|
|
|
\documentclass[MSNbibl,nameyear,dvips]{arxstspdf} |
|
\usepackage{tikz} |
|
\usepackage{graphicx} |
|
\usepackage{flushend} |
|
\usepackage{stfloats} |
|
|
|
|
|
\volume{29} |
|
\issue{3} |
|
\pubyear{2014} |
|
\firstpage{363} |
|
\lastpage{366} |
|
\doi{10.1214/14-STS485} \referstodoi{10.1214/14-STS480}\docsubty{FLA} |
|
|
|
\makeatletter |
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand{\lleft}{\left} |
|
\newcommand{\rright}{\right} |
|
|
|
\newcommand{\ind}{\mbox{$\,\perp\kern-5.5pt \perp\,$}} |
|
|
|
|
|
\renewcommand{\citep}[1]{(\citeauthor{#1}, \citeyear{#1})} |
|
\newcommand{\citepp}[1]{\citeauthor{#1}, \citeyear{#1}} |
|
|
|
\makeatother |
|
|
|
\begin{document} |
|
\begin{frontmatter} |
|
|
|
\vspace*{12pt}\title{ACE Bounds; SEMs with Equilibrium Conditions} |
|
\runtitle{ACE Bounds; SEMS with Equilibrium Conditions} |
|
\begin{aug} |
|
\author[a]{\fnms{Thomas S.} \snm{Richardson}\ead[label=e1]{thomasr@uw.edu}} |
|
\and |
|
\author[b]{\fnms{James M.} \snm{Robins}\ead[label=e2]{robins@hsph.harvard.edu}} |
|
|
|
\runauthor{T. S. Richardson and J. M. Robins} |
|
|
|
\affiliation{University of Washington and Harvard School of Public Health} |
|
|
|
\address[a]{Thomas S. Richardson is Professor and Chair, Department of Statistics, University of Washington, |
|
Box 354322, Seattle, Washington 98195, USA \printead{e1}.} |
|
|
|
\address[b]{James M. Robins is Mitchell L. and Robin LaFoley Dong Professor, |
|
Department of Epidemiology, Harvard School of |
|
Public Health, |
|
677 Huntington Avenue, Boston, Massachusetts 02115, USA \printead{e2}.} |
|
\end{aug} |
|
|
|
|
|
\end{frontmatter} |
|
|
|
We congratulate the author on an enlightening account of |
|
the instrumental variable approach from the viewpoint of Econometrics. |
|
We first make some comments regarding the bounds on the ACE under the |
|
nonparametric IV model, |
|
and then discuss potential outcomes in the market equilibrium model. |
|
|
|
\section{ACE Bounds Under the IV Model} |
|
We consider the model in which $X$ and $Y$ are binary, taking values in |
|
$\{0,1\}$, while |
|
$Z$ takes $K$ states $\{1,\ldots,K\}$. We use the notation $X(z_i)$ to indicate |
|
$X(z = i)$, similarly $Y(x_j)$ for $Y(x = j)$. We consider four |
|
different sets of assumptions: |
|
\begin{longlist}[(iii)] |
|
\item[(i)] $Z \ind Y({x}_0),Y({x}_1), X({z}_1),\ldots,X({z}_{K})$; |
|
\item[(ii)] $Z \ind Y({x}_0),Y({x}_1)$; |
|
\item[(iii)] for $i \in\{1,\ldots,K\}$, $j \in\{0,1\}$, $Z \ind |
|
X(z_i),\linebreak[4] Y(x_j)$; |
|
\item[(iv)] there exists a $U$ such that $U \ind Z$ and for $j \in\{ |
|
0,1\}$, $Y(x_j) \ind X,Z \mid U$. |
|
\end{longlist} |
|
Condition (i) is joint independence of $Z$ and all potential outcomes |
|
for $Y$ and $X$. (ii) does not assume independence (or existence) |
|
of counterfactuals for $X$. |
|
(iii)~is a subset of the independences in (i), none of which involve |
|
potential outcomes from different worlds.\footnote{In other words, |
|
they do not involve both $Y(x_0)$ and $Y(x_1)$, nor $X(z_i)$ and |
|
$X(z_j$) for $i\neq j$.} |
|
The counterfactual independencies (i), (ii), (iii) arise most naturally |
|
in the context |
|
where the instrument is randomized, as depicted by the DAG in Figure~\ref{figswig}(a). |
|
Assumption (iii) may be read (via d-separation) from the Single-World |
|
Intervention Graph (SWIG)\footnote{See \citet{richardsonrobins2013} |
|
for details.} |
|
$\mathcal{G}_1(z,x)$, depicted in Figure~\ref{figswig}(b), which |
|
represents the factorization of $P(Z,X(z),Y(x),U)$, implied by the IV model. |
|
|
|
Lastly (iv) consists of only three independence statements, but does |
|
assume the existence of an unobserved variable $U$ that |
|
is sufficient to control for confounding between $X$ and $Y$. No |
|
assumption is made concerning the existence of counterfactuals |
|
$X(z)$; confounding variables ($U^*$) between $Z$ and $X$ are permitted |
|
(so long as $U^* \ind U$). The DAG $\mathcal{G}_2$ and |
|
corresponding SWIG $\mathcal{G}_2(x)$ are shown in Figure~\ref{figswig}(c), (d). In \citet{richardsonrobins2014}, we prove the following. |
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{thm} Under any of the assumptions \textup{(i)}, \textup{(ii)}, \textup{(iii)}, \textup{(iv)}, the set of possible joint distributions |
|
$P(Y(x_0), Y(x_1))$ are characterized by |
|
the $8K$ inequalities:\vspace*{-2pt} |
|
\begin{eqnarray} |
|
\label{eqmarg}&&P\bigl(Y(x_i) = y\bigr) \nonumber\\[-1pt] |
|
&&\quad \leq P(Y = y, X = i | Z = z)\\[-1pt] |
|
&&\qquad {}+ P(X = 1-i | |
|
Z = z),\nonumber |
|
\\[4pt] |
|
\label{eqjoint}&&P\bigl(Y(x_0) = y, Y(x_1) = \tilde{y}\bigr) \nonumber\\[-1pt] |
|
&&\quad \leq P(Y |
|
= y, X = 0 | Z = z)\\[-1pt] |
|
&&\qquad {} + P(Y = \tilde{y}, X = 1 | Z = z).\nonumber |
|
\end{eqnarray} |
|
\end{thm} |
|
|
|
Thus a distribution $P(X,Y | Z)$ is compatible with the stated |
|
assumptions if and only if there exists a distribution |
|
$P(Y(x_0), Y(x_1))$ satisfying (\ref{eqmarg}) and (\ref{eqjoint}). |
|
|
|
\begin{thm} Under any of the assumptions \textup{(i)}, \textup{(ii)}, \textup{(iii)}, \textup{(iv)} |
|
for all $i,j \in\{0,1\}$, $P(Y(x_i) = j) \leq |
|
g(i,j)$, where\vspace*{-2pt} |
|
{\fontsize{10.9}{12.9}\selectfont{\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
g(i,j) &\equiv&\min \Bigl\{ \min_{z} \bigl[\vphantom{\hat{P}} P(X |
|
= i, Y = j | Z = z)\\ |
|
&&\hphantom{\min \Bigl\{\min_{z} \bigl[}{} + P(X = 1-i | Z = z) \bigr], |
|
\\ |
|
&&\hphantom{\min \Bigl\{} \min_{z, \tilde{z}: z \neq\tilde{z}} \bigl[ P(X = i, Y = j | Z |
|
= z) \\ |
|
&&\hphantom{\min \Bigl\{\min_{z, \tilde{z}: z \neq\tilde{z}} \bigl[}{}+ P(X = 1-i, Y = 0 | Z = z) |
|
\nonumber |
|
\\ |
|
&&\hphantom{\min \Bigl\{\min_{z, \tilde{z}: z \neq\tilde{z}} \bigl[}{} + P(X = i, Y = j | Z = |
|
\tilde{z}) \\ |
|
&&\hphantom{\min \Bigl\{\min_{z, \tilde{z}: z \neq\tilde{z}} \bigl[}{}+ P(X = 1-i, Y = 1 | Z = \tilde {z}) \bigr] \Bigr\}. |
|
\nonumber |
|
\end{eqnarray*}}} |
|
Furthermore, $P(Y(x_0))$ and $P(Y(x_1))$ are variation independent. |
|
Consequently, |
|
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
1-g(1,0)-g(0,1) &\leq& \operatorname{ACE}(X \rightarrow Y)\\ |
|
& \leq& g(0,0)+g(1,1)-1. |
|
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
These bounds are sharp. |
|
\end{thm} |
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
|
|
\includegraphics{485f01.eps} |
|
|
|
\caption{\textup{(a)} IV model with no confounding between $Z$ and $X$; \textup{(b)} |
|
SWIG representing $P(Z, X(z),Y(x),U)$; |
|
\textup{(c)} IV model with confounding between $Z$ and $X$; \textup{(d)} SWIG |
|
representing $P(Z, X,Y(x),U,U^*)$.}\label{figswig} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
|
|
Note that to evaluate $g(i,j)$ requires finding a minimum over $K^2$ |
|
expressions. In the case |
|
where $K=2$, these bounds reduce to those given by \citet |
|
{BalkPearboun1997}, who assume (i).\footnote{\citet{dawid2003} working |
|
in a non-counterfactual framework also established the bounds for $K=2$ |
|
under the DAG in Figure~\ref{figswig}(a); however, |
|
his proof also applies to Figure~\ref{figswig}(c). \citet |
|
{robinsgreenland1996} observed that the Balke--Pearl bounds |
|
were also sharp under (ii).} \citet{robins1989} and \citet{manski1990} derived what are called |
|
the ``natural bounds'' on the ACE under the weaker assumption that $Z |
|
\ind Y({x}_0)$ and $Z \ind Y({x}_1)$. |
|
As noted by Imbens, without further assumptions these bounds are not |
|
sharp. However, the natural bounds are sharp under (i) or (iii), if, in |
|
addition, we assume there are no Defiers (an assumption that has |
|
testable implications). \citet{chengsmall2006} considered bounds on |
|
the ACE when $K=3$ under additional assumptions. |
|
|
|
|
|
\section{Market Equilibrium and BiCausal Models} |
|
Imbens' clear description of the market equilibrium model is |
|
particularly informative. |
|
We also strongly endorse the author's contention that the RHS of |
|
systems of structural equations |
|
should be interpreted as describing potential outcomes for the |
|
LHS.\footnote{ |
|
\citet{pearl2000}, \citet{laucausal}, \citet{lauritzen02} argue that these are not |
|
really ``equations'' |
|
but are better viewed as ``assignments'' in computer languages, for example, $ y |
|
\leftarrow x +1$; |
|
see also \citet{strotzwoldrecursive1960}, page 420.} |
|
|
|
However, we note that this position has important implications both for |
|
interpretation and inference. |
|
Furthermore, it does not |
|
seem to be universally accepted within Economics. \citet{leroy2006} |
|
states that ``economic models use the equality symbol with its usual |
|
mathematical meaning, |
|
not with the meaning of the assignment operator''; |
|
an approach that is clearly incompatible with an interpretation in |
|
terms of potential outcomes. For example, |
|
it becomes permissible to renormalize structural equations to change |
|
which variable is on the LHS. |
|
|
|
It has also been argued that statistical analyses of such models should be |
|
invariant to the normalization; see \citet{hillier1990}, |
|
\citet{basmanncausal1963}.\hskip.2pt\footnote{For example, \citet{greene2003}, page 401, states (in the |
|
context of the IV model): |
|
``one significant virtue of [the Limited Information Maximum Likelihood |
|
Estimator] |
|
is its invariance to normalization of the equations.''} |
|
Contrary to Imbens' remark,\footnote{Footnote 8, page 331.} this |
|
alternative view does not appear to be motivated by |
|
considerations of measurement error. \citet{leroy2006} makes clear |
|
that he does not believe |
|
that structural equations describe potential outcomes for endogenous |
|
variables and does not discuss issues relating to measurement.\footnote |
|
{For example, |
|
\citet{leroy2006}, page 23, states that ``The assumption that it makes |
|
sense to delete one or more of the structural equations |
|
and replace the value of the internal variable so determined by a |
|
constant without altering the other equations [\ldots] is virtually never satisfied |
|
in economic models since each external variable typically affects |
|
equilibrium values of more than one internal variable.'' |
|
He goes on to assert ``In fact, it is difficult to think of nontrivial |
|
models in any area of research in which the [\ldots] assumption is satisfied.''} |
|
Rather, this appears to be a fundamental difference in interpretation. |
|
|
|
The market equilibrium model specifies potential outcomes for |
|
$Q^d_t(p)$, $Q^s_t(p)$: |
|
\begin{eqnarray} |
|
\label{eqqd}Q^d_t(p)&=& \alpha^d + \beta^d p |
|
+ \varepsilon_t^d, |
|
\\ |
|
\label{eqqs}Q^s_t(p)&=& \alpha^s + \beta^s p |
|
+ \varepsilon_t^s, |
|
\end{eqnarray} |
|
and imposes the equilibrium condition:\footnote{To simplify notation, |
|
throughout we work directly in terms of $\log$ price and $\log$ quantity.} |
|
\begin{eqnarray} |
|
Q^d_t(p) = Q^s_t(p).\label{eqequ} |
|
\end{eqnarray} |
|
\citet{strotzwoldrecursive1960} described such systems as \textit |
|
{bicausal}. |
|
It should be observed that the model does not |
|
specify potential outcomes for price ($P_t(q_s,q_d)$), nor does it view |
|
price as externally determined (i.e., exogenous). |
|
Instead price is determined implicitly as a consequence of the |
|
equilibrium condition. In this regard, the |
|
model might be regarded as incomplete: Indeed \citet |
|
{haavelmowhat1958} is quite critical of this model for failing to |
|
offer any \emph{explanation} as to |
|
how the equilibrium price is determined. The model also falls outside |
|
the scope of non-parametric structural equation models (NPSEM) (see, e.g., \cite{pearl2000}), which require one equation for each |
|
endogenous variable;\footnote{Indeed \citet{leroy2006} argues against the interpretation of |
|
structural equations in terms of potential outcomes on the grounds that |
|
this interpretation, as advanced by Pearl, requires a one-to-one |
|
mapping between equations and endogenous variables that he argues, does not |
|
make sense for the market equilibrium model.} |
|
likewise the model |
|
defies standard graphical representation, though see Figure~\ref{figone}(a). |
|
\begin{figure} |
|
|
|
\includegraphics{485f02.eps} |
|
|
|
\caption{\textup{(a)} Attempt to depict the bicausal model; \textup{(b)} a schematic |
|
showing the deterministic system (\protect\ref{eqcon})--(\protect\ref{eqmer}); |
|
the edge |
|
\protect\tikz\protect\path(0ex,0ex) edge[->] node[above=0pt, black] |
|
{$\scriptscriptstyle I$} (3ex,0ex); |
|
denotes that $P$ is the integral of $\Delta P$; see Iwasaki and Simon (\citeyear |
|
{iwasaki1994}).}\label{figone} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
A related question concerns whether there exist dynamic acyclic (i.e., |
|
recursive) |
|
systems of structural equations |
|
that lead to the equilibrium distribution corresponding either to a |
|
cyclic system |
|
of structural equations or a bicausal system.\footnote{Analysis of this question was stimulated by a heated debate that arose between |
|
Wold, who advocated a recursive, regression-based approach to demand |
|
analysis, and Haavelmo |
|
and the Cowles Commission who advocated simultaneous equations. See |
|
\citet{haavelmostatistical1943}, \citet{woldbentzelstatistical1946}, |
|
\citet{woldjureendemand1953}, \citet{bentzelhansenrecursiveness1954}, |
|
\citet{strotzwoldrecursive1960}, \citet{basmanncausal1963}; historical overviews |
|
are given by \citet{morganstamping1991}, |
|
\citet{epsteinhistory1987}.} \citet{fishcorr} provides just such a ``correspondence principle'' |
|
under which the distribution implied by a cyclic linear SEM is obtained |
|
as a time average of a deterministic |
|
set of first order difference equations reaching a static equilibrium |
|
subject to stochastic boundary conditions. |
|
The correspondence assumes that the equilibration time is very fast |
|
relative to the interval between observations |
|
so the time averaged variables are in deterministic equilibrium. |
|
Fisher also derived conditions on the coefficient matrices of a cyclic |
|
SEM that are required in order for the system |
|
to reach equilibrium; in fact he further required that each subset of |
|
structural equations also have this property. |
|
|
|
However, Fisher's correspondence presumes a normalization under which |
|
each variable is associated with |
|
a single equation (as in an NPSEM), and hence would not apply to a |
|
bicausal system. \citet{richphd}, Chapter~2, |
|
described a system of finite difference equations that gives rise to |
|
the bicausal system~(\ref{eqqd})--(\ref{eqequ}): |
|
\begin{eqnarray} |
|
\label{eqcon}\mbox{Consumers:}&&\hspace*{4pt} Q^d_{t+(k+1)\delta}(p_{t+k\delta})\nonumber \\[-8pt]\\[-8pt] |
|
&&\hspace*{4pt}\quad = |
|
\alpha^d+ \beta^d p_{t+k\delta} + \varepsilon_{t}^d,\nonumber |
|
\\ |
|
\label{eqsup}\mbox{Suppliers:}&&\hspace*{4pt} Q^s_{t+(k+1)\delta}(p_{t+k\delta}) \nonumber\\[-8pt]\\[-8pt] |
|
&&\hspace*{4pt}\quad = |
|
\alpha^s+ \beta^s p_{t+k\delta} + \varepsilon_{t}^s,\nonumber |
|
\\ |
|
\label{eqmer}\mbox{Merchants:}&&\hspace*{4pt} P_{t+(k+1)\delta}\bigl(q^d_{t+k\delta}, |
|
q^s_{t+k\delta},p_{t+k\delta}\bigr) \nonumber\\[-8pt]\\[-8pt] |
|
&&\hspace*{4pt}\quad = p_{t+k\delta} + |
|
\lambda \bigl(q^d_{t+k\delta} - q^s_{t+k\delta} |
|
\bigr),\nonumber |
|
\end{eqnarray} |
|
for $k=\{0,\ldots, \delta^{-1}-1\}$. Note that the disturbances |
|
$(\varepsilon_{t}^d, \varepsilon_{t}^s)$ represent boundary |
|
conditions and hence |
|
remain fixed during the interval $[t,t+1)$. |
|
As in Fisher's correspondence, the observed variables correspond to |
|
limiting time-averages over a unit |
|
interval: |
|
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
\overline{Q}^d_t &=& \lim_{\delta\rightarrow0} \delta |
|
\sum_{k=0}^{\delta^{-1}-1} {Q}^d_{t+k\delta},\quad |
|
\overline{Q}^s_t = \lim_{\delta\rightarrow0} \delta |
|
\sum_{k=0}^{\delta^{-1}-1} {Q}^s_{t+k\delta},\\ |
|
\overline{P}_t &=& \lim_{\delta\rightarrow0} \delta\sum |
|
_{k=0}^{\delta^{-1}-1} {P}_{t+k\delta}. |
|
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
Under suitable conditions on the coefficients, $(\overline{Q}^d_t, |
|
\overline{Q}^s_t,\allowbreak \overline{P}_t)$ obey |
|
equations (\ref{eqqd})--(\ref{eqequ}). Note that Merchants' |
|
equation (\ref{eqmer}) which includes $P$, leads to the equilibrium |
|
condition (\ref{eqequ}) that does not.\footnote{In causal terms, |
|
this model is similar to one presented in \citet{wold1959}. Wold |
|
viewed his model as a formalization of Cournot's theories.} |
|
It might be objected to the proposed model that there is no disturbance |
|
term in equation (\ref{eqmer}). |
|
The explanation for this is that the disturbance terms in the |
|
nonrecursive model correspond to constant factors in the deterministic |
|
evolution. |
|
The equation for price gives the change in price during a small |
|
interval (length $\delta$) to the discrepancy between supply and demand. |
|
Adding a disturbance term would say that throughout the observation |
|
period (length $1$) the Merchants' reaction to change in price was off |
|
by a constant factor, so that even if quantities supplied and demanded |
|
were identical, the Merchants would change the price. Thus, if we add |
|
an error $\varepsilon^p_t$ the model will not, in general, arrive at |
|
equilibrium |
|
within the unit interval.\footnote{Having said this, the equations |
|
(\ref{eqcon}) and (\ref{eqsup}) still imply that producers and |
|
consumers make systematic errors in computing prices over a time-scale |
|
of length $\delta$.} |
|
|
|
\citet{iwasaki1994} represent equilibrating mechanisms via ``causal |
|
influence diagrams'' in which the derivatives of variables are included. |
|
Under this scheme, model (\ref{eqcon})--(\ref{eqmer}) is |
|
represented by the graph in Figure~\ref{figone}(b). |
|
This example serves to show that time averages of (deterministic) |
|
equilibrating systems need not have a structural equation for each variable. |
|
See also \citep{2001.dash.esqaru} for related work. |
|
|
|
|
|
\section*{Acknowledgments} |
|
This work was supported by the US National Institutes of Health Grant |
|
R01 AI032475; Richardson was also supported by the US National Science |
|
Foundation Grant CNS-0855230. |
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{thebibliography}{28} |
|
|
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Balke and Pearl}{1997}]{BalkPearboun1997} |
|
\begin{barticle}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Balke},~\bfnm{Alexander}\binits{A.}} \AND |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Pearl},~\bfnm{Judea}\binits{J.}} |
|
(\byear{1997}). |
|
\btitle{Bounds on treatment effects from studies with imperfect compliance}. |
|
\bjournal{J. Amer. Statist. Assoc.} |
|
\bvolume{92} |
|
\bpages{1171--1176}. |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Basmann}{1963}]{basmanncausal1963} |
|
\begin{barticle}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Basmann},~\bfnm{R.~L.}\binits{R.~L.}} |
|
(\byear{1963}). |
|
\btitle{The causal interpretation of non-triangular systems of economic relations (with discussion)}. |
|
\bjournal{Econometrica} |
|
\bvolume{31} |
|
\bpages{439--453}. |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Bentzel and Hansen}{1954}]{bentzelhansenrecursiveness1954} |
|
\begin{barticle}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Bentzel},~\bfnm{R.}\binits{R.}} \AND |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Hansen},~\bfnm{B.}\binits{B.}} |
|
(\byear{1954}). |
|
\btitle{On recursiveness and interdependency in economic models}. |
|
\bjournal{Rev. Econom. Stud.} |
|
\bvolume{22} |
|
\bpages{153--168}. |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Bentzel and Wold}{1946}]{woldbentzelstatistical1946} |
|
\begin{barticle}[mr] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Bentzel},~\bfnm{R.}\binits{R.}} \AND |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Wold},~\bfnm{H.}\binits{H.}} |
|
(\byear{1946}). |
|
\btitle{On statistical demand analysis from the viewpoint of simultaneous equations}. |
|
\bjournal{Skand. Aktuarietidskr.} |
|
\bvolume{29} |
|
\bpages{95--114}. |
|
\bid{mr={0017907}} |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Cheng and Small}{2006}]{chengsmall2006} |
|
\begin{barticle}[mr] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Cheng},~\bfnm{Jing}\binits{J.}} \AND |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Small},~\bfnm{Dylan~S.}\binits{D.~S.}} |
|
(\byear{2006}). |
|
\btitle{Bounds on causal effects in three-arm trials with non-compliance}. |
|
\bjournal{J. R. Stat. Soc. Ser. B Stat. Methodol.} |
|
\bvolume{68} |
|
\bpages{815--836}. |
|
\bid{doi={10.1111/j.1467-9868.2006.00568.x}, issn={1369-7412}, mr={2301296}} |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Dash and Druzdzel}{2001}]{2001.dash.esqaru} |
|
\begin{binproceedings}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Dash}, \bfnm{Denver}\binits{D.}} \AND |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Druzdzel}, \bfnm{Marek J.}\binits{M. J.}} |
|
(\byear{2001}). |
|
\btitle{Caveats for causal reasoning with equilibrium models}. |
|
In \bbooktitle{Proceedings of the Sixth European Conference on |
|
Symbolic and Quantitative Approaches\vadjust{\goodbreak} to Reasoning with Uncertainty (ECSQARU), Toulouse, France} |
|
(\beditor{\bfnm{Salem}\binits{S.} \bsnm{Benferhat}} \AND |
|
\beditor{\bfnm{Philippe}\binits{P.} \bsnm{Besnard}}, eds.). |
|
\bseries{Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence} |
|
\bvolume{2143} |
|
\bpages{192--203}. |
|
\bpublisher{Springer}, |
|
\blocation{Berlin}. |
|
\end{binproceedings} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Dawid}{2003}]{dawid2003} |
|
\begin{bincollection}[mr] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Dawid},~\bfnm{A.~Philip}\binits{A.~P.}} |
|
(\byear{2003}). |
|
\btitle{Causal inference using influence diagrams: The problem of partial compliance}. |
|
In \bbooktitle{Highly Structured Stochastic Systems} |
|
(\beditor{\bfnm{P. J.}\binits{P. J.} \bsnm{Green}}, |
|
\beditor{\bfnm{N. L.}\binits{N. L.} \bsnm{Hjort}} \AND |
|
\beditor{\bfnm{S.}\binits{S.} \bsnm{Richardson}}, eds.). |
|
\bseries{Oxford Statist. Sci. Ser.} |
|
\bvolume{27} |
|
\bpages{45--81}. |
|
\bpublisher{Oxford Univ. Press}, |
|
\blocation{Oxford}. |
|
\bid{mr={2082406}} |
|
\bptnote{check related}\end{bincollection} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Epstein}{1987}]{epsteinhistory1987} |
|
\begin{bbook}[mr] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Epstein},~\bfnm{Roy~J.}\binits{R.~J.}} |
|
(\byear{1987}). |
|
\btitle{A History of Econometrics}. |
|
\bseries{Contributions to Economic Analysis} |
|
\bvolume{165}. |
|
\bpublisher{North-Holland}, |
|
\blocation{Amsterdam}. |
|
\bid{mr={0918969}} |
|
\end{bbook} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Fisher}{1970}]{fishcorr} |
|
\begin{barticle}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Fisher},~\bfnm{F.~M.}\binits{F.~M.}} |
|
(\byear{1970}). |
|
\btitle{A correspondence principle for simultaneous equation models}. |
|
\bjournal{Econometrica} |
|
\bvolume{38} |
|
\bpages{73--92}. |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Greene}{2003}]{greene2003} |
|
\begin{bbook}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Greene},~\bfnm{William~H.}\binits{W.~H.}} |
|
(\byear{2003}). |
|
\btitle{Econometric Analysis}, |
|
\bedition{5th} ed. |
|
\bpublisher{Prentice Hall}, |
|
\blocation{Upper Saddle River, NJ}. |
|
\end{bbook} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Haavelmo}{1943}]{haavelmostatistical1943} |
|
\begin{barticle}[mr] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Haavelmo},~\bfnm{Trygve}\binits{T.}} |
|
(\byear{1943}). |
|
\btitle{The statistical implications of a system of simultaneous equations}. |
|
\bjournal{Econometrica} |
|
\bvolume{11} |
|
\bpages{1--12}. |
|
\bid{issn={0012-9682}, mr={0007954}} |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Haavelmo}{1958}]{haavelmowhat1958} |
|
\begin{barticle}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Haavelmo},~\bfnm{T.}\binits{T.}} |
|
(\byear{1958}). |
|
\btitle{Hva kan statiske likevektsmodeller fortelle oss?} |
|
\bjournal{National{\o}konomisk Tidsskrift} |
|
\bvolume{96 (Suppl.)} |
|
\bpages{138--145} |
|
\bnote{(in {N}orwegian). English translation published as: {W}hat can static equilibrium models tell us? \textit{Economic Inquiry} \textbf{12} (1974) 27--34}. |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Hillier}{1990}]{hillier1990} |
|
\begin{barticle}[mr] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Hillier},~\bfnm{Grant~H.}\binits{G.~H.}} |
|
(\byear{1990}). |
|
\btitle{On the normalization of structural equations: Properties of direction estimators}. |
|
\bjournal{Econometrica} |
|
\bvolume{58} |
|
\bpages{1181--1194}. |
|
\bid{doi={10.2307/2938305}, issn={0012-9682}, mr={1079413}} |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Iwasaki and Simon}{1994}]{iwasaki1994} |
|
\begin{barticle}[mr] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Iwasaki},~\bfnm{Yumi}\binits{Y.}} \AND |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Simon},~\bfnm{Herbert~A.}\binits{H.~A.}} |
|
(\byear{1994}). |
|
\btitle{Causality and model abstraction}. |
|
\bjournal{Artificial Intelligence} |
|
\bvolume{67} |
|
\bpages{143--194}. |
|
\bid{doi={10.1016/0004-3702(94)90014-0}, issn={0004-3702}, mr={1281657}} |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Lauritzen}{2001}]{laucausal} |
|
\begin{bincollection}[mr] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Lauritzen},~\bfnm{Steffen~L.}\binits{S.~L.}} |
|
(\byear{2001}). |
|
\btitle{Causal inference from graphical models}. |
|
In \bbooktitle{Complex Stochastic Systems ({E}indhoven, 1999)}. |
|
\bseries{Monogr. Statist. Appl. Probab.} |
|
\bvolume{87} |
|
\bpages{63--107}. |
|
\bpublisher{Chapman \& Hall/CRC}, |
|
\blocation{Boca Raton, FL}. |
|
\bid{mr={1893411}} |
|
\end{bincollection} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Lauritzen and Richardson}{2002}]{lauritzen02} |
|
\begin{barticle}[mr] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Lauritzen},~\bfnm{Steffen~L.}\binits{S.~L.}} \AND |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Richardson},~\bfnm{Thomas~S.}\binits{T.~S.}} |
|
(\byear{2002}). |
|
\btitle{Chain graph models and their causal interpretations}. |
|
\bjournal{J. R. Stat. Soc. Ser. B Stat. Methodol.} |
|
\bvolume{64} |
|
\bpages{321--361}. |
|
\bid{doi={10.1111/1467-9868.00340}, issn={1369-7412}, mr={1924296}} |
|
\bptnote{check related}\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{{LeRoy}}{2006}]{leroy2006} |
|
\begin{btechreport}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{{LeRoy}},~\bfnm{Stephen~F.}\binits{S.~F.}} |
|
(\byear{2006}). |
|
\btitle{Causality in economics}. |
|
\btype{Technical report, Univ. California, Santa Barbara}. |
|
\end{btechreport} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Manski}{1990}]{manski1990} |
|
\begin{barticle}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Manski},~\bfnm{C.~F.}\binits{C.~F.}} |
|
(\byear{1990}). |
|
\btitle{Non-parametric bounds on treatment effects}. |
|
\bjournal{American Economic Review} |
|
\bvolume{80} |
|
\bpages{351--374}. |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Morgan}{1991}]{morganstamping1991} |
|
\begin{bincollection}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Morgan},~\bfnm{M.~S.}\binits{M.~S.}} |
|
(\byear{1991}). |
|
\btitle{The stamping out of process analysis in econometrics}. |
|
In \bbooktitle{Appraising Economic Theories} |
|
(\beditor{\bfnm{Neil}\binits{N.}~\bparticle{de}~\bsnm{Marchi}} \AND |
|
\beditor{\bfnm{Mark}\binits{M.}~\bsnm{Blaug}}, eds.) |
|
\bpages{237--272}. |
|
\bpublisher{Edward Elgar}, |
|
\blocation{Cheltenham}. |
|
\end{bincollection} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Pearl}{2000}]{pearl2000} |
|
\begin{bbook}[mr] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Pearl},~\bfnm{Judea}\binits{J.}} |
|
(\byear{2000}). |
|
\btitle{Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference}. |
|
\bpublisher{Cambridge Univ. Press}, |
|
\blocation{Cambridge}. |
|
\bid{mr={1744773}} |
|
\end{bbook} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Richardson}{1996}]{richphd} |
|
\begin{bphdthesis}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Richardson},~\bfnm{T.~S.}\binits{T.~S.}} |
|
(\byear{1996}). |
|
\btitle{Models of feedback: Interpretation and discovery}. |
|
\btype{Ph.D. thesis, Carnegie-Mellon Univ}. |
|
\end{bphdthesis} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Richardson and Robins}{2013}]{richardsonrobins2013} |
|
\begin{btechreport}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Richardson},~\bfnm{Thomas~S.}\binits{T.~S.}} \AND |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Robins},~\bfnm{James~M.}\binits{J.~M.}} |
|
(\byear{2013}). |
|
\btitle{{S}ingle {W}orld {I}ntervention {G}raphs {(SWIGs)}: A unification of the counterfactual and graphical approaches to |
|
causality}. |
|
\btype{Technical Report 128, Center for Statistics and the Social Sciences, Univ. |
|
Washington, Seattle, WA}. |
|
\end{btechreport} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Richardson and Robins}{2014}]{richardsonrobins2014} |
|
\begin{bunpublished}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Richardson},~\bfnm{T.~S.}\binits{T.~S.}} \AND |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Robins},~\bfnm{J.~M.}\binits{J.~M.}} |
|
(\byear{2014}). |
|
\btitle{Assumptions and bounds in the instrumental variable model}. |
|
\bnote{Preprint}. |
|
\end{bunpublished} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Robins}{1989}]{robins1989} |
|
\begin{bincollection}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Robins},~\bfnm{J.~M.}\binits{J.~M.}} |
|
(\byear{1989}). |
|
\btitle{The analysis of randomized and non-randomized AIDS treatment trials using a new approach to causal inference in longitudinal studies.} |
|
In \bbooktitle{Health Service Research Methodology: A Focus on {AIDS}} |
|
(\beditor{\bfnm{L.}\binits{L.}~\bsnm{Sechrest}}, |
|
\beditor{\bfnm{H.}\binits{H.}~\bsnm{Freeman}} \AND |
|
\beditor{\bfnm{A.}\binits{A.}~\bsnm{Mulley}}, eds.). |
|
\bpublisher{U.S. Public Health Service}, |
|
\blocation{Washington, DC}. |
|
\end{bincollection} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Robins and Greenland}{1996}]{robinsgreenland1996} |
|
\begin{barticle}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Robins},~\bfnm{James~M.}\binits{J.~M.}} \AND |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Greenland},~\bfnm{Sander}\binits{S.}} |
|
(\byear{1996}). |
|
\btitle{Identification of causal effects using instrumental variables: Comment}. |
|
\bjournal{J. Amer. Statist. Assoc.} |
|
\bvolume{91} |
|
\bpages{456--458}. |
|
\bid{issn={01621459}} |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Strotz and Wold}{1960}]{strotzwoldrecursive1960} |
|
\begin{barticle}[mr] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Strotz},~\bfnm{Robert~H.}\binits{R.~H.}} \AND |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Wold},~\bfnm{H.~O.~A.}\binits{H.~O.~A.}} |
|
(\byear{1960}). |
|
\btitle{Recursive vs. nonrecursive systems: An attempt at synthesis}. |
|
\bjournal{Econometrica} |
|
\bvolume{28} |
|
\bpages{417--427}. |
|
\bid{issn={0012-9682}, mr={0120034}} |
|
\end{barticle} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem\vfill\eject |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Wold}{1959}]{wold1959} |
|
\begin{bincollection}[mr] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Wold},~\bfnm{Herman~O.~A.}\binits{H.~O.~A.}} |
|
(\byear{1959}). |
|
\btitle{Ends and means in econometric model building}. |
|
In \bbooktitle{Probability and Statistics: {T}he {H}arald {C}ram\'er Volume} ({U}. {G}renander, ed.) |
|
\bpages{355--434}. |
|
\bpublisher{Almqvist \& Wiksell}, |
|
\blocation{Stockholm}. |
|
\bid{mr={0109088}} |
|
\end{bincollection} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem |
|
|
|
\bibitem[\protect\citeauthoryear{Wold and Jur{\'e}en}{1953}]{woldjureendemand1953} |
|
\begin{bbook}[author] |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Wold},~\bfnm{H.~O.~A.}\binits{H.~O.~A.}} \AND |
|
\bauthor{\bsnm{Jur{\'e}en},~\bfnm{L.}\binits{L.}} |
|
(\byear{1953}). |
|
\btitle{Demand Analysis}. |
|
\bpublisher{Wiley}, |
|
\blocation{New York}. |
|
\end{bbook} |
|
\bptok{imsref}\endbibitem\vfill |
|
|
|
|
|
\end{thebibliography} |
|
\end{document} |
|
|