File size: 116,931 Bytes
8cf8144
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
1001
1002
1003
1004
1005
1006
1007
1008
1009
1010
1011
1012
1013
1014
1015
1016
1017
1018
1019
1020
1021
1022
1023
1024
1025
1026
1027
1028
1029
1030
1031
1032
1033
1034
1035
1036
1037
1038
1039
1040
1041
1042
1043
1044
1045
1046
1047
1048
1049
1050
1051
1052
1053
1054
1055
1056
1057
1058
1059
1060
1061
1062
1063
1064
1065
1066
1067
1068
1069
1070
1071
1072
1073
1074
1075
1076
1077
1078
1079
1080
1081
1082
1083
1084
1085
1086
1087
1088
1089
1090
1091
1092
1093
1094
1095
1096
1097
1098
1099
1100
1101
1102
1103
1104
1105
1106
1107
1108
1109
1110
1111
1112
1113
1114
1115
1116
1117
1118
1119
1120
1121
1122
1123
1124
1125
1126
1127
1128
1129
1130
1131
1132
1133
1134
1135
1136
1137
1138
1139
1140
1141
1142
1143
1144
1145
1146
1147
1148
1149
1150
1151
1152
1153
1154
1155
1156
1157
1158
1159
1160
1161
1162
1163
1164
1165
1166
1167
1168
1169
1170
1171
1172
1173
1174
1175
1176
1177
1178
1179
1180
1181
1182
1183
1184
1185
1186
1187
1188
1189
1190
1191
1192
1193
1194
1195
1196
1197
1198
1199
1200
1201
1202
1203
1204
1205
1206
1207
1208
1209
1210
1211
1212
1213
1214
1215
1216
1217
1218
1219
1220
1221
1222
1223
1224
1225
1226
1227
1228
1229
1230
1231
1232
1233
1234
1235
1236
1237
1238
1239
1240
1241
1242
1243
1244
1245
1246
1247
1248
1249
1250
1251
1252
1253
1254
1255
1256
1257
1258
1259
1260
1261
1262
1263
1264
1265
1266
1267
1268
1269
1270
1271
1272
1273
1274
1275
1276
1277
1278
1279
1280
1281
1282
1283
1284
1285
1286
1287
1288
1289
1290
1291
1292
1293
1294
1295
1296
1297
1298
1299
1300
1301
1302
1303
1304
1305
1306
1307
1308
1309
1310
1311
1312
1313
1314
1315
1316
1317
1318
1319
1320
1321
1322
1323
1324
1325
1326
1327
1328
1329
1330
1331
1332
1333
1334
1335
1336
1337
1338
1339
1340
1341
1342
1343
1344
1345
1346
1347
1348
1349
1350
1351
1352
1353
1354
1355
1356
1357
1358
1359
1360
1361
1362
1363
1364
1365
1366
1367
1368
1369
1370
1371
1372
1373
1374
1375
1376
1377
1378
1379
1380
1381
1382
1383
1384
1385
1386
1387
1388
1389
1390
1391
1392
1393
1394
1395
1396
1397
1398
1399
1400
1401
1402
1403
1404
1405
1406
1407
1408
1409
1410
1411
1412
1413
1414
1415
1416
1417
1418
1419
1420
1421
1422
1423
1424
1425
1426
1427
1428
1429
1430
1431
1432
1433
1434
1435
1436
1437
1438
1439
1440
1441
1442
1443
1444
1445
1446
1447
1448
1449
1450
1451
1452
1453
1454
1455
1456
1457
1458
1459
1460
1461
1462
1463
1464
1465
1466
1467
1468
1469
1470
1471
1472
1473
1474
1475
1476
1477
1478
1479
1480
1481
1482
1483
1484
1485
1486
1487
1488
1489
1490
1491
1492
1493
1494
1495
1496
1497
1498
1499
1500
1501
1502
1503
1504
1505
1506
1507
1508
1509
1510
1511
1512
1513
1514
1515
1516
1517
1518
1519
1520
1521
1522
1523
1524
1525
1526
1527
1528
1529
1530
1531
1532
1533
1534
1535
1536
1537
1538
1539
1540
1541
1542
1543
1544
1545
1546
1547
1548
1549
1550
1551
1552
1553
1554
1555
1556
1557
1558
1559
1560
1561
1562
1563
1564
1565
1566
1567
1568
1569
1570
1571
1572
1573
1574
1575
1576
1577
1578
1579
1580
1581
1582
1583
1584
1585
1586
1587
1588
1589
1590
1591
1592
1593
1594
1595
1596
1597
1598
1599
1600
1601
1602
1603
1604
1605
1606
1607
1608
1609
1610
1611
1612
1613
1614
1615
1616
1617
1618
1619
1620
1621
1622
1623
1624
1625
1626
1627
1628
1629
1630
1631
1632
1633
1634
1635
1636
1637
1638
1639
1640
1641
1642
1643
1644
1645
1646
1647
1648
1649
1650
1651
1652
1653
1654
1655
1656
1657
1658
1659
1660
1661
1662
1663
1664
1665
1666
1667
1668
1669
1670
1671
1672
1673
1674
1675
1676
1677
1678
1679
1680
1681
1682
1683
1684
1685
1686
1687
1688
1689
1690
1691
1692
1693
1694
1695
1696
1697
1698
1699
1700
1701
1702
1703
1704
1705
1706
1707
1708
1709
1710
1711
1712
1713
1714
1715
1716
1717
1718
1719
1720
1721
1722
1723
1724
1725
1726
1727
1728
1729
1730
1731
1732
1733
1734
1735
1736
1737
1738
1739
1740
1741
1742
1743
1744
1745
1746
1747
1748
1749
1750
1751
1752
1753
1754
1755
1756
1757
1758
1759
1760
1761
1762
1763
1764
1765
1766
1767
1768
1769
1770
1771
1772
1773
1774
1775
1776
1777
1778
1779
1780
1781
1782
1783
1784
1785
1786
1787
1788
1789
1790
1791
1792
1793
1794
1795
1796
1797
1798
1799
1800
1801
1802
1803
1804
1805
1806
1807
1808
1809
1810
1811
1812
1813
1814
1815
1816
1817
1818
1819
1820
1821
1822
1823
1824
1825
1826
1827
1828
1829
1830
1831
1832
1833
1834
1835
1836
1837
1838
1839
1840
1841
1842
1843
1844
1845
1846
1847
1848
1849
1850
1851
1852
1853
1854
1855
1856
1857
1858
1859
1860
1861
1862
1863
1864
1865
1866
1867
1868
1869
1870
1871
1872
1873
1874
1875
1876
1877
1878
1879
1880
1881
1882
1883
1884
1885
1886
1887
1888
1889
1890
1891
1892
1893
1894
1895
1896
1897
1898
1899
1900
1901
1902
1903
1904
1905
1906
1907
1908
1909
1910
1911
1912
1913
1914
1915
1916
1917
1918
1919
1920
1921
1922
1923
1924
1925
1926
1927
1928
1929
1930
1931
1932
1933
1934
1935
1936
1937
1938
1939
1940
1941
1942
1943
1944
1945
1946
1947
1948
1949
1950
1951
1952
1953
1954
1955
1956
1957
1958
1959
1960
1961
1962
1963
1964
1965
1966
1967
1968
1969
1970
1971
1972
1973
1974
1975
1976
1977
1978
1979
1980
1981
1982
1983
1984
1985
1986
1987
1988
1989
1990
1991
1992
1993
1994
1995
1996
1997
1998
1999
2000
2001
2002
2003
2004
2005
2006
2007
2008
2009
2010
2011
2012
2013
2014
2015
2016
2017
2018
2019
2020
2021
2022
2023
2024
2025
2026
2027
2028
2029
2030
2031
2032
2033
2034
2035
2036
2037
2038
2039
2040
2041
2042
2043
2044
2045
2046
2047
2048
2049
2050
2051
2052
2053
2054
2055
2056
2057
2058
2059
2060
2061
2062
2063
2064
2065
2066
2067
2068
2069
2070
2071
2072
2073
2074
2075
2076
2077
2078
2079
2080
2081
2082
2083
2084
2085
\documentclass[10pt,twocolumn,conference]{IEEEtran}


\usepackage{graphicx}
\usepackage{listings,color}
\usepackage{listings}
\renewcommand{\ttdefault}{lmtt}
\ttfamily
\DeclareFontShape{OT1}{lmtt}{m}{it}
     {<->sub*lmtt/m/sl}{}
\lstdefinestyle{default}{language=Anglican, basicstyle=\ttfamily, columns=flexible, showstringspaces=false}

\usepackage{listings}
\usepackage{color}
\usepackage{xcolor}
\definecolor{blue}{rgb}{0,0.3,0.7}
\definecolor{red}{rgb}{0.60,0.0,0.0}
\definecolor{purple}{rgb}{0.5,0,0.7}
\definecolor{cyan}{rgb}{0.0,0.6,0.5}
\definecolor{gray}{rgb}{0.4,0.4,0.4}

\lstdefinelanguage{scheme}
{sensitive, alsoletter={:,-,+,*,?,/,!,>,<}, morecomment=[l];, }[comments]

\lstdefinelanguage{anglican}{morekeywords=[1]{},
morekeywords=[2]{def, def-, defn, defn-, defmacro, defmulti, defmethod, defstruct, defonce, declare, definline, definterface, defprotocol, defrecord, defstruct, deftype, defproject, ns, }, morekeywords=[3]{->, ->>, .., amap, and, areduce, as->, assert, binding, bound-fn, case, comment, cond, cond->, cond->>, condp, declare, definline, definterface, defmacro, defmethod, defmulti, defn, defn-, defonce, defprotocol, defrecord, defstruct, deftype, delay, doseq, dosync, dotimes, doto, extend-protocol, extend-type, fn, for, future, gen-class, gen-interface, if, if-let, if-not, if-some, import, io!, lazy-cat, lazy-seq, let, letfn, locking, loop, memfn, ns, or, proxy, proxy-super, pvalues, recur, refer-clojure, reify, some->, some->>, sync, time, when, when-first, when-let, when-not, when-some, while, with-bindings, with-in-str, with-loading-context, with-local-vars, with-open, with-out-str, with-precision, with-redefs}, morekeywords=[4]{*, *', +, +', -, -', ->ArrayChunk, ->Vec, ->VecNode, ->VecSeq, -cache-protocol-fn, -reset-methods, /, <, <=, =, ==, >, >=, accessor, aclone, add-classpath, add-watch, agent, agent-error, agent-errors, aget, alength, alias, all-ns, alter, alter-meta!, alter-var-root, ancestors, apply, array-map, aset, aset-boolean, aset-byte, aset-char, aset-double, aset-float, aset-int, aset-long, aset-short, assoc, assoc!, assoc-in, associative?, atom, await, await-for, await1, bases, bean, bigdec, bigint, biginteger, bit-and, bit-and-not, bit-clear, bit-flip, bit-not, bit-or, bit-set, bit-shift-left, bit-shift-right, bit-test, bit-xor, boolean, boolean-array, booleans, bound-fn*, bound?, butlast, byte, byte-array, bytes, cast, char, char-array, char?, chars, chunk, chunk-append, chunk-buffer, chunk-cons, chunk-first, chunk-next, chunk-rest, chunked-seq?, class, class?, clear-agent-errors, clojure-version, coll?, commute, comp, comparator, compare, compare-and-set!, compile, complement, concat, conj, conj!, cons, constantly, construct-proxy, contains?, count, counted?, create-ns, create-struct, cycle, dec, dec', decimal?, delay?, deliver, denominator, deref, derive, descendants, destructure, disj, disj!, dissoc, dissoc!, distinct, distinct?, doall, dorun, double, double-array, doubles, drop, drop-last, drop-while, empty, empty?, ensure, enumeration-seq, error-handler, error-mode, eval, even?, every-pred, every?, ex-data, ex-info, extend, extenders, extends?, false?, ffirst, file-seq, filter, filter-ns-publics, filterv, find, find-keyword, find-ns, find-protocol-impl, find-protocol-method, find-var, first, flatten, float, float-array, float?, floats, flush, fn?, fnext, fnil, force, format, frequencies, future-call, future-cancel, future-cancelled?, future-done?, future?, gensym, get, get-in, get-method, get-proxy-class, get-thread-bindings, get-validator, group-by, hash, hash-combine, hash-map, hash-ordered-coll, hash-set, hash-unordered-coll, identical?, identity, ifn?, in-ns, inc, inc', init-proxy, instance?, int, int-array, integer?, interleave, intern, interpose, into, into-array, ints, isa?, iterate, iterator-seq, juxt, keep, keep-indexed, key, keys, keyword, keyword?, last, line-seq, list, list*, list?, load, load-file, load-reader, load-string, loaded-libs, long, long-array, longs, macroexpand, macroexpand-1, make-array, make-hierarchy, map, map-indexed, map?, mapcat, mapv, max, max-key, memoize, merge, merge-with, meta, method-sig, methods, min, min-key, mix-collection-hash, mod, munge, name, namespace, namespace-munge, neg?, newline, next, nfirst, nil?, nnext, not, not-any?, not-empty, not-every?, not=, ns-aliases, ns-functions, ns-imports, ns-interns, ns-macros, ns-map, ns-name, ns-publics, ns-refers, ns-resolve, ns-unalias, ns-unmap, nth, nthnext, nthrest, num, number?, numerator, object-array, odd?, parents, partial, partition, partition-all, partition-by, pcalls, peek, persistent!, pmap, pop, pop!, pop-thread-bindings, pos?, pr, pr-str, prefer-method, prefers, print, print-ctor, print-simple, print-str, printf, println, println-str, prn, prn-str, promise, proxy-call-with-super, proxy-mappings, proxy-name, push-thread-bindings, quot, rand, rand-int, rand-nth, range, ratio?, rational?, rationalize, re-find, re-groups, re-matcher, re-matches, re-pattern, re-seq, read, read-line, read-string, realized?, record?, reduce, reduce-kv, reduced, reduced?, reductions, ref, ref-history-count, ref-max-history, ref-min-history, ref-set, refer, release-pending-sends, rem, remove, remove-all-methods, remove-method, remove-ns, remove-watch, repeat, repeatedly, replace, replicate, require, reset!, reset-meta!, resolve, rest, restart-agent, resultset-seq, reverse, reversible?, rseq, rsubseq, satisfies?, second, select-keys, send, send-off, send-via, seq, seq?, seque, sequence, sequential?, set, set-agent-send-executor!, set-agent-send-off-executor!, set-error-handler!, set-error-mode!, set-validator!, set?, short, short-array, shorts, shuffle, shutdown-agents, slurp, some, some-fn, some?, sort, sort-by, sorted-map, sorted-map-by, sorted-set, sorted-set-by, sorted?, special-symbol?, spit, split-at, split-with, str, string?, struct, struct-map, subs, subseq, subvec, supers, swap!, symbol, symbol?, take, take-last, take-nth, take-while, test, the-ns, thread-bound?, to-array, to-array-2d, trampoline, transient, tree-seq, true?, type, unchecked-add, unchecked-add-int, unchecked-byte, unchecked-char, unchecked-dec, unchecked-dec-int, unchecked-divide-int, unchecked-double, unchecked-float, unchecked-inc, unchecked-inc-int, unchecked-int, unchecked-long, unchecked-multiply, unchecked-multiply-int, unchecked-negate, unchecked-negate-int, unchecked-remainder-int, unchecked-short, unchecked-subtract, unchecked-subtract-int, underive, unsigned-bit-shift-right, update-in, update-proxy, use, val, vals, var-get, var-set, var?, vary-meta, vec, vector, vector-of, vector?, with-bindings*, with-meta, with-redefs-fn, xml-seq, zero?, zipmap}, morekeywords=[5]{def-cps-fn, defanglican, defm, defquery, defun, defproc, defdist}, morekeywords=[6]{cps-fn, fm, lambda, mem, query, with-primitive-procedures}, morekeywords=[7]{doquery, conditional, collect-by, equalize, exec, infer, log-marginal, print-predicts, rand, rand-int, rand-nth, rand-roulette, stripdown, warmup, ->CRP-process, ->DP-process, ->GP-process, ->bernoulli-distribution, ->beta-distribution, ->binomial-distribution, ->categorical-crp-distribution, ->categorical-distribution, ->categorical-dp-distribution, ->chi-squared-distribution, ->dirichlet-distribution, ->discrete-distribution, ->exponential-distribution, ->flip-distribution, ->gamma-distribution, ->mvn-distribution, ->normal-distribution, ->poisson-distribution, ->sample, ->observe, sample*, observe*, ->uniform-continuous-distribution, ->uniform-discrete-distribution, ->wishart-distribution, CRP, DP, GP, abs, absorb, acos, asin, atan, bernoulli, beta, binomial, categorical, categorical-crp, categorical-dp, cbrt, ceil, chi-squared, cos, cosh, cov, dirichlet, discrete, exp, exponential, flip, floor, gamma, gen-matrix, log, log-gamma-fn, log-mv-gamma-fn, log-sum-exp, map->CRP-process, map->DP-process, map->GP-process, map->bernoulli-distribution, map->beta-distribution, map->binomial-distribution, map->categorical-crp-distribution, map->categorical-distribution, map->categorical-dp-distribution, map->chi-squared-distribution, map->dirichlet-distribution, map->discrete-distribution, map->exponential-distribution, map->flip-distribution, map->gamma-distribution, map->mvn-distribution, map->normal-distribution, map->poisson-distribution, map->uniform-continuous-distribution, map->uniform-discrete-distribution, map->wishart-distribution, mvn, normal, poisson, pow, produce, rint, round, signum, sin, sinh, sqrt, tag, tan, tanh, transform-sample, uniform-continuous, uniform-discrete, wishart, add-log-weight, add-predict, clear-predicts, get-log-weight, get-mem, get-predicts, in-mem?, set-log-weight, set-mem, }, morekeywords=[8]{factor, observe, predict, retrieve, sample, store}, sensitive, alsoletter={:,-,+,*,?,/,!,>,<}, morecomment=[l];, morestring=[b]", keywordsprefix=:, }[keywords,comments,strings]
 
\lstset{
  language=anglican,
  basicstyle=\ttfamily,
  commentstyle=\em\color{gray},
keywordstyle=[1]\color{red},
  stringstyle=\color{gray},
keywordstyle=[2]\color{purple}\bfseries,
keywordstyle=[3]\color{red}\bfseries,
keywordstyle=[4]\color{cyan}\bfseries,
keywordstyle=[5]\color{purple}\bfseries,
keywordstyle=[6]\color{red}\bfseries,
keywordstyle=[7]\color{cyan}\bfseries,
keywordstyle=[8]\color{blue}\bfseries
}
 
\newcommand{\commentout}[1]{}
\newcommand{\shortversion}[1]{#1}
\newcommand{\longversion}[1]{}
\newcommand{\todo}{\textbf{To do: }}
\newcommand{\hy}[1]{
\smallskip\noindent\fbox{\begin{minipage}{.97\linewidth}{\bf HY:}
{\rm #1}\end{minipage}}}
\newcommand{\sss}[1]{
\smallskip\noindent\fbox{\begin{minipage}{.97\linewidth}{\bf SS:}
{\rm #1}\end{minipage}}}
\newcommand{\ok}[1]{
\smallskip\noindent\fbox{\begin{minipage}{.97\linewidth}{\bf OK:}
{\rm #1}\end{minipage}}}
\newcommand{\ch}[1]{
\smallskip\noindent\fbox{\begin{minipage}{.97\linewidth}{\bf CH:}
{\rm #1}\end{minipage}}}

\renewcommand{\hy}[1]{}
\renewcommand{\sss}[1]{}
\renewcommand{\ok}[1]{}
\renewcommand{\ch}[1]{}

\newcommand{\XI}{X^\omega}
\newcommand{\Xn}{X^n}
\newcommand{\RR}{\mathbb{R}}
\newcommand{\NN}{\mathbb{N}}
\newcommand{\sigalg}[1]{\Sigma_{#1}}
\newcommand{\qbtosig}[1]{\Sigma_{#1}}
\newcommand{\qb}[1]{M_{#1}}
\newcommand{\sigtoqb}[1]{M_{#1}}
\newcommand{\inv}[1]{{#1}^{\textup{-1}}}
\newcommand{\id}[1]{\mathrm{id}_{#1}}
\newcommand{\iid}{\mathrm{iid}}
\newcommand{\iidn}{\mathrm{iid}_n}
\newcommand{\iotan}{\iota_n}
\newcommand{\inviotan}{\inv{\iota}_n}
\newcommand{\op}[1]{{#1}^{\mathrm{op}}}
\newcommand{\defeq}{\stackrel {\textup{def}}=}
\newcommand{\QBS}{\mathbf{QBS}}
\newcommand{\Meas}{\mathbf{Meas}}
\newcommand{\Set}{\mathbf{Set}}
\newcommand{\SMeas}{\mathbf{SMeas}}
\newcommand{\dd}{\mathrm{d}}
\newcommand{\denot}[1]{\llbracket#1\rrbracket}
\newcommand{\Pmonad}{P}
\newcommand{\Giry}{G}
\newcommand{\curry}{\mathsf{curry}}
\newcommand{\uncurry}{\mathsf{uncurry}}
\newcommand{\bindsymbol}{\scalebox{0.5}[1]{$>\!>=$}}
\newcommand{\bind}[2]{#1\mathrel{\bindsymbol} #2}
\newcommand{\bindname}{(\bindsymbol)}
\newcommand{\bindGsymbol}{\scalebox{0.5}[1]{$>\!>=$}_G}
\newcommand{\bindG}[2]{#1\mathrel{\bindGsymbol} #2}
\newcommand{\bindGname}{(\bindGsymbol)}
\newcommand{\munit}{\eta}









\ifCLASSINFOpdf
\else
\fi






\usepackage{amssymb,amsthm,amsmath,amsfonts,mathtools,stmaryrd}
\usepackage{xy}
\xyoption{all}
\newtheorem{definition}{Definition}
\newtheorem{proposition}[definition]{Proposition}
\newtheorem{theorem}[definition]{Theorem}
\newtheorem{lemma}[definition]{Lemma}
\newtheorem{example}[definition]{Example}








































\hyphenation{op-tical net-works semi-conduc-tor}


\begin{document}
\title{A Convenient Category for \\ Higher-Order Probability Theory}

\author{
\IEEEauthorblockN{Chris Heunen}
\IEEEauthorblockA{University of Edinburgh, UK}
\and
\IEEEauthorblockN{Ohad Kammar}
\IEEEauthorblockA{University of Oxford, UK}
\and
\IEEEauthorblockN{Sam Staton}
\IEEEauthorblockA{University of Oxford, UK}
\and
\IEEEauthorblockN{Hongseok Yang}
\IEEEauthorblockA{University of Oxford, UK}
}





\IEEEoverridecommandlockouts
\IEEEpubid{\makebox[\columnwidth]{978-1-5090-3018-7/17/\$31.00~
\copyright2017 IEEE \hfill} \hspace{\columnsep}\makebox[\columnwidth]{ }} 





\maketitle


























\begin{abstract}
Higher-order probabilistic programming languages allow programmers to write sophisticated models in machine learning and statistics in a succinct and structured way, 
but step outside the standard measure-theoretic formalization of probability theory.
Programs may use both higher-order functions and continuous distributions, or even define a probability distribution on functions.
But standard probability theory does not handle higher-order functions well: the category of measurable spaces is not cartesian closed.

Here we introduce quasi-Borel spaces. 
We show that these spaces:
form a new formalization of probability theory replacing measurable spaces;
form a cartesian closed category and so support higher-order functions;
form a well-pointed category and so support good proof principles for equational reasoning;
and support continuous probability distributions.
We demonstrate the use of quasi-Borel spaces for higher-order functions and probability by: showing that a well-known construction of probability theory involving random functions gains a cleaner expression; and generalizing de Finetti's theorem, that is a crucial theorem in probability theory, to quasi-Borel spaces.








 \end{abstract}

\IEEEpeerreviewmaketitle
\allowdisplaybreaks


\section{Introduction}\label{sec:intro}
To express probabilistic models in machine learning and statistics in a succinct and structured way, it pays to use \emph{higher-order} programming languages, such as Church~\cite{goodman_uai_2008}, Venture~\cite{Mansinghka-venture14}, or Anglican~\cite{wood-aistats-2014}. These languages support advanced features from both
programming language theory and probability theory, while
providing generic inference algorithms for answering probabilistic queries, such as marginalization and posterior computation, for all models written in the language. As a result, the programmer can succinctly express a sophisticated probabilistic model and explore its properties while avoiding the nontrivial busywork of designing a custom inference algorithm.


This exciting development comes at a foundational price.
Programs in these languages may combine higher-order functions and continuous
distributions, or even define a probability distribution on functions.
But the standard measure-theoretic formalization of probability theory does not handle higher-order functions well, as the category of measurable spaces is not cartesian closed~\cite{aumann:functionspaces}. 
For instance, the Anglican implementation of Bayesian linear regression in Figure~\ref{fig:linearregression} goes beyond the standard measure-theoretic foundation of probability theory, as it defines a probability distribution on functions $\RR \to \RR$. 

\makeatletter
\lst@Key{countblanklines}{true}[t]{\lstKV@SetIf{#1}\lst@ifcountblanklines}

\lst@AddToHook{OnEmptyLine}{\lst@ifnumberblanklines\else \lst@ifcountblanklines\else \advance\c@lstnumber-\@ne\relax \fi \fi}
\makeatother
\lstset{frame=single, xleftmargin=8.25mm, framexleftmargin=7mm, numbers=left, numberblanklines=false, linewidth=.48\textwidth
}
\begin{figure}
\begin{lstlisting}[style=default,countblanklines=false, basicstyle=\ttfamily\small,escapechar=\|]
(defquery Bayesian-linear-regression |\vskip-.6\baselineskip|

  (let [f (let [s (sample (normal 0.0 3.0))
                  b (sample (normal 0.0 3.0))]
              (fn [x] (+ (* s x) b)))] |\vskip-.6\baselineskip|

    (observe (normal (f 1.0) 0.5) 2.5)        
    (observe (normal (f 2.0) 0.5) 3.8)
    (observe (normal (f 3.0) 0.5) 4.5)
    (observe (normal (f 4.0) 0.5) 6.2)
    (observe (normal (f 5.0) 0.5) 8.0)  |\vskip-.6\baselineskip|

    (predict :f f)))
\end{lstlisting}
\fbox{\includegraphics[width=.97\linewidth]{posterior.png}}
\caption{Bayesian linear regression in Anglican. The program defines a probability
distribution on functions $\RR \to \RR$. It first samples
a random linear function \texttt{f} by randomly selecting
slope \texttt{s} and intercept \texttt{b}. It then adjusts the probability distribution of the function
to better describe five observations $(1.0,2.5)$, $(2.0,3.8)$, $(3.0,4.5)$, $(4.0,6.2)$
and $(5.0,8.0)$ by posterior computation.
In the graph, each line has been sampled from the posterior distribution over linear functions.}
\label{fig:linearregression}
\end{figure}

We introduce a new formalization of probability theory that accommodates higher-order functions. The main notion replacing a measurable space is a \emph{quasi-Borel space}: a set~$X$ equipped with a collection of functions $\qb X \subseteq {[\RR \to X]}$ satisfying
certain conditions (Def.~\ref{def:qbs}). Intuitively, $\qb X$ is the set of random variables of type $X$.
Here $\RR$ means that the randomness of random variables in $\qb X$
comes from (a probability distribution on) $\RR$, one of the best behaving measurable spaces. 
Thus the primitive notion shifts from measurable subset to random variable, which is traditionally a derived notion.
For related ideas see \S\ref{sec:related}.

Quasi-Borel spaces have good properties and structure.
\begin{itemize}
\item The category of quasi-Borel spaces is \emph{well-pointed}, since a morphism is just a structure-preserving function (\S\ref{sec:quasiborel}). (This is in contrast to~\cite[\S8]{statonyangheunenkammarwood:higherorder}).

\item The category of quasi-Borel spaces is cartesian closed (\S\ref{sec:structure}), so that it becomes a setting to study probability distributions on \emph{higher-order} functions. 

\item There is a natural notion of probability measure on quasi-Borel spaces (Def.~\ref{def:probabilitymeasure}).
The space of all probability measures is again a 
quasi-Borel space, and forms the basis for a commutative \emph{monad} on the category of quasi-Borel spaces (\S\ref{sec:giry}). Thus quasi-Borel spaces form semantics for a probabilistic programming language in the monadic style~\cite{moggi-monads}.
\end{itemize}
We also illustrate the use of quasi-Borel spaces.
\begin{itemize}
\item \emph{Bayesian regression} (\S\ref{sec:example}). 
  Quasi-Borel spaces are a natural setting for understanding programs such as the one in Figure~\ref{fig:linearregression}:
  the prior (Lines 2--4) defines a probability distribution over functions~\lstinline|f|, i.e.\ a measure on $\RR^\RR$, and the posterior (illustrated in the graph), is again a probability measure on $\RR^\RR$, conditioned by the observations (Lines 5--9). 
\item \emph{Randomization} (\S\ref{sec:functions}). 
A key idea of categorical logic is that $\forall\exists$ statements should become statements
about quotients of objects. 
The structure of quasi-Borel spaces allows us to rephrase a crucial randomization lemma in this way. 
Classically, it says that every probability kernel arises from a random function. 
In the setting of quasi-Borel spaces, it says that
the space of probability kernels $P(\RR)^X$ is a quotient of the space of random functions, $P(\RR^X)$ (Theorem~\ref{theorem:random-quotient}).
Notice that the higher-order structure of quasi-Borel spaces allows us to succinctly state this result.
\item \emph{De Finetti's theorem} (\S\ref{sec:definetti}). 
Probability theorists often encounter problems when working with arbitrary probability measures on arbitrary measurable spaces.
Quasi-Borel spaces allow us to better manage the source of randomness. 
For example, de Finetti's theorem is a foundational result in Bayesian statistics which says that every exchangeable random sequence can be generated
by randomly mixing multiple independent and identically distributed sequences.
The theorem is known to hold for standard Borel spaces~\cite{deFinetti37} 
or measurable spaces that arise from good topologies~\cite{HewittSavage55}, but not for arbitrary measurable spaces~\cite{Dubins1979}. We show that it holds for all quasi-Borel spaces (Theorem~\ref{thm:deFinetti-qbs}). 
\end{itemize}
All of this is evidence that quasi-Borel spaces form a convenient category for higher-order probability theory.




 
\section{Preliminaries on probability measures and measurable spaces}\label{sec:prelims}
\begin{definition}\label{def:borel}
The \emph{Borel sets} form the least collection $\Sigma_\RR$ of subsets of $\RR$ that
  satisfies the following properties:
  \begin{itemize}
   \item intervals $(a,b)$ are Borel sets;
   \item complements of Borel sets are Borel;
   \item countable unions of Borel sets are Borel.
  \end{itemize}
\end{definition}

The Borel sets play a crucial role in probability theory because of the tight connection
between the notion of probability measure and the axiomatization of Borel sets. 

\begin{definition}\label{def:borelprob}
  A \emph{probability measure} on $\RR$ is a function $\mu\colon \sigalg\RR\to [0,1]$ satisfying $\mu(\RR)=1$ and $\mu(\biguplus S_i)=\sum \mu(S_i)$ for any countable sequence of disjoint Borel sets $S_i$.
\end{definition}

The natural generalization gives measurable spaces.

\begin{definition}\label{def:meas-space}
  A \emph{$\sigma$-algebra} on a set $X$ is a nonempty family of subsets of $X$ that is closed under complements and countable unions. A \emph{measurable space} is a pair $(X,\sigalg X)$ of a set $X$ and a $\sigma$-algebra $\sigalg X$ on it. A probability measure on a measurable space $X$ is a function $\mu\colon \sigalg X\to [0,1]$ satisfying $\mu(X)=1$ and $\mu(\biguplus S_i)=\sum \mu(S_i)$ for any countable sequence of disjoint sets $S_i\in\sigalg X$.
\end{definition}

The Borel sets of the reals form a leading example of a $\sigma$-algebra.
Other important examples are countable sets with their \emph{discrete $\sigma$-algebra}, which contains all subsets.
We can characterize these spaces as standard Borel spaces, but first introduce the appropriate structure-preserving maps.

\begin{definition}\label{def:measurablefunction}
  Let $(X,\sigalg X)$ and $(Y,\sigalg Y)$ be measurable spaces. 
  A \emph{measurable function} $f\colon X\to Y$ is a function such that $\inv{f}(U)\in\sigalg X$ when $U\in\sigalg Y$. 
\end{definition}

Thus a measurable function $f\colon X\to Y$ lets us \emph{push-forward} a probability measure $\mu$ on $X$ to a probability measure $f_*\mu$ on $Y$ by $(f_*\mu)(U)=\mu(\inv{f}(U))$.  Measurable spaces and measurable functions form a category $\Meas$.

Real-valued measurable functions $f \colon X \to \RR$ can be integrated with respect to a probability measure $\mu$ on $(X,\sigalg X)$. The \emph{integral} of a nonnegative function $f$ is
\[
\int_X f \,\dd\mu \defeq \sup_{\{U_i\}} \sum_i \left(\mu(U_i) \cdot \inf_{x \in U_i} f(x)\right)\text,
\]
where $\{U_i\}$ ranges over finite partitions of $X$ into measurable subsets.
When $f$ may be negative, its integral is\[
        \int_X f\,\dd\mu \defeq \left(\int_X \max(0,f)\,\dd\mu\right) - \left(\int_X \max(0,-f)\,\dd\mu\right)
\]
when those two integrals exist.
When it is convenient to make the integrated variable explicit, we write $\int_{x \in U} f(x)\,\dd\mu$ for $\int_X (\lambda x.\,f(x) \cdot [x \in U])\,\dd\mu$, where $U \in \sigalg X$ is a measurable subset and $[\varphi]$ has the value $1$ if $\varphi$ holds
and $0$ otherwise.

\subsection{Standard Borel spaces}
\begin{proposition}[e.g.~\cite{kallenberg}, App.~A1]\label{prop:char-sbs}
  For a measurable space $(X,\sigalg X)$ the following are equivalent:
  \begin{itemize}
   \item $(X,\sigalg X)$ is a retract of $(\RR,\sigalg \RR)$, that is, there exist measurable \smash{$X\xrightarrow f \RR\xrightarrow g X$} such that $g \circ f=\id X$;
   \item $(X,\sigalg X)$ is either measurably isomorphic to $(\RR,\sigalg \RR)$ or countable and discrete;
   \item $X$ has a complete metric with a countable dense subset and $\sigalg X$ is the least $\sigma$-algebra containing all open sets.
  \end{itemize}
\end{proposition}
When $(X,\sigalg X)$ satisfies any of the above conditions,  we call it
\emph{standard Borel space}. These spaces play an important role in
probability theory because they enjoy properties that do not hold for
general measurable spaces, such as the existence of conditional
probability kernels~\cite{kallenberg,Preston-Borel08}
and de Finetti's theorem for exchangeable random processes~\cite{Dubins1979}. 

Besides $\RR$, another popular uncountable standard Borel space is $(0,1)$ with
the $\sigma$-algebra ${\{U \cap (0,1) ~|~ U \in \sigalg \RR\}}$. As
the above proposition indicates, these spaces are isomorphic by, for instance,
$\lambda r.\,\frac1{(1+e^{-r})} : \RR \to (0,1)$.

\subsection{Failure of cartesian closure}
\begin{proposition}[Aumann, \cite{aumann:functionspaces}]\label{prop:not-ccc}
  The category $\Meas$ is not cartesian closed: there is no space of functions $\RR\to\RR$. 
\end{proposition}
Specifically, the evaluation function 
\[\varepsilon\colon \Meas(\RR,\RR)\times \RR\to \RR
\qquad\text{with}\qquad
\varepsilon(f,r)=f(r)\]
is never measurable 
$(\Meas(\RR,\RR)\times \RR,\Sigma\otimes \sigalg \RR)\to (\RR,\sigalg \RR)$
regardless of the choice of $\sigma$-algebra $\Sigma$ 
on $\Meas(\RR,\RR)$.
Here, $\Sigma\otimes \sigalg \RR$ is the product $\sigma$-algebra,
generated by rectangles ${(U\times V)}$ for $U\in\Sigma$ and $V\in\sigalg \RR$. 



 
\section{Quasi-Borel spaces}\label{sec:quasiborel}
The typical situation in probability theory is that there is a fixed measurable space $(\Omega,\sigalg\Omega)$, called the \emph{sample space}, from which all randomness originates, and that observations are made in terms of random variables, which are pairs $(X,f)$ of a measurable space of observations $(X,\sigalg X)$ and a measurable function $f\colon \Omega\to X$.
From this perspective, the notion of measurable function is more important
than the notion of measurable space. In some ways, the
$\sigma$-algebra $\sigalg X$ is only used as an intermediary to restrain the class of measurable functions $\Omega\to X$.

We now use this idea as a basis for our new notion of space.
In doing so, we assume that our sample space $\Omega$ is the real numbers,
which makes probabilities behave well.
\begin{definition}\label{def:qbs}
A \emph{quasi-Borel space}
is a set $X$ together with a set $\qb X \subseteq [\RR\to X]$ satisfying:
\begin{itemize}
\item $\alpha \circ f \in \qb X$ if $\alpha \in \qb X$ and $f\colon \RR\to\RR$ is measurable;
\item $\alpha \in \qb X$ if $\alpha\colon \RR\to X$ is constant;
\item if ${\RR=\biguplus_{i\in \NN}S_i}$, with each set $S_i$ Borel,
  and ${\alpha_1,\alpha_2,\ldots\in \qb X}$, then
  ${\beta}$ is in ${\qb X}$, where ${\beta(r) = \alpha_i(r)}$ for $r\in S_i$.
\end{itemize}
\end{definition}
The name `quasi-Borel space' is motivated firstly by analogy to quasi-topological spaces (see \S\ref{sec:related}),
and secondly in recognition of the intimate connection to the standard Borel space $\RR$ (see also Prop.~\ref{prop:adjunction}(2)).

\begin{example}\normalfont
  For every measurable space $(X,\sigalg X)$, let $\sigtoqb {\sigalg X}$ be the set of measurable functions $\RR\to X$.
  Thus $\sigtoqb {\sigalg X}$ is the set of $X$-valued random variables.
  In particular: $\RR$ itself can be considered as a quasi-Borel space, with $\qb \RR$ the set of measurable functions $\RR\to\RR$;  the two-element discrete space $2$ can be considered as a quasi-Borel space, with $\qb 2$ the set of measurable functions $\RR\to 2$, which are exactly the characteristic functions of the Borel sets~(Def.~\ref{def:borel}).
\end{example}

Before we continue, we remark that the notion of quasi-Borel space
is invariant under replacing $\RR$ with a different uncountable standard Borel space.
\begin{proposition}
  For any measurable space $(\Omega,\sigalg\Omega)$, any measurable isomorphism $\iota \colon \RR \to \Omega$,
  any set $X$, and any set $N$ of functions $\Omega\to X$, the pair
  $(X,\{\alpha \circ \iota~|~\alpha\in N\})$
is a quasi-Borel space if and only if:
  \begin{itemize}
   \item $\alpha \circ f \in N$ if $\alpha \in N$ and $f\colon \Omega\to\Omega$ is measurable;
   \item $\alpha \in N$ if $\alpha\colon \Omega\to X$ is constant;
\item if $\Omega=\biguplus_{i\in \NN}S_i$, with each set $S_i \in \sigalg \Omega$,
  and $\alpha_1,\alpha_2,\ldots\in N$, then
  $\beta$ is in $N$, where $\beta(r)=\alpha_i(r)$ if $r\in S_i$.
\end{itemize}
\end{proposition}
By Prop.~\ref{prop:char-sbs}, the measurable spaces isomorphic to $\RR$ are the uncountable standard Borel spaces.
Note that the choice of isomorphism~$\iota$ is not important: it does not appear in the three conditions.

Probability theory typically considers a basic probability measure on the sample
space $\Omega$. Each random variable, that is each measurable function
$\Omega\to X$, then induces a probability measure on $X$ by pushing forward the basic measure. Quasi-Borel spaces take this idea as an axiomatic notion of probability measure.
\begin{definition}\label{def:probabilitymeasure}
  A \emph{probability measure} on a quasi-Borel space $(X,\qb X)$ is a pair $(\alpha,\mu)$ of $\alpha \in \qb X$ and a probability measure $\mu$ on $\RR$ (as in Def.~\ref{def:borelprob}).
\end{definition}

\subsection{Morphisms and integration}

\begin{definition}\label{def:morphism}
  A \emph{morphism} of quasi-Borel spaces $(X,\qb X)\to (Y,\qb Y)$ is a function $f \colon X \to Y$ such that $f \circ \alpha \in \qb Y$ if $\alpha\in \qb X$. Write $\QBS\big((X,\qb X),(Y,\qb Y)\big)$ for the set of morphisms from $(X,\qb X)$ to $(Y,\qb Y)$.
\end{definition}

In particular, elements of $M_X$ are precisely morphisms $(\RR,\qb\RR)\to (X,\qb X)$, so $\qb X = \QBS\big((\RR,\qb \RR),(X,\qb X)\big)$.

Morphisms compose as functions, and identity functions are morphisms,
so quasi-Borel spaces form a category $\QBS$.

\begin{example}\normalfont
  There are two canonical ways to equip a set $X$ with a quasi-Borel
  space structure. The first structure $\qb X^R$ consists of all
  functions $\RR \to X$. The second structure $\qb X^L$ consists of
  all functions $\beta \colon \RR \to X$ for which there exist: a countable
  subset $I \subseteq \NN$; a measurable $f \colon \RR \to \RR$; a
  partition $\RR = \biguplus_{i \in I}S_i$ with every $S_i$
  measurable; and a sequence $(x_i)_{i \in I}$ in $X$, such that
  $\beta(r) = x_i$ whenever $f(r) \in
  S_i$. These are the right and left adjoints, respectively, to the
  forgetful functor from $\QBS$ to $\Set$.
\end{example}

Def.~\ref{def:morphism} is independent of $\RR$: the sample space may be any uncountable standard Borel space.

\begin{proposition}
  Consider a measurable space $(\Omega,\sigalg\Omega)$
  with a measurable isomorphism $\iota \colon \RR \to \Omega$.
  For $i \in {1,2}$, let $X_i$ be a set and $N_i$ a set of functions $\Omega\to X_i$ such that
  \[
    M_i = \big(X_i,\{\alpha \circ \iota~|~\alpha\in N_i\} \big)
  \]
  are quasi-Borel spaces. A function $g \colon X_1 \to X_2$ is a morphism $(X_1,M_1) \to (X_2,M_2)$ if and only if $g \circ \alpha \in N_2$ for $\alpha \in N_1$.
\end{proposition}

Morphisms between quasi-Borel spaces are analogous to measurable functions
between measurable spaces. The crucial properties of measurable functions
are that they work well with (probability) measures: we can push-forward these measures, and integrate over them.
Morphisms of quasi-Borel spaces also support these constructions.
\begin{itemize}
  \item\emph{Pushing forward:} if $f\colon X\to Y$ is a morphism and $(\alpha,\mu)$ is a probability measure on $X$ then $f\circ \alpha$ is by definition in $\qb Y$ and so $(f\circ\alpha,\mu)$ is a probability measure on $Y$.
  \item\emph{Integrating:} If $f\colon X\to \RR$ is a morphism of quasi-Borel spaces and $(\alpha,\mu)$ is a probability measure on $X$, the integral of $f$ with respect to $(\alpha,\mu)$ is
  \begin{equation}\label{eqn:def-qbs-integration}
    \int f\, \dd(\alpha,\mu)\defeq \int_\RR (f\circ \alpha)\,\dd\mu\text.
  \end{equation}
  So integration formally reduces to integration on $\RR$.
\end{itemize}

\subsection{Relationship to measurable spaces}

If we regard a subset $S\subseteq X$ as its characteristic function $\chi_S\colon X\to 2$, then we can regard a $\sigma$-algebra on a set $X$ as a set of characteristic functions $F_X\subseteq [X\to 2]$ satisfying certain conditions. Thus a measurable space (Def.~\ref{def:meas-space}) could equivalently be described
as a pair $(X,F_X)$ of a set $X$ and a collection $F_X\subseteq [X\to 2]$ of characteristic functions.
Moreover, from this perspective, a measurable function $f\colon (X,F_X)\to (Y,F_Y)$ is
simply a function $f\colon X\to Y$ such that $\chi\circ f \in F_X$ if $\chi\in F_Y$.
Thus quasi-Borel spaces shift the emphasis from characteristic functions $X\to 2$ to random variables $\RR\to X$.

\subsubsection{Quasi-Borel spaces as structured measurable spaces}
A subset $S\subseteq X$ is in the $\sigma$-algebra $\sigalg X$
of a measurable space $(X,\sigalg X)$ if and only if its
characteristic function $X\to 2$ is measurable.
With this in mind, we \emph{define} a measurable subset of a
quasi-Borel space $(X,\qb X)$ to be a subset $S\subseteq X$
such that the characteristic function $X\to 2$ is a morphism of quasi-Borel spaces.
\begin{proposition}
  The collection of all measurable subsets of a quasi-Borel space $(X,\qb X)$ is characterized as
  \begin{equation}\label{eqn:qb-sigma}
    \qbtosig {\qb X}\defeq \{U~|~\forall \alpha\in\qb X.\,\inv\alpha(U)\in\sigalg \RR\}
  \end{equation}
  and forms a $\sigma$-algebra.
\end{proposition}
Thus we can understand a quasi-Borel space as a measurable space $(X,\sigalg X)$ equipped
with a class of measurable functions $\qb X\subseteq [\RR\to X]$ determining the $\sigma$-algebra by $\sigalg X=\qbtosig{\qb X}$
as in~\eqref{eqn:qb-sigma}.

Moreover, every morphism $(X,\qb X)\to (Y,\qb Y)$ is also a measurable
function $(X,\qbtosig {\qb X})\to (Y,\qbtosig{\qb Y})$ (but the converse does not hold
in general).

A probability measure $(\alpha,\mu)$ on a quasi-Borel space $(X,\qb X)$ induces a
probability measure $\alpha_*\mu$ on the underlying measurable space.
Integration as in~\eqref{eqn:def-qbs-integration} matches the standard
definition for measurable spaces.

\subsubsection{An adjunction embedding standard Borel spaces}
Under some circumstances morphisms of quasi-Borel spaces coincide with measurable functions.
\begin{proposition}\label{prop:adjunction}
  Let $(Y,\sigalg Y)$ be a measurable space.
  \begin{enumerate}
  \item If $(X,\qb X)$ is a quasi-Borel space, a function $X\to Y$ is a measurable function
  $(X,\qbtosig{\qb X})\to (Y,\sigalg Y)$ if and only if it is a morphism $(X,\qb X)\to (Y,\sigtoqb {\sigalg Y})$.
  \item If $(X,\sigalg X)$ is a standard Borel space, a function $X\to Y$ is a morphism $(X,\sigtoqb{\sigalg X})\to (Y,\sigtoqb {\sigalg Y})$ if and only if it is a measurable function $(X,\sigalg X)\to (Y,\sigalg Y)$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{proposition}
\newcommand{\meastoqbs}{R}
\newcommand{\qbstomeas}{L}
Proposition~\ref{prop:adjunction}(1) means there is an adjunction
\[\xymatrix{\Meas\ar@/_/[rr]_\meastoqbs&&\ar@/_/[ll]_\qbstomeas^\bot \QBS}\]
where
$\qbstomeas(X,\qb X)= (X,\qbtosig{\qb X})$
and
$\meastoqbs(X,\sigalg X)= (X,\sigtoqb{\sigalg X})$.
Proposition~\ref{prop:adjunction}(2) means that the functor $\meastoqbs$ is full and faithful when restricted to standard Borel spaces. Equivalently,
$L(R(X,\sigalg X))=(X,\sigalg X)$, that is $\sigalg X = \qbtosig {\sigtoqb {\sigalg X}}$
for standard Borel spaces $(X,\sigalg X)$.


 
\section{Products, coproducts and function spaces}\label{sec:structure}
Quasi-Borel spaces support products, coproducts, and function spaces.
These basic constructions form the basis for interpreting simple type theory
in quasi-Borel spaces. 
\begin{proposition}[Products]\label{prop:qbsproduct}
  If $(X_i,\qb {X_i})_{i\in I}$ is a family of quasi-Borel spaces indexed by a set $I$, then $(\prod_iX_i,\qb {\Pi_i X_i})$ is a quasi-Borel space, where $\prod_iX_i$ is the set product, and 
  \[
    \qb {\Pi_iX_i}\defeq \textstyle{\Big\{f\colon \RR\to \prod_iX_i~|~\forall i.\, (\pi_i\circ f)\in\qb{X_i}\Big\}\text.}
  \]
  The projections $\prod_i X_i\to X_i$ are morphisms, and provide the structure of a categorical product in $\QBS$.
\end{proposition}

\begin{proposition}[Coproducts]\label{prop:qbscoproduct}
  If $(X_i,\qb{X_i})_{i\in I}$ is a family of quasi-Borel spaces indexed by a countable set $I$, then $(\coprod_iX_i,\qb{\amalg_i X_i})$ is a quasi-Borel space, where $\coprod_iX_i$ is the disjoint union of sets, 
  \begin{align*}
    \qb{\amalg_i X_i}\defeq \{\lambda r.\,(f(r),\alpha_{f(r)}(r))
    \mid\; &f\colon \RR\to I\ \mbox{is measurable},\\
    & (\alpha_{i}\in \qb {X_{i}})_{i\in \mathsf{image}(f)}\}\text,
  \end{align*}
  and $I$ carries the discrete $\sigma$-algebra.
  This space has the universal property of a coproduct in the category $\QBS$.
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}[Proof notes]
  The third condition of quasi-Borel spaces is needed here. 
  It is a crucial step in showing that for an $I$-indexed family of morphisms $(f_i\colon X_i\to Z)_{i\in I}$, the copairing $[f_i]_{i\in I}\colon\coprod_{i\in I}X_i\to Z$ is again a morphism.
\end{proof}

\begin{proposition}[Function spaces]\label{prop:functionspace}
  If $(X,\qb X)$ and $(Y,\qb Y)$ are quasi-Borel spaces, so is $(Y^X,\qb {Y^X})$,
  where ${Y^X\defeq \QBS(X,Y)}$ is the set of morphisms $X\to Y$, and 
  \[
    \qb{Y^X}\defeq \{\alpha\colon\RR\to Y^X \mid
\mathsf{uncurry}(\alpha)\in\QBS(\RR\times X,Y)\}\text.
  \] 
  The evaluation function $Y^X\times X\to Y$ is a morphism and has the universal property of the function space.
  Thus $\QBS$ is a cartesian closed category.
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}[Proof notes]
  The only difficult part is showing that $(Y^X,\qb{Y^X})$ satisfies the third condition of quasi-Borel spaces. 
  Prop.~\ref{prop:qbscoproduct} is useful here.
\end{proof}
\subsection{Relationship with standard Borel spaces}
Recall that standard Borel spaces can be thought of as a full subcategory 
of the quasi-Borel spaces, that is,
the functor $\meastoqbs\colon \Meas\to \QBS$ is full and faithful (Prop.~\ref{prop:adjunction}(2))
when restricted to the standard Borel spaces.
This full subcategory has the same countable products, coproducts and function spaces 
(whenever they exist). 
We may thus regard quasi-Borel spaces as a conservative extension of standard Borel spaces that supports simple type theory.

\begin{proposition} 
  The functor $\meastoqbs(X,\sigalg X)=(X,\sigtoqb {\sigalg X})$:
  \begin{enumerate} 
  \item preserves products of standard Borel spaces:
  $\meastoqbs(\prod_iX_i)=\prod_i\meastoqbs(X_i)$, where $(X_i,\sigalg{X_i})_{i\in I}$ is a countable family of standard Borel spaces;
  \item preserves spaces of functions between standard Borel spaces whenever they exist:
  if $(Y,\sigalg Y)$ is countable and discrete, 
  and $(X,\sigalg X)$ is standard Borel, then $\meastoqbs(X^Y)=\meastoqbs(X)^{\meastoqbs(Y)}$;
  \item preserves countable coproducts of standard Borel spaces:
  $\meastoqbs(\coprod_iX_i)=\coprod_i\meastoqbs(X_i)$, where $(X_i,\sigalg{X_i})_{i\in I}$ is a countable family of standard Borel spaces. 
\end{enumerate}
\end{proposition}
Consequently, a standard programming language semantics in standard Borel spaces can be conservatively embedded in quasi-Borel spaces, allowing higher-order functions while preserving all the type theoretic structure. 

We note, however, that in light of Prop.~\ref{prop:not-ccc},
the quasi-Borel space $\RR^\RR$ does not come from a standard Borel space. 
Moreover, the left adjoint $L\colon \QBS\to \Meas$ does not preserve products
in general.
For quasi-Borel spaces $(X,\qb X)$ and $(Y,\qb Y)$, we always have 
$\qbtosig{\qb X}\otimes \qbtosig{\qb Y}\subseteq \qbtosig {\qb {X\times Y}}$, 
but not always $\supseteq$. Indeed, $\qbtosig{\qb {\RR^\RR}}\otimes \sigalg \RR
\neq \qbtosig {\qb{(\RR^\RR\times \RR)}}$, by Prop.~\ref{prop:not-ccc}.
 
\section{A monad of probability measures}\label{sec:giry}
In this section we will show that the probability measures on a quasi-Borel space form a quasi-Borel space again. This gives a commutative monad that generalizes the Giry monad for measurable spaces~\cite{giry:monad}.
\subsection{Monads}
\newcommand{\CCat}{\mathcal C}
We use the Kleisli triple formulation of monads (see e.g.~\cite{moggi-monads}). Recall that a monad on a category $\CCat$ comprises 
\begin{itemize}
\item for any object $X$, an object $T(X)$;
\item for any object $X$, a morphism $\munit\colon X\to T(X)$;
\item for any objects $X,Y$, a function
 \[\bindname\colon \CCat(X,T(Y))\to \CCat(T(X),T(Y))\text.\]
  We write $(t\bindsymbol f)$ for $\bindname(f)(t)$. 
\end{itemize}
This is subject to the conditions $( t\bindsymbol \munit)=t$, $( {\munit(x)}\bindsymbol f)=f(x)$, and 
$\bind t {(\lambda x.\,(\bind {f(x)} g))}=
\bind{(\bind t f)}g$. 

The intuition is that $T(X)$ is an object of computations returning~$X$, 
that $\munit$ is the computation that returns immediately, and that 
$t\bindsymbol f$ sequences computations,
first running computation $t$ and then calling $f$ with the result.

When $\CCat$ is cartesian closed, 
a monad is \emph{strong} if $\bindname$ internalizes to an operation
$\bindname\colon (T(Y))^X\to (T(Y))^{T(X)}$,
and then the conditions are understood as expressions in a cartesian closed category.

\subsection{Kernels and the Giry monad}
We recall the notion of probability kernel, which is a measurable family of probability measures. 
\begin{definition}
  Let $(X,\sigalg X)$ and $(Y,\sigalg Y)$ be measurable spaces.
  A \emph{probability kernel} from $X$ to $Y$ is a function $k:X\times \sigalg Y\to [0,1]$ such that $k(x,-)$ is a probability measure for all $x\in X$ (Def.~\ref{def:meas-space}), and $k(-,U)$ is a measurable function for all $U\in\sigalg Y$ (Def.~\ref{def:measurablefunction}). 
\end{definition}
We can classify probability kernels as follows.
Let $\Giry(X)$ be the set of probability measures on $(X,\sigalg X)$. 
We can equip this set with the $\sigma$-algebra generated by 
${\{\mu\in\Giry(X)~|~\mu(U)<r\}}$, for $U\in\sigalg X$ and $r\in[0,1]$,
to form a measurable space $(\Giry(X),\sigalg{\Giry(X)})$.
A measurable function $X\to \Giry(Y)$ amounts to a probability kernel from $X$ to $Y$. 

The construction $\Giry$ has the structure of a monad, as first discussed by
Giry~\cite{giry:monad}.
A computational intuition is that $\Giry(X)$ is a space of probabilistic computations
over $X$, and this provides a semantic foundation for a first-order probabilistic programming language (see e.g.~\cite{statonyangheunenkammarwood:higherorder}). 
The unit $\eta\colon X\to \Giry(X)$ lets $\eta(x)$ be the Dirac measure on $x$, 
with $\eta(x)(U)= 1$ if $x\in U$, and $\eta(x)(U)= 0$ if $x\not\in U$.
If $\mu\in \Giry(X)$ and $k$ is a measurable function $X\to \Giry(Y)$, then $(\mu\bindGsymbol k)$ is the measure in $\Giry(Y)$ with 
$(\mu\bindGsymbol k)(U)= \int_{x \in X} k(x)(U) \,\dd\mu$. 

\subsection{Equivalent measures on quasi-Borel spaces}
Recall (Def.~\ref{def:probabilitymeasure}) that a probability measure $(\alpha,\mu)$ on a quasi-Borel space $(X,\qb X)$ is a pair $(\alpha,\mu)$ of a function 
$\alpha\in\qb X$ and a probability measure $\mu$ on $\RR$. 
Random variables are often equated when they describe the same distribution. 
Every probability measure $(\alpha,\mu)$ determines 
a push-forward measure $\alpha_* \mu$ on the corresponding 
measurable space $(X,\qbtosig{\qb X})$, that assigns to $U \subseteq X$ the real number $\mu(\alpha^{-1}(U))$.
We will identify two probability measures when they define the same push-forward measure, and write $\sim$ for this equivalence relation. 

This is a reasonable notion of equality even if we put aside the notion of 
measurable space, because two probability measures have the same push-forward measure precisely when they have the same integration operator: $(\alpha,\mu) \sim (\alpha',\mu')$ if and only if $\int f\, \dd(\alpha,\mu) = \int f\,\dd(\alpha',\mu')$ for all morphisms ${f \colon (X,\qb X) \to \RR}$.
Nevertheless, other notions of equivalence could be used.

\subsection{A probability monad}
We now explain how to build a monad of probability measures on the 
category of quasi-Borel spaces, modulo this notion of 
equivalence. 
This monad $\Pmonad$ will inherit properties 
from the Giry monad.
Technically, the functor
$L\colon \QBS\to \Meas$ (Prop.~\ref{prop:adjunction}) is a `monad opfunctor' 
taking $\Pmonad$ to the 
Giry monad $\Giry$, which means that it extends to a 
functor from the Kleisli category of~$\Pmonad$ to the Kleisli category of~$\Giry$~\cite{street-monads}.
\paragraph{On objects}
For a quasi-Borel space $(X,\qb X)$, let 
\begin{align*}
    P(X) &= \{ (\alpha,\mu) \text{ probability measure on } (X,\qb X)\}\slash\sim \text{,}\\
    \qb{P(X)} & = \{ \beta \colon \RR \to P(X) \mid \exists \alpha \in \qb X.\,\exists g \in \Meas(\RR, G(\RR)).\,
    \\
    & \phantom{= \{ \beta \colon \RR \to P(X) \mid\;\;} \forall r \in \RR.\, 
    \beta(r) = [\alpha,g(r)] \}  \text{,}
\end{align*}
where $[\alpha,\mu]$ denotes the equivalence class.
Note that \begin{equation}P(X)\cong \{\alpha_*\mu\in \Giry(X,\qbtosig{\qb X})~|~\alpha\in\qb X,\,\mu\in\Giry(\RR)\}\label{eqn:opfunctor-map}\end{equation}
as sets, and $l_X([\alpha,\mu])= \alpha_*\mu$ defines a measurable injection 
$l_X\colon L(P(X))\rightarrowtail \Giry (X,\qbtosig{\qb X})$.


\paragraph{Monad unit (return)}
Recall that the constant functions $(\lambda r.x)$ are all in $\qb X$.
For any probability measure $\mu$ on $\RR$, the push-forward measure
$(\lambda r.x)_*\,\mu$ on $(X,\qbtosig{\qb X})$ 
is the Dirac measure on $x$, with $((\lambda r.x)_*\,\mu)(U)=1$ if $x\in U$
and $0$ otherwise. 
Thus $(\lambda r.x,\mu) \sim (\lambda r.x,\mu')$ for all measures  $\mu,\mu'$ on $\RR$.
The unit of $\Pmonad$ at $(X,\qb X)$ is the morphism 
$\munit \colon X\to \Pmonad(X)$ given by
\begin{equation}\label{eq:giry:unit}
  \munit_{(X,\qb X)}(x) = [ \lambda r.x,\, \mu ]
\end{equation}
for an arbitrary probability measure $\mu$ on $\RR$. 

\paragraph{Bind}
To define ${\bindname\colon \Pmonad(Y)^X\to (\Pmonad(Y))^{\Pmonad(X)}}$,
suppose $f\colon X\to \Pmonad(Y)$ 
is a morphism and $[\alpha,\mu]$ in $\Pmonad(X)$.
Since $f$ is a morphism, there is a measurable $g\colon \RR\to\Giry(\RR)$ 
and a function $\beta\in \qb Y$ such that 
$(f\circ \alpha)(r) = [\beta,g(r)]$. 
Set $(\bind{[\alpha,\mu]} f) = [\beta,\bindG \mu g]$,
where $\bindG\mu g$ is the bind of the Giry monad.
This matches the bind of the Giry monad, since 
$(\bindG{(\alpha_*\mu)}{(l_Y \circ f)})=\beta_*(\bindG \mu g)$. 
\begin{theorem}
\label{thm:Pmonad}
The data $(P,\eta,\bindname)$ above defines a strong monad on the 
category $\QBS$ of quasi-Borel spaces.
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}[Proof notes]
  The monad laws can be reduced to the laws for the monad $\Giry$ on $\Meas$~\cite{giry:monad}. The monad on $\QBS$ is strong because
  $\bindname\colon \Pmonad(Y)^X\to (\Pmonad(Y))^{\Pmonad(X)}$ is a 
  morphism, which is shown by expanding the definitions. 
\end{proof}

\begin{proposition}\label{prop:giryproperties}
  The monad~$\Pmonad$ satisfies these properties:
\begin{enumerate}
\item For $f\colon (X,\qb X)\to (Y,\qb Y)$, the functorial action 
$\Pmonad(f)\colon P(X)\to P(Y)$ is $[\alpha,\mu] \mapsto [f\circ \alpha,\mu]$.
\item It is a commutative monad, i.e.\ the order of 
sequencing doesn't matter:
if $p\in \Pmonad(X)$, $q\in\Pmonad(Y)$, and $f$ is a morphism $X\times Y\to \Pmonad(Z)$, then $\bind p {\lambda x.\,\bind q{\lambda y.\,f(x,y)}}$ equals $\bind q {\lambda y.\,\bind p{\lambda x.\,f(x,y)}}$.
\item The faithful functor ${L\colon \QBS\to \Meas}$ with ${L(X,\qb X)=(X,\qbtosig{\qb X})}$ extends to a faithful functor ${\mathsf{Kleisli}(\Pmonad)\to \mathsf{Kleisli}(\Giry)}$, i.e.\ $(L,l)$ is a monad opfunctor~\cite{street-monads}.
\item When $(X,\sigalg X)$ is a standard Borel space, the map
  $l_X$ of Eq.~\eqref{eqn:opfunctor-map} is a measurable isomorphism.
\label{prop:monad-morphism}
\end{enumerate}
\end{proposition}

 
\section{Example: Bayesian regression}
\label{sec:example}
We are now in a position to explain the semantics of the Anglican program in Figure~\ref{fig:linearregression}.
The program can be split into three parts: a prior, a likelihood, and a posterior. 
Recall that Bayes' law says that the posterior is proportionate to the 
product of the prior and the likelihood.

\paragraph{Prior}
Lines 2--4 define a prior measure on $\RR^\RR$:
\newcommand*{\mlstinline}[1]{\text{\lstinline|#1|}}
\begin{align*}
\mathit{prior}\defeq 
\mlstinline{(let [}&\mlstinline{s (sample (normal 0.0 3.0)) }\\[-4pt]&\mlstinline{b (sample (normal 0.0 3.0))]}\\[-4pt]&\hspace{-0.5cm}\mlstinline{(fn [x] (+ (* s x) b)))}
\end{align*}

To describe this semantically, observe the following. 
\begin{proposition}
        \label{prop:change-randomsource}
Let $(\Omega,\sigalg \Omega)$ be a standard Borel space,
and $(X,\qb X)$ a quasi-Borel space. 
Let $\alpha\colon R(\Omega,\sigalg \Omega)\to X$ be a morphism and $\mu$ a probability measure on $(\Omega,\sigalg \Omega)$. 
Any section-retraction pair $(\Omega\xrightarrow\varsigma \RR \xrightarrow \rho\Omega)=\id\Omega$ has a probability measure $[\alpha\circ \rho,\varsigma_* \mu]\in \Pmonad(X)$, that is independent of the choice of $\varsigma$ and $\rho$. 
\label{prop:different-prob-space}
\end{proposition}
Write $[\alpha,\mu]$ for the probability measure in this case. 

Now, the program fragment $\mathit{prior}$ describes the distribution $[\alpha,\nu\otimes \nu]$ 
in $\Pmonad(\RR^\RR)$ 
where $\nu$ is the normal distribution on $\RR$ with mean $0$ and standard deviation $3$,
and where $\alpha\colon \RR\times \RR\to \RR^\RR$ is given by 
$\alpha(s,b)\defeq \lambda r.\,s \cdot r+b$. 
Informally, 
\begin{equation}
\label{eqn:linear-reg-prior}
\denot{\mathit{prior}}=[\alpha,\nu\otimes\nu]\in \Pmonad(\RR^\RR)\text.
\end{equation}
Figure~\ref{fig:prior} illustrates this measure $[\alpha, \nu \otimes \nu]$.
This denotational semantics can be made compositional, by using 
the commutative monad structure of $\Pmonad$ and the cartesian closed structure of the category $\QBS$ (following e.g.~\cite{moggi-monads,statonyangheunenkammarwood:higherorder}),
but in this paper we focus on this example rather than spelling out the general case once again.

\begin{figure}
\includegraphics[width=\linewidth]{prior.png}
\caption{Illustration of 1000 sampled functions from the prior on $\RR^\RR$ for Bayesian linear regression (\ref{eqn:linear-reg-prior}).}
\label{fig:prior}
\end{figure}

\newcommand{\nordens}{d}

\paragraph{Likelihood}Lines 5--9 define the likelihood of the observations:
\begin{align*}
\mathit{obs}\ \ \defeq &\phantom{\mbox{} \dots \mbox{} }    \mlstinline{(observe (normal (f 1.0) 0.5) 2.5)}\\&\dots
    \mlstinline{
    (observe (normal (f 5.0) 0.5) 8.0)}
\end{align*}
This program fragment has a free variable~$f$ of type~$\RR^\RR$. 
Let us focus on line~5 for a moment:
\[\mathit{obs}_1\defeq \mlstinline{(observe (normal (f 1.0) 0.5) 2.5)}\]
Given a function $f\colon \RR\to \RR$,
the likelihood of drawing $2.5$ from a normal distribution 
with mean $f(1.0)$ and standard deviation $0.5$ is 
\[
\denot{f\colon\RR^\RR\vdash \mathit{obs}_1}=\nordens(f(1.0),2.5)\text,
\]
where $\nordens\colon \RR^2\to[0,\infty)$ is the density of the normal distribution function with standard deviation $0.5$:
\[
\nordens(\mu,x)
\ =\ 
\sqrt{\tfrac 2\pi}\,e^{-2(x-\mu)^2}\text.
\]
Notice that we use a normal distribution 
to allow for some noise in the measurement. Informally, we are not recording an observation that $f(1.0)$ is \emph{exactly} $2.5$,
since this would make regression impossible; rather, $f(1.0)$ is roughly $2.5$.

Overall, lines 5--9 describe a likelihood weight which is 
the product of the likelihoods of the five data points, given 
$f\colon \RR^\RR$. 
\begin{align*}
\denot{f\colon \RR^\RR\vdash\mathit{obs}}
= \nordens(f(1),2.5)
&
{}
\cdot \nordens(f(2),3.8)
\cdot \nordens(f(3),4.5)
\\
&
{}
\cdot \nordens(f(4),6.2)
\cdot \nordens(f(5),8.0)\text.
\end{align*}

\paragraph{Posterior}
We follow the recipe for a semantic posterior given in~\cite{statonyangheunenkammarwood:higherorder}.
Putting the prior and likelihood together gives a probability measure 
in~$\Pmonad(\RR^\RR\times [0,\infty))$
which is found by pushing forward the measure 
$\denot{\mathit{prior}}\in\Pmonad(\RR)$ along the function 
\shortversion{$(\id\,,\,\denot{\mathit{obs}})\colon \RR^\RR\to \RR^\RR\times [0,\infty)$.}
\longversion{\[(\id\,,\,\denot{\mathit{obs}})\colon \RR^\RR\to \RR^\RR\times [0,\infty)\text.\]}
This push-forward measure
\[\Pmonad(\id\,,\,\denot{\mathit{obs}})\,(\denot{\mathit{prior}})\in \Pmonad(\RR^\RR\times [0,\infty))\]
is a measure over pairs $(f,w)$ of functions together with their likelihood weight.
We now find the posterior by multiplying the prior and the likelihood, and dividing by a normalizing constant.
To do this we define a morphism
\newcommand{\normalize}{\mathit{norm}}\begin{align*}
&
\normalize\colon \Pmonad(X\times [0,\infty))\to \Pmonad(X)\uplus\{\mathsf{error}\}
\\
&\normalize([(\alpha,\beta),\nu])\defeq 
\begin{cases}
[\alpha,\nu_\beta/(\nu_\beta(\RR))]&\text{if }{0\neq \nu_\beta(\RR)\neq \infty}\\
\mathsf{error}&\text{otherwise}\end{cases}
\end{align*}
where $\nu_\beta\colon \sigalg\RR\to [0,\infty] 
\defeq \lambda U.\,\int_{r \in U}(\beta(r))\, \dd \nu$.
The idea is that if $\beta\colon\RR\to [0,\infty)$ and $\nu$ is a probability measure on $\RR$ then 
$\nu_\beta$ is always a posterior measure on $\RR$, but it is typically not normalized, 
i.e.~$\nu_\beta(\RR)\neq 1$. We normalize it by dividing by the normalizing constant, 
as long as this division is well-defined.

Now, the semantics of the entire program in Figure~\ref{fig:linearregression}
is $\normalize(\Pmonad(\id\,,\,\denot{\mathit{obs}})\,(\denot{\mathit{prior}}))$, which is a measure in $\Pmonad(\RR^\RR)$. Calculating this posterior using Anglican's
inference algorithm \texttt{lmh} gives the plot in the lower half of 
Figure~\ref{fig:linearregression}.

\paragraph{Defunctionalized regression and non-linear regression}
Of course, one can do regression without explicitly considering distributions over the space of all measurable functions, 
by instead directly calculating posterior distributions for the slope~$s$ and the intercept~$b$.
For example, one could defunctionalize the program in Fig.~\ref{fig:linearregression} in the style of Reynolds~\cite{defunctionalization}.
But defunctionalization is a whole-program transformation. 
By structuring the semantics using quasi-Borel spaces, we are able to work compositionally, without mentioning~$s$ and~$b$ explicitly on lines 5--10. 
The internal posterior calculations actually happen at the level of standard Borel spaces, and so a defunctionalized version would be in some sense equivalent,
but from the programming perspective it helps to abstract away from this.
The regression program in Fig.~\ref{fig:linearregression} is quickly adapted to fit other kinds of functions, e.g.\ polynomials, or even programs from a small domain-specific language, simply by changing the prior in Lines~2--4. 

 
\section{Random functions}\label{sec:functions}
We discuss random variables and random functions, starting from the traditional setting.
Let $(\Omega,\sigalg\Omega)$ be a measurable space with a probability measure.
A \emph{random variable} is a measurable function
$(\Omega,\sigalg\Omega)\to (X,\sigalg X)$.
A \emph{random function} between measurable spaces
$(X,\sigalg X)$ and $(Y,\sigalg Y)$ is a measurable function
$(\Omega \times X,\sigalg \Omega \otimes \sigalg X)\to (Y,\sigalg Y)$.

We can push forward a probability measure on $\Omega$ along a random variable
$(\Omega,\sigalg\Omega)\to (X,\sigalg X)$ to get a probability measure on
$X$, but in the traditional setting we cannot push forward a measure along a
random function. Measurable spaces are not cartesian closed (Prop.~\ref{prop:not-ccc}),
and so we cannot form a measurable space $Y^X$ and we cannot curry a random function in general.

Now, if we revisit these definitions in the setting of quasi-Borel spaces,
we \emph{do} have function spaces, and so we can push forward along random functions.
In fact, this is somewhat tautologous because a probability measure (Def.~\ref{def:probabilitymeasure}) on a function space
is essentially the same thing as a random function: a probability measure on a function
space $(Y,\sigalg Y)^{(X,\sigalg X)}$ is defined to be a pair $(f,\mu)$ of a
probability measure $\mu$ on $\RR$, our sample space, and a morphism
$f \colon \RR\to Y^X$; but to give a morphism $\RR\to Y^X$ is to give a
morphism $\RR \times X \to Y$ (Prop.~\ref{prop:functionspace})
as in the traditional definition of random function.

We have already encountered an example of a random function in Section~\ref{sec:example}: the prior for linear regression is a random function from $\RR$ to $\RR$
over the measurable space $(\RR\times \RR, \sigalg \RR \otimes \sigalg \RR)$ with the measure $\nu\otimes \nu$.
Random functions abound throughout probability theory and stochastic processes.
The following section explores their use in the so-called randomization lemma, which is
used throughout probability theory. By moving to quasi-Borel spaces,
we can state this lemma succinctly (Theorem~\ref{theorem:random-quotient}).


\subsection{Randomization}
An elementary but useful trick in probability theory is
that every probability distribution on $\RR$
arises as a push-forward of the uniform distribution on $[0,1]$.
Even more useful is that this can be done in a parameterized way.
\begin{proposition}[\cite{kallenberg}, Lem.~3.22]\label{prop:randomization}
Let $(X,\sigalg X)$ be a measurable space.
For any kernel ${k\colon X\times \sigalg \RR\to [0,1]}$
there is a measurable function ${f\colon\RR\times X\to \RR}$ such that
${k(x,U)=\upsilon\{r~|~f(r,x)\in U\}}$, where
$\upsilon$ is the uniform distribution on $[0,1]$.
\end{proposition}
For quasi-Borel spaces we can phrase this more succinctly: it is a result
about a quotient of the space of random functions.
We first define quotient spaces.
\begin{proposition}
Let $(X,\qb X)$ be a quasi-Borel space, let $Y$ be a set,
and let $q\colon X\to Y$ be a surjection.
Then $(Y,\qb Y)$ is a quasi-Borel space with $\qb Y=\{q\circ \alpha~|~\alpha\in \qb X\}$.
\end{proposition}
We call such a space a \emph{quotient} space.
\begin{theorem}\label{theorem:random-quotient}
Let $(X,\qb X)$ be a quasi-Borel space.
The space $(\Pmonad(\RR))^X$ of kernels is a quotient of the
space $\Pmonad(\RR^X)$ of random functions.
\end{theorem}
Before proving this theorem, we use Prop.~\ref{prop:randomization}
to give an alternative characterization of our probability monad.
\begin{lemma}\label{lemma:alt-qb-pmonad}
Let $(X,\qb X)$ be a quasi-Borel space.
The function $q\colon X^\RR\to \Pmonad(X)$ given by $q(\alpha)\defeq [\alpha,\upsilon]$
is a surjection, with corresponding quotient space
$(\Pmonad(X),\qb{\Pmonad(X)})$:
\begin{align}
\label{eqn:altMPmonad}
M_{\Pmonad(X)}&=\{\lambda r\in\RR.\,[\gamma(r),\upsilon]~|~\gamma\in \qb{X^\RR}\}\text,
\end{align}
where $\upsilon$ is the uniform distribution on $[0,1]$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}[Proof notes]
The direction $(\subseteq)$ follows immediately from Prop.~\ref{prop:randomization}.
For the direction $(\supseteq)$ we must consider $\gamma\in \qb{X^\RR}$ and show that
$(\lambda r\in \RR.\,[\gamma(r),\upsilon])$ is in $\qb{\Pmonad(X)}$.
This follows by considering the kernel $k\colon \RR\to \Giry(\RR\times \RR)$ with
$k(r)=\upsilon\otimes\delta_r$,
so that $[\gamma(r),\upsilon]=[\uncurry(\gamma),k(r)]$. Here we are using Prop.~\ref{prop:change-randomsource}.
\end{proof}
\shortversion{
\begin{proof}[Proof of Theorem~\ref{theorem:random-quotient}]
Consider the  evident morphism
$q\colon \Pmonad(\RR^X)\to (\Pmonad(\RR))^X$
that comes from the monadic strength.
That is, $(q([\alpha,\mu]))(x)=[\lambda r.\,\alpha(r)(x),\mu]$.
We show that $q$ is a quotient morphism.

We first show that $q$ is surjective.
To give a morphism $k\colon (X,\qb X)\to \Pmonad(\RR)$
is to give a measurable function $(X,\qbtosig{\qb X})\to\Giry(\RR)$,
since
$(\Pmonad(\RR),\qb{\Pmonad(\RR)})\cong (\Giry(\RR),\sigtoqb{\sigalg{\Giry(\RR)}})$ (Prop.~\ref{prop:giryproperties}(4))and by using the adjunction between measurable spaces
and quasi-Borel spaces (Prop.~\ref{prop:adjunction}(1)).
Directly, we understand a morphism $k\colon  (X,\qb X)\to \Pmonad(\RR)$
as the kernel $k^\sharp\colon X\times \sigalg \RR\to [0,1]$ with
$k^\sharp(x,U)\defeq \mu_x(\inv{\alpha}_x(U))$ whenever
$k(x)=[\alpha_x,\mu_x]$. The definition of $k^\sharp$ does not depend on the choice
of $\alpha_x,\mu_x$.

Now we can
use the randomization lemma (Prop.~\ref{prop:randomization})
to find a measurable function $f_{k^\sharp}\colon \RR\times X\to \RR$ such that
$k^\sharp(x,U)=\upsilon\{r \mid f_{k^\sharp}(r,x)\in U\}$.
In general, if a function ${Y\times X\to Z}$ is jointly measurable
then it is also a morphism from the product quasi-Borel space.
So  $f_{k^\sharp}$ is a morphism,
and we can form $(\curry{f_{k^\sharp}}) \colon \RR\to \RR^X$.
So,
\begin{align*}
        q([\curry{f_{k^\sharp}},\,\upsilon])(x)
        & = [\lambda r.\curry{f_{k^\sharp}}(r)(x),\,\upsilon]
        \\
        & = [\lambda r. f_{k^\sharp}(r,x),\,\upsilon]
          = k(x)\text{,}
\end{align*}
and $q$ is surjective, as required.

Finally we show that $\qb{(\Pmonad(\RR))^X}=\{q\circ \alpha~|~
\alpha\in\qb {\Pmonad(\RR^X)}\}$.
We have $(\supseteq)$ since $q$ is a morphism, so it remains to show $(\subseteq)$.
Consider $\beta\in\qb{(\Pmonad(\RR))^X}$.
We must show that $\beta=q\circ\alpha$ for some $\alpha\in \qb{\Pmonad(\RR^X)}$.
By Prop.~\ref{prop:functionspace}, $\beta\in\qb{(\Pmonad(\RR))^X}$
means the uncurried function
$(\uncurry\,\beta)\colon\RR\times X\to \Pmonad (\RR)$ is a morphism.
As above, this morphism corresponds to a kernel
$(\uncurry\,\beta)^\sharp\colon (\RR\times X)\times \sigalg \RR\to [0,1]$.
The randomization lemma (Prop.~\ref{prop:randomization}) gives a measurable function $f_{\beta}\colon \RR\times (\RR\times X)\to \RR$ such that
$(\uncurry\,\beta)^\sharp((r,x),U)=\upsilon\{s \mid f_{\beta}(s,(r,x))\in U\}$.
By Prop.~\ref{prop:adjunction}(1) and the fact that
the $\sigma$-algebra of a product quasi-Borel space
$\RR \times (\RR \times X)$ includes the product $\sigma$-algebras
$\sigalg \RR \otimes \sigalg {\qb {\RR \times X}}$,
this function $f_\beta$ is also a morphism.
Define $\gamma\colon \RR\to (\RR^X)^\RR$ by
${\gamma = \lambda r.\,\lambda s.\,\lambda x.\,f_\beta(s,(r,x))}$.
This is a morphism since we can interpret $\lambda$-calculus in a cartesian closed
category.
Define $\alpha\colon \RR\to \Pmonad(\RR^X)$ by
$\alpha(r)= [\gamma(r),\upsilon]$;
this function is in $\qb{\Pmonad(\RR^X)}$ by Lemma~\ref{lemma:alt-qb-pmonad}.
A direct calculation now gives $\beta=q\circ\alpha$, as required.
\end{proof}
}
\longversion{
\begin{proof}[Proof of Theorem~\ref{theorem:random-quotient}]
We consider the  evident morphism
$q\colon \Pmonad(\RR^X)\to (\Pmonad(\RR))^X$
that comes from the monadic strength.
That is, $(q([\alpha,\mu]))(x)\defeq[\lambda r.\,\alpha(r)(x),\mu]$.
We show that $q$ is a quotient morphism.

We first show that $q$ is a surjection.
Note that to give a morphism $k\colon (X,\qb X)\to \Pmonad(\RR)$
is to give a measurable function $(X,\qbtosig{\qb X})\to\Giry(\RR)$,
since
$(\Pmonad(\RR),\qb{\Pmonad(\RR)})\cong (\Giry(\RR),\sigtoqb{\sigalg{\Giry(\RR)}})$ (Prop.~\ref{prop:monad-morphism}(4))
 and by using the adjunction between measurable spaces
and quasi-Borel spaces (Prop.~\ref{prop:adjunction}(1)).
Directly, we understand a morphism $k\colon  (X,\qb X)\to \Pmonad(\RR)$
as the kernel $k^\sharp\colon X\times \sigalg \RR\to [0,1]$ with
$k^\sharp(x,U)\defeq \mu_x(\inv{\alpha_x}(U))$ whenever
$k(x)=[\alpha_x,\mu_x]$. The definition of $k^\sharp$ does not depend on the choice
of $\alpha_x,\mu_x$.

Now we can
use the randomization lemma (Prop.~\ref{prop:randomization})
to find a measurable function $f_{k^\sharp}\colon \RR\times X\to \RR$ such that
$k^\sharp(x,U)=\upsilon\{r~|~f_{k^\sharp}(r,x)\in U\}$.
In general, if a function ${Y\times X\to Z}$ is jointly measurable
then it is also a morphism from the product quasi-Borel space
(but the converse is unknown).
So  $f_{k^\sharp}$ is a morphism,
and we can form $(\curry{f_{k^\sharp}}) \colon \RR\to \RR^X$.
So,
\begin{align*}
        q([\curry{f_{k^\sharp}},\,\upsilon])(x)
        & = [\lambda r.\curry{f_{k^\sharp}}(r)(x),\,\upsilon]
        \\
        & = [\lambda r. f_{k^\sharp}(r,x),\,\upsilon]
          = k(x)\text{,}
\end{align*}
and $q$ is surjective, as required.

Finally we must show that \[\qb{(\Pmonad(\RR))^X}=\{q\circ \alpha~|~
\alpha\in\qb {\Pmonad(\RR^X)}\}\text.\]
We have $(\supseteq)$ since $q$ is a morphism, so it remains to show $(\subseteq)$.
Consider $\beta\in\qb{(\Pmonad(\RR))^X}$.
We must show that $\beta=q\circ\alpha$ for some $\alpha\in \qb{\Pmonad(\RR^X)}$.
By Prop.~\ref{prop:functionspace}, $\beta\in\qb{(\Pmonad(\RR))^X}$
means that the uncurried function
$(\uncurry\,\beta)\colon\RR\times X\to \Pmonad (\RR)$ is a morphism.
As above, this morphism corresponds to a kernel
$(\uncurry\,\beta)^\sharp\colon (\RR\times X)\times \sigalg \RR\to [0,1]$.
We use the randomization lemma (Prop.~\ref{prop:randomization})
to find a measurable function $f_{\beta}\colon \RR\times (\RR\times X)\to \RR$ such that
$(\uncurry\,\beta)^\sharp((r,x),U)=\upsilon\{s~|~f_{\beta}(s,(r,x))\in U\}$.
By Prop.~\ref{prop:adjunction}(1) and the fact that
the $\sigma$-algebra of a product quasi-Borel space
$\RR \times (\RR \times X)$ includes the product $\sigma$-algebras
$\sigalg \RR \otimes \sigalg {\qb {\RR \times X}}$,
this function $f_\beta$ is also a morphism.
Let $\gamma\colon \RR\to (\RR^X)^\RR$ be given by
$\gamma\defeq \lambda r.\,\lambda s.\,\lambda x.\,f_\beta(s,(r,x))$.
This is a morphism since we can interpret $\lambda$-calculus in a cartesian closed
category.
Let $\alpha\colon \RR\to \Pmonad(\RR^X)$ be given by
$\alpha(r)\defeq [\gamma(r),\upsilon]$;
this function is in $\qb{\Pmonad(\RR^X)}$ by Lemma~\ref{lemma:alt-qb-pmonad}.
Moreover a direct calculation gives $\beta=q\circ\alpha$, as required.
\end{proof}
}





 

\section{De Finetti's theorem}\label{sec:definetti}
De Finetti's theorem \cite{deFinetti37} is one of the foundational results in Bayesian statistics.
It says that every exchangeable sequence of random observations on $\RR$ 
or another well-behaved measurable space can be modeled accurately by the following 
two-step process: first choose a probability 
measure on $\RR$ randomly (according to some distribution on probability measures) 
and then generate a sequence with independent samples from this measure. Limiting observations to values in a well-behaved space like $\RR$ in the theorem is important: Dubins and Freedman 
proved that the theorem fails for a general measurable space~\cite{Dubins1979}.

In this section, we show that a version of de Finetti's theorem holds for all quasi-Borel spaces, not just $\RR$. Our result does not 
contradict Dubins and Freedman's obstruction; probability measures on quasi-Borel spaces may only use $\RR$ as their 
source of randomness, whereas those on measurable spaces are allowed to use
any measurable space for the same purpose. As we will show shortly, this careful choice
of random source lets us generalize key arguments in a proof
of de Finetti's theorem~\cite{Austin-IISC13} to quasi-Borel spaces.

Let $(X,\qb X)$ be a quasi-Borel space and $(\Xn, \qb \Xn)$ 
the product quasi-Borel space $\prod_{i = 1}^n X$ for each positive integer $n$.
Recall that $\Pmonad(X)$ consists of equivalence classes $[\beta,\nu]$ of probability measures $(\beta,\nu)$ on $X$.
For $n \geq 1$, define a morphism $\iidn \colon \Pmonad(X) \to \Pmonad(\Xn)$ by
\[
        \textstyle{\iidn([\beta,\nu])}
        = \textstyle{\left[\left(\prod_{i = 1}^n \beta \circ \iotan\right),\,
        \left(\left(\inviotan\right)_* \bigotimes_{i = 1}^n \nu\right)\right]}
\] 
where $\iotan$ is a measurable isomorphism $\RR \to \prod_{i =1}^n \RR$,
and $\bigotimes_{i = 1}^n \nu$ is the product measure formed by $n$ copies of $\nu$. 
The name $\iidn$ represents `independent and identically distributed'.
Indeed, $\iidn$ transforms a probability measure $(\beta,\nu)$ on $X$ to the measure of the random sequence in $\Xn$ that independently samples from $(\beta,\nu)$.
The function $\iidn$ is a morphism $\Pmonad(X) \to \Pmonad(\Xn)$ because 
it can also be written in terms of the strength of the monad $\Pmonad$.

Write $(\XI,\qb \XI)$ for the countable product $\prod_{i = 1}^\infty X$.
\begin{definition} 
        A probability measure $(\alpha,\mu)$ on $\XI$ is \emph{exchangeable} 
        if for all permutations $\pi$ on positive integers, 
        \shortversion{
        $[\alpha,\mu] = [\alpha_\pi, \mu]$, 
        where $\alpha_\pi(r)_i \defeq \alpha(r)_{\pi(i)}$ for all $r$ and $i$.
        }
        \longversion{
        \[
                [\alpha,\mu] = [\alpha_\pi, \mu]\text,
        \]
        where $\alpha_\pi(r)_i \defeq \alpha(r)_{\pi(i)}$ for all $r \in \RR$ and $i \geq 1$.
        }
\end{definition}

\newcommand{\projn}[1]{(#1)_{1\dots n}}
\newcommand{\projnname}{\projn{-}}
\begin{theorem}[Weak de Finetti for quasi-Borel spaces]
        \label{thm:deFinetti-qbs}
        If $(\alpha,\mu)$ is an exchangeable probability measure on $\XI$,
        then there exists a probability measure $(\beta,\nu)$ in $\Pmonad(\Pmonad(X))$ such that
        for all $n \geq 1$, the measure $(\bind{[\beta,\nu]} \iidn)$ on $\Pmonad(\Xn)$ equals $\Pmonad(\projnname)(\alpha,\mu)$
        when considered as a measure on the 
        product measurable space $(\Xn,\bigotimes_{i = 1}^n\qbtosig {\qb X})$. 
        (Here $\projnname\colon \XI\to X^n$ is $\projn x\defeq (x_1,\dots,x_n)$.)
\end{theorem}
In the theorem, $(\beta,\nu)$ represents a random variable that has a probability measure on $X$
as its value. The theorem says that (every finite prefix of) a sample sequence from $(\alpha,\mu)$ can be generated
by first sampling a probability measure on~$X$ according to $(\beta,\nu)$, then generating
independent $X$-valued samples from the measure, and finally forming a sequence with these samples.

We call the theorem \emph{weak} for two reasons. First, the $\sigma$-algebra 
$\qbtosig {\qb \Xn}$ includes the product $\sigma$-algebra $\bigotimes_{i = 1}^n \qbtosig {\qb X}$,
but we do not know that they are equal; two different probability 
measures in $\Pmonad(\Xn)$ may induce the same measure on $(\Xn,\bigotimes_{i = 1}^n \qbtosig {\qb X})$,
although they always induce different measures on $(\Xn,\qbtosig {\qb \Xn})$. In the theorem,
we equate such measures, which lets us use a standard
technique for proving the equality of measures on product $\sigma$-algebras. Second, we are unable to
construct a version of $\iidn$ for infinite sequences, i.e.\ a morphism $\Pmonad(X) \to \Pmonad(\XI)$
implementing the independent identically-distributed random sequence. The theorem is stated only for finite prefixes. 

The rest of this section provides an overview of our proof of Theorem~\ref{thm:deFinetti-qbs}.
The starting point is to unpack definitions in the theorem, especially those related to quasi-Borel spaces, and to rewrite the statement of the theorem purely in terms of standard measure-theoretic notions.
\begin{lemma}
        \label{lemma:deFinetti-qbs:paraphrase}
        Let $(\alpha,\mu)$ be an exchangeable probability measure on $\XI$. Then,
        the conclusion of Theorem~\ref{thm:deFinetti-qbs} holds if and only if
        there exist a probability 
        measure $\xi \in G(\RR)$, a measurable function
        $k \colon \RR \to G(\RR)$, and $\gamma \in \qb X$ 
        such that for all $n \geq 1$ and all $U_1,\ldots,U_n \in \qbtosig {\qb X}$,
        \begin{multline*}
                \int_{r \in \RR} \left(\prod_{i=1}^n [\alpha(r)_i \in U_i]\right)\, \dd\mu 
                \\
                {}
                = 
                \int_{r \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^n \left(\int_{s \in \RR} \left[\gamma(s) \in U_i\right] \dd (k(r))\right)\dd\xi\text.  
        \end{multline*}
        Here we express the domain of integration and the integrated variable explicitly to avoid confusion.
\end{lemma}
\shortversion{
\begin{proof}
        Let $(\alpha,\mu)$ be an exchangeable probability measure on~$\XI$. We 
        unpack definitions in the conclusion of Theorem~\ref{thm:deFinetti-qbs}. 
        The first definition to unpack is the notion of probability measure in $\Pmonad(\Pmonad(X))$. 
        Here are the crucial facts that enable this unpacking. First, for every probability measure 
        $(\beta,\nu)$ on $\Pmonad(X)$, there exist a function $\gamma \colon \RR \to X$ in $\qb X$ 
        and a measurable $k \colon \RR \to G(\RR)$ such that $\beta(r) = [\gamma,k(r)]$
        for all $r \in \RR$. Second, conversely, for a function $\gamma \in \qb X$, 
        a measurable $k \colon \RR \to G(\RR)$, and a probability measure $\nu \in G(\RR)$,
        the function $(\lambda r.\,[\gamma,k(r)],\nu)$ 
        is a probability measure in $\Pmonad(\Pmonad(X))$. Thus, we can look for $(\gamma,k,\nu)$ in 
        the conclusion of the theorem instead of $(\beta,\nu)$.  
        
        The second is the definition of $\bind{[\beta,\nu]}{\iidn}$. Using 
        $(\gamma,k,\nu)$ instead of $(\beta,\nu)$, we find that
        $\bind{[\beta,\nu]}\iidn$ is the measure $[(\prod_{i=1}^n\gamma)\circ \iotan,\;(\inviotan)_*\,(\bind\nu{\lambda r.\,\bigotimes_{i=1}^n k(r)})]$. 
        
        Recall that two measures $p$ and $q$ on the product space 
        $(\Xn,\bigotimes_{i = 1}^n X)$ are 
        equivalent when
        $p(U_1\times\cdots\times U_{n})$ equals $q(U_1\times\cdots\times U_{n})$
        for all $U_1,\ldots, U_n\in \qbtosig{\qb X}$. Thus we must show that
        $(\projnname \circ \alpha)_*\mu)(U_1\times\ldots\times U_{n})$ is equal to $\big((\prod_{i = 1}^n\gamma)_*\,(\bind\nu{\lambda r.\,\bigotimes_{i = 1}^nk(r)})\big)(U_1\times\ldots\times U_{n})$. 
        This equation is equivalent to the one in the statement of the lemma with $\xi= \nu$. 
\end{proof}
}
\longversion{
\begin{proof}
        Let $(\alpha,\mu)$ be an exchangeable probability measure on $\XI$. We 
        unpack various definitions in the conclusion of Theorem~\ref{thm:deFinetti-qbs}. 
        This semantics-preserving rewriting and some post-processing will give us 
        the equivalence claimed in the lemma.
        
        The first definition to unpack is the notion of probability measure in $\Pmonad(\Pmonad(X))$. 
        Here are the crucial facts that enable this unpacking. First, for every probability measure 
        $(\beta,\nu)$ on $\Pmonad(X)$, there exist a function $\gamma \colon \RR \to X$ in $\qb X$ 
        and a measurable $k \colon \RR \to G(\RR)$ such that for all $r \in \RR$, 
        \[ 
                \beta(r) = [\gamma,k(r)]\text.  
        \] 
        Second, conversely, for a function $\gamma \colon \RR \to X$ in $\qb X$, 
        a measurable $k \colon \RR \to G(\RR)$, and a probability measure $\nu$ on~$\RR$, 
        \[ 
                (\lambda r.\,[\gamma,k(r)],\nu) 
        \] 
        is a probability measure in $\Pmonad(\Pmonad(X))$. Thus, we can look for $(\gamma,k,\nu)$ in 
        the conclusion of the theorem instead of $(\beta,\nu)$.  
        
        The second is the definition of $\bind{[\beta,\nu]}{\iidn}$. If we do this and use 
        $(\gamma,k,\nu)$ instead of $(\beta,\nu)$, we have
        \begin{multline*} 
                \textstyle{(\bind{[\beta,\nu]}\iidn)}\\
                {} = \textstyle{[(\prod_{i=1}^n\gamma)\circ \iotan,\;(\inviotan)_*\,(\bind\nu{\lambda r.\,\bigotimes_{i=1}^n k(r)})]} 
        \end{multline*}
        
        Now, recall that two measures $p$ and $q$ on the product space 
        $(\Xn,\bigotimes_{i = 1}^n X)$ are 
        equivalent if and only if for all $U_1,\ldots, U_n\in \qbtosig{\qb X}$, 
        \[ 
                \textstyle {p(U_1\times\ldots\times U_{n})} = \textstyle{q(U_1\times\ldots\times U_{n})\text.} 
        \]
        Thus we must show that
        \begin{multline*} 
                \textstyle{(\projnname \circ \alpha)_*\mu)(U_1\times\ldots\times U_{n})} 
                \\ 
                {} = \textstyle{\big((\prod_{i = 1}^n\gamma)_*\,(\bind\nu{\lambda r.\,\bigotimes_{i = 1}^nk(r)})\big)(U_1\times\ldots\times U_{n})} 
        \end{multline*}
        This equation is equivalent to the one in the statement of the lemma,
        where $\xi\defeq \nu$. 
\end{proof}
}

Thus we just need to show how to construct $\xi$, $k$ and $\gamma$ in Lemma~\ref{lemma:deFinetti-qbs:paraphrase}
from a given exchangeable probability measure $(\alpha,\mu)$ on $\XI$.
Constructing $\xi$ and $\gamma$ is easy:
\[
        \xi \defeq \mu,\qquad
        \gamma \defeq \lambda r.\,\alpha(r)_1\text.
\]
Note that these definitions type-check: $\xi = \mu \in G(\RR)$,
and $\gamma \in \qb X$ because $\alpha \in \qb \XI$ and the first projection
$(-)_1$ is a morphism $\XI \to X$. 

Constructing $k$ is not that easy. We need to use the fact that
$\mu$ is defined over $\RR$, a standard Borel space. This fact itself
holds because all probability measures on quasi-Borel spaces use $\RR$
as their source of randomness. Define measurable functions
$\alpha_e,\alpha_o \colon (\RR,\sigalg \RR) \to (\XI,\qbtosig {\qb \XI})$ by
\[
\alpha_e(r)_i \defeq \alpha(r)_{2i}\quad\text{(even),}\qquad
\alpha_o(r)_i \defeq \alpha(r)_{2i-1}\quad\text{(odd)}\text.
\]
Since $\mu$ is a probability measure on $\RR$,  there exists a measurable function
$k' \colon (\XI,\qbtosig {\qb \XI}) \to (G(\RR),\sigalg {G(\RR)})$,
called a conditional probability kernel, such that for all measurable $f \colon \RR \to \RR$
and $U \in \inv{(\alpha_e)}(\qbtosig {\qb \XI})$,
\begin{equation}
        \label{eqn:deFinetti-qbs:0}
        \int_{r \in U} f(r) \,\dd\mu = \int_{r \in U} \left(\int_\RR f \,\dd((k' \circ \alpha_e)(r))\right) \dd\mu\text.
\end{equation}
Define $k \defeq k' \circ \alpha_e$.

Our $\xi$, $k$ and $\gamma$ satisfy the requirement in Lemma~\ref{lemma:deFinetti-qbs:paraphrase}
because of the following three properties, which follow from exchangeability of
$(\alpha,\mu)$.
\begin{lemma} 
        \label{lemma:deFinetti-qbs:odd}
        For all $n \geq 1$ and all $U_1,\ldots,U_n \in \qbtosig {\qb X}$,
        \[
                \int_{r \in \RR} \left(\prod_{i=1}^n [\alpha(r)_i \in U_i]\right)\, \dd\mu 
                =
                \int_{r \in \RR} \left(\prod_{i=1}^n [\alpha_o(r)_i \in U_i]\right)\, \dd\mu \text.
        \]
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
        Consider $n \geq 1$ and $U_1,\ldots,U_n \in \qbtosig {\qb X}$. 
        Pick a permutation $\pi$ on positive integers such that 
        $\pi(i) = 2i-1$ for all integers $1 \leq i \leq n$.
        Then, $[\alpha,\mu] = [\alpha_\pi,\mu]$ 
        by the exchangeability of $(\alpha,\mu)$. Thus
        \begin{align*}
                \int_{r \in \RR} \left(\prod_{i=1}^n [\alpha(r)_i \in U_i]\right) \dd\mu 
                & =
                \int_{r \in \RR} \left(\prod_{i=1}^n [\alpha_\pi(r)_i \in U_i]\right) \dd\mu 
                \text,
\end{align*}
        from which the statement follows.
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma} 
        \label{lemma:deFinetti-qbs:marginal}
        For all $U \in \qbtosig {\qb X}$ and all $i,j \geq 1$,
        \[
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U\right] \dd(k(r)) 
                = 
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_j \in U\right] \dd(k(r))
        \]
        holds for $\mu$-almost all $r \in \RR$.
\end{lemma}
\shortversion{
\begin{proof}
        Consider a measurable set ${U \in \qbtosig {\qb X}}$ and ${i,j \geq 1}$.
        The function ${\lambda r.\;\int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U\right] \dd(k(r))}:{\RR\to \RR}$ is a conditional expectation of the indicator function ${\lambda s.\,[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U]}$
        with respect to the probability measure $\mu$ and the $\sigma$-algebra 
        generated by the measurable function $\alpha_e \colon \RR \to (\XI,\qbtosig {\qb \XI})$.
        By the almost-sure uniqueness of conditional expectation, it suffices to show that
        $\lambda r.\, \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_j \in U\right] \dd(k(r))$
        is also a conditional expectation of $\lambda s.\,[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U]$
        with respect to $\mu$ and $\alpha_e$. Pick a measurable subset $V \in \qbtosig {\qb \XI}$. Then:
        \begin{align*}
                & \int_{r \in \RR} \left[\alpha_e(r) \in V\right] \cdot 
                \left(\int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_j \in U\right] \dd(k(r))\right)
                \dd\mu
                \\
                & \qquad \qquad \qquad {} =
                \int_{r \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(r)_j \in U \wedge \alpha_e(r) \in V\right] \dd\mu
                \\
                & \qquad \qquad \qquad {} =
                \int_{r \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(r)_i \in U \wedge \alpha_e(r) \in V\right] \dd\mu\text.
        \end{align*}
        The first equation holds because the function 
        $\lambda r.\, \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_j \in U\right] \dd(k(r))$ 
        is a conditional expectation of $\lambda s.\,[\alpha_o(s)_j \in U]$ with respect to $\mu$ and $\alpha_e$. 
        The second equation follows from the exchangeability of $(\alpha,\mu)$. We have just shown that 
        $\lambda r.\, \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_j \in U\right] \dd(k(r))$ is a conditional 
        expectation of $\lambda s.\,[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U]$
        with respect to $\mu$ and $\alpha_e$. 
\end{proof}
}
\longversion{
\begin{proof}
        Consider a measurable subset $U \in \qbtosig {\qb X}$ and $i,j \geq 1$.
        We remind the reader that when viewed as a function on $r \in \RR$,
        \[
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U\right] \dd(k(r)) 
        \]
        is a conditional expectation of the indicator function $\lambda s.\,[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U]$
        with respect to the measure $\mu$ and the $\sigma$-algebra 
        generated by the measurable function $\alpha_e \colon \RR \to (\XI,\qbtosig {\qb \XI})$.
        By the almost-sure uniqueness of conditional expectation, it suffices to show that
        \[ 
                \lambda r.\, \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_j \in U\right] \dd(k(r))
        \]
        is also a conditional expectation of $\lambda s.\,[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U]$
        with respect to $\mu$ and $\alpha_e$. Pick a measurable subset $V \in \qbtosig {\qb \XI}$. Then,
        \begin{align*}
                & \int_{r \in \RR} \left[\alpha_e(r) \in V\right] \cdot 
                \left(\int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_j \in U\right] \dd(k(r))\right)
                \dd\mu
                \\
                & \qquad \qquad \qquad {} =
                \int_{r \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(r)_j \in U \wedge \alpha_e(r) \in V\right] \dd\mu
                \\
                & \qquad \qquad \qquad {} =
                \int_{r \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(r)_i \in U \wedge \alpha_e(r) \in V\right] \dd\mu\text.
        \end{align*}
        The first equation holds because the function
        \[
                \lambda r.\, \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_j \in U\right] \dd(k(r)) 
        \]
        is a conditional expectation of $\lambda s.\,[\alpha_o(s)_j \in U]$ with respect to $\mu$ and $\alpha_e$. 
        The second equation follows from the exchangeability of $(\alpha,\mu)$. We have just shown that 
        $\lambda r.\, \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_j \in U\right] \dd(k(r))$ is a conditional 
        expectation of $\lambda s.\,[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U]$
        with respect to $\mu$ and $\alpha_e$. 
\end{proof}
}
\begin{lemma} 
        \label{lemma:deFinetti-qbs:independence}
        For all $n \geq 1$ and all $U_1,\ldots,U_n \in \qbtosig {\qb X}$, 
        \begin{multline*}
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left(\prod_{i = 1}^n\left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right]\right) \dd(k(r)) 
                \\
                {}
                = 
                \prod_{i = 1}^n \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))
        \end{multline*}
        holds for $\mu$-almost all $r \in \RR$. 
\end{lemma} 
\shortversion{
\begin{proof}[Proof notes]
Use induction on $n \geq 1$. There is nothing to
        prove for the base case $n = 1$. To handle the inductive case, assume that $n > 1$.
        Let $U_1,\ldots,U_n$ be subsets in $\qbtosig {\qb X}$.
        Define a function $\alpha' \colon \RR \to \XI$ as follows:
        \[
                \alpha'(r)_i = 
                \left\{\begin{array}{ll}
                        \alpha_o(r)_i & \mbox{if $1 \leq i \leq n-1$}
                        \\
                        \alpha_e(r)_{i-n+1} & \mbox{otherwise.}
                \end{array}\right.
        \]
        Then, $\alpha'$ is in $\qb \XI$, so that $\alpha'$ is a measurable
        function $(\RR,\sigalg \RR) \to (\XI,\sigalg {\qb \XI})$. Thus there exists a measurable 
        $k'_0 \colon (\XI,\qbtosig {\qb \XI}) \to (G(\RR),\sigalg {G(\RR)})$, the
        conditional probability kernel, such that
        for all measurable functions $f \colon \RR \to \RR$, 
        $\lambda r.\, \int_\RR f \,\dd((k'_0 \circ \alpha')(r))$
        is a conditional expectation of $f$ with respect to $\mu$
        and the $\sigma$-algebra generated by~$\alpha'$.  
        Define $k' \colon \RR \to G(\RR) = k'_0 \circ \alpha'$.
        Then $k'$ is measurable because so are $k'_0$ and $\alpha'$. 
        More importantly, for $\mu$-almost all $r \in \RR$, 
        \begin{equation}
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k(r))
                =
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k'(r))\text.
                \label{eqn:deFinetti:3}
        \end{equation}
        The proof of this equality appears in the full version of this paper.
        
        Recall that $k = k_0 \circ \alpha_e$ and $k' = k'_0 \circ \alpha'$ are 
        defined in terms of conditional expectation. Thus, they inherit all the properties
        of conditional expectation. In particular, 
        for $\mu$-almost all $r \in \RR$
        and all measurable $h \colon \RR \to \RR$,
        \begin{align}
                \begin{split}
                & \int_{s \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^{n} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))
                \\
                & \quad {}=
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left(\int_{t \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^{n} \left[\alpha_o(t)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k'(s))\right) 
                \dd(k(r))\text,
                \end{split}
                \label{eqn:deFinetti:4}
                \\[1ex]
                \begin{split}
                & \int_{s \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^{n} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k'(r))
                \\
                & \quad {}=
                \prod_{i = 1}^{n-1} \left[\alpha_o(r)_i \in U_i\right]
                \cdot
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k'(r))\text,
                \end{split}
                \label{eqn:deFinetti:5}
                \\[1ex]
                \begin{split}
                & \int_{s \in \RR} \left(h(s)
                \cdot \int_{t \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(t)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k(s))\right)
                \dd(k(r))
                \\
                & \quad {}=
                \left(\int_{t \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(t)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k(r))\right)
                \cdot 
                \left(\int_{s \in \RR} h(s)\, \dd(k(r))\right)\text.
                \end{split}
                \label{eqn:deFinetti:6}
        \end{align}
        Using the assumption \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:3}
        and the properties \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:4}, \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:5} and \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:6},
        we complete the proof of the inductive case as follows: 
        for all subsets $V \in \inv{(\alpha_e)}(\qbtosig {\qb \XI})$,
        \begin{align*}
                &
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{s \in \RR} 
                \prod_{i = 1}^{n} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))\,\dd\mu
                \\
                &
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{s \in \RR} 
                \int_{t \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^{n} \left[\alpha_o(t)_i \in U_i\right] 
                \dd(k'(s))\,\dd(k(r))\,\dd\mu
                \\
                &
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{s \in \RR}
                \prod_{i = 1}^{n-1} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right]
                \\*
                &
                \phantom{{} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{s \in \RR}}
                {} \cdot
                \int_{t\in\RR} \left[\alpha_o(t)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k'(s))\,
                \dd(k(r))\,
                \dd\mu
                \\
                &
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{s \in \RR}
                \prod_{i = 1}^{n-1} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right]
                \\*
                &
                \phantom{
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{s \in \RR}}
                {}\cdot
                \int_{t \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(t)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k(s))\,\dd(k(r))\,\dd\mu
                \\
                &
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \left(\int_{t \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(t)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k(r))\right)
                \\*
                &
                \phantom{
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}}
                {}
                \cdot
                \left(\int_{s \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^{n-1} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))\right)\,
                \dd\mu
                \\
                &
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \prod_{i = 1}^n \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] 
                \dd(k(r))\,\dd\mu\text.
        \end{align*}
        The first and the second equalities hold because of \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:4} and \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:5}.
        The third equality uses \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:3}, and the fourth the equality 
        in \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:6}. The fifth follows from the induction hypothesis. Our derivation
        implies that both
                $\lambda r.\,\int_{s \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^{n} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))$
                and
                $\lambda r.\,\prod_{i = 1}^n \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))$
        are conditional expectations of the same function with respect to $\mu$ and the same $\sigma$-algebra.
        So, they are equal for $\mu$-almost all inputs~$r$.
\end{proof}
}
\longversion{
\begin{proof}
        We prove the lemma by induction on $n \geq 1$. There is nothing to
        prove for the base case $n = 1$. To handle the inductive case, assume that $n > 1$.
        Let $U_1,\ldots,U_n$ be subsets in $\qbtosig {\qb X}$.
        Define a function $\alpha' \colon \RR \to \XI$ as follows:
        \[
                \alpha'(r)_i = 
                \left\{\begin{array}{ll}
                        \alpha_o(r)_i & \mbox{if $1 \leq i \leq n-1$}
                        \\
                        \alpha_e(r)_{i-n+1} & \mbox{otherwise.}
                \end{array}\right.
        \]
        Then, $\alpha'$ is in $\qb \XI$, so that $\alpha'$ is a measurable
        function $(\RR,\sigalg \RR) \to (\XI,\sigalg {\qb \XI})$. Thus, there exists a measurable 
        $k'_0 \colon (\XI,\qbtosig {\qb \XI}) \to (G(\RR),\sigalg {G(\RR)})$, called
        conditional probability kernel, such that
        for all measurable $f \colon \RR \to \RR$,
        \[
                \lambda r.\, \int_\RR f \,\dd((k'_0 \circ \alpha')(r))
        \]
        is a conditional expectation of $f$ with respect to $\mu$
        and the $\sigma$-algebra generated by $\alpha'$.  Let
        \begin{align*}
                k' & \colon \RR \to G(\RR)
                \\
                k' & = k'_0 \circ \alpha'\text.
        \end{align*}
        The function $k'$ is measurable because so are $k'_0$ and $\alpha'$. 
        At the end of this proof, we will show that for $\mu$-almost all $r \in \RR$, 
        \begin{multline}
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k(r))
                \\
                =
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k'(r))\text.
                \label{eqn:deFinetti:3}
        \end{multline}
        For now, just assume that this equation holds and see how this assumption lets
        us complete the proof. 
        
        Recall that $k = k_0 \circ \alpha_e$ and $k' = k'_0 \circ \alpha'$ are 
        defined in terms of conditional expectation. Thus, they inherit all the properties
        of conditional expectation after minor adjustment. In particular, 
        since the $\sigma$-algebra generated by $\alpha'$ is larger than the one
        generated by $\alpha_e$ and it makes $\alpha_i$ measurable for all $1 \leq i \leq (n-1)$,
        we have the following equalities: for $\mu$-almost all $r \in \RR$
        and all measurable functions $h \colon \RR \to \RR$,
        \begin{multline}
                \int_{s \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^{n} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))
                \\
                =
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left(\int_{t \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^{n} \left[\alpha_o(t)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k'(s))\right) 
                \dd(k(r))\text,
                \label{eqn:deFinetti:4}
        \end{multline}
        \begin{multline}
                \int_{s \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^{n} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k'(r))
                \\
                =
                \prod_{i = 1}^{n-1} \left[\alpha_o(r)_i \in U_i\right]
                \cdot
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k'(r))\text,
                \label{eqn:deFinetti:5}
        \end{multline}
        \begin{multline}
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left(h(s)
                \cdot \int_{t \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(t)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k(s))\right)
                \dd(k(r))
                \\
                =
                \left(\int_{t \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(t)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k(r))\right)
                \cdot 
                \left(\int_{s \in \RR} h(s)\, \dd(k(r))\right)\text.
                \label{eqn:deFinetti:6}
        \end{multline}
        Using the assumption \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:3}
        and the properties \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:4}, \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:5} and \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:6},
        we complete the proof of the inductive case as follows: 
        for all subsets $V \in \inv{(\alpha_e)}(\qbtosig {\qb \XI})$,
        \begin{align*}
                &
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{s \in \RR} 
                \prod_{i = 1}^{n} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))\,\dd\mu
                \\
                &
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{s \in \RR} 
                \int_{t \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^{n} \left[\alpha_o(t)_i \in U_i\right] 
                \dd(k'(s))\,\dd(k(r))\,\dd\mu
                \\
                &
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{s \in \RR}
                \prod_{i = 1}^{n-1} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right]
                \\
                &
                \phantom{{} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{s \in \RR}}
                {} \cdot
                \int_{t\in\RR} \left[\alpha_o(t)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k'(s))\,
                \dd(k(r))\,
                \dd\mu
                \\
                &
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{s \in \RR}
                \prod_{i = 1}^{n-1} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right]
                \\
                &
                \phantom{
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{s \in \RR}}
                {}\cdot
                \int_{t \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(t)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k(s))\,\dd(k(r))\,\dd\mu
                \\
                &
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \left(\int_{t \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(t)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k(r))\right)
                \\
                &
                \phantom{
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}}
                {}
                \cdot
                \left(\int_{s \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^{n-1} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))\right)\,
                \dd\mu
                \\
                &
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \int_{t \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(t)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k(r))
                \\
                &
                \phantom{{} = \int_{r \in V}}
                {}\cdot
                \prod_{i = 1}^{n-1} \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))\,
                \dd\mu
                \\
                &
                {} =
                \int_{r \in V}
                \prod_{i = 1}^n \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] 
                \dd(k(r))\,\dd\mu\text.
        \end{align*}
        The first and the second equalities hold because of \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:4} and \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:5}.
        The third equality uses our assumption in \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:3}, and the fourth the equality 
        in \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:6}. The fifth equality follows from the induction hypothesis. Our derivation
        implies that both
        \begin{align*}
                & \lambda r.\,\int_{s \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^{n} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))
                \\
                & \mbox{and}\quad
                \lambda r.\,\prod_{i = 1}^n \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))
        \end{align*}
        are conditional expectations of the same function with respect to $\mu$ and the same $\sigma$-algebra.
        Thus, they are equal for $\mu$-almost all inputs $r \in \RR$.

        It remains to show that the equality in \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:3} holds for $\mu$-almost all $r \in \RR$. 
        Define two functions $h, h' \colon \RR \to \RR$ as follows:
        \begin{align*}
                h(r) & = \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k(r))\text,
                \\
                h'(r) & = \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n\right] \dd(k'(r))\text.
        \end{align*}
        Let $\Sigma$ and $\Sigma'$ be the $\sigma$-algebras generated by $\alpha_e$ and $\alpha'$, respectively.
        Then, $\Sigma \subseteq \Sigma'$, the function $h$ is $\Sigma$-measurable and bounded, 
        and $h'$ is $\Sigma'$-measurable and bounded. Let 
        $L^2(\RR,\Sigma',\mu)$ be the Hilbert space of the equivalence classes of
        square integrable functions that are $\Sigma'$-measurable.
        Let $M$ be the subspace of $L^2(\RR,\Sigma',\mu)$ consisting of the equivalence
        classes of some square-integrable and $\Sigma$-measurable functions. Then, 
        \[
                [h] \in M
                \quad\mbox{and}\quad
                [h'] \in L^2(\RR,\Sigma',\mu)\text,
        \]
        where $[h]$ and $[h']$ are equivalence classes of $L^2(\RR,\Sigma',\mu)$. Furthermore, $[h]$ is 
        the projection of $[h']$ to the subspace $M$, because $h$ and
        $h'$ are conditional expectations of the same bounded function with respect to $\mu$. 
        Thus, when $\Vert {-} \Vert_2$ is the $L^2$ norm with respect to the probability measure $\mu$,
        \[
                \Vert h \Vert_2 \leq \Vert h' \Vert_2\text.
        \]
        The equality holds here if and only if $[h] = [h']$, i.e.~$h$ and $h'$ are equal except at some $\mu$-null
        set in $\Sigma'$. So, it is sufficient to prove that $\Vert h \Vert_2 = \Vert h' \Vert_2$. We
        rewrite $\Vert h \Vert^2_2$ as follows:
        \begin{align*}
                & \Vert h \Vert^2_2 
                \\
                & = \int_\RR h^2 \dd\mu
                \\
                & = \int_{r \in \RR} \left(\int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n \right] \dd(k(r))\right)^2 \dd\mu
                \\
                & = \int_{r \in \RR} \left(\int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n \right] \dd((k_0 \circ \alpha_e)(r))\right)^2 \dd\mu
                \\
                & = \int_{u \in \XI} \left(\int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n \right] \dd(k_0(u))\right)^2 
                \dd\left((\alpha_e)_*(\mu)\right)
                \\
                & = \int_{u \in \XI} \left(\int_{x \in X} \left[x \in U_n \right] \dd\left((\alpha_o(-)_n)_*(k_0(u))\right)\right)^2 
                \\
                & \phantom{= \int_{u \in \XI} \left(\right)}
                \dd\left((\alpha_e)_*(\mu)\right)
                \\
                & = \int_{(x_0,u) \in X \times \XI} \left(\int_{x \in X} \left[x \in U_n \right] \dd\left((\alpha_o(-)_n)_*(k_0(u))\right)\right)^2 
                \\
                & \phantom{= \int_{u \in \XI} \left(\right)}
                \qquad\qquad
                \dd\left((\alpha_o(-)_n,\alpha_e)_*(\mu)\right)\text.
        \end{align*}
        At the last line, $X \times \XI$ denotes the product measurable space
        $(X \times \XI, \qbtosig {\qb X}\otimes \qbtosig {\qb \XI})$. A similar rewriting gives
        \begin{align*}
                & \Vert h' \Vert^2_2 =
                \\
                & \quad \int_{(x_0,u) \in X \times \XI} \left(\int_{x \in X} \left[x \in U_n \right] \dd\left((\alpha_o(-)_n)_*(k_0'(u))\right)\right)^2 
                \\
                & \phantom{= \int_{u \in \XI} \left(\right)} 
                \qquad\qquad
                \dd\left((\alpha_o(-)_n,\alpha'_e)_*(\mu)\right)\text.
        \end{align*}
        By the exchangeability of $(\alpha,\mu)$, 
        \begin{equation}
                \label{eqn:deFinetti:6.5}
                (\alpha_o(-)_n,\alpha_e)_*(\mu) = (\alpha_o(-)_n,\alpha')_*(\mu)
        \end{equation}
        as probability measures on $(X \times \XI,\qbtosig {\qb {(X \times \XI)}})$.
        This equality continues to hold when its LHS and RHS are viewed as
        probability measures on $(X \times \XI, \qbtosig {\qb X} \otimes \qbtosig {\qb \XI})$. 
        Then, the following functions from $X \times \XI$ to $\RR$:
        \begin{align}
                & \lambda (x_0,u).\, \int_{x \in X} \left[x \in U_n \right] \dd\left((\alpha_o(-)_n)_*(k_0(u))\right)
                \label{eqn:deFinetti:7}
                \\
                & \mbox{and}\quad
                \lambda (x_0,u).\, 
                \int_{x \in X} \left[x \in U_n \right] \dd\left((\alpha_o(-)_n)_*(k_0'(u))\right)
                \label{eqn:deFinetti:8}
        \end{align}
        are conditional expectations of $\lambda (x,u).\,[x \in U_n]$ with respect to 
        $(\alpha_o(-)_n,\alpha_e)_*(\mu)$ on $(X \times \XI,\qbtosig {\qb X} \otimes \qbtosig {\qb \XI})$
        and the $\sigma$-algebra generated by the projection $\lambda (x,u).\,u$. This is because
        $k_0$ and $k'_0$ are appropriate conditional probability kernels. Concretely,
        for all $U \in \qbtosig {\qb \XI}$, we can show that
        \begin{align*}
                & \int_{(x_0,u) \in X \times U} 
                \int_{x \in X} \left[x \in U_n \right] \dd((\alpha_o(-)_n)_*(k_0(u)))
                \\
                & \phantom{\int_{(x_0,u) \in X \times U} 
                \int_{x \in X} \left[x \in U_n \right]}
                \quad
                \dd((\alpha_o(-)_n,\alpha_e)_*(\mu))
                \\
                & =
                \int_{u \in U} 
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n \right] \dd(k_0(u))\,\dd((\alpha_e)_*(\mu))
                \\
                & =
                \int_{r \in \inv{\alpha}_e(U)} 
                \int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_n \in U_n \right] \dd((k_0 \circ \alpha_e)(u))\,\dd\mu
                \\
                & =
                \int_{r \in \inv{\alpha}_e(U)} 
                \left[\alpha_o(r)_n \in U_n \right] \dd\mu\text.
        \end{align*}
        By similar reasoning and the equation in \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:6.5},
        \begin{align*}
                & \int_{(x_0,u) \in X \times U} 
                \int_{x \in X} \left[x \in U_n \right] \dd((\alpha_o(-)_n)_*(k'_0(u)))
                \\
                & \phantom{\int_{(x_0,u) \in X \times U} 
                \int_{x \in X} \left[x \in U_n \right]}
                \quad
                \dd((\alpha_o(-)_n,\alpha)_*(\mu))
                \\
                & = \int_{(x_0,u) \in X \times U} 
                \int_{x \in X} \left[x \in U_n \right] \dd((\alpha_o(-)_n)_*(k'_0(u)))
                \\
                & \phantom{\int_{(x_0,u) \in X \times U} 
                \int_{x \in X} \left[x \in U_n \right]}
                \quad
                \dd((\alpha_o(-)_n,\alpha')_*(\mu))
                \\
                & =
                \int_{r \in \inv{\alpha}_e(U)} 
                \left[\alpha_o(r)_n \in U_n \right] \dd\mu\text.
        \end{align*}
        The outcomes of these calculations imply that
        the functions in \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:7} and \eqref{eqn:deFinetti:8}
        are the claimed conditional expectations. Thus, these functions 
        are equal for $(\alpha_o(-)_n,\alpha_e)_*(\mu)$-almost all $(x_0,u)$. From this it follows that
        $\Vert h \Vert_2^2 = \Vert h' \Vert_2^2$, as desired.
\end{proof}
}
The following calculation combines these lemmas and shows that $\xi$, $k$ and $\gamma$ 
satisfy the requirement in Lemma~\ref{lemma:deFinetti-qbs:paraphrase}: 
\begin{align*} 
        & \int_{r \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^n \left[\alpha(r)_i \in U_i\right] \dd\mu
        \\ 
        &
        = \int_{r \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^n \left[\alpha_o(r)_i \in U_i\right] \dd\mu 
        & \mbox{Lem.~\ref{lemma:deFinetti-qbs:odd}}
        \\ 
        &
        = \int_{r \in \RR} \left(\int_{s \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^n \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))\right)\dd\mu 
        & \mbox{Eq.~\eqref{eqn:deFinetti-qbs:0}}
        \\
        &
        = \int_{r \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^n \left(\int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_i \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))\right) \dd\mu 
        & \mbox{Lem.~\ref{lemma:deFinetti-qbs:independence}}
        \\ 
        &
        = \int_{r \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^n \left(\int_{s \in \RR} \left[\alpha_o(s)_1 \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))\right) \dd\mu 
        & \mbox{Lem.~\ref{lemma:deFinetti-qbs:marginal}}
        \\ 
        &
        = \int_{r \in \RR} \prod_{i = 1}^n \left(\int_{s \in \RR} \left[\gamma(s) \in U_i\right] \dd(k(r))\right) \dd\xi
        & \mbox{Def. of $\gamma,\xi$}\text.  
\end{align*}
This concludes our proof outline for Theorem~\ref{thm:deFinetti-qbs}.
 
\section{Related work}\label{sec:related}


\subsection{Quasi-topological spaces and categories of functors}


Our development of a cartesian closed category from measurable spaces mirrors the development of cartesian closed categories of topological spaces
over the years. 

For example, quasi-Borel spaces are reminiscent of \emph{subsequential spaces}~\cite{johnstone-topological-topos}: a set $X$ together with a collection of functions $Q\subseteq {[\NN\cup \{\infty\}\to X]}$ satisfying some conditions. 
The functions in  $Q$ are thought of as convergent sequences.
Another notion of generalized topological space is \emph{C-space}~\cite{xu-escardo}: a set~$X$ together with a collection $Q\subseteq [2^\NN\to X]$
of `probes' satisfying some conditions;
this is a variation on Spanier's early notion of \emph{quasi-topological space}~\cite{spanier:quasitopologies}.
Another reminiscent notion in the context of differential geometry is a \emph{diffeological space}~\cite{bh-convenient}:
a set $X$ together with a set $Q_U\subseteq [U\to X]$ of `plots' for each open subset $U$ of $\RR^n$ satisfying some conditions.
These examples all form cartesian closed categories. 

A common pattern is that these spaces can be understood as extensional (concrete) sheaves 
on an established category of spaces. 
Let $\SMeas$ be the category of standard Borel spaces and measurable functions.
There is a functor
\shortversion{
  $J\colon \QBS\to[\op\SMeas,\Set]$
}
\longversion{
\[
  J\colon \QBS\to[\op\SMeas,\Set]
\]
}
with $\big(J(X,\qb X))(Y,\sigalg Y\big)\defeq \QBS\big((Y,\sigtoqb{\sigalg Y}),(X,\qb X)\big)$,
which is full and faithful by Prop.~\ref{prop:adjunction}(2).
We can characterize those functors that arise in this way.
\begin{proposition}\label{prop:extensionalpresheaf}
  Let $F\colon\op\SMeas\to\Set$ be a functor.
  The following are equivalent:
  \begin{itemize}
  \item $F$ is naturally isomorphic to $J(X,\qb X)$, for some quasi-Borel space $(X,\qb X)$;
  \item $F$ preserves countable products and $F$ is extensional: the functions $i_{(X,\sigalg X)}\colon F(X,\sigalg X)\to\Set(X,F(1))$ are injective, where $(i_{(X,\sigalg X)}(\xi))(x)=(F(\ulcorner x\urcorner))(\xi)$, and we consider $x\in X$ as a function $\ulcorner x\urcorner \colon 1\to X$. 
  \end{itemize}
\end{proposition}

There are similar characterizations of subsequential spaces~\cite{johnstone-topological-topos}, quasi-topological spaces~\cite{dubuc-concrete-quasitopoi} and diffeological spaces~\cite{bh-convenient}. Prop.~\ref{prop:extensionalpresheaf}
is an instance of a general pattern (e.g.~\cite{bh-convenient,dubuc-concrete-quasitopoi});
but that is not to say that the definition of quasi-Borel space (Def.~\ref{def:qbs})
arises automatically.
The method of 
extensional presheaves also arises in other models of computation
such as finiteness spaces~\cite{ehrhard-extensional} and realizability models~\cite{rosolini-streicher}. 
This work appears to be the first application to probability theory, 
although via Prop.~\ref{prop:extensionalpresheaf} there are connections 
to Simpson's probability sheaves~\cite{simpson-cippmi}.

The characterization of Prop.~\ref{prop:extensionalpresheaf} gives a canonical categorical status to quasi-Borel spaces.
It also connects with our earlier work~\cite{statonyangheunenkammarwood:higherorder}, which used the cartesian closed category of countable-product-preserving functors
in $[\op\SMeas, \Set]$.
Quasi-Borel spaces have several advantages over this functor category. 
For one thing, they are more concrete, leading
to better intuitions for their constructions. For example, measures in~\cite{statonyangheunenkammarwood:higherorder} are built abstractly from left Kan extensions, whereas for quasi-Borel spaces they have a straightforward concrete definition (Def.~\ref{def:probabilitymeasure}). 
For another thing, in contrast to the functor category in~\cite{statonyangheunenkammarwood:higherorder}, quasi-Borel spaces form a well-pointed category:
if two morphisms $(X,\qb X)\to (Y,\qb Y)$ are different
then they disagree on some point in $X$.
From the perspective of semantics of programming languages, 
where terms in context $\Gamma\vdash t :A$ are interpreted as morphisms
$\denot t \colon \denot \Gamma\to\denot A$, well-pointedness is a crucial property.
It says that if two open terms
are different, $\denot t\neq \denot u:\denot \Gamma\to\denot A$, 
then there is a ground context $\mathcal C \colon 1\to\denot \Gamma$ that 
distinguishes them: $\denot{\mathcal C[t]}\neq \denot{\mathcal C[u]}:1\to \denot A$. 

Quasi-Borel spaces add objects to make the category of measurable spaces cartesian closed. Another interesting future direction is to add morphisms to make more objects isomorphic, and so find a cartesian closed subcategory~\cite{steenrod:convenient}.


 \subsection{Domains and valuations}
In this paper our starting point has been the standard foundation for probability theory, 
based on $\sigma$-algebras and probability measures. 
An alternative foundation for probability is based on topologies and valuations. 
An advantage of our starting point is that we can reference the canon of work on
probability theory. Having said this, an advantage to the approach based on valuations
is that it is related to domain theoretic methods, which have already been used to 
give semantics to programming languages. 

Jones and Plotkin~\cite{jones-plotkin} showed that valuations form a monad which is 
analogous to our probability monad. However, there is considerable debate
about which cartesian closed category this monad should be based on~(e.g.~\cite{jung-tix,gl-qrb-domains}).
For a discussion of the concerns in the context of programming languages, see e.g.~\cite{escardo-high-type-prob-testing}. 
One recent proposal is to use Girard's probabilistic coherence spaces~\cite{etp-pcoh}.
Another is to use a topological domain theory as a cartesian closed category for analysis and probability~(\cite{bss-convenient-domains,pape-streicher,huang-morrisett}). 

Concerns about probabilistic powerdomains have led instead to domains of random variables~(e.g.~\cite{mislove-randvar,barker-monad,scott-stochastic}). 
We cannot yet connect formally with this work, but there are many intuitive links. For example, our measures on quasi-Borel spaces (Def.~\ref{def:probabilitymeasure}) are reminiscent of continuous random variables on a dcpo.

An additional advantage of a domain theoretic approach is that it naturally  
supports recursion. We are currently investigating a notion of `ordered quasi-Borel
space', by enriching Prop.~\ref{prop:extensionalpresheaf} over dcpo's.

 \subsection{Other related work}
Our work is related to two recent semantic studies on probabilistic 
programming languages. The first is Borgstr\"om et al.'s \emph{operational} (not denotational as
in this paper) semantics for
a higher-order probabilistic programming language with continuous 
distributions~\cite{blgs-lambda-prob-untyped},
which has been used to justify a basic inference algorithm for the language. 
Recently, Culpepper and Cobb refined 
this operational approach using logical relations~\cite{Culpepper-esop17}. The second study is Freer 
and Roy's results on a computable variant of de Finetti's theorem and its implication 
on exchangeable random processes implemented in
higher-order probabilistic programming languages~\cite{FreerR12}. One interesting future direction is 
to revisit the results about logical relations and computability in these studies with quasi-Borel spaces,
and to see whether they can be extended to spaces other than standard Borel spaces.
 
 
\section{Conclusion}\label{sec:conclusion}


We have shown that quasi-Borel spaces (\S\ref{sec:quasiborel})
support higher-order functions (\S\ref{sec:structure}) 
as well as spaces of probability measures (\S\ref{sec:giry}). 
We have illustrated the power of this new formalism by
giving a semantic analysis of Bayesian regression (\S\ref{sec:example}),
by rephrasing the randomization lemma as a quotient-space construction (\S\ref{sec:functions}),
and by showing that it supports de Finetti's theorem (\S\ref{sec:definetti}).



 
\shortversion{
\section*{Acknowledgment}
We thank Radha Jagadeesan and Dexter Kozen for encouraging us to think about a well-pointed cartesian closed category for probability theory, Vincent Danos and Dan Roy for nudging us to work on de Finetti's theorem, Mike Mislove for discussions of quasi-Borel spaces, and Martin Escard\'o for explaining C-spaces, and Alex Simpson for detailed report with many suggestions. This research was supported by a Royal Society Research Fellowship and EPSRC grants EP/L002388/2 and EP/N007387/1, and also by Institute for Information \& communications Technology Promotion (IITP) grant funded by the Korea government (MSIP) (No.R0190-16-2011, Development of Vulnerability Discovery Technologies for IoT Software Security). 
}
\longversion{
\section*{Acknowledgment}
We thank Radha Jagadeesan and Dexter Kozen for encouraging us to think about a well-pointed cartesian closed category for probability theory, Vincent Danos and Dan Roy for nudging us to work on de Finetti's theorem, Mike Mislove for discussions of quasi-Borel spaces, Martin Escard\'o for explaining C-spaces, and Alex Simpson for detailed report with many suggestions. This research was supported by a Royal Society Research Fellowship and EPSRC grants EP/L002388/2 and EP/N007387/1, and also by an Institute for Information \& communications Technology Promotion (IITP) grant funded by the Korea government (MSIP) (No.R0190-16-2011, Development of Vulnerability Discovery Technologies for IoT Software Security). 
}




\bibliographystyle{IEEEtranS}
\bibliography{lics2017}
\end{document}