivariant isomorphism | |
$g : P \to f^{-1}P'$ such that $\varphi = \varphi' \circ g$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
In exactly the same manner as above we obtain a functor | |
$$ | |
[[X/G]] \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
which turns $[[X/G]]$ into a stack in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
The constant sheaf $\underline{G}$ is (provided the cardinality of $G$ is | |
not too large) representable by $G_S$ on $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ | |
and this version of $[[X/G]]$ is equivalent to the stack | |
$[[X/G_S]]$ introduced above. | |
\end{remark} | |
\section{The Picard stack} | |
\label{section-picard-stack} | |
\noindent | |
In this section we introduce the Picard stack in complete generality. | |
In the chapter on Quot and Hilb we will show that it is an algebraic | |
stack under suitable hypotheses, see | |
Quot, Section \ref{quot-section-picard-stack}. | |
\medskip\noindent | |
Let $S$ be a scheme. | |
Let $\pi : X \to B$ be a morphism of algebraic spaces over $S$. | |
We define a category $\Picardstack_{X/B}$ as follows: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item An object is a triple $(U, b, \mathcal{L})$, where | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $U$ is an object of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$, | |
\item $b : U \to B$ is a morphism over $S$, and | |
\item $\mathcal{L}$ is in invertible sheaf on the base change | |
$X_U = U \times_{b, B} X$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\item A morphism $(f, g) : (U, b, \mathcal{L}) \to (U', b', \mathcal{L}')$ | |
is given by a morphism of schemes $f : U \to U'$ over $B$ and an | |
isomorphism $g : f^*\mathcal{L}' \to \mathcal{L}$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
The composition of | |
$(f, g) : (U, b, \mathcal{L}) \to (U', b', \mathcal{L}')$ | |
with | |
$(f', g') : (U', b', \mathcal{L}') \to (U'', b'', \mathcal{L}'')$ | |
is given by $(f \circ f', g \circ f^*(g'))$. | |
Thus we get a category $\Picardstack_{X/B}$ and | |
$$ | |
p : \Picardstack_{X/B} \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf}, | |
\quad | |
(U, b, \mathcal{L}) \longmapsto U | |
$$ | |
is a functor. Note that the fibre category of $\Picardstack_{X/B}$ over $U$ | |
is the disjoint union over $b \in \Mor_S(U, B)$ of the categories | |
of invertible sheaves on $X_U = U \times_{b, B} X$. Hence the fibre | |
categories are groupoids. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-picard-stack} | |
Up to a replacement as in | |
Stacks, Remark \ref{stacks-remark-stack-make-small} | |
the functor | |
$$ | |
\Picardstack_{X/B} \longrightarrow (\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
defines a stack in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
As usual, the hardest part is to show descent for objects. | |
To see this let $\{U_i \to U\}$ be a covering of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
Let $\xi_i = (U_i, b_i, \mathcal{L}_i)$ be an object of | |
$\Picardstack_{X/B}$ lying over $U_i$, and let | |
$\varphi_{ij} : \text{pr}_0^*\xi_i \to \text{pr}_1^*\xi_j$ | |
be a descent datum. This implies in particular that the morphisms | |
$b_i$ are the restrictions of a morphism $b : U \to B$. | |
Write $X_U = U \times_{b, B} X$ and | |
$X_i = U_i \times_{b_i, B} X = | |
U_i \times_U U \times_{b, B} X = U_i \times_U X_U$. | |
Observe that $\mathcal{L}_i$ is an invertible $\mathcal{O}_{X_i}$-module. | |
Note that $\{X_i \to X_U\}$ forms an fppf covering as well. | |
Moreover, the descent datum $\varphi_{ij}$ translates into a | |
descent datum on the invertible sheaves $\mathcal{L}_i$ relative | |
to the fppf covering $\{X_i \to X_U\}$. | |
Hence by | |
Descent on Spaces, | |
Proposition \ref{spaces-descent-proposition-fpqc-descent-quasi-coherent} | |
we obtain a unique invertible sheaf $\mathcal{L}$ on $X_U$ | |
which recovers $\mathcal{L}_i$ and the descent data over $X_i$. | |
The triple $(U, b, \mathcal{L})$ is therefore the object of | |
$\Picardstack_{X/B}$ over $U$ we were looking for. | |
Details omitted. | |
\end{proof} | |
\section{Examples of inertia stacks} | |
\label{section-examples-inertia} | |
\noindent | |
Here are some examples of inertia stacks. | |
\begin{example} | |
\label{example-inertia-stack-of-X-mod-G} | |
Let $S$ be a scheme. Let $G$ be a commutative group. | |
Let $X \to S$ be a scheme over $S$. | |
Let $a : G \times X \to X$ be an action of $G$ on $X$. | |
For $g \in G$ we denote $g : X \to X$ the corresponding automorphism. | |
In this case the inertia stack of $[X/G]$ (see | |
Remark \ref{remark-X-mod-G-group}) | |
is given by | |
$$ | |
I_{[X/G]} = \coprod\nolimits_{g\in G} [X^g/G], | |
$$ | |
where, given an element $g$ of $G$, the symbol $X^g$ denotes the | |
scheme $X^g = \{x \in X \mid g(x) = x\}$. In a formula | |
$X^g$ is really the fibre | |
product | |
$$ | |
X^g = X \times_{(1, 1), X \times_S X, (g, 1)} X. | |
$$ | |
Indeed, for any $S$-scheme $T$, a | |
$T$-point on the inertia stack of $[X/G]$ consists of a | |
triple $(P/T, \phi, \alpha)$ consisting of an fppf $G$-torsor | |
$P\to T$ together with a $G$-equivariant morphism | |
$\phi : P \to X$, together | |
with an automorphism $\alpha$ of $P\to T$ over $T$ such that | |
$\phi \circ \alpha = \phi$. | |
Since $G$ is a sheaf of \emph{commutative} groups, | |
$\alpha$ is, locally in the fppf topology over $T$, | |
given by multiplication by some element $g$ of $G$. | |
The condition that $\phi \circ \alpha = \phi$ means that $\phi$ | |
factors through the inclusion of $X^g$ | |
in $X$, i.e., $\phi$ is obtained by composing that inclusion with a | |
morphism $P \to X^\gamma$. | |
The above discussion allows us to define a morphism of fibred categories | |
$I_{[X/G]} \to \coprod_{g\in G} [X^g/G]$ given on $T$-points by the discussion | |
above. We omit showing that this is an equivalence. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{example} | |
\label{example-inertia-stack-of-picard} | |
Let $f : X \to S$ be a morphism of schemes. | |
Assume that for any $T \to S$ the base change $f_T : X_T \to T$ | |
has the property that the map $\mathcal{O}_T \to f_{T, *}\mathcal{O}_{X_T}$ | |
is an isomorphism. (This implies that $f$ is | |
{\it cohomologically flat in dimension $0$} (insert future reference here) | |
but is stronger.) Consider the Picard stack $\Picardstack_{X/S}$, see | |
Section \ref{section-picard-stack}. | |
The points of its inertia stack over an | |
$S$-scheme $T$ consist of pairs $(\mathcal{L}, \alpha)$ | |
where $\mathcal{L}$ is a line bundle | |
on $X_T$ and $\alpha$ is an automorphism of that line bundle. | |
I.e., we can think of $\alpha$ as an element of | |
$H^0(X_T, \mathcal{O}_{X_T})^\times = H^0(T, \mathcal{O}_T^*)$ | |
by our condition. Note that $H^0(T, \mathcal{O}_T^*) = \mathbf{G}_{m, S}(T)$, | |
see Groupoids, Example \ref{groupoids-example-multiplicative-group}. | |
Hence the inertia stack of $\Picardstack_{X/S}$ is | |
$$ | |
I_{\Picardstack_{X/S}} = \mathbf{G}_{m, S} \times_S \Picardstack_{X/S}. | |
$$ | |
as a stack over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\end{example} | |
\section{Finite Hilbert stacks} | |
\label{section-hilbert-d-stack} | |
\noindent | |
We formulate this in somewhat greater generality than is perhaps strictly | |
needed. Fix a $1$-morphism | |
$$ | |
F : \mathcal{X} \longrightarrow \mathcal{Y} | |
$$ | |
of stacks in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. For each integer | |
$d \geq 1$ consider a category $\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}/\mathcal{Y})$ | |
defined as follows: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item An object $(U, Z, y, x, \alpha)$ where $U, Z$ are objects of | |
in $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$ and $Z$ is a finite locally free of degree | |
$d$ over $U$, where | |
$y \in \Ob(\mathcal{Y}_U)$, $x \in \Ob(\mathcal{X}_Z)$ | |
and $\alpha : y|_Z \to F(x)$ is an isomorphism\footnote{ | |
This means the data gives rise, via the $2$-Yoneda lemma | |
(Categories, Lemma \ref{categories-lemma-yoneda-2category}), to a | |
$2$-commutative diagram | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
(\Sch/Z)_{fppf} \ar[r]_-x \ar[d] & \mathcal{X} \ar[d]^F \\ | |
(\Sch/U)_{fppf} \ar[r]^-y & \mathcal{Y} | |
} | |
$$ | |
of stacks in groupoids over $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
Alternatively, we may picture $\alpha$ as a $2$-morphism | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
(\Sch/Z)_{fppf} | |
\rrtwocell^{y \circ (Z \to U)}_{F \circ x}{\alpha} & & | |
\mathcal{Y}. | |
} | |
$$ | |
}. | |
\item A morphism $(U, Z, y, x, \alpha) \to (U', Z', y', x', \alpha')$ is | |
given by a morphism of schemes $f : U \to U'$, a morphism of schemes | |
$g : Z \to Z'$ which induces an isomorphism $Z \to Z' \times_U U'$, | |
and isomorphisms $b : y \to f^*y'$, $a : x \to g^*x'$ inducing a commutative | |
diagram | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
y|_Z \ar[rr]_\alpha \ar[d]_{b|_Z} & & | |
F(x) \ar[d]^{F(a)} \\ | |
f^*y'|_Z \ar[rr]^{\alpha'} & & | |
F(g^*x') \\ | |
} | |
$$ | |
\end{enumerate} | |
It is clear from the definitions that there is a canonical | |
forgetful functor | |
$$ | |
p : | |
\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}/\mathcal{Y}) | |
\longrightarrow | |
(\Sch/S)_{fppf} | |
$$ | |
which assigns to the quintuple $(U, Z, y, x, \alpha)$ the scheme $U$ | |
and to the morphism | |
$(f, g, b, a) : (U, Z, y, x, \alpha) \to (U', Z', y', x', \alpha')$ | |
the morphism $f : U \to U'$. | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-hilbert-d-stack} | |
The category $\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}/\mathcal{Y})$ endowed with | |
the functor $p$ above defines a stack in groupoids over | |
$(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
As usual, the hardest part is to show descent for objects. | |
To see this let $\{U_i \to U\}$ be a covering of $(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$. | |
Let $\xi_i = (U_i, Z_i, y_i, x_i, \alpha_i)$ be an object of | |
$\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}/\mathcal{Y})$ lying over $U_i$, and let | |
$\varphi_{ij} : \text{pr}_0^*\xi_i \to \text{pr}_1^*\xi_j$ | |
be a descent datum. First, observe that $\varphi_{ij}$ | |
induces a descent datum $(Z_i/U_i, \varphi_{ij})$ which is effective by | |
Descent, Lemma \ref{descent-lemma-affine} | |
This produces a scheme $Z/U$ which is finite locally free of degree $d$ by | |
Descent, Lemma \ref{descent-lemma-descending-property-finite-locally-free}. | |
From now on we identify $Z_i$ with $Z \times_U U_i$. | |
Next, the objects $y_i$ in the fibre categories $\mathcal{Y}_{U_i}$ | |
descend to an object $y$ in $\mathcal{Y}_U$ because $\mathcal{Y}$ is a | |
stack in groupoids. Similarly the objects $x_i$ in the fibre categories | |
$\mathcal{X}_{Z_i}$ descend to an object $x$ in $\mathcal{X}_Z$ because | |
$\mathcal{X}$ is a stack in groupoids. Finally, the given | |
isomorphisms | |
$$ | |
\alpha_i : | |
(y|_Z)_{Z_i} = y_i|_{Z_i} | |
\longrightarrow | |
F(x_i) = F(x|_{Z_i}) | |
$$ | |
glue to a morphism $\alpha : y|_Z \to F(x)$ as the $\mathcal{Y}$ | |
is a stack and hence $\mathit{Isom}_\mathcal{Y}(y|_Z, F(x))$ is | |
a sheaf. Details omitted. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{definition} | |
\label{definition-hilbert-d-stack} | |
We will denote $\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}/\mathcal{Y})$ | |
the {\it degree $d$ finite Hilbert stack of $\mathcal{X}$ over $\mathcal{Y}$} | |
constructed above. If $\mathcal{Y} = S$ we write | |
$\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}) = \mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}/\mathcal{Y})$. | |
If $\mathcal{X} = \mathcal{Y} = S$ we denote it $\mathcal{H}_d$. | |
\end{definition} | |
\noindent | |
Note that given $F : \mathcal{X} \to \mathcal{Y}$ as above we have the | |
following natural $1$-morphisms of stacks in groupoids over | |
$(\Sch/S)_{fppf}$: | |
\begin{equation} | |
\label{equation-diagram-hilbert-d-stack} | |
\vcenter{ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}) \ar[rd] & | |
\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}/\mathcal{Y}) \ar[d] \ar[l] \ar[r] & | |
\mathcal{Y} \\ | |
& \mathcal{H}_d | |
} | |
} | |
\end{equation} | |
Each of the arrows is given by a "forgetful functor". | |
\begin{lemma} | |
\label{lemma-faithful-hilbert} | |
The $1$-morphism | |
$\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}/\mathcal{Y}) \to \mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X})$ | |
is faithful. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
To check that | |
$\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}/\mathcal{Y}) \to \mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X})$ | |
is faithful it suffices to prove that it is faithful on fibre categories. | |
Suppose that $\xi = (U, Z, y, x, \alpha)$ and $\xi' = (U, Z', y', x', \alpha')$ | |
are two objects of $\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}/\mathcal{Y})$ over the | |
scheme $U$. Let $(g, b, a), (g', b', a') : \xi \to \xi'$ be two morphisms | |
in the fibre category of $\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X}/\mathcal{Y})$ over $U$. | |
The image of these morphisms in $\mathcal{H}_d(\mathcal{X})$ agree | |
if and only if $g = g'$ and $a = a'$. Then the commutative diagram | |
$$ | |
\xymatrix{ | |
y|_Z \ar[rr]_\alpha \ar[d]_{b|_Z, \ b'|_Z} & & | |
F(x) \ar[d]^{F(a) = F(a')} \\ | |
y'|_Z \ar[rr]^-{\alpha'} & & | |
F(g^*x') = F((g')^*x') \\ | |
} | |
$$ | |
implies that $b|_Z = b'|_Z$. Since $Z \to U$ is finite locally free of degree | |
$d$ we see $\{Z \to U\}$ is an fppf covering, hence $b = b'$. | |
\end{proof} | |
\input{chapters} | |
\bibliography{my} | |
\bibliographystyle{amsalpha} | |
\end{document} | |