Datasets:
Tasks:
Text Generation
Modalities:
Text
Sub-tasks:
language-modeling
Languages:
English
Size:
100K - 1M
License:
\chapter{The $\spec$ of a ring} | |
\label{spec} | |
The notion of the $\spec$ of a ring is fundamental in modern | |
algebraic | |
geometry. It is the scheme-theoretic analog of classical affine | |
schemes. The | |
identification occurs when one identifies the maximal ideals of | |
the polynomial | |
ring $k[x_1, \dots, x_n]$ (for $k$ an algebraically closed | |
field) with the | |
points of the classical variety $\mathbb{A}^n_k = k^n$. In | |
modern algebraic | |
geometry, one adds the ``non-closed points'' given by the other | |
prime ideals. | |
Just as general varieties were classically defined by gluing | |
affine varieties, a | |
scheme is defined by gluing open affines. | |
This is not a book on schemes, but it will nonetheless be | |
convenient to introduce the $\spec$ construction, outside of the obvious | |
benefits of including preparatory material for algebraic geometry. First of | |
all, it will provide a convenient | |
notation. Second, and more importantly, it will provide a | |
convenient geometric | |
intuition. For example, an $R$-module can be thought of as a | |
kind of ``vector | |
bundle''---technically, a sheaf---over the space $\spec R$, with | |
the caveat | |
that the rank might not be locally constant (which is, however, | |
the case when the module | |
is projective). | |
\section{The spectrum of a ring} | |
We shall now associate to every commutative ring a topological | |
space $\spec R$ | |
in a functorial manner. | |
That is, there will be a contravariant functor | |
\[\spec: \mathbf{CRing} \to \mathbf{Top} \] | |
where $\mathbf{Top}$ is the category of topological spaces. | |
This construction is the basis for scheme-theoretic | |
algebraic geometry and will be used frequently in the sequel. | |
The motivating observation is the following. If $k$ is an algebraically closed | |
field, then the maximal ideals in $k[x_1, \dots, x_n]$ are of the form | |
$(x_1-a_1, \dots, x_n - a_n)$ for $(a_1, \dots, a_n) \in k[x_1, \dots, x_n]$. | |
This is the Nullstellensatz, which we have not proved yet. We can thus | |
identify the maximal ideals in the polynomial ring with the space $k^n$. | |
If $I \subset k[x_1, \dots, x_n]$ is an ideal, then the maximal ideals in | |
$k[x_1,\dots,x_n]$ correspond to points where everything in $I$ vanishes. See | |
\rref{twovarpoly} for a more detailed explanation. Classical affine algebraic | |
geometry thus studies the set of maximal ideals in an algebra finitely | |
generated over an algebraically closed field. | |
The $\mathrm{Spec}$ of a ring is a generalization of this construction. | |
In general, it is more natural to | |
use all prime ideals instead of just maximal ideals. | |
\subsection{Definition and examples} | |
We start by defining $\spec$ as a set. We will next | |
construct the | |
Zariski topology and later the functoriality. | |
\begin{definition} | |
Let $R$ be a commutative ring. The \textbf{spectrum} of $R$, | |
denoted $\spec R$, is | |
the set of prime ideals of $R$. | |
\end{definition} | |
We shall now make $\spec R$ into a topological space. First, we | |
describe a | |
collection of sets which will become the closed sets. | |
If $I \subset R$ is an ideal, let | |
\[ V(I) = \left\{\mathfrak{p}: \mathfrak{p} \supset I\right\} | |
\subset \spec R. | |
\] | |
\begin{proposition} | |
There is a topology on $\spec R$ such that the closed subsets | |
are of the form | |
$V(I)$ for $I \subset R$ an ideal. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Indeed, we have to check the familiar axioms for a topology: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $\emptyset = V((1))$ because no prime contains $1$. So | |
$\emptyset$ is closed. | |
\item $\spec R = V((0))$ because any ideal contains zero. So | |
$\spec R$ is | |
closed. | |
\item We show the closed sets are stable under intersections. | |
Let | |
$K_{\alpha} = V(I_{\alpha})$ be closed subsets of $\spec R$ for | |
$\alpha$ | |
ranging over some index set. Let $I | |
= \sum I_{\alpha}$. Then | |
\[ V(I) = \bigcap K_{\alpha} = \bigcap V(I_{\alpha}), \] | |
which follows because $I$ is the smallest ideal containing each | |
$I_{\alpha}$, | |
so a prime contains every $I_{\alpha}$ iff it contains $I$. | |
\item The union of two closed sets is closed. Indeed, if $K,K' | |
\subset \spec | |
R$ are closed, we show $K \cup K'$ is closed. Say $K= V(I), K' = | |
V(I')$. Then | |
we claim: | |
\[ K \cup K' = V(II'). \] | |
Here, as usual, $II'$ is the ideal generated by products $ii', i \in I, i' | |
\in I'$. If | |
$\mathfrak{p}$ is \textbf{prime} and contains $II'$, it must | |
contain one of $I$, $I'$; | |
this implies the displayed equation above and implies the | |
result. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{definition} | |
The topology on $\spec R$ defined above is called the | |
\textbf{Zariski | |
topology}. With it, $\spec R$ is now a topological space. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{exercise} | |
What is the $\spec$ of the zero ring? | |
\end{exercise} | |
In order to see the geometry of this construction, let us work | |
several examples. | |
\begin{example} | |
Let $R = \mathbb{Z}$, and consider $\spec \mathbb{Z}$. Then | |
every prime is generated by one element, since | |
$\mathbb{Z}$ is a PID. We have that $\spec \mathbb{Z} = \{(0)\} | |
\cup \bigcup_{p \ | |
\mathrm{prime}} \{ (p)\}$. The picture is that one has all the | |
familiar primes $(2), (3), | |
(5), \dots, $ and then a special point $(0)$. | |
Let us now describe the closed subsets. These are of the form | |
$V(I)$ where $I | |
\subset \mathbb{Z}$ is an ideal, so $I = (n)$ for some $n \in | |
\mathbb{Z}$. | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item If $n=0$, the closed subset is all of $\spec \mathbb{Z}$. | |
\item If $n \neq 0$, then $n$ has finitely many prime divisors. | |
So $V((n))$ consists | |
of the prime ideals corresponding to these prime divisors. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
The only closed subsets besides the entire space are the finite | |
subsets | |
that exclude $(0)$. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{example} \label{twovarpoly} | |
Say $R = \mathbb{C}[x,y]$ is a polynomial ring in two variables. | |
We will not give a complete description of $\spec R$ here. But we will write | |
down several | |
prime ideals. | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item For every pair of complex numbers $s,t \in \mathbb{C}$, | |
the collection of polynomials | |
$f \in R$ such that $f(s,t) = 0$ is a prime ideal $\mathfrak{m} | |
_{s,t} \subset R$. In | |
fact, it is maximal, as the residue ring is all of | |
$\mathbb{C}$. Indeed, | |
$R/\mathfrak{m}_{s,t} \simeq \mathbb{C}$ under the map $f \to | |
f(s,t)$. | |
In fact, | |
\begin{theorem} | |
The $\mathfrak{m}_{s,t}$ are all the maximal ideals in $R$. | |
\end{theorem} | |
This will follow from the \emph{Hilbert Nullstellensatz} to be | |
proved later | |
(\rref{gennullstellensatz}). | |
\item $(0) \subset R$ is a prime ideal since $R$ is a domain. | |
\item If $f(x,y) \in R$ is an irreducible polynomial, then $(f)$ | |
is a prime | |
ideal. This is equivalent to unique factorization in | |
$R$.\footnote{To be | |
proved later \rref{}.} | |
\end{enumerate} | |
To draw $\spec R$, we start by drawing $\mathbb{C}^2$, which is identified | |
with the | |
collection of | |
maximal ideals $\mathfrak{m}_{s,t}, s, t \in \mathbb{C}$. $\spec R$ has | |
additional (non-closed) points | |
too, as | |
described above, but for now let us | |
consider the topology induced on $\mathbb{C}^2$ as a subspace of | |
$\spec R$. | |
The closed subsets of $\spec R$ are subsets $V(I)$ where $I$ is | |
an ideal, | |
generated by polynomials $\left\{f_{\alpha}(x,y)\right\}$. It is of interest to | |
determine the subset of $\mathbb{C}^2$ that | |
$V(I)$ | |
induces. In other words, we ask: | |
\begin{quote} | |
What points of $\mathbb{C}^2$ (with $(s,t)$ identified with | |
$\mathfrak{m}_{s,t}$) lie in $V(I)$? | |
\end{quote} | |
Now, by definition, we know that $(s,t)$ corresponds to a point of $V(I)$ if | |
and only if $I | |
\subset \mathfrak{m}_{s,t}$. | |
This is true iff all the | |
$f_{\alpha} $ lie in $ \mathfrak{m}_{s,t}$, i.e. if | |
$f_{\alpha}(s,t) =0$ for all | |
$\alpha$. So the closed subsets of $\mathbb{C}^2$ (with the | |
induced Zariski | |
topology) are \emph{precisely the subsets | |
that can be defined by polynomial equations}. | |
This is | |
\textbf{much} coarser | |
than the usual topology. For instance, $\left\{(z_1,z_2): | |
\Re(z_1) \geq 0\right\}$ is | |
not Zariski-closed. | |
The Zariski topology is so coarse because one has only algebraic | |
data (namely, | |
polynomials, or elements of $R$) to define the topology. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{exercise} | |
Let $R_1, R_2$ be commutative rings. Give $R_1 \times R_2$ a | |
natural structure | |
of a ring, and describe $\spec( R_1 \times R_2)$ in terms of | |
$\spec R_1$ and | |
$\spec R_2$. | |
\end{exercise} | |
\begin{exercise} | |
Let $X$ be a compact Hausdorff space, $C(X)$ the ring of real | |
continuous | |
functions $X \to \mathbb{R}$. | |
The maximal ideals in $\spec C(X)$ are in bijection with the | |
points of $X$, | |
and the topology induced on $X $ (as a subset of $\spec C(X)$ with the Zariski | |
topology) | |
is just the usual topology. | |
\end{exercise} | |
\begin{exercise} | |
Prove the following result: if $X, Y$ are compact Hausdorff | |
spaces and $C(X), | |
C(Y)$ the associated rings of continuous functions, if $C(X), | |
C(Y)$ are | |
isomorphic as $\mathbb{R}$-algebras, then $X$ is homeomorphic to | |
$Y$. | |
\end{exercise} | |
\subsection{The radical ideal-closed subset correspondence} | |
We now return to the case of an arbitrary commutative ring $R$. | |
If $I \subset R$, we get a closed | |
subset $V(I) \subset \spec R$. It is called $V(I)$ because one | |
is supposed to | |
think of it as the places where the elements of $I$ ``vanish,'' | |
as the | |
elements of $R$ are something like ``functions.'' This analogy | |
is perhaps best | |
seen in the example of a polynomial ring over an algebraically | |
closed field, | |
e.g. \rref{twovarpoly} above. | |
The map from ideals into closed sets is very far from being | |
injective in | |
general, though by definition it is surjective. | |
\begin{example} | |
If $R = \mathbb{Z}$ and $p$ is prime, then $I = (p), I' = (p^2)$ | |
define the | |
same subset (namely, $\left\{(p)\right\}$) of | |
$\spec R$. | |
\end{example} | |
We now ask why the map from ideals to closed | |
subsets fails to | |
be injective. As we shall see, the entire problem disappears if | |
we restrict to | |
\emph{radical} ideals. | |
\begin{definition} | |
If $I$ is an ideal, then the \textbf{radical} $\rad(I) $ or $ | |
\sqrt{I}$ is | |
defined as $$\rad(I) = | |
\left\{x \in R: x^n \in I \ \mathrm{for} \ \mathrm{some} \ n | |
\right\}.$$ | |
An ideal is \textbf{radical} if it is equal to its radical. | |
(This is | |
equivalent to the earlier \rref{def-radical-ideal}.) | |
\end{definition} | |
Before proceeding, we must check: | |
\begin{lemma} | |
If $I$ an ideal, so is $\rad(I)$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Clearly $\rad(I)$ is closed under multiplication since $I$ is. | |
Suppose $x,y \in \rad(I)$; we show $x+y \in \rad(I)$. Then $x^n, | |
y^n \in I$ | |
for some $n$ (large) and thus for all larger $n$. The binomial | |
expansion now | |
gives | |
\[ (x+y)^{2n} = x^{2n} + \binom{2n}{1} x^{2n-1}y + \dots + | |
y^{2n}, \] | |
where every term contains either $x,y$ with power $ \geq n$, so | |
every term | |
belongs to $I$. Thus $(x+y)^{2n} \in I$ and, by definition, we | |
see then that $x+y \in \rad(I)$. | |
\end{proof} | |
The map $I \to V(I)$ does in fact depend only on the radical of | |
$I$. In fact, if $I,J$ have the same radical $\rad(I) = | |
\rad(J)$, then $V(I) = V(J)$. | |
Indeed, $V(I) = V(\rad(I)) = V(\rad(J)) = V(J)$ by: | |
\begin{lemma} | |
For any $I$, $V(I) = V(\rad(I))$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Indeed, $I \subset \rad(I)$ and therefore obviously $V(\rad(I)) | |
\subset V(I)$. We have to show the | |
converse inclusion. Namely, we must prove: | |
\begin{quote} | |
If $\mathfrak{p} \supset I$, then $\mathfrak{p} \supset | |
\rad(I).$ | |
\end{quote} | |
So suppose $\mathfrak{p} \supset I$ is prime and $x \in | |
\rad(I)$; then $x^n \in I \subset \mathfrak{p}$ for some $n$. | |
But $\mathfrak{p}$ is prime, so whenever a product of things | |
belongs to | |
$\mathfrak{p}$, a factor does. Thus since $x^n = x \cdot x | |
\cdots x$, we must | |
have $x \in \mathfrak{p}$. So | |
\[ \rad(I) \subset \mathfrak{p}, \] | |
proving the quoted claim, and thus the lemma. | |
\end{proof} | |
There is a converse to this remark: | |
\begin{proposition} | |
If $V(I) = V(J)$, then $\rad(I) = \rad(J)$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
So two ideals define the same closed subset iff they have the | |
same radical. | |
\begin{proof} | |
We write down a formula for $\rad(I)$ that will imply this at | |
once. | |
\begin{lemma} \label{radprimescontaining} For a commutative ring $R$ and an | |
ideal $I \subset | |
R$, | |
\[ \rad(I) = \bigcap_{\mathfrak{p} \supset I} \mathfrak{p}. \] | |
\end{lemma} | |
From this, it follows that $V(I)$ determines $\rad(I)$. This | |
will thus imply | |
the proposition. | |
We now prove the lemma: | |
\begin{proof} | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item We show $\rad(I) \subset \bigcap_{\mathfrak{p} \in V(I)} | |
\mathfrak{p} $. In | |
particular, this follows if we show that if a prime contains | |
$I$, it contains $\rad(I)$; but we have already | |
discussed this above. | |
\item If $x \notin \rad(I)$, we will show that there is a prime | |
ideal $\mathfrak{p} | |
\supset I$ not containing $x$. This will imply the reverse | |
inclusion and the | |
lemma. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
We want to find $\mathfrak{p}$ not containing $x$, more | |
generally not | |
containing any power of $x$. In particular, we want | |
$\mathfrak{p} \cap \left\{1, | |
x, x^2 \dots, \right\} = \emptyset$. This set $S = \left\{1, x, | |
\dots\right\}$ | |
is multiplicatively closed, in that it contains 1 and is closed | |
under | |
finite products. Right now, it does not interset $I$; we want to find | |
a | |
\emph{prime} containing $I$ that still does not intersect $\left\{x^n, n | |
\geq 0\right\}$. | |
More generally, we will prove: | |
\begin{sublemma}\label{sublemmamultclosed} | |
Let $S$ be multiplicatively closed set in any ring $R$ and let | |
$I$ be any ideal with $I \cap S = | |
\emptyset$. There is a prime ideal $\mathfrak{p} \supset I$ and | |
does not | |
intersect $S$ (in fact, any ideal maximal with respect to the condition of | |
not intersecting $S$ will do). | |
\end{sublemma} | |
In English, any ideal missing $S$ can be enlarged to a prime | |
ideal missing $S$. | |
This is actually fancier version of a previous argument. We | |
showed earlier that any ideal not | |
containing the multiplicatively closed subset $\left\{1\right\}$ | |
can be | |
contained in a prime ideal not containing $1$, in | |
\rref{anycontainedinmaximal}. | |
Note that the sublemma clearly implies the lemma when applied to | |
$S = | |
\left\{1, x, \dots\right\}.$ | |
\begin{proof}[Proof of the sublemma] | |
Let $P = \left\{J: J \supset I, J \cap S = \emptyset \right\}$. | |
Then $P$ is a | |
poset with respect to inclusion. Note that $P \neq \emptyset$ | |
because $I \in P$. Also, | |
for any nonempty linearly ordered subset of $P$, the union is in | |
$P$ (i.e. there is an | |
upper bound). | |
We can invoke Zorn's lemma to get a maximal element of $P$. This | |
element is an | |
ideal $\mathfrak{p} \supset I$ with $\mathfrak{p} \cap S = | |
\emptyset$. We claim | |
that $\mathfrak{p}$ is prime. | |
First of all, $1 \notin \mathfrak{p}$ because $1 \in S$. We need | |
only check | |
that if $xy \in \mathfrak{p}$, then $x \in \mathfrak{p}$ or $y | |
\in | |
\mathfrak{p}$. Suppose otherwise, so $x,y \notin \mathfrak{p}$. | |
Then $(x,\mathfrak{p}) \notin P$ or | |
$\mathfrak{p}$ would not be maximal. Ditto for $(y, | |
\mathfrak{p})$. | |
In particular, we have that these bigger ideals both intersect | |
$S$. This means | |
that there are | |
\[ a \in \mathfrak{p} , r \in R \quad \text{such that}\quad a+rx | |
\in S \] | |
and | |
\[ b \in \mathfrak{p} , r' \in R \quad \text{such that}\quad | |
b+r'y \in S .\] | |
Now $S$ is multiplicatively closed, so multiply $(a+rx)(b+r'y) | |
\in S$. | |
We find: | |
\[ ab + ar'y+brx+rr'xy \in S. \] | |
Now $a,b \in \mathfrak{p}$ and $xy \in \mathfrak{p}$, so all the | |
terms above are in $\mathfrak{p}$, and the sum is too. But this contradicts | |
$\mathfrak{p} | |
\cap S = \emptyset$. | |
\end{proof} | |
\end{proof} | |
\end{proof} | |
The upshot of the previous lemmata is: | |
\begin{proposition} | |
There is a bijection between the closed subsets of $\spec R$ and | |
radical ideals | |
$I \subset R$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\subsection{A meta-observation about prime ideals} | |
We saw in the previous subsection (\cref{sublemmamultclosed}) | |
that an ideal maximal with respect to the property of not intersecting a | |
multiplicatively closed subset is prime. | |
It turns out that this is the case for many such properties of ideals. | |
A general method of seeing this was developed in \cite{LaRe08}. | |
In this (optional) subsection, we digress to explain this phenomenon. | |
If $I$ is an ideal and $a \in R$, we define the notation | |
\[ (I:a) = \left\{ x\in R: xa \in I\right\} . \] | |
More generally, if $J$ is an ideal, we define | |
\[ (I:J) = \left\{x \in R: xJ \subset I\right\} . \] | |
Let $R$ be a ring, and $\mathcal{F}$ a collection of ideals of $R$. | |
We are interested in conditions that will guarantee that the maximal elements | |
of $\mathcal{F}$ are \emph{prime}. | |
Actually, we will do the opposite: the following condition will guarantee that | |
the ideals maximal at \emph{not} being in $\mathcal{F}$ are prime. | |
\begin{definition} \label{okafamily} | |
The family $\mathcal{F}$ is called an \textbf{Oka family} if $R \in | |
\mathcal{F}$ (where $R$ is considered as an ideal) and whenever $I \subset R$ is an | |
ideal and $(I:a), (I,a) \in \mathcal{F}$ (for some $a \in R$), then $I \in | |
\mathcal{F}$. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{example} \label{exm:okacard} | |
Let us begin with a simple observation. If $(I:a)$ is generated by | |
$a_1, \dots, a_n$ and $(I,a)$ is generated by $a, b_1, \dots, b_m$ (where we | |
may take | |
$b_1, \dots, b_m \in I$, without loss of generality), then $I$ | |
is generated by $aa_1, \dots, aa_n, b_1, \dots, b_m$. | |
To see this, note that if $x \in I$, then $x \in (I,a)$ is a linear | |
combination of the $\left\{a, b_1, \dots, b_m\right\}$, but the coefficient of | |
$a$ must | |
lie in $(I:a)$. | |
As a result, we may deduce that | |
the family of finitely generated ideals is an Oka family. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{example} | |
Let us now show that the family of \emph{principal} ideals is an Oka family. | |
Indeed, suppose $I \subset R$ is an ideal, and $(I,a)$ and $(I:a)$ are | |
principal. | |
One can easily check that | |
$(I:a) = (I: (I, a))$. | |
Setting $J = (I,a)$, we find that $J$ is principal and $(I:J)$ is too. | |
However, for \emph{any} principal ideal $J$, and for any ideal $I \subset J$, | |
\[ I = J (I: J) \] | |
as one easily checks. Thus we find in our situation that since $J=(I,a)$ and | |
$(I:J)$ | |
are principal, $I$ is principal. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{proposition}[\cite{LaRe08}]\label{okathm} If $\mathcal{F}$ is an Oka | |
family of | |
ideals, then any maximal element of the complement of $\mathcal{F}$ is prime. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Suppose $I \notin \mathcal{F}$ is maximal with respect | |
to not being in $\mathcal{F}$ | |
but $I$ is not prime. Note that $I \neq R$ by hypothesis. | |
Then there is $a \in R$ such that $(I:a), (I,a)$ both strictly contain $I$, | |
so they must belong to $\mathcal{F}$. | |
Indeed, we can find $a,b \in R - I$ with $ab \in I$; it follows that $(I,a) | |
\neq I$ and $(I:a)$ contains $b \notin I$. | |
By the Oka condition, we have $I \in | |
\mathcal{F}$, a contradiction. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{corollary}[Cohen] \label{primenoetherian} | |
If every prime ideal of $R$ is finitely generated, then every ideal of $R$ is | |
finitely generated.\footnote{Later we will say that $R$ is \emph{noetherian.}} | |
\end{corollary} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Suppose that there existed ideals $I \subset R$ which were not finitely | |
generated. | |
The union of a totally ordered chain $\left\{I_\alpha\right\}$ of ideals that | |
are not finitely generated is not finitely | |
generated; indeed, if $I = \bigcup I_\alpha$ were generated by $a_1, \dots, | |
a_n$, then all the generators would belong to some $I_\alpha $ and would | |
consequently generate it. | |
By Zorn's lemma, there is an ideal maximal with respect to being not finitely | |
generated. However, by \rref{okathm}, this ideal is necessarily | |
prime (since the family of finitely generated ideals is an Oka family). This contradicts the hypothesis. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{corollary} | |
If every prime ideal of $R$ is principal, then every ideal of $R$ is principal. | |
\end{corollary} | |
\begin{proof} | |
This is proved in the same way. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{exercise} | |
Suppose every nonzero prime ideal in $R$ contains a non-zerodivisor. Then $R$ | |
is a domain. (Hint: consider the set $S$ of nonzerodivisors, and argue that | |
any ideal maximal with respect to not intersecting $S$ is prime. Thus, $(0)$ | |
is prime.) | |
\end{exercise} | |
\begin{remark} | |
\label{remark-cohen-bound-cardinality} | |
Let $R$ be a ring. Let $\kappa$ be an infinite cardinal. | |
By applying | |
\rref{exm:okacard} and | |
\rref{okathm} | |
we see that any ideal maximal with respect to the property of not being | |
generated by $\kappa$ elements is prime. This result is not so | |
useful because there exists a ring for which every prime ideal | |
of $R$ can be generated by $\aleph_0$ elements, but some | |
ideal cannot. Namely, let $k$ be a field, let $T$ be a set whose | |
cardinality is greater than $\aleph_0$ and let | |
\[ R = k[\{x_n\}_{n \geq 1}, \{z_{t, n}\}_{t \in T, n \geq 0}]/ | |
(x_n^2, z_{t, n}^2, x_n z_{t, n} - z_{t, n - 1}) \] | |
This is a local ring with unique prime ideal | |
$\mathfrak m = (x_n)$. But the ideal $(z_{t, n})$ cannot | |
be generated by countably many elements. | |
\end{remark} | |
\subsection{Functoriality of $\spec$} | |
The construction $R \to \spec R$ is functorial in $R$ in a | |
contravariant sense. That is, if $f: R \to R'$, there is a | |
continuous map $\spec | |
R' \to \spec R$. This map sends $\mathfrak{p} \subset R'$ to | |
$f^{-1}(\mathfrak{p}) \subset R$, which is easily seen to be a | |
prime ideal | |
in $R$. Call this map $F: \spec R' \to \spec R$. So far, we have | |
seen that | |
$\spec R$ induces a contravariant functor from $\mathbf{Rings} | |
\to \mathbf{Sets}$. | |
\begin{exercise} | |
A contravariant functor $F: \mathcal{C} \to \mathbf{Sets}$ (for | |
some category | |
$\mathcal{C}$) is called \textbf{representable} if it is | |
naturally isomorphic | |
to a functor of the form $X \to \hom(X, X_0)$ for some $X_0 \in | |
\mathcal{C}$, | |
or equivalently if the induced covariant functor on | |
$\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}}$ is corepresentable. | |
The functor $R \to \spec R $ is not representable. (Hint: | |
Indeed, a representable | |
functor must send the initial object into a one-point set.) | |
\end{exercise} | |
Next, we check that the morphisms induced on $\spec$'s from a | |
ring-homomorphism are in fact \emph{continuous} maps of | |
topological spaces. | |
\begin{proposition} | |
$\spec $ induces a contravariant functor from $\mathbf{Rings}$ | |
to the category | |
$\mathbf{Top}$ of topological spaces. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} Let $f : R \to R'$. | |
We need to check that this map $ \spec R' \to \spec R$, which we | |
call $F$, is | |
continuous. | |
That is, we must check that $F^{-1}$ sends closed | |
subsets of $\spec R$ to closed subsets of $\spec R'$. | |
More precisely, if $I \subset | |
R$ and we take the inverse image $F^{-1}(V(I)) \subset \spec | |
R'$, it is just | |
the closed set $V(f(I))$. This is best left to the reader, but | |
here is the justification. If $\mathfrak{p} \in \spec R'$, then | |
$F(\mathfrak{p}) = f^{-1}(\mathfrak{p}) | |
\supset I$ if and only if $\mathfrak{p} \supset f(I)$. So | |
$F(\mathfrak{p}) \in | |
V(I)$ if and only if $\mathfrak{p} \in V(f(I))$. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{example} | |
Let $R$ be a commutative ring, $I \subset R$ an ideal, $f: R \to | |
R/I$. There is a map | |
of topological spaces | |
\[ F: \spec (R/I) \to \spec R .\] | |
This map is a closed embedding whose image is $V(I)$. Most of | |
this follows because | |
there is a bijection between ideals of $R$ containing $I$ and | |
ideals of $R/I$, and this bijection preserves primality. | |
\begin{exercise} | |
Show that this map $\spec R/I \to \spec R$ is indeed a | |
homeomorphism from $\spec R/I | |
\to V(I)$. | |
\end{exercise} | |
\end{example} | |
\subsection{A basis for the Zariski topology} | |
In the previous section, we were talking about the Zariski | |
topology. If $R$ is a | |
commutative ring, we recall that $\spec R$ is defined to be the | |
collection of | |
prime ideals in $R$. This has a topology where the closed sets | |
are the sets of | |
the form | |
\[ V(I) = \left\{\mathfrak{p} \in \spec R: \mathfrak{p} \supset | |
I\right\} . \] | |
There is another way to describe the Zariski topology in terms | |
of | |
\emph{open} sets. | |
\begin{definition} | |
If $f \in R$, we let | |
\[ U_f = \left\{\mathfrak{p}: f \notin \mathfrak{p}\right\} \] | |
so that $U_f$ is the subset of $\spec R$ consisting of primes | |
not containing | |
$f$. This is the complement of $V((f))$, so it is open. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{proposition} | |
The sets $U_f$ form a basis for the Zariski topology. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Suppose $U \subset \spec R$ is open. We claim that $U$ is a | |
union of basic | |
open sets $U_f$. | |
Now $U = \spec R - V(I)$ for some ideal $I$. Then | |
\[ U = \bigcup_{f \in I} U_f \] | |
because if an ideal is not in $V(I)$, then it fails to contain | |
some $f \in I$, | |
i.e. is in $U_f$ for that $f$. Alternatively, we could take | |
complements, whence | |
the above statement becomes | |
\[ V(I) = \bigcap_{f \in I} V((f)) \] | |
which is clear. | |
\end{proof} | |
The basic open sets have nice properties. | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $U_1 = \spec R$ because prime ideals are not allowed to | |
contain the | |
unit element. | |
\item $U_0 = \emptyset$ because every prime ideal contains $0$. | |
\item $U_{fg} = U_f \cap U_g$ because $fg$ lies in a prime ideal | |
$\mathfrak{p}$ if and only if one of $f,g$ does. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
Now let us describe what the Zariski topology has to do with | |
localization. | |
Let $R$ be a ring and $f \in R$. Consider $S = \left\{1, f, f^2, | |
\dots | |
\right\}$; this is a multiplicatively closed subset. Last week, | |
we defined | |
$S^{-1}R$. | |
\begin{definition} | |
For $S$ the powers of $f$, we write $R_f$ or $R[f^{-1}]$ for the | |
localization $S^{-1}R$. | |
\end{definition} | |
There is a map $\phi: R \to R[f^{-1}]$ and a corresponding map | |
\[ \spec R[f^{-1}] \to \spec R \] | |
sending a prime $\mathfrak{p} \subset R[f^{-1}]$ to | |
$\phi^{-1}(\mathfrak{p})$. | |
\begin{proposition} | |
This map induces a homeomorphism of $\spec R[f^{-1}]$ onto $U_f | |
\subset \spec | |
R$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
So if one takes a commutative ring and inverts an element, one | |
just gets an open | |
subset of $\spec$. This is why it's called localization: one is | |
restricting to | |
an open subset on the $\spec $ level when one inverts something. | |
\begin{proof} | |
The reader is encouraged to work this proof out for herself. | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item | |
First, we show that $\spec R[f^{-1}] \to \spec R$ lands in | |
$U_f$. If | |
$\mathfrak{p} \subset R[f^{-1}]$, then we must show that the | |
inverse image | |
$\phi^{-1}(\mathfrak{p})$ can't contain $f$. If otherwise, that | |
would imply that | |
$\phi(f) \in \mathfrak{p}$; however, $\phi(f)$ is invertible, | |
and then | |
$\mathfrak{p}$ would be $(1)$. | |
\item Let's show that the map surjects onto $U_f$. If | |
$\mathfrak{p} \subset R$ is a prime | |
ideal not containing $f$, i.e. $\mathfrak{p} \in U_f$. We want | |
to construct a | |
corresponding prime in the ring $R[f^{-1}]$ whose inverse image | |
is $\mathfrak{p}$. | |
Let $\mathfrak{p}[f^{-1}]$ be the collection of all fractions | |
\[ \{\frac{x}{f^n}, x \in \mathfrak{p}\} \subset R[f^{-1}], \] | |
which is evidently an ideal. Note that whether the numerator is | |
in | |
$\mathfrak{p}$ is \textbf{independent} of the | |
representing fraction $\frac{x}{f^n}$ used.\footnote{Suppose | |
$\frac{x}{f^n} = | |
\frac{y}{f^k}$ for $y \in \mathfrak{p}$. Then there is $N$ such | |
that | |
$f^N(f^k x - f^n y) = 0 \in \mathfrak{p}$; since $y \in | |
\mathfrak{p}$ and $f | |
\notin \mathfrak{p}$, it follows that $x \in \mathfrak{p}$.} | |
In fact, $\mathfrak{p}[f^{-1}]$ is a prime ideal. Indeed, | |
suppose | |
\[ \frac{a}{f^m} \frac{b}{f^n} \in \mathfrak{p}[f^{-1}] .\] | |
Then $\frac{ab}{f^{m+n}}$ belongs to this ideal, which means $ab | |
\in | |
\mathfrak{p}$; so one of $a,b \in \mathfrak{p}$ and one of the | |
two fractions | |
$\frac{a}{f^m}, \frac{b}{f^n}$ belongs to | |
$\mathfrak{p}[f^{-1}]$. Also, $1/1 | |
\notin \mathfrak{p}[f^{-1}]$. | |
It is clear that the inverse image of $\mathfrak{p}[f^{-1}]$ is | |
$\mathfrak{p}$, | |
because the image of $x \in R$ is $x/1$, and this belongs to | |
$\mathfrak{p}[f^{-1}]$ precisely when $x \in \mathfrak{p}$. | |
\item The map $\spec R[f^{-1}] \to \spec R$ is injective. | |
Suppose | |
$\mathfrak{p}, \mathfrak{p'}$ are prime ideals in the | |
localization and the | |
inverse images are the same. | |
We must show that $\mathfrak{p} = \mathfrak{p'}$. | |
Suppose $\frac{x}{f^n} \in \mathfrak{p}$. Then $x/1 \in | |
\mathfrak{p}$, so $x | |
\in \phi^{-1}(\mathfrak{p}) = \phi^{-1}(\mathfrak{p}')$. This | |
means that $x/1 | |
\in \mathfrak{p}'$, so | |
$\frac{x}{f^n} \in \mathfrak{p}'$ too. So a fraction that | |
belongs to | |
$\mathfrak{p}$ belongs to $\mathfrak{p}'$. By symmetry the two | |
ideals must be | |
the same. | |
\item We now know that the map $\psi: \spec R[f^{-1}] \to U_f$ | |
is a continuous | |
bijection. It is left to see that it is a homeomorphism. We will | |
show that it | |
is open. | |
In particular, we have to show that a basic open set on the left | |
side is mapped | |
to an open set on the right side. | |
If $y/f^n \in R[f^{-1}]$, we have to show that $U_{y/f^n} | |
\subset \spec | |
R[f^{-1}]$ has open image under $\psi$. We'll in fact show what | |
open set it is. | |
We claim that | |
\[ \psi(U_{y/f^n}) = U_{fy} \subset \spec R. \] | |
To see this, $\mathfrak{p}$ is contained in $U_{f/y^n}$. This | |
mean that | |
$\mathfrak{p}$ doesn't contain $y/f^n$. In particular, | |
$\mathfrak{p}$ doesn't | |
contain the multiple $yf/1$. So $\psi(\mathfrak{p})$ doesn't | |
contain $yf$. | |
This proves the inclusion $\subset$. | |
\item | |
To complete the proof of the claim, and | |
the result, we must show that if $\mathfrak{p} \subset \spec | |
R[f^{-1}]$ and | |
$\psi(\mathfrak{p}) = \phi^{-1}(\mathfrak{p}) \in U_{fy}$, then | |
$y/f^n$ doesn't | |
belong to $\mathfrak{p}$. (This is kosher and dandy because we | |
have a bijection.) But the hypothesis implies that $fy \notin | |
\phi^{-1}(\mathfrak{p})$, so $fy/1 \notin \mathfrak{p}$. | |
Dividing by $f^{n+1}$ | |
implies that | |
\[ y/f^{n} \notin \mathfrak{p} \] | |
and $\mathfrak{p} \in U_{f/y^n}$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
\end{proof} | |
If $\spec R$ is a space, and $f$ is thought of as a ``function'' | |
defined on | |
$\spec R$, the space $U_f$ is to be thought of as the set of | |
points where $f$ | |
``doesn't vanish'' or ``is invertible.'' | |
Thinking about rings in terms of their spectra is a very useful | |
idea. We will bring it up when appropriate. | |
\begin{remark} | |
The construction $R \to R[f^{-1}]$ as discussed above is an | |
instance of | |
localization. More generally, we defined $S^{-1}R$ for $S | |
\subset R$ | |
multiplicatively closed. We can thus define maps | |
\( \spec S^{-1}R \to \spec R . \) | |
To understand $S^{-1}R$, it may help to note that | |
\[ \varinjlim_{f \in S} R[f^{-1}] \] | |
which is a direct limit of rings where one inverts more and more elements. | |
As an example, consider $S = R - \mathfrak{p}$ for a prime | |
$\mathfrak{p}$, and for | |
simplicity that $R$ is countable. We can write $S = | |
S_0 \cup S_1 \cup \dots$, where each $S_k$ is generated by a | |
finite number of | |
elements $f_0, \dots, f_k$. Then $R_{\mathfrak{p}} = \varinjlim | |
S_k^{-1} R$. | |
So we have | |
\[ S^{-1}R = \varinjlim_k R[f_0^{-1} , f_1^{-1}, \dots, f_k^{-1} | |
] = \varinjlim | |
R[(f_0\dots f_k)^{-1}]. \] | |
The functions we invert in this construction are precisely those | |
which do not | |
contain $\mathfrak{p}$, or where ``the functions don't vanish.'' | |
The geometric idea is | |
that to construct $\spec S^{-1}R = \spec R_{\mathfrak{p}}$, we | |
keep cutting out | |
from $\spec R$ vanishing locuses of various functions that do | |
not | |
intersect $\mathfrak{p}$. In the end, you don't restrict to an | |
open set, but | |
to an intersection of them. | |
\end{remark} | |
\begin{exercise} \label{semilocal} | |
Say that $R$ is \emph{semi-local} if it has finitely many maximal ideals. | |
Let $\mathfrak{p}_1$, \dots, $\mathfrak{p}_n\subset R$ be primes. The complement of | |
the union, $S=R\smallsetminus \bigcup \mathfrak{p}_i$, is closed under | |
multiplication, so we can | |
localize. $R[S^{-1}] = R_S$ is called the \emph{semi-localization} | |
\index{semi-localization} of $R$ at the $\mathfrak{p}_i$. | |
The result of semi-localization is always semi-local. To see this, recall that | |
the ideals | |
in $R_S$ are in bijection with ideals in $R$ contained in $\bigcup | |
\mathfrak{p}_i$. Now use prime avoidance. | |
\end{exercise} | |
\begin{definition} | |
For a finitely generated $R$-module $M$, define $\mu_R(M)$ to be the smallest | |
number | |
of elements that can generate $M$. | |
\end{definition} | |
This is not the same as the cardinality of a minimal set of generators. For | |
example, 2 | |
and 3 are a minimal set of generators for $\mathbb{Z}$ over itself, but | |
$\mu_\mathbb{Z} (\mathbb{Z}) =1$. | |
\begin{theorem} | |
Let $R$ be semi-local with maximal ideals $\mathfrak{m}_1,\dots, | |
\mathfrak{m}_n$. Let $k_i = R/\mathfrak{m}_i$. Then | |
\[ | |
\mathfrak{m}u_R(M) = \mathfrak{m}ax \{\dim_{k_i} M/\mathfrak{m}_i M\} | |
\] | |
\end{theorem} | |
\begin{proof} | |
\add{proof} | |
\end{proof} | |
\section{Nilpotent elements} | |
We will now prove a few general results about nilpotent results in a ring. | |
Topologically, the nilpotents do very little: quotienting by them will not | |
change the $\spec$. Nonetheless, they carry geometric importance, and one | |
thinks of these nilpotents as ``infinitesimal thickenings'' (in a sense to be | |
elucidated below). | |
\subsection{The radical of a ring} | |
There is a useful corollary of the analysis in the previous section about the | |
$\spec$ of a ring. | |
\begin{definition} | |
$x \in R$ is called \textbf{nilpotent} if a power of $x$ is zero. The set of | |
nilpotent elements in $R$ is called the \textbf{radical} of $R$ and is denoted | |
$\rad(R)$ (which is an abuse of notation). | |
\end{definition} | |
The set of nilpotents is just the radical $\rad((0))$ of the zero ideal, so it | |
is an ideal. It can vary greatly. | |
A domain clearly has no nonzero nilpotents. On the other hand, many rings do: | |
\begin{example} | |
For any $n \geq 2$, the ring $\mathbb{Z}[X]/(X^n)$ has a nilpotent, namely $X$. | |
The ideal of nilpotent elements is $(X)$. | |
\end{example} | |
It is easy to see that a nilpotent must lie in any prime ideal. The converse | |
is also true by the previous analysis. | |
As a corollary of it, we find in fact: | |
\begin{corollary} \label{nilradicalisprimes} | |
Let $R$ be a commutative ring. Then the set of nilpotent elements of $R$ is | |
precisely $\bigcap_{\mathfrak{p} \in \spec R} \mathfrak{p}$. | |
\end{corollary} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Apply \rref{radprimescontaining} to the zero ideal. | |
\end{proof} | |
We now consider a few examples of nilpotent elements. | |
\begin{example}[Nilpotents in polynomial rings] | |
Let us now compute the nilpotent elements in the polynomial $R[x]$. | |
The claim is that a polynomial $\sum_{m=0}^n a_m x^m \in R[x]$ is nilpotent if | |
and only | |
if all the coefficients $a_m \in R$ are nilpotent. That is, $\rad(R[x]) = | |
(\rad(R))R[x]$. | |
If $a_0,\ldots,a_n$ are nilpotent, then because the nilpotent | |
elements form an ideal, $f=a_0+\cdots+a_nx^n$ is nilpotent. Conversely, | |
if $f$ is nilpotent, then $f^m=0$ and thus $(a_nx^n)^m=0$. Thus $a_nx^n$ | |
is nilpotent, and because the nilpotent elements form an ideal, $f-a_nx^n$ | |
is nilpotent. By induction, $a_ix^i$ is nilpotent for all $i$, so that all | |
$a_i$ are nilpotent. | |
\end{example} | |
Before the next example, we need to define a new notion. | |
We now define a power series ring intuitively in the same way they are used in | |
calculus. In fact, we will use power series rings much the same way we used them | |
in calculus; they will serve as keeping track of fine local data that the | |
Zariski topology might ``miss'' due to its coarseness. | |
\begin{definition} \label{powerseriesring} Let $R$ be a ring. The \textbf{power series ring} $R[[x]]$ is just the set of all | |
expressions of the form $\sum_{i=0}^\infty c_i x^i$. The arithmetic for the | |
power series ring will be done term by term formally (since we have no topology, | |
we can't consider questions of convergence, though a natural topology can be | |
defined making $R[[x]]$ the \emph{completion} of another ring, as we shall | |
see later). \end{definition} | |
\begin{example}[Nilpotence in power series rings] | |
Let $R$ be a ring such that $\rad(R)$ is a finitely generated ideal. (This is | |
satisfied, e.g., if $R$ is \emph{noetherian}, cf. \rref{noetherian}.) | |
Let us consider the question of how $\rad(R)$ and $\rad(R[[x]])$ are related. | |
The claim is that | |
\[ \rad(R[[x]]) = (\rad(R))R[[x]]. \] | |
If $f\in R[[x]]$ is nilpotent, say with $f^n=0$, then | |
certainly $a_0^n=0$, so that $a_0$ is nilpotent. Because the nilpotent elements | |
form an ideal, we have that $f-a_0$ is also nilpotent, and hence by induction | |
every coefficient of $f$ must be nilpotent in $R$. | |
For the converse, let $I = | |
\rad(R)$. There | |
exists an $N>0$ such that the ideal power $I^N = 0$ by finite generation. | |
Thus if $f \in IR[[x]]$, then $f^N \in I^N R[[x]] = 0$. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{exercise} \label{nilpcriterion} | |
Prove that $x \in R$ is nilpotent if and only if the localization $R_x$ is the | |
zero ring. | |
\end{exercise} | |
\begin{exercise} | |
Construct an example where $\rad(R) R[[x]] \neq \rad(R[[x]])$. (Hint: consider | |
$R = \mathbb{C}[X_1, X_2, X_3, \dots]/(X_1, X_2^2, X_3^3, \dots)$.) | |
\end{exercise} | |
\subsection{Lifting idempotents} | |
If $R$ is a ring, and $I \subset R$ a nilpotent ideal, then we want to think | |
of $R/I$ as somehow close to $R$. For instance, the inclusion $\spec R/I | |
\hookrightarrow \spec R$ is a homeomorphism, and one pictures that $\spec R$ | |
has some ``fuzz'' added (with the extra nilpotents in $I$) that is killed in | |
$\spec R/I$. | |
One manifestation of the ``closeness'' of $R$ and $R/I$ is the following | |
result, which states that the idempotent elements\footnote{Recall that an | |
element $e \in R$ is idempotent if $e^2 = e$.} of the two are in natural | |
bijection. | |
For convenience, we state it in additional generality (that is, for | |
noncommutative rings). | |
\begin{lemma}[Lifting idempotents] | |
Suppose $I \subset R$ is a nilpotent two-sided ideal, for $R$ any\footnote{Not | |
necessarily commutative.} ring. Let | |
$\overline{e} \in R/I$ be an idempotent. Then there is an idempotent $e | |
\in R$ which reduces to $\overline{e}$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
Note that if $J$ is a two-sided ideal in a noncommutative ring, then so are the | |
powers of $J$. | |
\begin{proof} Let us first assume that $I^2 = 0$. | |
We can find $e_1 \in R$ which reduces to $e$, but $e_1$ is not necessarily | |
idempotent. | |
By replacing $R$ with $\mathbb{Z}[e_1]$ and $I$ with $\mathbb{Z}[e_1] \cap I$, | |
we may assume that $R$ is in fact commutative. | |
However, | |
\[ e_1^2 \in e_1 + I. \] | |
Suppose we want to modify $e_1$ by $i$ such that $e = e_1 + i$ is | |
idempotent and $i \in I$; then $e$ will do as in the lemma. We would then | |
necessarily have | |
\[ e_1 + i = (e_1 + i)^2 = e_1^2 + 2e_1 i\quad \mathrm{as} \ I^2 =0 . \] | |
In particular, we must satisfy | |
\[ i(1-2e_1) = e_1^2 - e_1 \in I. \] | |
We claim that $1 - 2e_1 \in R$ is invertible, so that we can solve for $i \in I$. | |
However, $R$ is commutative. It thus suffices to check that $1 - 2e_1$ lies in | |
no maximal ideal of $R$. But the image of $e_1$ in $R/\mathfrak{m}$ for any | |
maximal ideal $\mathfrak{m} \subset R$ is either zero or one. So $1 - 2e_1$ has | |
image either $1$ or $-1$ in $R/\mathfrak{m}$. Thus it is invertible. | |
This establishes the result when $I$ has zero square. In general, suppose $I^n | |
= 0$. We have the sequence of noncommutative rings: | |
\[ R \twoheadrightarrow R/I^{n-1} \twoheadrightarrow R/I^{n-2} \dots | |
\twoheadrightarrow R/I. \] | |
The kernel at each step is an ideal whose square is zero. Thus, we can use the | |
lifting idempotents partial result proved above each step of the way and left | |
$\overline{e} \in R/I$ to some $e \in R$. | |
\end{proof} | |
While the above proof has the virtue of applying to noncommutative rings, | |
there is a more conceptual argument for commutative rings. The idea is that | |
idempotents in $A$ measure disconnections of $\spec A$.\footnote{More | |
generally, in any \emph{ringed space} (a space with a sheaf of rings), the | |
idempotents in the ring of global sections correspond to the disconnections of | |
the topological space.} Since the topological space underlying $\spec A$ is | |
unchanged when one quotients by nilpotents, idempotents are unaffected. | |
We prove: | |
\begin{proposition} If $X = \mathrm{Spec} \ A$, then there is a one-to-one | |
correspondence between $\idem(A)$ and the open and closed subsets of $X$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} Suppose $I$ is the radical of $(e)$ for an | |
an idempotent $e \in R$. We show that $V(I)$ is open and closed. Since $V$ is | |
unaffected by passing to the radical, we will assume without loss of | |
generality that | |
\[ I = (e). \] | |
I claim that $\spec R - V(I)$ is just $V(1-e) = V((1-e))$. This is a closed | |
set, so proving this claim will imply that $V(I)$ is open. Indeed, | |
$V(e)=V((e))$ cannot intersect $V(1-e)$ because if | |
\[ \mathfrak{p} \in V(e) \cap V(1-e), \] | |
then $e, 1-e \in \mathfrak{p}$, so $1 \in \mathfrak{p}$. This is a | |
contradiction since $\mathfrak{p}$ is necessarily prime. | |
Conversely, suppose that $\mathfrak{p} \in \spec R$ belongs to neither $V(e)$ | |
nor $V(1-e)$. Then $e \notin \mathfrak{p}$ and $1-e \notin \mathfrak{p}$. So | |
the product | |
\[ e(1-e) = e-e^2 = 0 \] | |
cannot lie in $\mathfrak{p}$. But necessarily $0 \in \mathfrak{p}$, | |
contradiction. So $V(e) \cup V(1-e) = \spec R$. This implies the claim. | |
Next, we show that if $V(I)$ is open, then $I$ is the radical of $(e)$ for an | |
idempotent $e$. For this it is sufficient to prove: | |
\begin{lemma} | |
Let $I \subset R$ be such that $V(I) \subset \spec R$ is open. Then $I$ | |
is principal, generated by $(e)$ for some idempotent $e \in R$. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Suppose that $\spec R - V(I) = V(J)$ for some ideal $J \subset R$. Then the | |
intersection $V(I) \cap V(J) = V(I+J)$ is all of $R$, so $I+J$ cannot be a | |
proper ideal (or it would be contained in a prime ideal). In particular, $I+J = | |
R$. So we can write | |
\[ 1 = x + y, \quad x \in I, y \in J. \] | |
Now $V(I) \cup V(J) = V(IJ) = \spec R$. This implies that every element of | |
$IJ$ is nilpotent by the next lemma. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{lemma} | |
Suppose $V(X)=\spec R$ for $X \subset R$ an ideal. Then every element of $X$ is | |
nilpotent. | |
\end{lemma} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Indeed, suppose $x \in X$ were non-nilpotent. Then the ring $R_x$ is not the | |
zero ring, so it has a prime ideal. The map $\spec R_x \to \spec R$ is, as | |
discussed in class, a homeomorphism of $\spec R_x$ onto $D(x)$. So $D(x) | |
\subset \spec R$ (the collection of primes not containing $x$) is nonempty. In | |
particular, there is $\mathfrak{p} \in \spec R$ with $x \notin \mathfrak{p}$, | |
so $\mathfrak{p} \notin V(X)$. So $V(X) \neq \spec R$, contradiction. | |
\end{proof} | |
Return to the proof of the main result. We have shown that $IJ$ is nilpotent. | |
In particular, in the expression $x+y=1$ we had earlier, we have that $xy$ is | |
nilpotent. Say $(xy)^k = 0$. Then expand | |
\[ 1 = (x+y)^{2k} = \sum_{i=0}^{2k} \binom{2k}{i}x^i y^{2k-i} = \sum' + \sum'' \] | |
where $\sum'$ is the sum from $i=0$ to $i=k$ and $\sum''$ is the sum from | |
$k+1$ to $2k$. Then $\sum' \sum'' = 0$ because in every term occurring in the | |
expansion, a multiple of $x^k y^k$ occurs. Also, $\sum' \in I$ and $\sum'' \in | |
J$ because $x \in I, y \in J$. | |
All in all, we find that it is possible to write | |
\[ 1 = x' + y', \quad x' \in I, y' \in J, \ x'y' = 0. \] | |
(We take $x' = \sum', y' = \sum''$.) | |
Then $x'(1-x') = 0$ so $x' \in I$ is idempotent. Similarly $y' = 1-x'$ is. | |
We have that | |
\[ V(I) \subset V(x'), \quad V(J) \subset V(y') \] | |
and $V(x'), V(y')$ are complementary by the earlier arguments, so necessarily | |
\[ V(I) = V(x'), \quad V(J) = V(y'). \] | |
Since an ideal generated by an idempotent is automatically radical, it follows | |
that: | |
\[ I = (x'), \quad, J = (y'). \] | |
\end{proof} | |
There are some useful applications of this in representation theory, because | |
one can look for idempotents in endomorphism rings; these indicate whether a module can be decomposed as a direct sum into smaller parts. Except, of course, that endomorphism rings aren't necessarily commutative and this proof breaks down. | |
Thus we get: | |
\begin{proposition} Let $A$ be a ring and $I$ a nilpotent ideal. Then | |
$\idem(A) \to \idem(A/I)$ is bijective. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
Indeed, the topological spaces of $\mathrm{Spec} \ A$ and $\mathrm{Spec} \ | |
A/I$ are the same. The result then follows from \cref{}. | |
\end{proof} | |
\subsection{Units} | |
Finally, we make a few remarks on \emph{units} modulo nilideals. | |
It is a useful and frequently used trick that adding a nilpotent does not | |
affect the collection of units. This trick is essentially an algebraic version of | |
the | |
familiar ``geometric series;'' convergence questions do not appear thanks to | |
nilpotence. | |
\begin{example} | |
Suppose $u$ is a unit in a ring $R$ and $v \in R$ is nilpotent; we show that $a+v$ is a unit. | |
Suppose $ua=1$ and $v^m=0$ for some | |
$m>1$. Then $(u+v)\cdot a(1-av+(av)^2-\cdots\pm(av)^{m-1})=$ | |
$(1-(-av))(1+(-av)+(-av)^2+\cdots+(-av)^{m-1})=1-(-av)^m=1-0=1$, so $u+v$ | |
is a unit. | |
\end{example} | |
So let $R$ be a ring, $I \subset R$ a nilpotent ideal \emph{of square zero}. | |
Let $R^*$ denote the group of units in $R$, as usual, and let $(R/I)^*$ denote | |
the | |
group of units in $R/I$. | |
We have an exact sequence of abelian groups: | |
\[ 0 \to I \to R^* \to (R/I)^* \to 0 \] | |
where the second map is reduction and the first map sends $i \to 1+i$. | |
The hypothesis that $I^2 = 0$ shows that the first map is a homomorphism. | |
We should check that the last map is surjective. But if any $a \in R$ maps to a | |
unit in $R/I$, it clearly can lie in no prime ideal of $R$, so is a unit itself. | |
\section{Vista: sheaves on $\spec R$} | |
\subsection{Presheaves} | |
Let $X$ be a topological space. | |
\begin{definition} | |
A \textbf{presheaf of sets} $\mathcal{F}$ on $X$ assigns to | |
every open subset | |
$U \subset X$ a set $\mathcal{F} (U)$, and to every inclusion $U | |
\subset V$ a | |
\textbf{restriction map} | |
$\mathrm{res}^V_U : \mathcal{F}(V) \to \mathcal{F}(U)$. The | |
restriction map is | |
required to satisfy: | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item $\res^U_U = \id_{\mathcal{F}(U)} $ for all open sets $U$. | |
\item $\res^W_U = \res^V_U \circ \res^W_V $ if $U \subset V | |
\subset W$. | |
\end{enumerate} | |
If the sets $\mathcal{F}(U)$ are all groups (resp. rings), and | |
the restriction | |
maps are morphisms of groups (resp. rings), then we say that | |
$\mathcal{F}$ is a | |
sheaf of groups (resp. rings). Often the restriction of an | |
element $a\in U$ to a subset $W$ is denoted $a|_W$. | |
A \textbf{morphism} of presheaves $\mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{G}$ is a | |
collection of maps $\mathcal{F}(U) \to \mathcal{G}(U)$ for each open set $U$, | |
that commute with the restriction maps in the obvious way. Thus the collection | |
of presheaves on a topological space forms a category. | |
\end{definition} | |
One should think of the restriction maps as kind of like | |
restricting the | |
domain of a function. | |
The standard example of presheaves is given in this way, in | |
fact. | |
\begin{example} | |
Let $X$ be a topological space, and $\mathcal{F}$ the presheaf | |
assigning to | |
each $U \subset X$ the set of continuous functions $U \to | |
\mathbb{R}$. The | |
restriction maps come from restricting the domain of a function.\end{example} | |
Now, in classical algebraic geometry, there are likely to be | |
more | |
continuous functions in the Zariski topology than one really | |
wants. One wants | |
to focus on functions that are given by polynomial equations. | |
\begin{example} | |
Let $X$ be the topological space $\mathbb{C}^n$ with the | |
topology where the | |
closed sets are those defined by the zero loci of polynomials | |
(that is, the | |
topology induced on $\mathbb{C}^n$ from the Zariski topology of | |
$\spec | |
\mathbb{C}[x_1, \dots, x_n]$ via the canonical imbedding | |
$\mathbb{C}^n | |
\hookrightarrow \spec \mathbb{C}[x_1, \dots, x_n]$). Then there | |
is a presheaf | |
assigning to each open set $U$ the collection of rational | |
functions defined | |
everywhere on $U$, with the restriction maps being the obvious | |
ones. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{remark} | |
The notion of presheaf thus defined relied very little on the topology of $X$. | |
In fact, we could phrase it in purely categorical terms. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be | |
the category consisting of open subsets $U \subset X$ and inclusions of open | |
subsets $U | |
\subset U'$. This is a rather simple category (the hom-sets are either empty | |
or consist of one element). Then a \emph{presheaf} is just a contravariant | |
functor from $\mathcal{C}$ to $\mathbf{Sets}$ (or $\mathbf{Grp}$, etc.). A | |
morphism of presheaves is a natural transformation of functors. | |
In fact, given any category $\mathcal{C}$, we can define the \emph{category of | |
presheaves} on it to be the category of functors $\mathbf{Fun}(\mathcal{C}^{op}, \mathbf{Set})$. | |
This category is complete and cocomplete (we can calculate limits and colimits | |
``pointwise''), and the Yoneda embedding realizes $\mathcal{C}$ as a full | |
subcategory of it. So if $X \in \mathcal{C}$, we get a presheaf $Y \mapsto | |
\hom_{\mathcal{C}}(Y, X)$. In general, however, such representable presheaves | |
are rather special; for instance, what do they look like for the category of | |
open sets in a topological space? | |
\end{remark} | |
\subsection{Sheaves} | |
\begin{definition} Let $\mathcal{F}$ be a presheaf of sets | |
on a topological space $X$. We call $\mathbb{F}$ a | |
\textbf{sheaf} if $\mathcal{F}$ further satisfies the following two | |
``sheaf conditions.'' | |
\begin{enumerate} | |
\item(Separatedness) {If $U$ is an open set of $X$ covered by a family of open subsets $\{U_i\}$ and there | |
are two elements $a,b\in \mathcal{F}(U)$ such that | |
$a|_{U_i}=b|_{U_i}$ for all $U_i$, then $a=b$.} | |
\item(Gluability) {If $U$ is an open set of $X$ covered by $U_i$ and there | |
are elements $a_i\in \mathcal{F}(U_i)$ such that $a_i|_{U_i\cap | |
U_j} = a_j|_{U_i\cap U_j}$ for all $i$ and $j$, then there | |
exists an element $a\in\mathcal{F}(U)$ that restricts to the | |
$a_i$. Notice that by the first axiom, this element is unique.} | |
\end{enumerate} | |
A \emph{morphism} of sheaves is just a morphism of presheaves, so the sheaves | |
on a topological space $X$ form a | |
full subcategory of presheaves on $X$. | |
\end{definition} | |
The above two conditions can be phrased more compactly as follows. Whenever | |
$\left\{U_i\right\}_{i \in I}$ is an open cover of $U \subset X$, we require that the | |
following sequence be an equalizer of sets: | |
\[ \mathcal{F}(U) \to \prod_{i \in I} \mathcal{F}(U_i) \rightrightarrows \prod_{i,j \in I} | |
\mathcal{F}(U_i \cap U_j) \] | |
where the two arrows correspond to the two allowable restriction maps. | |
Similarly, we say that a presheaf of abelian groups (resp. rings) is a | |
\textbf{sheaf} if it is a sheaf of sets. | |
\begin{example} | |
The example of functions gives an example of a sheaf, because functions are | |
determined by their restrictions to an open cover! Namely, if $X$ is a | |
topological space, and we consider the presheaf | |
\[ U \mapsto \left\{\text{continuous functions } U \to \mathbb{R}\right\} , \] | |
then this is clearly a presheaf, because we can piece together continuous | |
functions in a unique manner. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{example} | |
Here is a refinement of the above example. Let $X$ be a smooth manifold. | |
For each $U$, let $\mathcal{F} (U)$ denote the group of smooth functions $U | |
\to \mathbb{R}$. This is easily checked to be a sheaf. | |
We could, of course, replace ``smooth'' by ``$C^r$'' or by ``holomorphic'' in | |
the case of a complex manifold. | |
\end{example} | |
\begin{remark} | |
As remarked above, the notion of presheaf can be defined on any category, and | |
does not really require a topological space. The definition of a sheaf | |
requires a bit more topologically, because the idea that a family | |
$\left\{U_i\right\}$ \emph{covers} an open set $U$ was used inescapably in the | |
definition. The idea of covering required the internal structure of the open | |
sets and was not a purely categorical idea. However, Grothendieck developed a | |
way to axiomatize this, and introduced the idea of a \emph{Grothendieck | |
topology} on a category (which is basically a notion of when a family of maps | |
\emph{covers} something). On a category with a Grothendieck topology (also | |
known as a \emph{site}), one can define the notion of a sheaf in a similar | |
manner as above. See \cite{Vi08}. | |
\end{remark} | |
There is a process that allows one to take any presheaf and | |
associate a sheaf to it. In some sense, this associated sheaf should also be the best ``approximation'' of our presheaf with a sheaf. This motivates the | |
following universal property: | |
\begin{definition} Let $\mathcal{F}$ be a presheaf. Then $\mathcal{F'}$ is said | |
to be the sheafification of $\mathcal{F}$ if for any sheaf $\mathcal{G}$ and a | |
morphism $\mathcal{F}\rightarrow \mathcal{G}$, there is a unique factorization | |
of this morphism as $\mathcal{F}\rightarrow\mathcal{F'}\rightarrow\mathcal{G}$. | |
\end{definition} | |
\begin{theorem} We can construct the sheafification of a presheaf $\mathcal{F}$ | |
as follows: $\mathcal{F}'(U)=\{s:U\rightarrow\coprod_{x\in U}\mathcal{F}_x | | |
\text{for all }x\in U, s(x)\in\mathcal{F}_x \text{ and there is a neighborhood | |
}V\subset U \text{ and }t\in \mathcal{F}(V) \text{ such that for all }y\in V, | |
s(y) \text{ is the image of } t \text{ in the local ring }\mathcal{F}_y\}$. | |
\end{theorem} | |
\add{proof} | |
In the theory of schemes, when one wishes to replace polynomial | |
rings over | |
$\mathbb{C}$ (or an algebraically closed field) with arbitrary | |
commutative | |
rings, one must drop the idea that a sheaf is necessarily given | |
by functions. | |
A \emph{scheme} is defined as a space with a certain type of | |
sheaf of rings on | |
it. We shall not define a scheme formally, but show how on the | |
building blocks | |
of schemes---objects of the form $\spec A$---a sheaf of rings | |
can be defined. | |
\subsection{Sheaves on $\spec A$} | |
\add{we need to describe how giving sections over basic open sets gives a | |
presheaf in general}. | |
\begin{proposition} | |
Let $ A$ be a ring and let $ X = \mathrm{Spec}(A)$. Then the | |
assignment of the ring $A_f$ to the basic open set $X_f$ defines | |
a presheaf of rings on $X$. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} \mbox{} | |
\emph{Part (i)}. If $ X_g \subset X_f$ are basic open sets, | |
then there exist $ n \geq 1$ and $ u \in A$ such that $ g^n = | |
uf$. | |
\emph{Proof of part (i)}. Let $ S = \{g^n : n \geq 0\}$ and | |
suppose $ S \cap (f) = \emptyset$. Then the extension $ (f)^e$ | |
into $ S^{-1}A$ is a proper ideal, so there exists a maximal | |
ideal $ S^{-1}\mathfrak{p}$ of $ S^{-1}A$, where $ \mathfrak{p} | |
\cap S = \emptyset$. Since $ (f)^e \in S^{-1}\mathfrak{p}$, we | |
see that $ f/1 \in S^{-1}\mathfrak{p}$, so $ f \in | |
\mathfrak{p}$. But $ S \cap \mathfrak{p} = \emptyset$ implies | |
that $ g \notin \mathfrak{p}$. This is a contradiction, since | |
then $ \mathfrak{p} \in X_g \setminus X_f$. | |
\emph{Part (ii)}. If $ X_g \subset X_f$, then there exists a | |
unique map $ \rho : A_f \to A_g$, called the restriction map, | |
which makes the following diagram commute. | |
\[ \xymatrix{ & A \ar[dl] \ar[dr] & \\ A_f \ar[rr] & & A_g } \] | |
\emph{Proof of part (ii)}. | |
Let $ n \geq 1$ and $ u \in A$ be such that $ g^n = uf$ by part | |
(i). Note that in $ A_g$, | |
\[ (f/1)(u/g^n) = (fu/g^n) = 1/1 = 1 \] | |
which means that $ f$ maps to a unit in $ A_g$. Hence every $ | |
f^m$ maps to a unit in $ A_g$, so the universal property of $ | |
A_f$ yields the desired unique map $ \rho : A_f \to A_g$. | |
\emph{Part (iii)}. | |
If $ X_g = X_f$, then the corresponding restriction $ \rho : A_f | |
\to A_g$ is an isomorphism. | |
\emph{Proof of part (iii)}. | |
The reverse inclusion yields a $ \rho' : A_g \to A_f$ such that | |
the diagram | |
\[ \xymatrix{ | |
& A \ar[dr] \ar[dl] & \\ | |
A_f \ar@/^/[rr]^{\rho} & & A_g \ar@/^/[ll]^{\rho'} | |
} \] | |
commutes. But since the localization map is epic, this implies | |
that $ \rho \rho' = \rho' \rho = \mathbf{1}$. | |
\emph{Part (iv)}. | |
If $ X_h \subset X_g \subset X_f$, then the diagram | |
\[ \xymatrix{ | |
A_f \ar[rr] \ar[dr] & & A_h \\ | |
& A_g \ar[ur] & | |
} \] | |
of restriction maps commutes. | |
\emph{Proof of part (iv)}. | |
Consider the following tetrahedron. | |
\[ \xymatrix{ | |
& A \ar[dl] \ar[dr] \ar[dd] & \\ | |
A_f \ar@{.>}[rr] \ar[dr] & & A_h \\ | |
& A_g \ar[ur] & | |
} \] | |
Except for the base, the commutativity of each face of the | |
tetrahedron follows from the universal property of part (ii). | |
But its easy to see that commutativity of the those faces | |
implies commutativity of the base, which is what we want to | |
show. | |
\emph{Part (v)}. | |
If $ X_{\tilde{g}} = X_g \subset X_f = X_{\tilde{f}}$, then | |
the diagram | |
\[ \xymatrix{ | |
A_f \ar[r] \ar[d] & A_g \ar[d] \\ | |
A_{\tilde{f}} \ar[r] & A_{\tilde{g}} | |
} \] | |
of restriction maps commutes. (Note that the vertical maps here | |
are isomorphisms.) | |
\emph{Proof of part (v)}. | |
By part (iv), the two triangles of | |
\[ \xymatrix{ | |
A_f \ar[r] \ar[d] \ar[dr] & A_g \ar[d] \\ | |
A_{\tilde{f}} \ar[r] & A_{\tilde{g}} | |
} \] | |
commute. Therefore the square commutes. | |
\emph{Part (vi)}. | |
Fix a prime ideal $ \mathfrak{p}$ in $ A$. Consider the direct | |
system consisting of rings $ A_f$ for every $ f \notin | |
\mathfrak{p}$ and restriction maps $ \rho_{fg} : A_f \to A_g$ | |
whenever $ X_g \subset X_f$. Then $ \varinjlim A_f \cong | |
A_{\mathfrak{p}}$. | |
\emph{proof of part (vi)}. | |
First, note that since $ f \notin \mathfrak{p}$ and $ | |
\mathfrak{p}$ is prime, we know that $ f^m \notin \mathfrak{p}$ | |
for all $ m \geq 0$. Therefore the image of $ f^m$ under the | |
localization $ A \to A_\mathfrak{p}$ is a unit, which means the | |
universal property of $ A_f$ yields a unique map $ \alpha_f : | |
A_f \to A_\mathfrak{p}$ such that the following diagram | |
commutes. | |
\[ \xymatrix{ | |
& A \ar[dr] \ar[dl] & \\ | |
A_f \ar[rr]^{\alpha_f} & & A_{\mathfrak{p}} | |
} \] | |
Then consider the following tetrahedron. | |
\[ \xymatrix{ | |
& A \ar[dl] \ar[dr] \ar[dd] & \\ | |
A_f \ar@{.>}[rr] \ar[dr] & & A_h \\ | |
& A_\mathfrak{p} \ar[ur] & | |
} \] | |
All faces except the bottom commute by construction, so the | |
bottom face commutes as well. This implies that the $ \alpha_f$ | |
commute with the restriction maps, as necessary. Now, to see | |
that $ \varinjlim A_f \cong A_\mathfrak{p}$, we show that $ | |
A_\mathfrak{p}$ satisfies the universal property of $ \varinjlim | |
A_f$. | |
Suppose $ B$ is a ring and there exist maps $ \beta_f : A_f \to | |
B$ which commute with the restrictions. Define $ \beta : A \to | |
B$ as the composition $ A \to A_f \to B$. The fact that $ \beta$ | |
is independent of choice of $ f$ follows from the commutativity | |
of the following diagram. | |
\[ \xymatrix{ | |
& A \ar[dr] \ar[dl] & \\ | |
A_f \ar[rr]^{\rho_{fg}} \ar[dr]^{\beta_f} & & A_g | |
\ar[dl]_{\beta_g} \\ | |
& B | |
} \] | |
Now, for every $ f \notin \mathfrak{p}$, we know that $ | |
\beta(f)$ must be a unit since $ \beta(f) = \beta_f(f/1)$ and $ | |
f/1$ is a unit in $ A_f$. Therefore the universal property of $ | |
A_\mathfrak{p}$ yields a unique map $ A_{\mathfrak{p}} \to B$, | |
which clearly commutes with all the arrows necessary to make $ | |
\varinjlim A_f \cong A_\mathfrak{p}$. | |
\end{proof} | |
\begin{proposition} | |
Let $ A$ be a ring and let $ X = \mathrm{Spec}(A)$. The presheaf | |
of rings $ \mathcal{O}_X$ defined on $ X$ is a sheaf. | |
\end{proposition} | |
\begin{proof} | |
The proof proceeds in two parts. Let $ (U_i)_{i \in I}$ be a | |
covering of $ X$ by basic open sets. | |
\emph{Part 1}. If $ s \in A$ is such that $ s_i := \rho_{X, | |
U_i}(s) = 0$ for all $ i \in I$, then $ s = 0$. | |
\emph{Proof of part 1}. Suppose $ U_i = X_{f_i}$. Note that $ | |
s_i$ is the fraction $ s/1$ in the ring $ A_{f_i}$, so $ s_i = | |
0$ implies that there exists some integer $ m_i$ such that $ | |
sf_i^{m_i} = 0$. Define $ g_i = f_i ^{m_i}$, and note that we | |
still have an open cover by sets $ X_{g_i}$ since $ X_{f_i} = | |
X_{g_i}$ (a prime ideal contains an element if and only if it | |
contains every power of that element). Also $ s g_i = 0$, so the | |
fraction $ s/1$ is still $ 0$ in the ring $ A_{g_i}$. | |
(Essentially, all we're observing here is that we are free to | |
change representation of the basic open sets in our cover to | |
make notation more convenient). | |
Since $ X$ is quasi-compact, choose a finite subcover $ X = | |
X_{g_1} \cup \dotsb \cup X_{g_n}$. This means that $ g_1, | |
\dotsc, g_n$ must generate the unit ideal, so there exists some | |
linear combination $ \sum x_i g_i = 1$ with $ x_i \in A$. But | |
then | |
\[ s = s \cdot 1 = s \left( \sum x_i g_i \right) = \sum x_i (s | |
g_i) = 0.\] | |
\emph{Part 2}. Let $ s_i \in \mathcal{O}_X(U_i)$ be such that | |
for every $ i, j \in I$, | |
\[ \rho_{U_i, U_i \cap U_j}(s_i) = \rho_{U_j, U_i \cap | |
U_j}(s_j).\] | |
(That is, the collection $ (s_i)_{i \in I}$ agrees on overlaps). | |
Then there exists a unique $ s \in A$ such that $ \rho_{X, | |
U_i}(s) = s_i$ for every $ i \in I$. | |
\emph{Proof of part 2}. Let $ U_i = X_{f_i}$, so that $ s_i = | |
a_i/(f_i^{m_i})$ for some integers $ m_i$. As in part 1, we can | |
clean up notation by defining $ g_i = f_i^{m_i}$, so that $ s_i | |
= a_i/g_i$. Choose a finite subcover $ X = X_{g_1} \cup \dotsb | |
\cup X_{g_n}$. Then the condition that the cover agrees on | |
overlaps means that | |
\[ \frac{a_i g_j}{g_i g_j} = \frac{a_j g_i}{g_i g_j} \] | |
for all $ i, j$ in the finite subcover. This is equivalent to | |
the existence of some $ k_{ij}$ such that | |
\[ (a_i g_j - a_j g_i) (g_i g_j)^{k_{ij}} = 0.\] | |
Let $ k$ be the maximum of all the $ k_{ij}$, so that $ (a_i g_j | |
- a_j g_i)(g_i g_j)^k = 0$ for all $ i, j$ in the finite | |
subcover. Define $ b_i = a_i g_i^k$ and $ h_i = g_i^{k+1}$. We | |
make the following observations: | |
\[ b_i h_j - b_j h_i = 0, X_{g_i} = X_{h_i}, \text{ and } s_i = | |
a_i/g_i = b_i/h_i \] | |
The first observation implies that the $ X_{h_i}$ cover $ X$, so | |
the $ h_i$ generate the unit ideal. Then there exists some | |
linear combination $ \sum x_i h_i = 1$. Define $ s = \sum x_i | |
b_i$. I claim that this is the global section that restricts to | |
$ s_i$ on the open cover. | |
The first step is to show that it restricts to $ s_i$ on our | |
chosen finite subcover. In other words, we want to show that $ | |
s/1 = s_i = b_i/h_i$ in $ A_{h_i}$, which is equivalent to the | |
condition that there exist some $ l_i$ such that $ (sh_i b_i) | |
h_i^{l_i} = 0$. But in fact, even $ l_i = 0$ works: | |
\[ sh_i - b_i = \left(\sum x_j b_j\right) h_i - b_i\left(\sum | |
x_j h_j\right) = \sum x_j\left(h_i b_j - b_i h_j\right) = 0. \] | |
This shows that $ s$ restricts to $ s_i$ on each set in our | |
finite subcover. Now we need to show that in fact, it restricts | |
to $ s_i$ for all of the sets in our cover. Choose any $ j \in | |
I$. Then $ U_1, \dotsc, U_n, U_j$ still cover $ X$, so the above | |
process yields an $ s'$ such that $ s'$ restricts to $ s_i$ for | |
all $ i \in \{1, \dotsc, n, j\}$. But then $ s - s'$ satisfies | |
the assumptions of part 1 using the cover $ \{U_1, \dotsc, U_n, | |
U_j\}$, so this means $ s = s'$. Hence the restriction of $ s$ | |
to $ U_j$ is also $ s_j$. | |
\end{proof} | |