|
\PassOptionsToPackage{table}{xcolor} |
|
\PassOptionsToPackage{bookmarksnumbered,unicode,ocgcolorlinks,pdftex}{hyperref} |
|
\documentclass[acmsmall,10pt,screen]{acmart} |
|
\usepackage{etex} |
|
\settopmatter{} |
|
|
|
\usepackage{suffix} |
|
\usepackage{okgeneralmath} |
|
\usepackage{okcategory} |
|
\usepackage{bbm} |
|
\usepackage{multicol} |
|
\usepackage{mathtools} |
|
\usepackage{mathpartir} |
|
\usepackage{oksemantics} |
|
\usepackage{commath} |
|
\usepackage{listings} |
|
\usepackage[inline]{enumitem} |
|
\usepackage{wrapfig} |
|
\renewcommand\mathbf\textbf |
|
|
|
\newcommand{\mv}[1]{ |
|
\smallskip\noindent\fbox{\begin{minipage}{.97\linewidth}{\bf MV:} |
|
{\rm #1}\end{minipage}}} |
|
\newcommand{\hy}[1]{ |
|
\smallskip\noindent\fbox{\begin{minipage}{.97\linewidth}{\bf HY:} |
|
{\rm #1}\end{minipage}}} |
|
\newcommand{\sss}[1]{ |
|
\smallskip\noindent\fbox{\begin{minipage}{.97\linewidth}{\bf SS:} |
|
{\rm #1}\end{minipage}}} |
|
\newcommand{\ok}[1]{ |
|
\smallskip\noindent\fbox{\begin{minipage}{.97\linewidth}{\bf OK:} |
|
{\rm #1}\end{minipage}}} |
|
\newcommand{\adam}[1]{ |
|
\smallskip\noindent\fbox{\begin{minipage}{.97\linewidth}{\bf AS:} |
|
{\rm #1}\end{minipage}}} |
|
\newcommand{\todo}[1]{ |
|
\smallskip\noindent\fbox{\begin{minipage}{.97\linewidth}{\bf To do:} |
|
{\rm #1}\end{minipage}}} |
|
\newcommand{\commentout}[1]{} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\seclabel[1]{\label{sec:#1}} |
|
\renewcommand\secref[1]{Sec.~\ref{sec:#1}} |
|
\newcommand\subseclabel[1]{\label{subsec:#1}} |
|
\newcommand\subsecref[1]{\S~\ref{subsec:#1}} |
|
\newcommand\subsubseclabel[1]{\label{subsubsec:#1}} |
|
\newcommand\subsubsecref[1]{\S~\ref{subsubsec:#1}} |
|
\newcommand\figlabel[1]{\label{fig:#1}} |
|
\renewcommand\figref[1]{Fig.~\ref{fig:#1}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\AddReferences[2]{ |
|
\expandafter\newcommand\csname#1ref\endcsname[1]{#2~\ref{#1:##1}} |
|
\expandafter\newcommand\csname#1label\endcsname[1]{\label{#1:##1}} |
|
\WithSuffix\expandafter\newcommand\csname#1ref\endcsname*[1]{\ref{#1:##1}} |
|
\WithSuffix\expandafter\newcommand\csname#1label\endcsname+[1]{\hypertarget{#1+:##1}{}\zref@labelbyprops{#1:##1}{oktheoremfreetext}} |
|
\WithSuffix\expandafter\newcommand\csname#1ref\endcsname+[1]{\hyperlink{#1+:##1}{{{\let\ref\@refstar#2~\zref@extract{#1:##1}{oktheoremfreetext}}}}} |
|
\WithSuffix\expandafter\newcommand\csname#1ref\endcsname-[1]{\hyperlink{#1+:##1}{{\let\ref\@refstar{\zref@extract{#1:##1}{oktheoremfreetext}}}}} |
|
} |
|
|
|
\AddReferences{example}{Ex.} |
|
\AddReferences{lemma}{Lemma} |
|
\AddReferences{theorem}{Thm.} |
|
\AddReferences{definition}{Def.} |
|
\newcommand\defref\definitionref |
|
\newcommand\deflabel\definitionlabel |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand{\citepos}[1]{\citeauthor{#1}'s~\citeyearpar{#1}} |
|
\WithSuffix\newcommand\citepos*[2]{\citeauthor{#1}'s #2~\citeyearpar{#1}} |
|
\WithSuffix\newcommand\citepos-[2]{\citeauthor{#1}#2~\citeyearpar{#1}} |
|
|
|
|
|
\newcounter{countitems} |
|
\newcounter{nextitemizecount} |
|
\newcommand{\setupcountitems}{ |
|
\stepcounter{nextitemizecount} |
|
\setcounter{countitems}{0} |
|
\preto\item{\stepcounter{countitems}} |
|
} |
|
\makeatletter |
|
\newcommand{\computecountitems}{ |
|
\edef\@currentlabel{\number\c@countitems} |
|
\label{countitems@\number\numexpr\value{nextitemizecount}-1\relax} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\nextitemizecount}{ |
|
\getrefnumber{countitems@\number\c@nextitemizecount} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\previtemizecount}{ |
|
\getrefnumber{countitems@\number\numexpr\value{nextitemizecount}-1\relax} |
|
} |
|
\makeatother |
|
\newenvironment{AutoMultiColItemize}{ |
|
\ifnumcomp{\nextitemizecount}{>}{3}{\begin{multicols}{2}}{} |
|
\setupcountitems\begin{itemize}} |
|
{\end{itemize} |
|
\unskip\computecountitems\ifnumcomp{\previtemizecount}{>}{3}{\end{multicols}}{}} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\definecolor{shade}{RGB}{223,223,223} |
|
\definecolor{unshade}{RGB}{255,255,255} |
|
|
|
\usepackage{tcolorbox} |
|
\newtcbox{\shadebox}{on line,arc=1pt, outer arc=2pt, |
|
colback=shade,colframe=shade,boxsep=0pt, |
|
left=1pt,right=1pt,top=2pt,bottom=2pt, |
|
boxrule=0pt,bottomrule=1pt,toprule=1pt} |
|
\newcommand{\shade}[1]{ |
|
\shadebox{\ensuremath{#1}} |
|
} |
|
\newtcbox{\unshadebox}{on line,arc=1pt, outer arc=2pt, |
|
colback=unshade,colframe=shade,boxsep=0pt, |
|
left=1pt,right=1pt,top=2pt,bottom=2pt, |
|
boxrule=0pt,bottomrule=1pt,toprule=1pt} |
|
\newcommand{\unshade}[1]{ |
|
\unshadebox{\ensuremath{#1}} |
|
} |
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand\syncat[1]{\mspace{-25mu}\synname{#1}} |
|
\newcommand\synname[1]{\qquad\text{#1}} |
|
|
|
\newenvironment{syntax}[1][]{ |
|
\( |
|
\rowcolors{100}{white}{white} |
|
\begin{array}[t]{#1l@{\quad\!\!}*3{l@{}}@{\,}l} |
|
}{ |
|
\end{array} |
|
\) |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newenvironment{sugar}{ |
|
\( |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{\bullet\ }l@{\mspace{25mu}}ll} |
|
\multicolumn{1}{@{\hphantom{\bullet}}l}{\text{Sugar}} & \text{Elaboration}\\ |
|
\hline |
|
}{ |
|
\end{array} |
|
\) |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\gdefinedby{::=} |
|
\newcommand\gor{\mathrel{\lvert}} |
|
\makeatletter |
|
|
|
\newcommand\@TyAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or \tau\or \sigma\or \rho\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
\newcommand\ty[1][1]{{\@TyAlph{#1}}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\tvar[1][1]{{\@TyVarAlph{#1}}} |
|
\newcommand\@TyVarAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or \alpha\or \beta\or \gamma\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\Functor[1][1]{\TypeCons{\@FunAlph{#1}}} |
|
\newcommand\@FunAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or F\or G\or H\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\Type[1][1]{{\mathrm{\@TypeAlph{#1}}}} |
|
\newcommand\@TypeAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or A\or B\or C\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\var[1][1]{{\@VarAlph{#1}}} |
|
\newcommand\@VarAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or x\or y\or z\or u\or v\or w\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\trm[1][1]{{\@TermAlph{#1}}} |
|
\newcommand\@TermAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or t\or s\or r\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\ir[1][1]{\monad{\uir[#1]}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\uir[1][1]{\mathop{{}\@IRAlph{#1}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\@IRAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or T\or S\or R\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\IF[1][1]{\monad{\uIF[#1]}} |
|
\newcommand\uIF[1][1]{\mathop{{}\@IFAlph{#1}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\@IFAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or F\or G\or H\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand\tfm[1][1]{\mathop{{}\underline{\trm[#1]}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand\cat[1][1]{\Cat{\@CatAlph#1}} |
|
\newcommand\@CatAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or C\or D\or A\or B\or E\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\F[1][1]{\@FunctorAlph#1} |
|
\newcommand\@FunctorAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or F\or G\or H\\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\nt[1][1]{\@NatTransAlph#1} |
|
\newcommand\@NatTransAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or \alpha\or \beta\or \gamma\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\alg[1][1]{\@AlgAlph#1} |
|
\newcommand\@AlgAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or A\or B\or C\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\qmu[1][1]{\underline{\@MuAlph#1}} |
|
\newcommand\@MuAlph[1]{ |
|
\ifcase #1\or \mu\or \nu\or \xi\or \zeta\else \@ctrerr \fi |
|
} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\makeatother |
|
|
|
\newcommand\Cns{\ell} |
|
\newcommand\Inj[2][\,]{\mathrm{#2}#1} |
|
\newcommand\Variant[1]{\{ #1 \}} |
|
\newcommand\vor{\mathrel{\big\lvert}} |
|
\newcommand\Unit{\textbf{1}} |
|
\WithSuffix\newcommand\t*{*} |
|
\newcommand\rec[2]{\mu#1.#2} |
|
\newcommand\To{\to} |
|
\newcommand\ctx{\Gamma} |
|
\newcommand\Tyctx{\Delta} |
|
\newcommand\kinf{\vdash_{\mathrm k}} |
|
\newcommand\Dkinf[2][]{\Tyctx#1\kinf#2 : \typ} |
|
\newcommand\typ{\mathrm{type}} |
|
\newcommand\context{\mathrm{context}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\TypeCons[1]{\mathop{{}\mathrm{#1}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\List{\TypeCons{List}} |
|
\newcommand\boolty{{\TypeCons{bool}}} |
|
\newcommand\tru{\mathop{\Inj[]{True}}} |
|
\newcommand\fls{\mathop{\Inj[]{False}}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\I{\mathbb{I}} |
|
\newcommand\ereals{\overline\reals} |
|
\WithSuffix\newcommand\ereals+{\overline\reals_+} |
|
\WithSuffix\newcommand\reals+{\reals_+} |
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand\tInj[3][\,]{#2.#3#1} |
|
\newcommand\tUnit{()} |
|
\newcommand\tpair[2]{(#1, #2)} |
|
\newcommand\ttriple[3]{(#1, #2, #3)} |
|
\newcommand\troll[2][\,]{#2.\textbf{roll}#1} |
|
\newcommand\fun[1]{\lambda #1.\,} |
|
\newcommand\pfun[1]{ |
|
\lambda\,\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
\!\{\, |
|
#1 |
|
\} |
|
\end{array}} |
|
\newcommand\vmatch[2]{\textbf{match}\,#1\,\textbf{with}\,\{#2\}} |
|
\newcommand\pmatch[4]{\textbf{match}\,#1\,\textbf{with}\,\tpair{#2}{#3}\To#4} |
|
\newcommand\rmatch[4][\,]{\textbf{match}\,#2\,\textbf{with}#1\roll#3\To#4} |
|
\newcommand\imatch[2]{\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{\,}l} |
|
\vmatch{}{\\ |
|
& \begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{\To}l} |
|
#2 |
|
}\end{array} |
|
\end{array}} |
|
\newcommand\tfold[2][\,]{#2.\textbf{fold}#1} |
|
\newcommand\tsample[1][\ ]{\textbf{sample}#1} |
|
\newcommand\tflip{\textbf{flip}} |
|
\newcommand\tscore{\textbf{score}} |
|
\newcommand\tcts{\phi} |
|
\newcommand\roll[1][\,]{\textbf{roll}#1} |
|
\newcommand\unroll[1][\,]{\textbf{unroll}#1} |
|
\newcommand\fold{\textbf{fold}\,} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\expfun[2]{\lambda #1:#2.} |
|
\newcommand\letin[3]{\textbf{let}\,#1=#2\,\textbf{in}\,#3} |
|
\newcommand\expletin[2]{\letin{(#1:#2)}} |
|
\newcommand\tif[3]{\mathrel{\textbf{if}}#1\mathrel{\textbf{then}}#2\mathrel{\textbf{else}}#3} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\foldlist[2]{\mathrm{foldr}\,#1\,#2} |
|
\WithSuffix\newcommand\++{\mathbin{+\kern-.4em+}} |
|
\newcommand\tmap[1][\,]{\mathrm{map}#1} |
|
\newcommand\fmap[3][\,]{(#2.#3).\textbf{fmap}#1} |
|
\newcommand\lst[1]{[#1]} |
|
\WithSuffix\newcommand\lst-{\lst{\ }} |
|
\newcommand\aggr{\mathop{\mathrm{aggr}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\add{\mathop{\mathrm{add}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\waggr{\mathop{\mathrm{waggr}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\sequence{\mathop{\mathrm{sequence}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\concat{\mathop{\mathrm{concat}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\replicate{\mathop{\mathrm{replicate}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\tinf{\vdash} |
|
\newcommand\Ginf[3][]{\ctx #1\tinf #2 : #3} |
|
\newcommand\subst[2]{#1{}[#2]} |
|
\newcommand\sfor[2]{#1 \mapsto #2} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\scomment[1]{\texttt{--}\ \text{#1}} |
|
\newcommand\gobble[1]{} |
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand\sem\scottbrackets |
|
\newcommand\carrier[1]{\left\lvert#1\right\rvert} |
|
\renewcommand\terminal{\mathbbold{1}} |
|
\newcommand\Two{\mathbbold{2}} |
|
\DeclareMathAlphabet{\mathbbold}{U}{bbold}{m}{n} |
|
\renewcommand\mathbbold\underline |
|
\renewcommand\initial{\mathbbold{0}} |
|
\newcommand\zero{\mathbbold{Z}} |
|
\newcommand\zeromor{\textbf{0}} |
|
\newcommand\algin[1][]{\mathrm{in}^{#1}} |
|
\newcommand\algout[1][]{\mathrm{out}^{#1}} |
|
\newcommand\algfold[1][]{\mathrm{fold}^{#1}} |
|
\newcommand\codiag{\nabla} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\Base{\mathcal{B}\sem} |
|
\newcommand\tenv{d} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\usepackage{extpfeil} |
|
\newextarrow{\xtoto}{{20}{20}{20}{20}} |
|
{\bigRelbar\bigRelbar{\bigtwoarrowsleft\rightarrow\rightarrow}} |
|
\makeatletter |
|
\newbox\xrat@below |
|
\newbox\xrat@above |
|
\newcommand{\xrightarrowtail}[2][]{ |
|
\setbox\xrat@below=\hbox{\ensuremath{\scriptstyle #1}} |
|
\setbox\xrat@above=\hbox{\ensuremath{\scriptstyle #2}} |
|
\pgfmathsetlengthmacro{\xrat@len}{max(\wd\xrat@below,\wd\xrat@above)+.6em} |
|
\mathrel{\tikz [>->,baseline=-.75ex] |
|
\draw (0,0) -- node[below=-2pt] {\box\xrat@below} |
|
node[above=-2pt] {\box\xrat@above} |
|
(\xrat@len,0) ;}} |
|
\makeatletter |
|
\usepackage{tikz} |
|
\newcommand{\xdasharrow}[2][->]{ |
|
\tikz[baseline=-\the\dimexpr\fontdimen22\textfont2\relax]{ |
|
\node[anchor=south,font=\scriptsize, inner ysep=1.5pt,outer xsep=2.2pt](x){$ #2$}; |
|
\draw[shorten <=3.4pt,shorten >=3.4pt,dashed,#1](x.south west)--(x.south east); |
|
} |
|
} |
|
\makeatother |
|
\newcommand\monad\underline |
|
\newcommand\return{\mathop{\mathrm{return}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\sreturn{\mathop{\textbf{return}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand{\bind}{\mathrel{\scalebox{0.8}[1]{\(>\!\!>\!=\)}}} |
|
\newcommand\GenMonad[4]{ |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
\textbf{in}&\multicolumn{2}{@{}l@{}}{\textbf{stance}\hphantom\ \mathrm{#1}\, (#3)\, \textbf{where}\qquad} #2\\ |
|
#4 |
|
\end{array} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand\GenMonadBreak[4]{ |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{}l@{}l@{\qquad}l@{}l@{}l@{}l@{}l@{}l@{}l@{}l} |
|
\textbf{in}&\multicolumn{2}{@{}l@{}}{\textbf{stance}\hphantom\ \mathrm{#1}\, (#3)\, \textbf{where}\qquad} #2\\[3pt] |
|
#4 |
|
\end{array} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand\Monad[4][]{ |
|
\GenMonad{Monad}{#1}{#2}{\\} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand\DiscMonad[7][]{ |
|
\GenMonad{Discrete\ Monad}{#1}{#2} |
|
{\\\\\\\\} |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\InferenceMonad[7][]{ |
|
\GenMonad{Inf\ Monad}{#1}{#2} |
|
{\\\\\\\\} |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\SampleMonad[6][]{ |
|
\GenMonad{Sampling\ Monad}{#1}{#2} |
|
{\\\\\\} |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\ScoreMonad[7][]{ |
|
\GenMonad{Conditioning\ Monad}{#1}{#2} |
|
{\\\\\\\\} |
|
} |
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand\DiscTrans[9][]{ |
|
\GenMonad{Inf\ Trans}{#1}{#2} |
|
{\\\\\\\\\\\\	} |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\DiscTransBreak[9][]{ |
|
\GenMonadBreak{Inf\ Trans}{#1}{#2} |
|
{&&\\&\\\\\\\\\\	} |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\RepTrans[9][]{ |
|
\GenMonad{\FromKind{#2}#3\ Trans} |
|
{#1} |
|
{#4} |
|
{\\\\\\\\	} |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\FromKind[1]{ |
|
\ifthenelse{\equal{#1}{Rep}} |
|
{} |
|
{#1\implies} |
|
} |
|
|
|
|
|
\WithSuffix\newcommand\<-{\mathrel{\leftarrow}} |
|
\newcommand\domon[1]{\textbf{do}\,\{#1\}} |
|
\newcommand\expdomon[2]{#1.\domon{#2}} |
|
\newcommand\strength{\mathop{\mathrm{str}}} |
|
\newcommand\balg[3]{\begin{array}{@{}l@{}l@{}}#1\end{array}#2\begin{array}{@{}l@{}l@{}}#3\end{array}} |
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand\sflip{\textbf{flip}} |
|
\newcommand\sscore{\mathop{\textbf{score}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\flip{\mathrm{flip}} |
|
\newcommand\score{\mathop{\mathrm{score}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\Mass{\mathop{\mathrm{Mass}}} |
|
\newcommand\restricted[1]{\big\lvert_{#1}} |
|
\newcommand{\support}{\mathop{\mathrm{supp}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\constantly\underline |
|
|
|
\newcommand\mean{\mathop{{}m}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\Mea{\mathop{\mathrm{{}M}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\Prob{\mathop{\mathrm{{}P}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\sub{\mathop{\mathrm{sub}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\Qmonad{\Mea} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\Term{\mathop{\mathrm{Term}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\Enum{\mathop{\mathrm{Enum}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\DSam{\mathop{\mathrm{DSam}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\Sam{\mathop{\mathrm{Sam}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\half{\tfrac12} |
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand\Writer{\mathop{{}\mathrm{W}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\itmap{\mathop{\mathrm{tmap}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\stmap{\mathop{\textbf{tmap}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\lift{\mathop{\mathrm{lift}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\slift{\mathop{\textbf{lift}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\ListT{\mathop{{}\mathrm{ListT}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\Pop{\mathop{{}\mathrm{Pop}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\Sus{\mathop{{}\mathrm{Sus}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\Seq\Sus |
|
\newcommand\WSam{\mathop{{}\mathrm{WSam}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand\noassumptions[1]{ |
|
\multicolumn{1}{@{}l@{}}{}&\multicolumn{1}{@{}l@{\definedby{}}}{ |
|
#1 |
|
} |
|
} |
|
\newenvironment{notation} |
|
{ |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{{}\tinf{}}l@{{}\definedby{}}l@{\ \ }l} |
|
\multicolumn{1}{@{}l@{}}{} |
|
& |
|
\multicolumn{1}{@{}l@{\ }}{ |
|
\text{Notation} |
|
} |
|
& |
|
\multicolumn{1}{@{}l}{ |
|
\text{Meaning} |
|
} |
|
& |
|
\multicolumn{1}{@{}l}{ |
|
\text{Terminology} |
|
} |
|
\\ |
|
\hline |
|
}{ |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\ignorespacesafterend |
|
} |
|
\newcommand\qdelta{\underline\delta} |
|
\DeclareSymbolFont{largesymbolsA}{U}{txexa}{m}{n} |
|
\DeclareMathSymbol{\sqintop}{\mathop}{largesymbolsA}{14} |
|
\DeclareMathSymbol{\sqiintop}{\mathop}{largesymbolsA}{80} |
|
\DeclareMathSymbol{\sqiiintop}{\mathop}{largesymbolsA}{82} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\qint{\sqintop} |
|
\newcommand\qiint{\sqiintop} |
|
\newcommand\qiiint{\sqiiintop} |
|
\newcommand\Exp[1][]{\mathop{\mathbb{E}^{\mathrlap{#1}}}} |
|
\newcommand\sampled{\sim} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\absc{\mathrel{<\kern-.4em<}} |
|
\newcommand\der[2]{\tfrac{\dif #1}{\dif #2}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand{\braid}[1][\ ]{\mathrm{swap}#1} |
|
\newcommand\bprod{\boxtimes} |
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand{\ismc}[1][\,]{\mathrm{smc}#1} |
|
\newcommand{\imodel}[1][\,]{\mathrm{model}#1} |
|
\newcommand\Sampling[1][\ ]{\mathrm{Sam}#1} |
|
\newcommand{\isample}[1][\,]{\mathrm{sample}#1} |
|
\newcommand{\iscore}[1][\,]{\mathrm{score}#1} |
|
|
|
\newcommand{\code}[1]{\lstinline{#1}} |
|
|
|
\lstset{basicstyle=\footnotesize\ttfamily} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand\Qbs{\Category{Qbs}} |
|
\newcommand\sample{\textbf{sample}} |
|
\newcommand\ssample{\mathrm{sample}} |
|
\newcommand\Uniform[1][]{\textbf{U}_{#1}} |
|
\newcommand\UniformD{\mathrm{Uniform}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\spawn{\mathop{\mathrm{spawn}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\dwrand{\mathop{\mathrm{dwrand}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\dwsampler{\mathop{\mathrm{dwsample}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\resample{\mathop{\mathrm{resample}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\fuel{\textit{fuel}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\result{\textit{result}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\fail{\mathrm{fail}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\spark{\mathop{\mathrm{spark}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\finish{\mathop{\mathrm{finish}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\adva{\mathop{\mathrm{advance}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\smc{\mathop{\mathrm{smc}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\rmsmc{\mathop{\mathrm{rmsmc}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\newcommand\mh[1][\pert]{\eta_{#1}} |
|
\newcommand\paths{\mathop{\mathrm{Paths}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\weight[1]{w_{#1}} |
|
\newcommand\valuate[1]{v_{#1}} |
|
\newcommand\Trace{\mathop{\mathrm{Tr}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand\iprior{\mathop{\mathrm{pri}}\nolimits} |
|
\newcommand{\UD}{\mathrm{U_D}} |
|
\newcommand\marginal{\mathop{\mathrm{marginal}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\isubterm{\mathop{\mathrm{sub}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\itake{\mathop{\mathrm{take}}\nolimits} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\usepackage{booktabs} |
|
\usepackage{subcaption} |
|
|
|
\setcopyright{rightsretained} |
|
\acmPrice{} |
|
\acmDOI{10.1145/3158148} |
|
\acmYear{2018} |
|
\copyrightyear{2018} |
|
\acmJournal{PACMPL} |
|
\acmVolume{2} |
|
\acmNumber{POPL} |
|
\acmArticle{60} |
|
\acmMonth{1} |
|
|
|
\bibliographystyle{ACM-Reference-Format} |
|
\citestyle{acmauthoryear} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{document} |
|
|
|
\title{Denotational Validation of Higher-Order Bayesian Inference} |
|
\author{Adam \'Scibior} |
|
\email{ams240@cam.ac.uk} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\department{Department of Engineering} |
|
\institution{University of Cambridge} |
|
\streetaddress{Trumpington Street} |
|
\city{Cambridge} |
|
\postcode{CB2 1PZ} |
|
\country{England} |
|
} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\department{Empirical Inference Deparment} |
|
\institution{Max Planck Institute for Intelligent Systems} |
|
\streetaddress{Spemannstrasse 34} |
|
\city{T\"ubingen} |
|
\postcode{72076} |
|
\country{Germany} |
|
} |
|
\author{Ohad Kammar} |
|
\orcid{0000-0002-2071-0929} |
|
\email{ohad.kammar@cs.ox.ac.uk} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\institution{University of Oxford} |
|
\department{Department of Computer Science} |
|
\streetaddress{Wolfson Building, Parks Road} |
|
\city{Oxford} |
|
\postcode{OX1 3QD} |
|
\country{England} |
|
} |
|
\author{Matthijs V\'ak\'ar} |
|
\email{matthijs.vakar@magd.ox.ac.uk} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\institution{University of Oxford} |
|
\department{Department of Computer Science} |
|
\streetaddress{Wolfson Building, Parks Road} |
|
\city{Oxford} |
|
\postcode{OX1 3QD} |
|
\country{England} |
|
} |
|
\author{Sam Staton} |
|
\email{sam.staton@cs.ox.ac.uk} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\institution{University of Oxford} |
|
\department{Department of Computer Science} |
|
\streetaddress{Wolfson Building, Parks Road} |
|
\city{Oxford} |
|
\postcode{OX1 3QD} |
|
\country{England} |
|
} |
|
\author{Hongseok Yang} |
|
\email{Hongseok.Yang@cs.ox.ac.uk} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\institution{KAIST} |
|
\country{South Korea} |
|
} |
|
\author{Yufei Cai} |
|
\email{yufei.cai@uni-tuebingen.de} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\institution{Universit\"at T\"ubingen} |
|
\department{Programming Languages and Software Technology} |
|
\streetaddress{Sand 13} |
|
\city{T\"ubingen} |
|
\postcode{72076} |
|
\country{Germany} |
|
} |
|
\author{Klaus Ostermann} |
|
\email{klaus.ostermann@uni-tuebingen.de} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\institution{Universit\"at T\"ubingen} |
|
\department{Programming Languages and Software Technology} |
|
\streetaddress{Sand 13} |
|
\city{T\"ubingen} |
|
\postcode{72076} |
|
\country{Germany} |
|
} |
|
\author{Sean K.~Moss} |
|
\email{S.K.Moss@dpmms.cam.ac.uk} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\department{Department of Pure Mathematics and Mathematical Statistics} |
|
\institution{University of Cambridge} |
|
\streetaddress{Centre for Mathematical Sciences, Wilberforce Road} |
|
\city{Cambridge} |
|
\postcode{CB3 0WB} |
|
\country{England} |
|
} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\department{University College} |
|
\institution{University of Oxford} |
|
\streetaddress{High Street} |
|
\city{Oxford} |
|
\postcode{OX1 4BH} |
|
\country{England} |
|
} |
|
\author{Chris Heunen} |
|
\email{chris.heunen@ed.ac.uk} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\department{School of Informatics} |
|
\institution{University of Edinburgh} |
|
\streetaddress{Informatics Forum, 10 Crichton Street} |
|
\city{Edinburgh} |
|
\postcode{EH8 9AB} |
|
\country{Scotland} |
|
} |
|
\author{Zoubin Ghahramani} |
|
\email{zoubin@eng.cam.ac.uk} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\department{Department of Engineering} |
|
\institution{University of Cambridge} |
|
\streetaddress{Trumpington Street} |
|
\city{Cambridge} |
|
\postcode{CB2 1PZ} |
|
\country{England} |
|
} |
|
\affiliation{ |
|
\institution{Uber AI Labs} |
|
\city{San Francisco} |
|
\country{California, USA} |
|
} |
|
|
|
\newcommand\newshortauthors{ |
|
\'Scibior, Kammar, V\'ak\'ar, Staton, Yang, Cai, Ostermann, Moss, Heunen, and Ghahramani |
|
} |
|
\authorsaddresses{} |
|
\begin{abstract} |
|
We present a modular semantic account of Bayesian inference algorithms for |
|
probabilistic programming languages, as used in data |
|
science and machine learning. Sophisticated inference algorithms are |
|
often explained in terms of composition of smaller parts. However, |
|
neither their theoretical justification nor their implementation |
|
reflects this modularity. We show how to conceptualise and analyse |
|
such inference algorithms as manipulating intermediate |
|
representations of probabilistic programs using higher-order |
|
functions and inductive types, and their denotational semantics. |
|
|
|
Semantic accounts of continuous distributions use measurable |
|
spaces. However, our use of higher-order functions presents a |
|
substantial technical difficulty: it is impossible to define a |
|
measurable space structure over the collection of measurable |
|
functions between arbitrary measurable spaces that is compatible |
|
with standard operations on those functions, such as function |
|
application. We overcome this difficulty using quasi-Borel spaces, |
|
a recently proposed mathematical structure that supports both |
|
function spaces and continuous distributions. |
|
|
|
We define a class of semantic structures for representing |
|
probabilistic programs, and semantic validity criteria for |
|
transformations of these representations in terms of distribution |
|
preservation. We develop a collection of building blocks for |
|
composing representations. We use these building blocks to validate |
|
common inference algorithms such as Sequential Monte Carlo and |
|
Markov Chain Monte Carlo. To emphasize the connection between the semantic manipulation and its traditional measure theoretic origins, we use Kock's |
|
synthetic measure theory. We demonstrate its usefulness by proving a |
|
quasi-Borel counterpart to the Metropolis-Hastings-Green |
|
theorem. |
|
\end{abstract} |
|
\begin{CCSXML} |
|
\begin{CCSXML} |
|
<ccs2012> |
|
<concept> |
|
<concept_id>10002950.10003648.10003670.10003677.10003679</concept_id> |
|
<concept_desc>Mathematics of computing~Metropolis-Hastings algorithm</concept_desc> |
|
<concept_significance>500</concept_significance> |
|
</concept> |
|
<concept> |
|
<concept_id>10002950.10003648.10003670.10003682</concept_id> |
|
<concept_desc>Mathematics of computing~Sequential Monte Carlo methods</concept_desc> |
|
<concept_significance>500</concept_significance> |
|
</concept> |
|
<concept> |
|
<concept_id>10003752.10003753.10003757</concept_id> |
|
<concept_desc>Theory of computation~Probabilistic computation</concept_desc> |
|
<concept_significance>500</concept_significance> |
|
</concept> |
|
<concept> |
|
<concept_id>10003752.10010070.10010071.10010077</concept_id> |
|
<concept_desc>Theory of computation~Bayesian analysis</concept_desc> |
|
<concept_significance>500</concept_significance> |
|
</concept> |
|
<concept> |
|
<concept_id>10003752.10010124.10010131.10010133</concept_id> |
|
<concept_desc>Theory of computation~Denotational semantics</concept_desc> |
|
<concept_significance>500</concept_significance> |
|
</concept> |
|
<concept> |
|
<concept_id>10011007.10011006.10011008.10011009</concept_id> |
|
<concept_desc>Software and its engineering~Language types</concept_desc> |
|
<concept_significance>500</concept_significance> |
|
</concept> |
|
<concept> |
|
<concept_id>10011007.10011006.10011008.10011009.10011012</concept_id> |
|
<concept_desc>Software and its engineering~Functional languages</concept_desc> |
|
<concept_significance>300</concept_significance> |
|
</concept> |
|
<concept> |
|
<concept_id>10011007.10011006.10011041.10010943</concept_id> |
|
<concept_desc>Software and its engineering~Interpreters</concept_desc> |
|
<concept_significance>300</concept_significance> |
|
</concept> |
|
<concept> |
|
<concept_id>10011007.10011006.10011050.10011017</concept_id> |
|
<concept_desc>Software and its engineering~Domain specific languages</concept_desc> |
|
<concept_significance>100</concept_significance> |
|
</concept> |
|
<concept> |
|
<concept_id>10010147.10010257</concept_id> |
|
<concept_desc>Computing methodologies~Machine learning</concept_desc> |
|
<concept_significance>300</concept_significance> |
|
</concept> |
|
</ccs2012> |
|
\end{CCSXML} |
|
|
|
\ccsdesc[500]{Mathematics of computing~Metropolis-Hastings algorithm} |
|
\ccsdesc[500]{Mathematics of computing~Sequential Monte Carlo methods} |
|
\ccsdesc[500]{Theory of computation~Probabilistic computation} |
|
\ccsdesc[500]{Theory of computation~Bayesian analysis} |
|
\ccsdesc[500]{Theory of computation~Denotational semantics} |
|
\ccsdesc[500]{Software and its engineering~Language types} |
|
\ccsdesc[300]{Software and its engineering~Functional languages} |
|
\ccsdesc[300]{Software and its engineering~Interpreters} |
|
\ccsdesc[100]{Software and its engineering~Domain specific languages} |
|
\ccsdesc[300]{Computing methodologies~Machine learning} |
|
\keywords{quasi-Borel spaces, synthetic measure theory, |
|
Bayesian inference, applied category theory, |
|
commutative monads, Kock integration, initial algebra semantics, |
|
sigma-monoids} |
|
|
|
|
|
\maketitle |
|
\renewcommand{\shortauthors}{\newshortauthors} |
|
\begin{acks} |
|
|
|
Supported by a Royal Society University Research Fellowship, |
|
Institute for Information \& Communications Technology Promotion |
|
(IITP) grant funded by the Korea government (MSIP) No.~R0190-16-2011 |
|
`Development of Vulnerability Discovery Technologies for IoT |
|
Software Security', Engineering and Physical Sciences Research |
|
Council (ESPRC) Early Career Fellowship EP/L002388/1 `Combining |
|
viewpoints in quantum theory', an EPSRC studentship and grants |
|
EP/N007387/1 `Quantum computation as a programming language' and |
|
EP/M023974/1 `Compositional higher-order model checking: logics, |
|
models, and algorithms', a Balliol College Oxford Career Development |
|
Fellowship, and a University College Oxford Junior Research |
|
Fellowship. We would like to thank Samson Abramsky, Thorsten |
|
Altenkirch, Bob Coecke, Mathieu Huot, Radha Jagadeesan, Dexter |
|
Kozen, Paul B.~Levy, and the anonymous reviewers for fruitful |
|
discussions and suggestions. |
|
\end{acks} |
|
|
|
\section{Introduction} |
|
One of the key challenges in Bayesian data analysis is to develop or find |
|
an efficient algorithm for estimating the |
|
posterior distribution of a probabilistic model with respect to a given |
|
data set. This posterior distribution combines prior knowledge encoded |
|
in the model and information present in the data set consistently according |
|
to the rules of probability theory, but its mathematical definition often |
|
involves integration or summation over a large index set |
|
and does not yield to an efficient computation strategy immediately. |
|
A data scientist typically has to make one of the suboptimal decisions: |
|
she has to consult a large body of specialised |
|
research in order to pick an algorithm suitable for her model, or |
|
to change the model so that it falls into one of those cases with efficient known |
|
algorithms for posterior inference, or to face the challenge directly |
|
by developing a new algorithm for herself. |
|
|
|
Recent probabilistic programming languages aim to |
|
resolve this dilemma. They include constructs for describing |
|
probability distributions and conditioning, and enable data |
|
scientists to express sophisticated probabilistic models as programs. |
|
More importantly, they come with the implementation of multiple algorithms for |
|
performing posterior inference for models and data sets |
|
expressed in the languages. The grand vision is that by using these languages, |
|
a data scientist no longer has to worry about the choice or design of |
|
such an inference algorithm but focuses on the design of an appropriate model, instead. |
|
|
|
In this paper, we provide a denotational validation of inference algorithms |
|
for higher-order probabilistic programming languages, such as Church~\cite{goodman_uai_2008}, |
|
Anglican~\cite{wood-aistats-2014} and Venture~\cite{Mansinghka-venture14}. The correctness of these |
|
algorithms is subtle. The early version of the lightweight Metropolis-Hastings algorithm |
|
had a bug because of an incorrect acceptance ratio \cite{Wingate2011}. The correctness |
|
often relies on intricate interplay between facts from probability theory |
|
and those from programming language theory. Moreover, correctness typically requires |
|
stronger results from probability theory than those used for the usual |
|
$\reals^n$ case in the machine-learning community |
|
(e.g., Green's measure-theoretic justification of Markov |
|
Chain Monte Carlo rather than the usual one for $\reals^n$ |
|
based on density functions). |
|
|
|
Our starting point is the body of existing results on validating inference algorithms for probabilistic |
|
programs~\cite{HurNRS15,BorgstromLGS-icfp16}. |
|
Those earlier results tend to be based on operational semantics, and often (not always) focus on first-order programs. |
|
By working in a modular way with monads, denotational semantics and higher-order functions, we are able to validate |
|
sophisticated inference algorithms, such as resample-move Sequential Monte Carlo~\cite{doucet-johansen:smc-tutorial11}, |
|
that are complex yet modular, being composed of smaller reusable components, by combining our semantic |
|
analysis of these components. |
|
|
|
The probabilistic programming language considered in the paper includes |
|
continuous distributions, which means that semantic accounts |
|
of them or their inference algorithms need to use measure theory and Lebesgue integration. |
|
Meanwhile, our semantic account uses a meta-language |
|
with higher-order functions for specifying and interpreting intermediate |
|
representations of probabilistic programs that are manipulated by |
|
components of inference algorithms. |
|
Such higher-order functions let us achieve modularity and handle |
|
higher-order functions in the target probabilistic programming language. |
|
These two features cause a tension because it is impossible to define a |
|
measurable space structure over the collection of measurable |
|
functions between arbitrary measurable spaces that is compatible |
|
with standard operations on those functions, such as function |
|
application. We resolve the tension using quasi-Borel spaces~\cite{HeunenKSY-lics17}, |
|
a recently proposed mathematical structure that supports both |
|
function spaces and continuous distributions. |
|
|
|
We define a semantic class of structures for |
|
various intermediate representations of probabilistic programs, |
|
and semantic validity criteria for |
|
transformations of these representations in terms of distribution |
|
preservation. We develop a collection of building blocks for |
|
composing representations. We use these building blocks to validate |
|
common inference algorithms such as Sequential Monte Carlo and |
|
Markov Chain Monte Carlo. To emphasize the connection between the semantic manipulation and its traditional measure theoretic origins, we use Kock's |
|
synthetic measure theory. We demonstrate its usefulness by proving a |
|
quasi-Borel counterpart to the Metropolis-Hastings-Green |
|
theorem. |
|
|
|
To ease the presentation, we proceed in two steps. First, we present |
|
our development in the discrete setting, where the set-theoretic |
|
account is simpler and more accessible. Then, after |
|
developing an appropriate mathematical toolbox, we transfer this |
|
account to the continuous case. Inference in the continuous setting, |
|
while conceptually very similar to the discrete case, is inseparable |
|
from our development. The semantic foundation for continuous |
|
distributions over higher-order functions has been very problematic in |
|
the past. The fact that our approach \emph{does} generalise to the |
|
continuous case, and does so smoothly, is one of our significant |
|
contributions, only brought about through the careful combination of |
|
quasi-Borel spaces, synthetic measure theory, the meta-language, and |
|
the inference building blocks. |
|
|
|
|
|
The rest of the paper is structured as follows. |
|
\secref{calculus} presents a core calculus, our metalanguage, with its type system and |
|
set-theoretic denotational semantics. |
|
\secref{discrete} presents the core ideas of our development in a |
|
simpler discrete set-theoretic setting. |
|
\secref{preliminaries} reviews the mathematical concepts required for |
|
dealing with continuous distributions. |
|
\secref{continuous} presents representations and transformations for |
|
continuous distributions. |
|
\secref{SMC} decomposes the common Sequential Monte Carlo inference |
|
algorithm into simpler inference representations and |
|
transformations. |
|
\secref{MHG} similarly decomposes the general Trace |
|
Markov Chain Monte Carlo algorithm. |
|
\secref{conclusion} concludes. |
|
Basic results in synthetic measure theory are listed for the reader's convenience in Appendix \ref{sec:kock-equations}. |
|
|
|
\commentout{ |
|
\hy{Plan. |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item Background and problem. Probabilistic programming. Vision. One major challenge is to design and implement efficient and correct inference algorithms. A large body of work on improving efficiency with a wide range of techniques. Warning: unless careful, we get something incorrect. Story about incorrect implementation of a lightweight Metropolis-Hastings algorithm in the early implementations of probabilistic programming systems. |
|
\item Our results. Compositional construction of inference algorithms from components or modules, which come with |
|
correctness arguments. Novel use of semantics. Large amount of new work. Synthetic measure theory. |
|
Generalised Green theorem. Annecdote. Often the correctness of LMH is argued based on |
|
reversible-jump MCMC. |
|
\item Difficulties and ideas. Higher-order. Algorithms that do not preserve semantics. How to formulate correctness at all? QBS. Approximation in the semantics function, which happens only at the end. |
|
\item Illustration. Easy implementation of a correct advanced MC algorithm simply by composing existing components. |
|
\item Speculation 1. Ultimate vision: automatically choose a right inference algorithm for |
|
each piece of code, and put these chosen algorithms together. Enabler for future research. |
|
MC and deterministic algorithms together. Algorithms |
|
designed for special kinds of models, variable elimination, Kalman filter, Hamiltonian |
|
Monte Carlo, reparameterisation trick in BBVI. Automatically selected for each part |
|
of a given program. |
|
\item Speculation 2. Connection with program analysis. Instrumented non-standard semantics. |
|
Inference algorithm - operational semantics in a sense. Denotational semantics. |
|
Improvement formalised denotationally. |
|
\item Cons and pros. No convergence. Mostly focus on the preservation of the invariant distribution. |
|
Interesting future work. Practical convergence guarantee. But can handle higher-order |
|
functions. Compositional. Say something about Andy's work. Daniel Wang's work. Gil's |
|
FSTTCS paper. Not quite LMH algorithm. No higher-order nor combination. A particular |
|
choice of underlying measurable space based on global variables. Compositional |
|
in a sense, but no correctness guarantee. Only for the construction of a proposal for |
|
MCMC, a particular inference algorithm. |
|
\item Something to cite. Andy's work. Daniel Wang. Major PP systems, Church, WebPPL, Stan, Aditya's |
|
system, PyMC, Venture, Hakaru, Edward, Infer.NET, Scala-based one. |
|
Compositional inference - Wang's work a little bit, |
|
Adam's previous work, Vikash's PPS workshop paper at least, nested inference by Goodman etc. |
|
Semantics. Ramsey and his colleague on monad. Old ESOP paper. Source of randomness explicit, |
|
and similar to our seed monad. Our LICS papers. Plotkin's domain-theoretic approach. |
|
Anglican's SMC and various variants (ASMC, PMCMC, ASPMCMC, IPMCMC). |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
} |
|
|
|
|
|
\ok{Need to be careful and stress that we do not deal with |
|
convergence. (For example, Andy Gordon et al. have gone to a |
|
\emph{lot} of trouble to show convergence, and they'll be quite |
|
annoyed if we fail to mention this issue.)} |
|
|
|
\ok{core idea: Our development consists of three conceptual |
|
steps. First, we identify an appropriate semantic structure for the |
|
probabilistic programming language at hand as a suitable |
|
(category-theoretic) \emph{monad}. Next, we define the interface |
|
each representation of a probabilistic program should support and |
|
the invariants it must satisfy, and call the resulting abstraction |
|
an \emph{inference representation}. We define that a transformation |
|
from one representation to another is \emph{valid} when it preserves |
|
the semantics, calling this abstraction an \emph{inference |
|
transformation}. Finally, the two notions combine to that of an |
|
\emph{inference transformer}: a construction transforming every |
|
inference representation into another inference representation, and |
|
an inference transformation between representations into a |
|
transformation between their transformed representations.} |
|
|
|
\ok{When discussing synthetic measure theory (SMT): SMT has two |
|
advantages. First, we can port proof ideas with very little change |
|
from measure theory to quasi-Borel spaces. Second, we decouple our |
|
development from a specific choice of probability monad. So if we do |
|
find a suitable ranked s-finite measure monad, a lot less would |
|
change in our development.} |
|
|
|
\ok{ Can mention the difference between \emph{statistical} complexity |
|
(how many times/steps do we need to run our simulation to converge) |
|
and \emph{computational} complexity (how long does it take to run |
|
one iteration of the simulation). According to Adam, the main |
|
bottleneck is usually the statistical complexity, and so we are not |
|
too concerned with computation complexity. Nonetheless, we benchmark |
|
both in the implementation section.} |
|
|
|
\ok{Motivate the use of a calculus: |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item easier to show that functions of interest are structure-preserving |
|
\item more accessible |
|
\item brings closer the semantic foundation and our implementation |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
No worries if not all/any of it doesn't fit, we can move whatever is |
|
left into the intro to \secref{calculus}. } |
|
|
|
\ok{Stress that the core calculus is a tool. Our goal is to give a |
|
semantic development, and the syntactic development is only there to |
|
make it easy for us to define things semantically.} |
|
} |
|
\section{The core calculus}\seclabel{calculus} |
|
We use a variant of the simply-typed $\lambda$-calculus with sums and |
|
inductive types, base types and constructors, primitives, and |
|
primitive recursion, but without effects. We also use monad-like |
|
constructs in the spirit of \citepos*{Moggi89}{computational |
|
$\lambda$-calculus}. The core calculus is very simple, and at |
|
places we need an inherently semantic treatment, which the core |
|
calculus alone cannot express. In those cases, we resort directly to |
|
the semantic structures, sets or spaces. However, the calculus still |
|
serves a very important purpose: every type and function expressed in |
|
it denote well-formed objects and well-formed morphisms. In the |
|
continuous case, using this calculus yields correct-by-construction |
|
quasi-Borel spaces and their morphisms, avoiding a tedious and |
|
error-prone manual verification. Using the core calculus also brings |
|
our theoretical development closer to potential implementations in |
|
functional languages. |
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Syntax} |
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{syntax} |
|
\ty,\ty[2],\ty[3] & \gdefinedby & &\syncat{types} \\ |
|
& & \tvar &\synname{positive variable}\\ |
|
&\gor& \Variant{ |
|
\Inj{\Cns_1}{\ty_1} |
|
\vor \ldots \vor |
|
\Inj{\Cns_n}{\ty_n} |
|
} &\synname{variant} \\ |
|
&\gor& \Unit ~\gor~ \ty \t* \ty[2] & \synname{finite product} \\ |
|
&\gor& \rec \tvar \ty & \synname{inductive type} \\ |
|
\end{syntax} |
|
~ |
|
\begin{syntax} |
|
\\ |
|
&\gor& \ty \To \ty[2] & \synname{function} \\ |
|
&\gor& \Type & \synname{base}\\ |
|
&\gor& \Functor \ty&\synname{base constructors}\\ |
|
\multicolumn{3}{@{}l@{}}{\ctx \definedby{} x_1 : \ty_1, \ldots, x_n : \ty_n }& \syncat{variable contexts} |
|
\end{syntax} |
|
|
|
\begin{tabular}{cc} |
|
{\begin{syntax} |
|
\trm, \trm[2], \trm[3] & \gdefinedby & & \syncat{terms} \\ |
|
& & \var & \synname{variable} \\ |
|
&\gor&\tInj\ty\Cns\trm & \synname{variant constructor} \\ |
|
&\gor& \tUnit |
|
\ \gor\ \tpair{\trm}{\trm[2]} & \synname{nullary and binary tuples} \\ |
|
&\gor& \troll\ty & \synname{iso-inductive constructor} \\ |
|
&\gor& \expfun \var\ty \trm & \synname{function abstraction} \\ |
|
&\gor& \mathrlap{\begin{array}[t]{@{}r@{\,}l@{}l@{}}\vmatch {\trm \\} |
|
{ |
|
&\Inj{\Cns_1}{\var_1}\To{\trm[2]_1} |
|
\vor \cdots |
|
\vor \Inj{\Cns_n}{\var_n}\To{\trm[2]_n} |
|
}\end{array}} & \synname{pattern matching: variants} |
|
\end{syntax} |
|
}& |
|
{\begin{syntax}&\hphantom{\gdefinedby}\\ |
|
&\gor& \mathrlap{\begin{array}[t]{@{}r@{\,}l@{}l@{}}\pmatch |
|
{\trm\\} |
|
{&\var[1]}{\var[2]} |
|
{\trm[2]} |
|
\end{array}} |
|
& \synname{binary products} \\ |
|
&\gor& \mathrlap{\begin{array}[t]{@{}r@{\,}l@{}l@{}} |
|
\rmatch[{&}] |
|
{\trm\\} |
|
\var{\trm[2]} |
|
\end{array}} |
|
& \synname{inductive types} \\ |
|
|
|
&\gor& \tfold\ty\trm & \synname{inductive recursion} \\ |
|
&\gor& \trm\, \trm[2] & \synname{function application} \\ |
|
&\gor& \tcts & \synname{primitive} |
|
\end{syntax} |
|
}\end{tabular} |
|
\caption{Core calculus types (top) and terms (bottom)}\figlabel{types}\figlabel{terms} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
\figref{types}~(top) presents the types of our core calculus. To support |
|
inductive types, we include type variables, taken from a countable set |
|
ranged over by $\tvar, \tvar[2], \tvar[3], \ldots$. Our kind system |
|
will later ensure these type variables are \emph{strictly positive}: |
|
they can only appear free covariantly --- to the right of a |
|
function type. Variant types use constructor labels taken from a |
|
countable set ranged over by $\Cns, \Cns_1, \Cns_2, \ldots$. Variant |
|
types are in fact partial functions with a finite domain from the set |
|
of constructor labels to the set of types. When $\ty[2]$ is a variant |
|
type, we write $(\Inj\Cns \ty) \in \ty[2]$ for the assertion that |
|
$\ty[2]$ assigns the type $\ty$ to $\Cns$. We include the standard |
|
unit type, binary products, and function types. We include unary |
|
uninterpreted base types and constructors. While we use a list syntax |
|
for variable contexts $\ctx$, they are in fact partial functions with |
|
a finite domain from the countable set of variables, ranged over by |
|
$\var, \var[2], \var[3], \ldots$, to the set of types. |
|
|
|
We desugar stand-alone labels in a variant type |
|
$\Variant{\cdots \vor \Inj\Cns \vor \cdots}$ to the unit type |
|
$\Variant{\cdots \vor \Inj\Cns\tUnit \vor \cdots}$. We also desugar |
|
seemingly-recursive type declarations |
|
$\ty \definedby \subst{\ty[2]}{\sfor \tvar\ty}$ to |
|
$\ty \definedby \rec\tvar\ty[2]$. |
|
|
|
\begin{example}\examplelabel{types} |
|
The type of booleans is given by \( |
|
\boolty \definedby \Variant{\tru \vor \fls} |
|
\). |
|
The type of natural numbers is given by \( |
|
\naturals |
|
\definedby |
|
\Variant{\Inj[]{Zero} |
|
\vor \Inj{Succ}\naturals} |
|
\) |
|
desugaring to \( |
|
\naturals |
|
\definedby \rec \tvar |
|
\Variant{\Inj[]{Zero} |
|
\vor \Inj{Succ}\tvar} |
|
\). |
|
The type of $\alpha$-lists is given by |
|
\( |
|
\List\tvar |
|
\definedby |
|
\Variant{ |
|
\Inj[]{Nil} |
|
\vor |
|
\Inj{Cons}{\tvar\t* \List\tvar} |
|
} |
|
\), desugaring to |
|
\( |
|
\List\tvar |
|
\definedby |
|
\rec{\tvar[2]}\Variant{ |
|
\Inj[]{Nil} |
|
\vor |
|
\Inj{Cons}{\tvar\t* \tvar[2]} |
|
} |
|
\). |
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
Base types and constructors allow us to include semantic type |
|
declarations into our calculus. For example, we will always include |
|
the following base types: |
|
\begin{center} |
|
\vspace{-.4cm} |
|
\begin{tabular}{@{}*3{l}@{}} |
|
\textbullet\ $\I\,\, $: unit interval $[0,1]$; & |
|
\textbullet\ $\ereals $: extended real line $[-\infty, \infty]$; & |
|
\textbullet\ $\ereals+$: non-negative extended reals \\ |
|
\textbullet\ $\reals $: real line $(-\infty, \infty)$; & |
|
\textbullet\ $\reals+ $: non-negative reals $[0, \infty)$; and & |
|
\hspace{.75cm}$[0, \infty]$. |
|
\end{tabular} |
|
\end{center} |
|
In addition, once we define a type constructor such as $\List\tvar$, |
|
we will later reuse it as a base type constructor $\List\ty$, |
|
effectively working in an extended calculus. Thus we are working with |
|
a family of calculi, extending the base signature with each type |
|
definition in our development. |
|
|
|
\figref{terms}~(bottom) presents the terms in our core calculus. Variant |
|
constructor terms $\tInj\ty\Cns\trm$ are annotated with their variant |
|
type $\ty$ to avoid label clashes. The tupling constructors are |
|
standard. We use \emph{iso-inductive} types: construction of inductive |
|
types requires an explicit rolling of the inductive definition such as |
|
$\troll\naturals{(\Inj[]{Zero}\tUnit)}$. Variable binding in function |
|
abstraction is \emph{intrinsically typed} in standard Church-style. We |
|
include standard pattern matching constructs for variants, binary |
|
products, and inductive types. We include a structural recursion |
|
construct $\tfold\ty$ for every inductive type $\ty$. Function |
|
application is standard, as is the inclusion of primitives. |
|
|
|
|
|
To ease the construction of terms, we use the standard syntactic sugar |
|
(e.g. $\letin\var \trm{\trm[2]}$ for $(\fun \var\trm)\trm[2]$, |
|
$\tif{\,}{\,}{}$ for pattern matching booleans), |
|
informally elide types from the terms, elide $\roll$ing/unrolling inductive types, |
|
and informally use nested pattern matching. |
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{example}\examplelabel{terms} |
|
For $\List \ty = |
|
\rec{\tvar}\Variant{ |
|
\Inj[]{Nil} |
|
\vor |
|
\Inj{Cons}{\ty\t* \tvar} |
|
}$, we can express standard list manipulation: |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
x :: x_s &= \Inj[]{Cons}{\tpair x{x_s}} |
|
& |
|
\foldlist a f &= \tfold{\List \ty} \pfun { |
|
\Inj[]{{Nil}} \To a |
|
\vor{}\Inj{{Cons}}{\tpair{x}{b}\ } \To f(x, b) |
|
} |
|
\\ |
|
x_s \++ y_s &= \foldlist {y_s}{(::)}\ x_s |
|
& |
|
\tmap f\, x_s |
|
&= |
|
\foldlist {\lst-} {(\pfun{\tpair{y}{y_s}\To\tpair{f(y)}{y_s}})} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
where we abbreviate $\lst{a_1, \ldots ,a_n}$ to |
|
\( |
|
\Inj{{Cons}}{\tpair{a_1}{\ldots,\Inj{{Cons}}{\tpair{a_n}{\Inj[]{{Nil}}}\ldots}}} |
|
\). |
|
|
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
\subsection{Type system} |
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}c@{}} |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
~ |
|
}{ |
|
\Dkinf \tvar |
|
} |
|
(\tvar \in \Tyctx) |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\text{for all $1 \leq i \leq n$: } |
|
\Dkinf {\ty_i} |
|
}{ |
|
\Dkinf{\Variant{ |
|
\Inj{\Cns_1}{\ty_1} |
|
\vor \ldots \vor |
|
\Inj{\Cns_n}{\ty_n} |
|
}} |
|
} |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
~ |
|
}{ |
|
\Dkinf\Unit |
|
} |
|
\\ |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\Dkinf{\ty} |
|
\\ |
|
\Dkinf{\ty[2]} |
|
}{ |
|
\Dkinf{\ty\t*\ty[2]} |
|
} |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\Dkinf[, \tvar]{\ty} |
|
}{ |
|
\Dkinf{\rec \tvar \ty} |
|
} |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\shade{\kinf \ty : \typ} |
|
\\ |
|
\Dkinf{\ty[2]} |
|
}{ |
|
\Dkinf{\ty \To \ty[2]} |
|
} |
|
\\ |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
~ |
|
}{ |
|
\Dkinf{\Type} |
|
} |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\Dkinf \ty |
|
}{ |
|
\Dkinf{\Functor \ty} |
|
} |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\text{for all $(x : \ty) \in \ctx$: } |
|
\kinf \ty : \typ |
|
}{ |
|
\kinf{\ctx} : \context |
|
} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\caption{Core calculus kind system}\figlabel{kind system} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
To ensure the well-formedness of types, which involve type variables, |
|
we use a simple kind system, presented in \figref{kind system}. Each |
|
kinding judgement $\Dkinf\ty$ asserts that a given type $\ty$ is |
|
well-formed in the \emph{type variable context} $\Tyctx$, which is |
|
finite set of type variables. |
|
|
|
The kinding judgements are standard. All type variables must be bound |
|
by the enclosing context, or by an inductive type binder. The |
|
contravariant position in the function type $\ty[1] \To \ty[2]$ must |
|
contain a \emph{closed} type, ensuring that free type variables can |
|
only appear in strictly positive positions. Variable contexts $\ctx$ |
|
must only assign closed types. |
|
|
|
\begin{example} |
|
The types from \exampleref{types} are well-kinded: |
|
$\kinf \boolty, \naturals, \List\tvar : \typ$. |
|
\end{example} |
|
We define capture avoiding substitution of types for type variables in |
|
the standard way, which obeys the usual structural |
|
properties. Henceforth we consider only well-formed types in context, |
|
leaving the context implicit wherever possible, and gloss over issues |
|
of alpha-convertibility of bound type variables. |
|
|
|
To type terms, we assume each primitive $\tcts$ has a well-formed type |
|
$\kinf \ty_{\tcts} : \typ$ associated with it. \figref{type system} |
|
presents the resulting type system. Each typing judgement |
|
$\Ginf\trm\ty$ asserts that a given term $\trm$ is well-typed |
|
with the well-formed closed type $\kinf \ty : \typ$ in the |
|
variable context $\kinf \ctx : \context$. |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}c@{}} |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
~ |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf \var\ty |
|
}((\var : \ty) \in \ctx) |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\Ginf\trm{\ty_i} |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf{\tInj\ty{\Cns_i}\trm}{\ty} |
|
}((\Inj{\Cns_i}\ty_i) \in \ty) |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
~ |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf\tUnit\Unit |
|
} |
|
\\ |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\Ginf {\trm[1]}{\ty[1]} |
|
\\ |
|
\Ginf {\trm[2]}{\ty[2]} |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf{\tpair{\trm[1]}{\trm[2]}}{\ty[1] \t* \ty[2]} |
|
} |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
~ |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf{\troll\ty}{\parent{\subst{\ty[2]}{\sfor{\tvar}{\ty}}}\To\ty} |
|
}(\ty = \rec\tvar\ty[2]) |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\Ginf[, \var : \ty]{\trm}{\ty[2]} |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf{\expfun \var\ty\trm}{\ty\To\ty[2]} |
|
} |
|
\\ |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\Ginf\trm{\Variant{ |
|
\Inj{\Cns_1}{\ty_1} |
|
\vor \ldots \vor |
|
\Inj{\Cns_n}{\ty_n}}} |
|
\\ |
|
\text{for each $1 \leq i \leq n$: } |
|
\Ginf[, \var_i : \ty_i]{\trm[2]_i}{\ty} |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf{\vmatch \trm |
|
{\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{\,}l@{}l@{}} |
|
\Inj{\Cns_1}{\var_1}\To{\trm[2]_1} |
|
\vor\cdots |
|
\vor\Inj{\Cns_n}{\var_n}&\To{\trm[2]_n} |
|
}} |
|
\ty |
|
\end{array} |
|
} |
|
\\ |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\Ginf{\trm}{\ty[2]\t*\ty[3]} |
|
\\ |
|
\Ginf[,{\var[1] : \ty[2], \var[2] : \ty[3]}]{\trm[2]}\ty |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf{\pmatch |
|
\trm |
|
{\var[1]}{\var[2]} |
|
{\trm[2]}}{\ty} |
|
} |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\Ginf{\trm}{\rec\tvar\ty[2]} |
|
\\ |
|
\Ginf[,{\var : \subst{\ty[2]}{\sfor\tvar{\rec\tvar\ty[2]}}}]{\trm[2]}\ty |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf{\rmatch |
|
\trm |
|
{\var} |
|
{\trm[2]}}{\ty} |
|
} |
|
\\ |
|
|
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\Ginf\trm{\parent{\subst{\ty[2]}{\sfor\tvar{\ty[3]}}}\To \ty[3]} |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf{\tfold\ty\trm}{\ty \To \ty[3]} |
|
}(\ty = \rec\tvar\ty[2]) |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\Ginf{\trm}{\ty[2]\To\ty} |
|
\\ |
|
\Ginf{\trm[2]}{\ty[2]} |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf{\trm\, \trm[2]}{\ty} |
|
} |
|
\quad |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
~ |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf{\tcts}{\ty_{\tcts}} |
|
} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\caption{Core calculus type system}\figlabel{type system} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
The rules are standard. By design, every term has at most one type in |
|
a given context. |
|
|
|
\begin{example} |
|
Once desugared, the list manipulation terms from \exampleref{terms} |
|
have types: |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
(::) &: \ty \t* \List \ty \To \List \ty |
|
& |
|
\foldlist &: \ty[2] \t* (\ty\t*\ty[2] \To \ty[2]) |
|
\t* \List\ty |
|
\To \ty[2] |
|
\\ |
|
\tmap &: (\ty \To \ty[2])\To (\List \ty \To \List \ty[2]) |
|
& |
|
(\++) &: (\List \ty) \t* (\List \ty) \To \List \ty |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
\subsection{Primitive recursion} |
|
|
|
As is |
|
well-known~\cite{hutton:a-tutorial-on-the-universality-and-expressiveness-of-fold, |
|
geuvers2007iteration}, structural recursion on inductive types |
|
allows us to express primitive recursion. By `primitive recursion', we |
|
mean recursing through values of an inductive type $\rec\tvar{\ty[2]}$ |
|
using a term of the form: |
|
$\ctx, k : \subst{\ty[2]}{\sfor\tvar{(\rec\tvar{\ty[2]})\t*\ty[3]}} |
|
\tinf \trm[1] : \ty[3]$ |
|
with the intention that $\trm[1]$ can use either arbitrary (total) processing |
|
on the sub-structures of its input $k$, or make a primitive recursive |
|
call to itself with a sub-structure. In order to desugar such a term |
|
into a function of type $\ty \t* (\rec\tvar\ty[2]) \To \ty[3]$, we use terms of the following type, defined by induction on types: |
|
\[ |
|
\projection_{\tvar.\ty[2],\ty[3]} : |
|
\subst{\ty[2]}{\sfor\tvar{(\rec\tvar{\ty[2]})\t*\ty[3]}} \to |
|
\subst{\ty[2]}{\sfor\tvar{\rec\tvar{\ty[2]}}} |
|
\] |
|
and interpret the primitive recursive declaration $t$ embodied by: |
|
\[ |
|
\ctx, \var : \rec\tvar\ty[2] \tinf |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}*3{l@{}}} |
|
\pmatch |
|
{\tfold{(\rec\tvar\ty[2])} |
|
{}& |
|
\parent{\expfun k{\subst{\ty[2]}{\sfor\tvar{(\rec\tvar{\ty[2]})\t*\ty[3]}}} |
|
\,\tpair {\roll \projection_{\tvar.\ty[2],\ty[3]}k}{t}} |
|
\var\\\! |
|
} {\_}{r}{r} : \ty[2] |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
This translation is global in nature: the structure of the term |
|
$\projection$ depends on the type of $t$. Thus, it does not constitute |
|
a \emph{macro} |
|
translation~\cite{felleisen:on-the-expressive-power-of-programming-languages}. |
|
With this point in mind, we will allow ourselves to use primitive |
|
recursive definitions. |
|
|
|
\begin{example}\examplelabel{aggr intro} |
|
We define a function |
|
$\aggr : \List(\reals+\t*X) \To \List(\reals+\t*X)$ which takes a |
|
list of weighted values and aggregates all the weights based on |
|
their values. We make use of the auxiliary function |
|
$\add : (\reals+\t* X) \t* \List (\reals+ \t*X) \To \List |
|
(\reals+ \t*X)$, which adds a weighted value to an already |
|
aggregated list. We define $\add$ by primitive recursion: |
|
\[ |
|
\add \tpair{\tpair sa}{x_s} \definedby |
|
\vmatch {x_s} {\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{\To}l} |
|
\lst{\,} \;& \;\lst{\tpair sa} \mspace{175mu}\scomment{new entry}\\ |
|
\tpair rx :: x_s \;& \;\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{\,}l@{\qquad}l} |
|
\tif |
|
{&x = a\\} |
|
{&\tpair {s + r}a :: x_s &\scomment{accumulate}\\} |
|
{&\tpair rx :: \add\tpair{\tpair sa}{x_s}}\} &\scomment{recurse}\gobble |
|
} \end{array} |
|
|
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
and set $\aggr \definedby \foldlist {\lst-}\add$. This example makes |
|
use of an equality predicate between $X$ elements, restricting its |
|
applicability. |
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Denotational semantics} |
|
We give a set-theoretic semantics to the calculus. In such |
|
set-theoretic semantics, types-in-context $\Dkinf\ty$ are interpreted |
|
as functors $\sem{\ty} : \Set^{\Tyctx} \to \Set$, i.e., $\sem{\ty}$ |
|
assigns a set $\sem{\ty}\seq[\tvar \in \Tyctx]{X_{\tvar}}$ for every |
|
$\Tyctx$-indexed tuple of sets, and a function |
|
\[ \sem\ty\seq[\tvar \in \Tyctx]{f_{\tvar} : X_{\tvar} \to Y_{\tvar}} |
|
: \sem\ty\seq{X_{\tvar}} \to \sem\ty\seq{Y_{\tvar}} |
|
\] |
|
for every $\Tyctx$-indexed tuple of functions between the sets with |
|
corresponding index, and this assignment preserves composition and |
|
identities. |
|
|
|
In order to interpret iso-inductive types $\rec\tvar\ty$, we need |
|
canonical isomorphisms between the sets |
|
$\sem{\ty} (\sem{\rec\tvar\ty}) \isomorphic \sem{\rec\tvar\ty}$. |
|
We will do this in a standard way, by interpreting $\sem{\rec\tvar \ty}$ as the initial algebra |
|
for the functor $\sem{\ty}:[\Set^\Delta\to \Set]\to [\Set^\Delta\to \Set]$. |
|
This means that for every functor $A:\Set^\Delta\to \Set$ |
|
with a natural family of functions $\{a_{X}:(\sem{\ty} A)(X)\to A(X)\}_{X\in\Set^\Delta}$, |
|
there is a canonical natural family of functions |
|
$\{\algfold_X : \sem{\rec\tvar\ty}(X) \to A(X)\}_{X\in\Set^\Delta}$. |
|
|
|
A technical requirement is needed to ensure that this initial algebra exists: |
|
we fix a regular cardinal $\kappa$, and |
|
demand that each type denotes a $\kappa$-\emph{ranked} functor |
|
(ranked functor for short), |
|
that is, that it denotes a functor that preserves $\kappa$-filtered |
|
colimits\footnote{ |
|
We do not use simpler classes of functors, such as \emph{polynomial |
|
functors} or \emph{containers}, as they are not closed under |
|
subfunctors, given by subsets in the discrete case and subspaces in |
|
the continuous case, which we need in the sequel. |
|
}. The |
|
$\kappa$-ranked functors are closed under composition, products, sums, |
|
and initial algebras. Initial algebras for $\kappa$-ranked functors |
|
on locally presentable categories always exist, because they can be |
|
built in an iterative way by transfinite induction (see |
|
e.g.~\cite{kelly-transfinite}). |
|
|
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Set-theoretic interpretation}\subsubseclabel{interpretation} |
|
To interpret types, we assume a given interpretation $\Base-$ of |
|
the base types $\Type$ as sets $\Base{\Type}$ and of base type |
|
constructors $\Functor$ as ranked functors |
|
$\Base\Functor : \Set \to \Set$. We then interpret each well-formed |
|
type in context $\Dkinf\ty$ as a ranked functor |
|
$\sem{\ty} : \Set^{\Tyctx} \to \Set$, as depicted in |
|
\figref{sem types}. |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{gather*} |
|
\sem{\alpha}\tenv \definedby \tenv(\alpha) |
|
\qquad |
|
\sem{\Variant{ |
|
\Inj{\Cns_1}{\ty_1} |
|
\vor \ldots \vor |
|
\Inj{\Cns_n}{\ty_n} |
|
}}\tenv |
|
\definedby |
|
\sum_{i = 1}^n \sem{\ty_i}\tenv |
|
\qquad |
|
\sem{\Unit} \definedby \qquad |
|
\sem{\Functor \ty}\tenv \definedby \Base\Functor(\sem\ty\tenv) |
|
\\[-12pt] |
|
\sem{\rec \tvar \ty}\tenv \definedby \rec X{\sem\ty}\subst\tenv{\sfor \tvar X} |
|
\qquad |
|
\sem{\ty \To \ty[2]}\tenv \definedby \parent{\sem{\ty[2]}\tenv}^{\shade{\sem{\ty}\seq{}}} |
|
\qquad |
|
\sem{\Type}\tenv \definedby \Base\Type |
|
\end{gather*} |
|
\caption{Core calculus type-level semantics}\figlabel{sem types} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
In this definition, the parameter $d$ may be either a tuple of sets or |
|
functions. When interpreting type variables, we write $d(\alpha)$ for |
|
the $\alpha$-indexed component of $d$. The interpretation of simple |
|
types uses disjoint unions, singletons, finite products, and |
|
exponentials, i.e.~the bi-cartesian closed structure of $\Set$. We |
|
interpret inductive types $\sem{\rec \tvar\ty}\tenv$ using the initial |
|
algebra for the ranked functor $\fun X \sem\ty\subst\tenv{\sfor \tvar X} : \Set \to \Set$. In the |
|
semantics of the function type $\ty[1]\To\ty[2]$, the exponential |
|
makes no use of the functor's arguments, and relies on the fact that |
|
all type variables are strictly positive. We use the given |
|
interpretation of base types and type constructors to interpret them. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma}\lemmalabel{well type sem} |
|
The semantics of types is well-defined: every well-formed type |
|
$\Dkinf \ty$ denotes a ranked functor |
|
$\sem\ty : \Set^\Delta \to \Set$. In particular, every closed type |
|
denotes a set. |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
The proof is by induction on the kinding judgements, using well-known |
|
properties of $\Set$. |
|
|
|
We will always interpret the base types $\I$, $\reals$, etc.~by the |
|
sets they represent. |
|
\begin{example} |
|
We calculate the denotations of the types from |
|
\exampleref{types}. Booleans denote a two-element set |
|
$\sem\boolty = \set{\fls, \tru}$, and the natural numbers denote the |
|
set of natural numbers $\sem\naturals = \naturals$. By |
|
\lemmaref{well type sem}, $\sem{\List}$ denotes a ranked functor |
|
$\List : \Set \to \Set$, and this functor is given by the set of |
|
sequences of $X$-elements |
|
$\List X \definedby \Union_{n \in \naturals}X^n$. |
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
Beyond establishing the well-definedness of the semantic |
|
interpretation, \lemmaref{well type sem} equips us with syntactic |
|
means to define ranked functors. Once defined, we can add these |
|
functors to our collection of base types (in an extended instance of |
|
the core calculus). In the sequel, we will often restrict a given |
|
ranked functor $F : \Set \to \Set$ by specifying a subset |
|
$G X \subset FX$. Doing so is analogous to imposing an |
|
\emph{invariant} on a datatype. The subsets $GX$ form a |
|
\emph{subfunctor} $G \subset F$ precisely if they are closed under the |
|
functorial action of $F$, i.e., for every function $f : X \to Y$ and |
|
$a \in GX$, $Ff(a) \in GY$. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
Subfunctors of ranked functors over $\Set$ are ranked. |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
We can prove this lemma directly, but it also follows from a |
|
higher-level argument using the commutation of finite limits and |
|
$\kappa$-directed colimits in $\Set$. |
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Monadic programming}\subseclabel{monad interfaces} |
|
In the sequel, we will be working with types that support a monadic |
|
programming style. More precisely, a \emph{monadic interface} |
|
$\monad T$ consists of a triple |
|
$\monad T = \triple* T{\return^{\monad T}}{\bind^{\monad T}}$ where: |
|
$T$ assigns to each set $X$ a set $TX$; $\return^{\monad T}$ assigns |
|
to each set $X$ a function $\return_X^{\monad T} : X \to TX$; and |
|
$\bind^{\monad T}$ assigns to each pair of sets $X$ and $Y$ a function |
|
$\bind_{X, Y}^{\monad T}{} : TX\times (TY)^X \to TY$. We borrow |
|
Haskell's type-class syntax to define such interfaces. As an example, |
|
\figref{instance} defines a monadic interface over $\List$. |
|
|
|
Each such monadic interface $\monad T$ allows us to use standard |
|
do-notation summarised in \figref{do}. Though simple in principle, we |
|
must take care when treating this notation as syntactic sugar, as |
|
choosing the appropriate function $\return_X$ or $\bind_{X,Y}$ at each |
|
desugaring step must take typing information into account. When we use |
|
do-notation in the sequel, we ensure that such choices can be |
|
disambiguated. Finally, we will delimit our use of do-notation to |
|
within a \emph{do-block} $\expdomon{\monad T}{\ldots}$, omitting the |
|
monadic interface $\monad T$ or the entire delimiter when either is |
|
clear from the context. |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{minipage}[t]{.5\linewidth} |
|
\( |
|
\Monad{\List}{ |
|
\sreturn x &{}= \lst x |
|
}{ |
|
x_s \bind f &{}= |
|
\foldlist {\lst-} |
|
\parent{\fun{\tpair x{y_s}} |
|
f(x) \++ y_s}\ x_s |
|
\\\\} |
|
\) |
|
\subcaption{Declaring monadic interfaces}\figlabel{instance} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
\begin{minipage}[t]{.5\linewidth} |
|
\center |
|
\begin{sugar} |
|
\var \<- \trm; \trm[2] & \trm \bind \fun \var\trm[2] \\ |
|
\sreturn \trm & \return^{\monad T} \trm \\ |
|
\trm; \trm[2] & \_ \<- \trm; \trm[2] \\ |
|
\end{sugar} |
|
\subcaption{Haskell's do-notation}\figlabel{do} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
\caption{Monadic programming notation} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
Importantly, we do not insist that a monadic interface satisfies |
|
the monad associativity and unit laws: |
|
\( |
|
(\return x) \bind f = f(x) |
|
\), \( |
|
a \bind \return x = a |
|
\), and \( |
|
(a \bind f) \bind g = a \bind (\fun x (f\ x \bind g)) |
|
\). |
|
\section{Discrete inference}\seclabel{discrete} |
|
We can now lay-out the core ideas in the simpler, set-theoretic case: |
|
a semantic structure for higher-order (discrete) probabilistic |
|
programs, intermediate representations of these programs for the |
|
purpose of inference, valid transformations between these |
|
representations, and modular building blocks for creating new |
|
representations and transformations from existing ones. For simplicity, |
|
we consider representations and transformations from simple rather naive |
|
inference algorithms only in this section. In \secref{SMC} and |
|
\secref{MHG}, we show how the core ideas here apply to |
|
advanced algorithms when aided with further technical developments. |
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{The mass function monad} |
|
For our purposes, probabilistic programming languages contain |
|
standard control-flow mechanisms and data types, such as our core |
|
calculus, together with \emph{probabilistic choice} and |
|
\emph{conditioning} operations. In the discrete case, these are given |
|
by two effectful operations: |
|
\begin{mathpar} |
|
\inferrule{ |
|
~ |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf{_{\mathrm{comp}} \sflip} \boolty |
|
} |
|
|
|
\inferrule{ |
|
\Ginf {\trm} \reals+ |
|
}{ |
|
\Ginf {_{\mathrm{comp}}\sscore\trm} \Unit |
|
} |
|
\end{mathpar} |
|
In Bayesian probabilistic programming, we think of $\sflip$ as drawing from a (uniform) prior distribution on $\boolty$, |
|
and of $\sscore$ as recording a likelihood. Typically, one calls $\sscore(f(x))$ |
|
where $f$ is a density function of a distribution, which records the likelihood of |
|
observing data $x$ from the distribution $f$. |
|
The score might be zero, a hard constraint: this path is impossible. |
|
The score might be in the unit interval, the probability of a discrete observation; |
|
but in general a likelihood function can take any positive real value. |
|
The inference problem is to approximate the posterior distribution, from the unnormalized posterior defined by the program, combining a prior and likelihood. |
|
|
|
To give a set-theoretic semantic structure to such a higher-order |
|
language with these two constructs, it suffices to give a monadic |
|
interface $\monad T$ for which the associativity and unit laws hold, |
|
together with two functions: |
|
\begin{mathpar} |
|
\flip : \sem\Unit \to T\sem\boolty |
|
|
|
\score: \sem{\reals+} \to T\sem\Unit |
|
\end{mathpar} |
|
|
|
For the purposes of the discrete development, the following monad fits |
|
the bill. A (finite) \emph{mass function} over a set $X$ is a function |
|
$\mu : X \to \reals+$ for which there exists a finite set |
|
$F \subset X$ such that $\mu$ is $0$ outside $F$: |
|
in other words, the support set $\support \mu\definedby \set {x\in X\suchthat\mu(x)\neq 0}$ is finite. |
|
For every set $X$, let |
|
$\Mass X \definedby \set{ \mu : X \to \reals+ \suchthat \text{$\mu$ is |
|
a mass function}}$. The \emph{mass function} monad is given by: |
|
\[ |
|
\monad \Mass \definedby \Monad{\Mass}{ |
|
\return \var_0\ \ &= \fun {\var} \tif {(\var = \var_0)}{1}{0} |
|
}{ |
|
\mu \bind f &= \fun y \sum_{x \in \support \mu}\mu(x)\cdot (f(x)(y)) |
|
} |
|
\] |
|
and we set $\flip = \fun \_ \tfrac 12$ and |
|
$\score r = \pfun {\tUnit \To r}$. Intuitively, values of $\Mass X$ |
|
represent unnormalized probabilistic computations of a result in $X$. |
|
From the Bayesian perspective, the meaning of a program is the unnormalized posterior. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
The monadic interface $\monad \Mass$ defines a ranked monad over $\Set$. |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
This monad is also known as the \emph{free positive cone monad}, as it |
|
constructs the `positive fragment' of a vector space over the field of |
|
reals with basis $X$. |
|
|
|
\subsection{Inference representations} |
|
The mass function semantics is accurate, but idealised: realistic |
|
implementations cannot be expected to compute mass functions at |
|
arbitrary types, and especially at higher-order types. Instead, |
|
probabilistic inference engines would manipulate some representation |
|
of the program, while maintaining its semantics. |
|
|
|
\begin{definition}\definitionlabel{disc inf rep} |
|
A \emph{discrete inference representation} $\ir$ is a sextuple |
|
\[ |
|
\ir = \seq{T, \return^{\ir}, \bind^{\ir}, |
|
\flip^{\ir}, \score^{\ir}, \mean^{\ir}} |
|
\] consisting of: |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item a monadic interface $\triple T{\return^{\ir}}{\bind^{\ir}}$; |
|
\item two functions $\flip^{\ir} : \terminal \to T\Two$ and |
|
$\score^{\ir}: \reals+ \to T\terminal$, where $\terminal := |
|
\sem\Unit$, $\Two := \sem{\boolty}$; and |
|
\item an assignment of a \emph{meaning} function |
|
$\mean^{\ir}_X : TX \to \Mass X$ for every set $X$ |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
such that the following laws hold for all sets $X$, $Y$, and |
|
$x \in X$, $a \in TX$, $r \in \reals+$, and $f : X \to TY$: |
|
\begin{mathpar} |
|
\return^{\monad\Mass}x = \mean (\return^{\ir} x) |
|
|
|
\mean (a\bind^{\ir} f) = |
|
(\mean a)\bind^{\monad \Mass} \fun x \mean(f\ x) |
|
|
|
\\ |
|
|
|
\mean(\flip^{\ir}) = \flip^{\monad\Mass} |
|
|
|
\mean(\score^{\ir} r) = \score^{\monad\Mass} r |
|
\end{mathpar} |
|
\end{definition} |
|
|
|
As with monadic interfaces, we use a type-class notation for defining |
|
inference representations. |
|
|
|
\begin{example}[Discrete weighted sampler]\examplelabel{disc weighted sampler} |
|
Consider the type |
|
\[ |
|
\Term \tvar \definedby \Variant{\Inj{Return}{(\reals+\t*\tvar)} \vor |
|
\Inj{Flip}{(\Term\tvar\t* \Term\tvar)}} |
|
\] |
|
which induces a ranked functor $\Term$. The elements of $\Term X$ |
|
are binary trees, which we call terms, whose leaves contain weighted |
|
values of type $X$. \figref{disc free} presents the inference |
|
representation structure of the functor $\Term$. |
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{minipage}{\linewidth} |
|
\[ |
|
\DiscMonad{\Term}{ |
|
\sreturn x &= \Inj{Return}\tpair 1x |
|
}{ |
|
a \bind f &= |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
\expletin{&scale}{\reals+\t*\Term X \to \Term X} |
|
{\mspace{75mu}\scomment{uses primitive recursion}\\& |
|
\fun s\pfun{ |
|
&\Inj{Return}{\tpair rx} & \To \Inj{Return}{\tpair {s\cdot r}x}\\ |
|
\vor &\Inj{Flip}{\tpair{k_{\fls}}{k_{\tru}}} |
|
& \To \Inj{Flip} |
|
\tpair{scale\tpair{r}{k_{\fls}}} |
|
{scale\tpair{r}{k_{\fls}}} |
|
|
|
} |
|
\\\!} |
|
& \imatch a { |
|
\Inj{Return}{\tpair rx} & scale\tpair r{f\ x} \\ |
|
\mathllap\vor \Inj{Flip}\tpair {k_{\fls}}{k_{\tru}} |
|
& \Inj{Flip} |
|
\begin{aligned}[t] |
|
\tpair{&k_{\fls}\bind f} |
|
{\ |
|
\scomment{uses primitive recursion} |
|
\\&k_{\tru}\bind f}\} |
|
\end{aligned}\gobble |
|
} |
|
\end{array} |
|
} |
|
{ |
|
\sflip &= \Inj{Flip}{\tpair{\Inj{Return}{\tpair{1}\fls}} |
|
{\Inj{Return}{\tpair{1}\tru}}} |
|
} |
|
{ |
|
\sscore r &= \Inj{Return}{\tpair r\tUnit} |
|
} |
|
{ |
|
\mean a &= \fold{\pfun{ |
|
&\Inj{Return}{\tpair rx} |
|
&\To |
|
\expdomon\Mass{\sscore r; \sreturn x}\\ |
|
\vor &\Inj{Flip}{\tpair {\mu_{\fls}}{\mu_{\tru}}} |
|
& \To \expdomon\Mass{ |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}} |
|
x \<- \sflip; \\ |
|
\tif x {\mu_{\tru}}{\mu_{\fls}} |
|
} |
|
} |
|
\end{array} |
|
} |
|
} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{Discrete weighted sampler representation}\figlabel{disc free} |
|
\vspace{1\baselineskip} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
\begin{minipage}[t]{.55\linewidth} |
|
\( |
|
\DiscMonad{\Enum} |
|
{ |
|
\sreturn x &= \lst{\tpair 1x} |
|
}{ |
|
x_s \bind f &= |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
\expletin {&scale}{\reals+\t*\Enum X \To \Enum X} |
|
{\\&\pfun {\tpair {r}{x_s} \To{} \tmap {}&\pfun {\tpair sy \To \tpair {r\cdot s}y}\\&x_s}\\\!} |
|
& |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}} |
|
\foldlist {\lst-} \\ |
|
{\pfun{\tpair{\tpair rx}{y_s} \To scale\tpair r{f\ x} \++ y_s}}\\ |
|
x_s |
|
\end{array} |
|
\end{array} |
|
}{ |
|
\flip &= \lst{\tpair \half\fls, \tpair \half\tru} |
|
}{ |
|
\score r &= \lst{\tpair r\tUnit} |
|
}{ |
|
\mean x_s &= \fun a \qquad\scomment{ |
|
$\mean x_s\ a=\textstyle\sum_{\substack{\tpair rx \in x_s\\x = a}}r$ }\\ |
|
&& |
|
\foldlist{ |
|
0 } |
|
\parent{ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}} |
|
\pfun{\tpair{\tpair rx}{s} |
|
\To \\{}\tif{x = a}{r + s}s} |
|
\end{array} |
|
} |
|
\ x_s |
|
} |
|
\) |
|
\subcaption{Discrete enumeration sampler}\figlabel{disc enum} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
\begin{minipage}[t]{.35\linewidth} |
|
\( |
|
\DiscTransBreak {\Writer} |
|
{ |
|
\slift_{\ir} a &= \expdomon\ir{\begin{aligned}[t]&x \<- a;\\& \sreturn \tpair 1x |
|
} \end{aligned} |
|
|
|
} |
|
{ |
|
\sreturn_{\Writer\ir} x &= \return^{\ir} \tpair 1x |
|
} |
|
{ |
|
a \bind_{\Writer\ir} f &= |
|
\begin{aligned}[t] |
|
\expdomon\ir{&\tpair rx \<- a; |
|
\\&\tpair sy \<- f(x); |
|
\\&\sreturn \tpair{r\cdot s}y} |
|
\end{aligned} |
|
} |
|
{ |
|
\sflip_{\Writer\ir} &= \slift \sflip^{\ir} |
|
} |
|
{ |
|
\sscore_{\Writer\ir} r &= \return^{\ir} \tpair r\tUnit |
|
} |
|
{ |
|
\mean_{\Writer\ir} a &= \fun x\sum_{\tpair rx \in \support{\mean^{T}(a)}}r |
|
} |
|
{ |
|
(\stmap \tfm)_X &= \tfm_{\reals+\t* X} |
|
} |
|
\) |
|
\vspace{1.2\baselineskip} |
|
\subcaption{Discrete weighting transformer}\figlabel{disc weighting} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
\caption{Example inference representations (a,b) and transformers (c)} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
$\Inj{Flip}$ represents a probabilistic choice while $\Inj{Return}$ |
|
holds the final value and the total weight for the branch. |
|
Thus an |
|
immediately returning computation is represented by a leaf with |
|
weight $1$. The auxiliary function $scale$ in the definition of $\bind$ scales |
|
the leaves of its input term by the input weight. The function |
|
$\bind$ itself substitutes terms for the leaves according to its |
|
input function $f$, making sure the newly grafted terms are scaled |
|
appropriately. The probabilistic choice operation $\sflip$ constructs |
|
a single node with each leaf recording the probabilistic choice |
|
\emph{unweighted}. Conditioning records the input weight. |
|
|
|
The meaning function recurses over the term, replacing each node |
|
representing a probabilistic choice by probabilistic choice of the |
|
mass function monad, and reweighting the end result appropriately. |
|
|
|
The main step in validating the inference representation laws |
|
involves $\bind$: first show that composing the meaning function |
|
with the auxiliary function $scale$ scales the meaning of the input |
|
term appropriately, and then proceed by structural induction on terms. |
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
The weighted sampler representation in fact forms a proper monad over |
|
$\Set$: it is the free monad for an algebraic theory with a binary |
|
operation $\flip$ and unary operations $\score_r$ subject to |
|
\( |
|
\sflip(\sscore_r(x), \sscore_r(y)) = \sscore_r(\sflip(x, y))\text. |
|
\) |
|
As the mass function monad also validates these equations, the meaning |
|
function is then the unique monad morphism from $\Term$ to $\Mass$ |
|
preserving the operations $\sflip$ and $\sscore$. |
|
|
|
However, we emphasise that an inference representation need not form a |
|
proper monad, and that the meaning function need not be a monad |
|
morphism. Indeed, the $\Pop \Sam$ representation introduced in \secref{SMC} |
|
is not a monad and most of the non-trivial inference transformations we |
|
discuss are not monad morphisms. |
|
|
|
The weighted sampler representation allows us to incorporate both |
|
intensional and operational aspects into our development. Bayesian |
|
inference ultimately reduces a representation into probabilistic |
|
simulation. The weighted sampler representation can thus act as an |
|
internal representation of this simulation. Moreover, its continuous |
|
analogue will allow us to manipulate traces when analysing the Trace |
|
Markov Chain Monte Carlo algorithm in \secref{MHG}. |
|
|
|
\begin{example}[Enumeration]\examplelabel{enumeration} |
|
The type $\Enum \tvar \definedby \List (\reals+\t* \tvar)$ induces a |
|
ranked functor $\Enum$. Elements of $\Enum X$ form an enumeration of |
|
the mass function they represent, with the same value $x$ |
|
potentially appearing multiple times with different weights. Values |
|
not appearing in the list at all have weight $0$. |
|
|
|
\figref{disc enum} presents an inference representation structure |
|
using $\Enum$. Returning a value lists the unique non-zero point |
|
mass. The $\bind$ operation applies the given function to each |
|
element listed, scales the list appropriately and accumulates all |
|
intermediate lists. The choice operation enumerates both branches |
|
with equal probability, and conditioning inserts a scaling |
|
factor. The meaning function assigns to an element the sum of |
|
its weights. This definition uses an equality predicate. |
|
|
|
Establishing the inference representation laws is straightforward. |
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
\subsection{Inference transformations} |
|
We can now define the central validity criterion in our |
|
development. We decompose Bayesian inference algorithms into smaller |
|
transformations between inference representations. To be correct, |
|
these transformations need to preserve the meaning of the |
|
representation they manipulate: |
|
\begin{definition}\deflabel{disc inf tfm} |
|
Let $\ir$, $\ir[2]$ be two inference representations. A |
|
\emph{discrete inference transformation} ${\tfm : \ir \to \ir[2]}$ |
|
assigns to each set $X$ a function $\tfm_X : \uir[1]X \to \uir[2]X$ |
|
satisfying $\mean^{\ir}(a) = \mean^{\ir[2]}(\tfm_X(a))$ for every $a |
|
\in \ir[1]X$. |
|
\end{definition} |
|
This validity criterion guarantees nothing beyond the preservation of |
|
the overall mass function of our representation. The transformed |
|
representation may not be better for inference along any axis, such as |
|
better convergence properties or execution time. It is up to the |
|
inference algorithm designer to convince herself of such properties by |
|
other means: formal, empirical, or heuristic. |
|
|
|
Some transformations change the representation type: |
|
\begin{example}[Enumeration] |
|
Define a transformation: |
|
\( |
|
\tfm : \monad\Term \to \monad\Enum |
|
\) by: |
|
\[ |
|
\tfm \definedby \pfun{ |
|
\Inj{Return}\tpair rx |
|
& \To \expdomon\Enum{\sscore r; \sreturn x} \\ |
|
\vor \Inj{Flip }\tpair {x_s^{\fls}} |
|
{x_s^{\tru}} |
|
& \To \expdomon\Enum{b \<- \sflip; \tif b {x_s^{\tru} } |
|
{x_s^{\fls} } |
|
}} |
|
\] |
|
Straightforward calculation shows it preserves the meaning functions. |
|
\end{example} |
|
The last example is a special case: analogous functions form |
|
inference transformations $\tfm_{\ir} : \monad\Term \to \ir$ for every |
|
discrete inference representation $\ir$. To establish meaning |
|
preservation, calculate that both $\mean^{\monad\Term}$ and |
|
$\mean^{\ir}\compose\tfm_{\ir}$ are monad morphisms that preserve |
|
probabilistic choice and conditioning and appeal to the initiality of |
|
$\monad\Term$. |
|
|
|
An inference transformation need not be natural: |
|
\begin{example}[Aggregation] |
|
Recall the functions $\aggr_X : \List(\reals+\t* X) \to |
|
\List(\reals+\t* X)$ from \exampleref{aggr intro} which aggregate |
|
list elements according to their $X$ component by summing their weights. It forms an |
|
inference transformation $\aggr : \monad\Enum \to \monad\Enum$. The meaning preservation proof uses straightforward structural induction. Note that $\aggr$ is not a natural transformation. |
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Inference transformers} |
|
We can decompose the weighted sampler representation $\monad\Term$, |
|
which forms a monad, by transforming the \emph{discrete sampler} |
|
representation $\DSam X \definedby \Variant{\Inj{Return} X \vor |
|
\Inj{Sample}({\DSam X}\t*{\DSam X})}$ with the following |
|
\emph{writer monad transformer} |
|
\( |
|
\Writer \uir X \definedby \uir (\reals+\t* X) |
|
\), i.e.~\( |
|
\Term = \Writer \DSam |
|
\). |
|
Such decompositions form basic building blocks for constructing and |
|
reasoning about more sophisticated representations. |
|
|
|
\begin{definition} |
|
An \emph{inference transformer} $\IF$ is a triple |
|
$\triple*{\uIF}{\itmap^{\IF}}{\lift^{\IF}}$ whose components assign: |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item inference representation $\uIF \ir$ to every |
|
inference representation $\ir$; |
|
\item inference transformation |
|
$\itmap^{\IF} \tfm : \IF\ir \to \IF\ir[2]$ to every inference |
|
transformation $\tfm : \ir \to \ir[2]$; and |
|
\item inference transformation $\lift_{\uir} : \ir \to \uIF \ir$ to |
|
every inference representation $\ir$. |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
\end{definition} |
|
|
|
We use type-class notation for defining inference transformers. |
|
|
|
\begin{example}\examplelabel{disc weighting trans}\examplelabel{weighting} |
|
The \emph{weighting} inference transformer structure on $\Writer |
|
\uir X \definedby \uir (\reals+\t* X)$ is given in \figref{disc |
|
weighting}. We lift a representation in $\ir$ into $\Writer \ir$ |
|
by assigning weight $1$ to it. The monadic interface uses the |
|
standard writer monad for the multiplication structure on $\reals+$, |
|
accumulating the weights as computation proceeds. We lift the |
|
probabilistic choice from $\ir$, but crucially we reimplement a |
|
\emph{new} conditioning operation using the explicitly given |
|
weights. The mass function meaning of a representation then |
|
accumulates the mass of all weights associated to a given value. We |
|
transform an inference transformation by picking the component of |
|
the appropriate type. |
|
|
|
It is straightforward to show that $\Writer\ir$ is an inference representation, using preservation of $\return$ and $\bind$ by the |
|
meaning function to reduce the proof to manipulations of weighted |
|
sums over $\reals+$. Establishing the validity of $\lift$ and |
|
$\itmap$ is straightforward. |
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
The weighting transformer \emph{augments} the representation with a |
|
new conditioning operation, but \emph{transforms} its choice operation |
|
to the new representation. We will later see more examples of both |
|
kinds. |
|
|
|
\subsection{Summary} |
|
We have introduced our three core abstractions, inference |
|
representations, transformations, and transformers, in relation to a |
|
mathematical semantic structure, the mass function monad. The examples |
|
so far show that the higher-order structure in our core calculus acts |
|
as a useful glue for manipulating and defining these abstractions. In |
|
the continuous case, we will also use this higher-order structure to |
|
represent computations over the real numbers. |
|
\section{Preliminaries}\seclabel{preliminaries} |
|
In order to generalise this higher-order treatment to the continuous |
|
case, we first need to review and develop the mathematical theory of |
|
quasi-Borel spaces. Our development uses |
|
\citepos*{kock:commutative-monads-as-a-theory-of-distributions}{synthetic |
|
measure theory}, which allows us to reason analogously to measure |
|
theory. In order to present the synthetic theory, we briefly review |
|
the required category theoretic concepts. These sections are aimed at |
|
readers who are interested in the categorical context of our |
|
development. Other readers may continue directly to \subsecref{qbs}. |
|
|
|
\subsection{Category theory} |
|
\paragraph{Basic notions.} |
|
We assume basic familiarity with categories $\cat$, $\cat[2]$, functors |
|
$\F, \F[2] : \cat \to \cat[2]$, and natural transformations |
|
$\nt, \nt[2] : \F \to \F[2]$, and their theory of limits, colimits, |
|
and adjunctions. To fix notation, a \emph{cartesian closed category} |
|
is a category with finite products, denoted by $\terminal$, $\times$, |
|
$\prod_{i=1}^n$, and exponentials, denoted by $X^Y$. |
|
In this subsection, we use |
|
the fragment of our core calculus consisting of the simply-typed |
|
$\lambda$-calculus (with sums, if necessary) to more compactly review |
|
the relevant concepts. |
|
|
|
\paragraph{Monads.}A \emph{strong monad} $\monad T$ over a |
|
cartesian closed category is a triple $\triple T\return\bind$ |
|
consisting of an assignment of an object $TX$ and a morphism |
|
$\return_X : X \to TX$ for every object $X$, and an assignment of a |
|
morphism $\bind_{X,Y} : TX \times (TY)^X \to TY$, satisfying the monad |
|
laws from \subsecref{monad interfaces}. |
|
Given a monad $\ir$, a |
|
\emph{$\ir$-algebra} $\alg$ is a pair |
|
$\pair*{\carrier \alg}{\bind^{\alg}}$ consisting of an object |
|
$\carrier \alg$, called the \emph{carrier}, and an assignment of a |
|
morphism $\bind^{\alg}_X : \carrier \alg^X \to \carrier\alg^{TX}$ to |
|
every object $X$ satisfying |
|
\[ |
|
(\return x \bind^{\alg} f) = f\ x |
|
\quad\text{and}\quad |
|
((a \bind f) \bind^{\alg} g) |
|
= |
|
a \bind (\fun x f(x) \bind^{\alg} g) |
|
\text. |
|
\] |
|
The pair $\tpair {\uir X}\bind$ always forms a $\uir$-algebra called |
|
the \emph{free} $\ir$-algebra over $X$. The \emph{Eilenberg-Moore} |
|
category $\cat^{\ir}$ for a monad $\ir$ consists of $\ir$-algebras and |
|
their homomorphism. The \emph{Kleisli} category $\cat_{\ir}$ consists |
|
of the same objects as $\cat$, but morphisms from $X$ to $Y$ in $\cat_{\ir}$ are |
|
morphisms $X \to \uir Y$ in $\cat$. The Kleisli category $\cat_{\ir}$ |
|
inherits any coproducts $\cat$ has. |
|
A strong monad |
|
$\ir$ is \emph{commutative} when, for every |
|
\[ |
|
a : \ir X, b: \ir Y \tinf\ \ |
|
\expdomon\ir {x \<- a; |
|
y \<- b; |
|
\!\sreturn \tpair xy} |
|
\quad=\quad |
|
\expdomon\ir { y \<- b; |
|
x \<- a; |
|
\!\sreturn \tpair xy} |
|
\] |
|
(The notion of strong/commutative monad is due to \cite{kock:strong-functors-and-monoidal-monads}; |
|
our formulation of algebras also appears in |
|
\cite{marmolejo-wood:monads-as-extension-systems}.) |
|
\paragraph{Biproducts.} |
|
A zero object $\zero$ is both initial and terminal. |
|
A category has \emph{(finite, countable, etc.) |
|
biproducts} if it has a zero object (and hence zero morphisms |
|
$\zeromor_{X,Y}:X{\to}\zero{\to} Y$) |
|
and the following canonical |
|
morphisms are invertible: |
|
\[ |
|
\textstyle \coseq[i \in I]{\seq[j \in I]{\delta_{i,j}} }: \sum_{i \in |
|
I}X_i \to \prod_{j \in I} X_j |
|
\qquad |
|
\text{where: } |
|
\delta_{i,i} \definedby |
|
\id[X_i], \ |
|
\delta_{i,j} \definedby |
|
\zeromor_{X_i, X_j} \text{ for $i \neq j$}. |
|
\] |
|
|
|
\paragraph{Algebraic structure.} |
|
Recall the notion of a \emph{commutative monoid} $\triple{M}1\cdot$ in |
|
a category with finite products. We extend it to countably many |
|
arguments. Let $\cat$ be a category with countable products. A |
|
\emph{$\sigma$-monoid} |
|
(see also \cite{haghverdi-scott:cat-GoI}) is a triple $\triple M0\Sigma$ |
|
consisting of: an object $M$; a morphism $0 : \terminal \to M$; and |
|
a morphism $\Sigma : M^{\naturals} \to M$ |
|
such that: |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item setting $\delta_0\! \definedby \id[M] : M \to M$ and |
|
$\delta_i \definedby 0 \compose !{} : M \to \terminal \to M$, $i > 0$, |
|
we have $\Sigma \compose \seq[i \in \naturals]{\delta_i} = \delta_0$; and |
|
\item for every bijection |
|
$\phi : \naturals \isomorphic \naturals\times\naturals$, |
|
\( |
|
a_{\tpair - -} : M^{\naturals \times \naturals} \tinf |
|
\Sigma\seq[i \in \naturals]{\Sigma\seq[j \in \naturals]{a_{\tpair i j}}} |
|
= \Sigma\seq[k \in \naturals]{a_{\phi(k)}} |
|
\text. |
|
\) |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{proposition} |
|
In a category with countable biproducts, each object |
|
$M$ is a $\sigma$-monoid via: |
|
\begin{mathpar} |
|
\textstyle \zeromor_{\terminal, M} : \terminal \to M |
|
|
|
\Sigma : \prod_{i \in \naturals}M \isomorphic \sum_{i \in |
|
\naturals}M \xto{\codiag} M |
|
\text{ where $\codiag$ is the codiagonal.} |
|
\end{mathpar} |
|
Every morphism is a $\sigma$-monoid homomorphism with respect to |
|
this structure. |
|
\end{proposition} |
|
A \emph{$\sigma$-semiring} is a quintuple |
|
$\seq{S, 1, \cdot, 0, \Sigma}$ consisting of: |
|
a commutative monoid $\triple S1\cdot$; and |
|
a $\sigma$-monoid $\triple S0\Sigma$, such that |
|
\( |
|
a : S, b_{-} \in S^{\naturals} \tinf |
|
a\cdot \Sigma\seq[i \in \naturals]{b_i} |
|
= |
|
\Sigma\seq[i \in \naturals]{a\cdot b_i} |
|
\). |
|
Given a $\sigma$-semiring $\seq{S, 1, \cdot, 0, \Sigma}$, an |
|
\emph{$S$-module} is a pair $\pair M\odot$ consisting of a |
|
$\sigma$-monoid $M$; and a morphism $\odot : S\times M \to M$ satisfying: |
|
\(x = x, 0_S \odot x = 0_M, |
|
(a\cdot b)\odot x = a\odot (b \odot x), |
|
\parent{\Sigma\seq[n \in \naturals]{a_n}}\odot x |
|
= |
|
\Sigma\seq[n \in \naturals]{a_n \odot x} |
|
\). |
|
\subsection{Synthetic measure theory} |
|
Synthetic mathematics identifies structure and axioms from which we can |
|
recover the main concepts and results of specific mathematical |
|
theories, and transport them to new settings. We now briefly recount |
|
the relevant parts of |
|
\citepos{kock:commutative-monads-as-a-theory-of-distributions}{ |
|
development}. |
|
(In the finite discrete case, this is also related to |
|
\citepos{jacobs-effectus}{ work on effectuses}.) |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Axioms and structure} |
|
|
|
Let $\cat$ be a cartesian closed category with countable products and |
|
coproducts, and let $\monad{\Mea}$ be a commutative monad over |
|
$\cat$. If the morphism $! : \Mea\initial \to \terminal$ is invertible, |
|
then both the Eilenberg-Moore category $\cat^{\monad\Mea}$ and the |
|
Kleisli category $\cat_{\monad\Mea}$ have zero objects. As a |
|
consequence, we have a canonical $\monad\Mea$-homomorphism |
|
\( |
|
\bind\coseq[i]{\seq[j]{\delta_{i,j}}} : \Mea \sum_{i \in |
|
\naturals}X_i |
|
\to \prod_{j \in \naturals} \Mea X_j |
|
\). |
|
|
|
\begin{definition} |
|
A \emph{measure category} is a pair $\pair\cat{\monad\Mea}$ |
|
consisting of a cartesian closed category $\cat$ with countable |
|
products and coproducts, and equalisers; and a commutative monad |
|
$\monad\Mea$ over $\cat$ such that |
|
the morphisms |
|
$! : \Mea\initial \to \terminal$ |
|
and |
|
$\bind\coseq[i]{\seq[j]{\delta_{i, j}}} : \Mea\sum_{i \in \naturals}X_i |
|
\to \prod_{j \in \naturals}\Mea X_j$ |
|
are invertible. |
|
|
|
\end{definition} |
|
|
|
We fix a measure category $\pair\cat{\monad\Mea}$ for the remainder of |
|
this section. The intuition is that $\Mea X$ is the object of |
|
distributions/measures over $X$. Kock shows that, while short, the |
|
above definition has surprisingly many consequences. |
|
|
|
Both the Eilenberg-Moore and the Kleisli categories have countable |
|
biproducts, and as a consequence, all $\monad\Mea$-algebras have a |
|
$\sigma$-monoid structure and all $\monad\Mea$-homomorphisms are |
|
$\sigma$-monoid homomorphisms with respect to it. Moreover, this |
|
structure on the free algebra on the terminal object $R \definedby |
|
\Mea\terminal$ extends to a $\sigma$-semiring structure by setting: $ |
|
1 \definedby \sreturn \tUnit$ and $r\cdot s \definedby |
|
\expdomon{\monad\Mea}{r; s}$. |
|
Kock calls this structure the \emph{$\sigma$-semiring of scalars}. |
|
Each $\monad\Mea$-algebra $\alg$ has an $R$-module structure: |
|
\[ |
|
r : R, a : \carrier\alg \tinf r \odot a \definedby \expdomon{\monad\Mea}{r; a} |
|
\] |
|
As $\cat$ has equalisers, for each object $X$, we may form the |
|
equaliser |
|
\( \Prob X \xdasharrow{\sub_X} \Mea X \xtoto[\constantly 1]{\Mea !} R\) |
|
because $R = \Mea\terminal$. |
|
Each $\sub_X$ is monic, the monadic structure factors through $\sub$ |
|
turning $\Prob$ into a commutative monad $\monad\Prob$, and |
|
$\sub : \monad\Prob \monomo \monad\Mea$ into a strong monad monomorphism. |
|
|
|
The morphism $\Mea ! : \Mea X \to R$ is called the \emph{total measure} |
|
morphism, and $\Prob$ is then the sub-object of all the measures with |
|
total measure $1$, and so we think of it as the object of |
|
\emph{probability measures} over $X$. For example, every |
|
$\monad\Prob$-algebra is closed under \emph{convex} linear |
|
combinations of scalars: if $r_{-} : \naturals \to R$ satisfies |
|
$\Sigma \seq[i] {r_i} = 1$ then |
|
$\qmu_- : (\Prob X)^{\naturals} \tinf \Mea !(\Sigma\seq[i]{r_i\odot \qmu_i}) |
|
= 1$. |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Notation and basic properties} |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{notation} |
|
\noassumptions R & \Mea \terminal |
|
& \text{Scalars} |
|
\\ |
|
f : Y^X, \qmu : \Mea X |
|
& f_*\qmu |
|
& (\Mea f)(\qmu) |
|
& \text{Push-forward} |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X |
|
& \qmu(X) |
|
& !_*\qmu & \text{The total measure} |
|
\\ |
|
x : X |
|
& \qdelta_x |
|
& \sreturn(x) |
|
& \text{Dirac distribution} |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, f : (\Mea Y)^X |
|
& \qint_X f(x)\qmu(\dif x) |
|
& \qmu \bind f |
|
& \text{Kock integral} |
|
\\ |
|
w : R^X, \qmu : \Mea X |
|
& w \odot \qmu |
|
& \qint_X (w(x)\odot \qdelta_x)\qmu(\dif x) |
|
& \text{Rescaling} |
|
\\ |
|
\bracks{ |
|
\begin{aligned} |
|
&f : (TZ)^{X\times Y}, |
|
\\& x : X, k : (TY)^X |
|
\end{aligned}} |
|
&\qint_{Y} f(x,y)k(x, \dif y) |
|
&\qint_Y f(x,y)k(x)(\dif y) |
|
& \text{Kernel integration} |
|
\\[10pt] |
|
\bracks{ |
|
\begin{aligned} |
|
&f : (\Mea X)^{X\times Y }, |
|
\\& |
|
\qmu \in \Mea (X\times Y) |
|
\end{aligned}} |
|
& \qiint_{X\times Y} f(x,y)\qmu(\dif x,\dif y) |
|
& \qint_{X\times Y} f(z)\qmu(\dif z) |
|
& \text{Iterated integrals} |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, \qmu[2] : \Mea Y |
|
& \qmu\tensor\qmu[2] |
|
& \qint_X\parent{\qint_Y\qdelta_{\tpair xy}\qmu[2](\dif y)}\qmu(\dif x) |
|
& \text{Product measure} |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, f : \carrier \alg^X |
|
& \Exp[\alg]_{x\sampled\qmu}[f(x)] |
|
& \qmu \bind f |
|
& \text{Expectation} |
|
\\ |
|
f : R^X, \qmu : \Mea X |
|
& \int_X f(x)\qmu(\dif x) |
|
& \Exp[R]_{x \sampled \qmu}[f(x)] |
|
& \text{Lebesgue integral} |
|
\end{notation} |
|
\caption{Synthetic measure theory notation}\figlabel{notation} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
Kock's theory shines brightly when we adopt a measure-theoretic |
|
notation, as in \figref{notation}, by thinking of $\Mea X$ as the |
|
object of measures over $X$, and $R$ as the object of scalars these |
|
measures take values in. The functorial action of the monad allows us to |
|
push measures along morphisms, and pushing all the measure into the |
|
terminal object gives a scalar we think of as the total measure of an |
|
object. The monadic $\return$ acts as a dirac distribution. The main |
|
advantage is the \emph{Kock integral}, synonymous to the monadic |
|
$\bind$. The main difference between the Kock integral $\qint$ and the |
|
usual Lebesgue integral $\int$ from measure theory is that the |
|
Kock integral evaluates to a \emph{measure}, and not a scalar. Calculating with |
|
the Kock integral is analogous to using Lebesgue integrals with |
|
respect to a generic test function, and proceeding by algebraic |
|
manipulation. The scalar rescaling $\odot$ allows us to rescale a |
|
distribution by an arbitrary weight function. A \emph{kernel} is a |
|
morphism $k : X \to \Mea Y$, and we use the usual notation for integration |
|
against a kernel and iterated integration. We define the product |
|
measure by iterated integration. Finally, the $\bind$ operation of an |
|
$\monad\Mea$-algebra $\alg$ gives rise to an expectation operation. |
|
Here we will only make use of the scalars' algebra structure, which |
|
generalises the usual Lebesgue integral. |
|
|
|
The justification for this notation is that it obeys the expected |
|
properties, which we now survey. The commutativity of the monad lets |
|
us change the order of integration: |
|
\begin{theorem}[Fubini-Tonelli] |
|
For every pair of objects $X$, $Y$ in a measure category |
|
$\tpair \cat{\monad\Mea}$: |
|
\begin{multline*} |
|
\textstyle \qiint_{X\times Y}f(x,y)(\qmu\tensor\qmu[2])(\dif x, \dif y) |
|
= |
|
\qint_{Y}\qmu[2](\dif y)\qint_{X}\qmu(\dif x)f(x,y) |
|
= |
|
\qint_{Y}\qmu[2](\dif y)\qint_{X}\qmu(\dif x)f(x,y) |
|
\end{multline*} |
|
Moreover, for every $\Mea$-algebra $\alg$: |
|
\[ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, \qmu[2] : \Mea Y, f : \carrier\alg^{X\times Y} |
|
\tinf |
|
\Exp[\alg]_{\substack{x\sampled\qmu\\y\sampled\qmu[2]}}\,[f(x,y)] |
|
= \Exp[\alg]_{x\sampled\qmu}\,[\Exp[\alg]_{y\sampled\qmu[2]}\,[f(x,y)]] |
|
= \Exp[\alg]_{y\sampled\qmu[2]}\,[\Exp[\alg]_{x\sampled\qmu}\,[f(x,y)]] |
|
\] |
|
\end{theorem} |
|
As usual, we allow placing the binder $\qmu(\dif x)$ on either side of |
|
the integrand $f(x)$. |
|
|
|
Integrals and expectation interact well with the $R$-module structure in the sense that they are homomorphisms in both arguments. The precise statement of this fact can be found in Appendix \ref{sec:kock-equations}. |
|
|
|
The push-forward operation interacts with rescaling in the following |
|
way: |
|
\begin{theorem}[Frobenius reciprocity] |
|
For all objects $X$, $Y$ in a measure category $\pair \cat{\monad\Mea}$: |
|
\[ |
|
\textstyle w : R^X, \qmu : \Mea X, f : Y^X \tinf w \odot \parent{f_*\qmu} |
|
= |
|
f_*\parent{(w \compose f)\odot\qmu} |
|
\] |
|
\end{theorem} |
|
|
|
When calculating in this notation, we use the equations in |
|
Appendix \ref{sec:kock-equations} where we present a toolbox for synthetic measure theory. This toolbox includes most of the equations we come to expect from standard measure theory, like the change of variables law. To validate them, inline the definitions and |
|
proceed using the usual category-theoretic properties. |
|
|
|
The following two sections contain relevant extensions to Kock's |
|
theory. |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Radon-Nikodym derivatives}\subsubseclabel{Radon-Nikodym} |
|
The Radon-Nikodym Theorem is a powerful tool in measure theory, and we |
|
now phrase a synthetic counterpart. As usual in the synthetic setting, |
|
we set the definitions up such that the theorem will be true. Doing so |
|
highlights the difference between three measure-theoretic concepts |
|
that coincide in measure theory, but may differ in the synthetic setting. |
|
|
|
Let $\qmu, \qmu[2] \in \Mea X$ be measures. We say that $\qmu[2]$ is |
|
\emph{absolutely continuous} with respect to $\qmu$, and write |
|
$\qmu[2] \absc \qmu$, when there exists a morphism $w : X \to R$ such |
|
that $\qmu[2] = w\odot\qmu$. Given two morphisms $w, v : X \to R$ and |
|
a measure $\qmu \in \Mea X$, we say that $w$ and $v$ are \emph{equal |
|
$\qmu$-almost everywhere} ($\qmu$-a.e.) when |
|
$w \odot \qmu = v \odot \qmu$. A \emph{measurable property} over $X$ |
|
is a morphism $P : X \to \boolty$. Given a measure $\qmu \in \Mea X$ a |
|
measurable property $P$ over $X$ \emph{holds $\qmu$-a.e.}, when the |
|
morphism $[P] \definedby \fun x\tif{P\ x}{1}{0}$ is equal |
|
$\qmu$-a.e. to $1$. |
|
|
|
\begin{theorem}[Radon-Nikodym] |
|
Let $\pair \cat\Mea$ be a well-pointed measure category. For every |
|
$\qmu[2] \absc \qmu$ in $\Mea X$, there exists a $\qmu$-a.e.~unique |
|
morphism $\der {\qmu[2]}{\qmu} : X \to R$ satisfying |
|
$\der {\qmu[2]}{\qmu} \odot \qmu = \qmu[2]$. |
|
\end{theorem} |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Kernels} |
|
We say that a kernel $k: X\to \Mea Y$ is \emph{Markov} when, for all $x$, |
|
$k(x, Y) = 1$, i.e., when $k$ factors through the object of probability |
|
measures via $\sub : \Prob \monomo \Mea$. We now restrict attention to |
|
kernels $k : X \to \Mea X$ over the same object $X$. We say that such |
|
a kernel \emph{preserves} a measure $\qmu$ when $\qmu \bind k = \qmu$. |
|
Recall the morphism |
|
$\braid[] \definedby \fun{\tpair xy}{\tpair yx} : X\times Y \to Y\times |
|
X$. Given a measure $\qmu \in \Mea X$ and a kernel $k$, we define the |
|
\emph{box product} by |
|
$\qmu \bprod k \definedby \qiint_{X\times X}\qdelta_{\pair |
|
xy}\qmu(\dif x)k(x, \dif y)$. A kernel $k$ is \emph{reversible} |
|
with respect to a measure $\qmu \in \Mea X$ when |
|
$\braid[]_*(\qmu\bprod k) = \qmu\bprod k$. |
|
|
|
The following standard results on kernels transfer into the synthetic |
|
setting. If a \emph{Markov} kernel $k$ is reversible with respect to |
|
$\qmu$, then $k$ preserves $\qmu$. Kernels obtained by rescaling the |
|
Dirac kernel, i.e., $\fun x w(x) \odot \qdelta_x$ are reversible |
|
w.r.t.~all measures. Finally, linear combinations |
|
$\fun x\sum_{n \in \naturals}r_n\odot k_n(x)$ of reversible kernels |
|
w.r.t.~$\qmu$ are also reversible w.r.t.~$\qmu$. |
|
\subsection{Quasi-Borel spaces}\subseclabel{qbs} |
|
It remains to show that there is a concrete model of synthetic measure theory |
|
that contains the classical measure theoretic ideas that are central to probability theory and inference. |
|
This is novel because \citepos*{kock:commutative-monads-as-a-theory-of-distributions}{work} is targeted |
|
at the geometric/topological setting, whereas probability theory is based around Borel sets rather than open sets. |
|
It is non-trivial because the traditional setting for measure theory does not support higher-order functions~\cite{aumann:functionspaces} and |
|
commutativity of integration is subtle in general. |
|
In this section we resolve these problems by combining some |
|
recent discoveries \cite{HeunenKSY-lics17,sfinite}, |
|
and exhibit a model of synthetic measure theory which contains classical measure theory, for instance: |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item the $\sigma$-semiring over the morphisms $\terminal \to R$ |
|
is isomorphic to the usual $\sigma$-semiring over the extended non-negative reals, $\ereals+$; |
|
\item this isomorphism induces a bijective correspondence between the |
|
morphisms $R\to \terminal +\terminal $ and the Borel subsets of |
|
$\ereals+$, as characteristic functions, and also between the |
|
morphisms $R\to R$ and the measurable functions $\ereals+\to |
|
\ereals+$; |
|
\item it also induces an injection of the morphisms $\terminal |
|
\to \Mea(R)$ into the set of Borel measures on $\ereals+$, whose |
|
image contains all the probability measures; |
|
the morphisms $R\to \Mea(R)$ include all the Borel probability |
|
kernels; |
|
\item the canonical morphism $R^{R}\times \Mea(R)\to R$, $(f,\qmu)\mapsto \int f(x)\,\qmu(\dif x)$, corresponds to classical Lebesgue integration. |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
Moreover, each object $X$ can be seen as a |
|
set $U(X)=\cat(\terminal ,X)$ with structure, |
|
because the category is well-pointed, in the sense that |
|
the morphisms $X\to Y$ are a subset of the functions $U(X)\to U(Y)$. |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Rudiments of classical measure theory} |
|
Measurable spaces are the cornerstone of conventional measure theory, supporting a notion of measure. |
|
|
|
Recall that a \emph{$\sigma$-algebra} on a set $X$ is a set $\Sigma_X$ of subsets of $X$ that is closed under countable unions and complements. |
|
A \emph{measurable space} is a set together with a $\sigma$-algebra. |
|
A \emph{measure} is a $\sigma$-additive function $\Sigma_X\to \ereals+$. |
|
A function $f$ between measurable spaces is \emph{measurable} if the inverse image |
|
of every measurable set according to $f$ is measurable. |
|
|
|
For example, on a Euclidean space $\ereals^n$ we can consider the Borel sets, which form the smallest |
|
$\sigma$-algebra containing the open cubes. There is a canonical measure on $\ereals^n$, the \emph{Lebesgue measure}, |
|
which assigns to each cube its volume, and thus to every measurable function $f\colon \ereals^n\to \ereals+$ |
|
a Lebesgue integral $\int_{\ereals^n}f \in \ereals+$. |
|
A slightly more general class of measures is the \emph{$\sigma$-finite measures}, which include the Lebesgue measures and |
|
are closed under disjoint unions and product measures. |
|
|
|
A measurable space that arises from the Borel sets of a Polish space is called a \emph{standard Borel space}. |
|
In fact, every standard Borel space is either countable or isomorphic to $\ereals$. |
|
Standard Borel spaces are closed under countable products and countable disjoint unions. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Quasi-Borel spaces} |
|
\newcommand{\baseR}{\mathfrak R} |
|
\newcommand{\QBS}{\textbf{QBS}} |
|
In this section we fix an uncountable standard Borel space, $\baseR$. |
|
For example, $\baseR=\ereals$. |
|
The basic idea of quasi-Borel spaces is that rather than focusing |
|
on measurable sets of a set $X$, as in classical measure theory, |
|
one should focus on the admissible random elements $\baseR\to X$. |
|
\begin{definition}[\cite{HeunenKSY-lics17}] |
|
A \emph{quasi-Borel space (QBS)} is a set $X$ together with |
|
a set of functions $M_X\subseteq [\baseR,X]$ |
|
such that $(i)$~all the constant functions are in $M_X$, $(ii)$~$M_X$ is closed under |
|
precomposition with measurable functions on $\baseR$, and $(iii)$~$M_X$ satisfies the piecewise condition: |
|
if $\baseR=\biguplus_{i=1}^\infty U_i$, where $U_i$ is Borel measurable |
|
and $\alpha_i\in M_X$ for all $i$, then $\biguplus_{i=1}^\infty \alpha_i\cap (U_i\times X)$ is in $M_X$. |
|
|
|
A \emph{morphism} $f\colon X\to Y$ is a function that respects the structure, |
|
i.e.~if $\alpha\in M_X$ then $(f \compose \alpha)\in M_Y$. |
|
Morphisms compose as functions, and we have a category $\QBS$. |
|
|
|
A QBS $X$ is a \emph{subspace} of a QBS $Y$ if $X\subseteq Y$ and $M_X=\set{\alpha:\baseR\to X~\suchthat~\alpha\in M_Y}$. |
|
\end{definition} |
|
A measurable space $X$ can be turned into a QBS when given |
|
the set of measurable functions $\baseR \to X$ as $M_X$. When $X$ and $Y$ are standard Borel spaces |
|
considered as QBSes this way, $\QBS(X,Y)$ comprises the measurable functions, so |
|
$\QBS$ can be thought of as a conservative extension of the universe of standard Borel spaces. |
|
The three conditions on quasi-Borel spaces ensure that coproducts and products of standard Borel spaces |
|
retain their universal properties in $\QBS$. |
|
In fact, the category of $\QBS$s has all limits and colimits. |
|
It is also cartesian closed; e.g., $\reals^{\reals}\definedby\QBS(\reals,\reals)$, |
|
and $M_{(\reals^{\reals})}= \set{\alpha:\baseR\to(\reals^{\reals})~\suchthat~\mathrm{uncurry}(\alpha)\in\QBS(\baseR\times\reals\to\reals)}$. |
|
For any QBS $X$, $M_X=\QBS(\baseR,X)$. |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{A monad of measures} The following development is novel. |
|
\begin{definition}\label{def:measure} |
|
A \emph{measure} $\mu$ on a quasi-Borel space is a triple $(\Omega,\alpha,\mu)$ |
|
where $\Omega$ is a standard Borel space, $\alpha\in\QBS(\Omega,X)$, and $\mu$ is a $\sigma$-finite measure on $\Omega$. |
|
\end{definition} |
|
For example, $\Omega$ might be $\ereals ^n$ and $\mu$ might be the Lebesgue measure. |
|
A measure determines an integration operator: if $f\in\QBS(X,\ereals+)$ then define |
|
\[\textstyle\int f \dif\,(\Omega,\alpha,\mu)\definedby \int_\Omega f(\alpha(x))\,\mu(\dif x)\] |
|
using Lebesgue integration according to $\mu$. |
|
We say that two measures are equal, denoted $(\Omega,\alpha,\mu)\approx(\Omega',\alpha',\mu')$, if they determine the same integration operator. |
|
We write $[\Omega,\alpha,\mu]$ for an equivalence class of measures. |
|
|
|
As an aside, we note that not every integration operator on $\ereals$ in the classical sense is a measure in the sense of Def.~\ref{def:measure}, |
|
because we restrict to $\sigma$-finite $\mu$. |
|
Technically, the only integration operators that arise in this way are those corresponding to s-finite measures. This is a class of measures that includes the probability measures, and which works well with iterated integration |
|
and probabilistic programming~\cite{sfinite}. |
|
|
|
The measures up-to $\approx$ form a monad, as follows. |
|
First, the set of all measures $\Qmonad X$ forms a QBS by setting |
|
$M_{\Qmonad X}=\set{\fun r [D_r,\alpha(r,-),\mu|_{D_r}]~\suchthat~ |
|
\mu\text{\,$\sigma$-finite on $\Omega$},\,D\subseteq \baseR\times \Omega\,\text{measurable},\,\alpha\in \QBS(D, X)}$, |
|
where $D_r=\{\omega~|~(r,\omega)\in D\}$. |
|
In consequence, when $\Omega'$ is a standard Borel space, |
|
for every morphism $f:\Omega'\to \Qmonad X$, |
|
there exist $\Omega$, $\mu$, $D\subseteq \Omega'\times \Omega$ and $\alpha\in \QBS(D, X)$ |
|
such that $f(\omega')=[D_{\omega'},\alpha(\omega',-),\mu|_{D_{\omega'}}]$. |
|
One intuition is that $\alpha$ is a partial function $\Omega'\times \Omega\to X$, with domain $D$. |
|
|
|
The unit of the monad, $\return:X\to \Qmonad X$, is $\return(x)\definedby[\terminal,\fun{\_} x,\delta_{\tUnit}]$ |
|
where $\delta_{\tUnit}$ is the Dirac measure on the one-point space $\terminal$. |
|
We often write $\qdelta_x$ for $\return(x)$. |
|
The bind $\bind:\Qmonad X\times \Qmonad Y^X\to \Qmonad Y$ is |
|
\[ |
|
[\Omega,\alpha,\mu]\bind \phi\ \definedby \ [D,\beta,(\mu\otimes \mu')|_D] |
|
\] |
|
where $\phi(\alpha(r))=[D_r,\beta(r,-),\mu']$. Note that $(\phi \compose \alpha):\Omega\to \Qmonad X$ must be of this form because it is a morphism from a standard Borel space. |
|
The measure $\mu\otimes \mu'$ is the product measure, which exists because $\mu$ and $\mu'$ are $\sigma$-finite. |
|
|
|
|
|
This structure satisfies the monad laws, it is commutative by the |
|
Fubini-Tonelli theorem, and it satisfies the biproduct axioms, and so |
|
it is a model of synthetic measure theory. Every measure on |
|
$\terminal$ is equivalent to one of the form $([0,r],!,\mu)$ where |
|
$r\in \ereals+$, $! : [0,r] \to \terminal$ is the unique such random |
|
element, and $\mu$ is the Lebesgue measure. Thus $\Qmonad \terminal |
|
\cong \ereals+$. |
|
|
|
As another aside, we note that when $\Omega,\Omega'$ are standard Borel spaces, |
|
the Kleisli morphisms $\Omega\to \Qmonad \Omega'$ correspond to s-finite kernels, |
|
which were shown in \cite{sfinite} to provide a fully complete model of first-order probabilistic programming. |
|
\section{Continuous inference}\seclabel{continuous} |
|
We now develop the continuous counterpart to \secref{discrete}. The |
|
semantic structure of the category of quasi-Borel spaces allows |
|
us to transport many of the definitions with little change. For example, a |
|
monadic interface $\ir$ consists of analogous data, but the |
|
assignments are indexed by quasi-Borel spaces, $\uir$ assigns |
|
quasi-Borel spaces, and $\return^{\ir}$ and $\bind^{\ir}$ assign |
|
quasi-Borel space morphisms. |
|
|
|
\begin{definition} |
|
A \emph{continuous representation} $\ir$ is a tuple |
|
\( |
|
\seq*{\uir, \return^{\ir}, \bind^{\ir}, \mean^{\ir}} |
|
\) |
|
consisting of: |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item a monadic interface $\triple*{\uir}{\return^{\ir}}{\bind^{\ir}}$; |
|
\item an assignment of a \emph{meaning} morphism |
|
$\mean^{\ir}_X : \uir X \to \Mea X$ for every space $X$ |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
such that $\mean^{\ir}$ preserves $\return^{\ir}$ and $\bind^{\ir}$. |
|
|
|
A \emph{sampling} representation is a tuple |
|
$\seq*{\uir, \return^{\ir}, \bind^{\ir}, \mean^{\ir}, |
|
\sample^{\ir}}$ such that its first four components form a continuous |
|
representation, it has an additional $\Qbs$-morphism |
|
$\sample^{\ir} : \terminal \to \uir\I$, and |
|
$\mean^{\ir}$ maps $\sample^{\ir}\tUnit$ to |
|
the uniform $\Qbs$-measure $\Uniform[] = [\I,\id,\UniformD]$ |
|
on the unit interval $\I$, where $\UniformD$ is the usual |
|
uniform distribution on $\I$. |
|
|
|
A \emph{conditioning} representation $\ir$ is |
|
similarly a tuple |
|
\( \seq*{\uir, \return^{\ir}, \bind^{\ir}, \score^{\ir}, |
|
\mean^{\ir}} \), with a $\Qbs$-morphism |
|
$\score^{\ir} : \reals+ \to \uir\terminal$ such that for each $r$, |
|
$\mean^{\ir}$ maps $\score^{\ir}(r)$ to the $r$-rescaled unit $\Qbs$-measure |
|
$r \odot \qdelta_{\tUnit} = [\terminal,\fun{\_} \tUnit, r \cdot \delta_{\tUnit}]$. |
|
|
|
An \emph{inference} representation $\ir$ is a |
|
tuple |
|
$\seq*{\uir, \return^{\ir}, \bind^{\ir}, \sample^{\ir}, |
|
\score^{\ir}, \mean^{\ir}}$ with the appropriate components |
|
forming both a sampling representation and a conditioning representation. |
|
\end{definition} |
|
This definition refines \defref{disc inf rep} with sampling and |
|
scoring representations, allowing us to talk about inference |
|
transformers that augment a representation of one kind into another. |
|
|
|
\begin{example}[Continuous sampler] |
|
By analogy with \exampleref{disc weighted sampler}, we define in |
|
\figref{sam} a sampling representation using the type |
|
\( \Sam \tvar \definedby \Variant{\Inj{Return} \tvar \vor |
|
\Inj{Sample} (\I \to \Sam\tvar)} \). Validating the preservation of sample |
|
and the monadic interface is straightforward. It also follows from |
|
more general principles: $\monad\Sam$ is the initial monad with an |
|
operation $\sample : \uir\I$. |
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{minipage}[b]{.5\linewidth} |
|
\[ |
|
\SampleMonad{\Sam}{ |
|
\sreturn \var\ \ &= \Inj{Return} \var |
|
}{ |
|
a \bind f &= \imatch a{\Inj{Return} \var & f(x) \\ |
|
\Inj{Sample} k \\ |
|
\multicolumn{2}{@{\quad}l@{}}{ |
|
\Inj{Sample} (\fun r k(r) \bind f)}} |
|
}{ |
|
\ssample &= \Inj{Sample}{\fun r(\Inj{Return} r)} |
|
}{ |
|
\mean a &= \imatch a{\Inj{Return} \var & \qdelta_x \\[.2ex] |
|
\Inj{Sample} k & \qint_{\ \I}k(x)\Uniform(\dif x)} |
|
} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{Continuous sampler representation}\figlabel{sam} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
\begin{minipage}[b]{.5\linewidth} |
|
\[ |
|
\RepTrans{Rep}{Cond}{\Writer} |
|
{ |
|
\sreturn_{\Writer\ir} x &= \return^{\ir} \tpair 1x |
|
}{ |
|
a \bind_{\Writer\ir} f &= |
|
\begin{aligned}[t] |
|
\expdomon\ir{&\tpair rx \<- a; |
|
\\&\tpair sy \<- f(x); |
|
\\&\sreturn \tpair{r\cdot s}y} |
|
\end{aligned} |
|
}{ |
|
(\stmap \tfm)_X &= \tfm_{\reals+\t* X} |
|
}{ |
|
\slift_{\ir} a &= \expdomon\ir{x \<- a; \sreturn \tpair 1x} |
|
}{ |
|
\mean_{\Writer\ir} a &= |
|
\fun x\qint_{\ \reals+\times X}r\odot |
|
\qdelta_x m^{\ir}(a)(\dif r, \dif x) |
|
\\& |
|
\sscore_{\Writer\ir} r &= \return^{\ir} \tpair r\tUnit |
|
} |
|
\] |
|
\medskip |
|
\subcaption{Continuous weighting inference transformer} |
|
\figlabel{cont weighting} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
\caption{Continuous representations and tranformers}\figlabel{cont |
|
weight sampler} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
|
|
We define inference transformations between any two representations as |
|
in \defref{disc inf tfm}. We have four kinds of representations, and |
|
when defining transformers we can augment a representation with |
|
additional capabilities: |
|
|
|
\begin{definition} |
|
Let $k_1$, $k_2$ be a pair of kinds of representation. |
|
A \emph{$k_1$ to $k_2$ transformer} $\IF$ is a tuple |
|
$\seq*{\uIF, \itmap^{\IF}, \lift^{\IF}}$ consisting of an assignments |
|
of: |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item a $k_2$ representation $\uIF \ir$ to every |
|
$k_1$ representation $\ir$; |
|
\item an inference transformation |
|
$\itmap^{\IF} \tfm : \IF\ir \to \IF\ir[2]$ to every |
|
transformation $\tfm : \ir \to \ir[2]$; and |
|
\item an inference transformation $\lift_{\uir} : \ir \to \uIF \ir$ to |
|
every $k_1$ representation $\ir$. |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
When the two kinds $k_1$, $k_2$ differ, we say that that the |
|
transformer is \emph{augmenting}. |
|
\end{definition} |
|
|
|
When defining a $k_1$ to $k_2$ transformer, we adopt a Haskell-like |
|
type-class constraint notation $k_1 \implies k_2$ used for example in |
|
\figref{suspend}. |
|
|
|
\begin{example}\examplelabel{cont weighting trans} |
|
By analogy with \exampleref{disc weighting trans}, \figref{cont |
|
weighting} presents the \emph{continuous weighting} transformer |
|
structure on \( \Writer \ir\, X \definedby T(\reals+ \t* X) \). It |
|
augments any representation transformer with conditioning |
|
capabilities. Each conditioning operation is deferred to the return |
|
value, and so we can view this transformer as freely adding a |
|
conditioning operation that commutes with all other operations. |
|
When the starting representation had conditioning capabilities, we |
|
have an inference transformation $\waggr : \Writer\ir \to \ir $, |
|
given by |
|
\( \waggr a \definedby \expdomon\ir{ \tpair rx \<- a; \score^{\ir} |
|
r; \sreturn x } \) which conditions based on the aggregated |
|
weight. |
|
|
|
Its validity follows from a straightforward calculation using the |
|
meaning preservation of $\ir$. |
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
In the continuous case, the output of the final inference transformation |
|
will always be $\Writer \Sampling X$ or a similar $\Pop \Sampling X$ described |
|
in the next section. From this representation, we obtain the Monte Carlo |
|
approximation to the posterior by using a random number generator to supply |
|
the values required by $\Sampling\!\!$. Interpreting the program directly in |
|
$\Writer \Sampling X$ and sampling from that would correspond to simple |
|
importance sampling from the prior, which usually needs a very large number |
|
of samples to give a good approximation to the posterior. Our goal in approximate |
|
Bayesian inference is therefore to find another representation for the program |
|
and a sequence of inference transformations that map it to $\Writer \Sampling X$. |
|
While, in principle, this output represents the same posterior distribution, |
|
hopefully it uses a representation that requires fewer samples to obtain a good |
|
approximation than a direct interpretation in $\Writer \Sampling X$. We emphasise |
|
that approximation is only done in this final sampling step, while all the |
|
inference transformations that happen before it are exact. |
|
\section{Sequential Monte Carlo}\seclabel{SMC} |
|
\emph{Sequential Monte Carlo (SMC)} is a family of inference algorithms |
|
for approximating sequences of distributions. In SMC, every distribution is |
|
approximated by a collection of weighted samples called a \emph{population}, |
|
with each population obtained from the previous one in the sequence by a |
|
suitable transformation. In a sub-class of SMC known as \emph{particle filters}, |
|
each distribution in the sequence is generated by a known random process from |
|
the previous distribution and we can apply this process to samples in the |
|
previous population to obtain the current population. In particle filters |
|
the samples in the population are called \emph{particles}. |
|
|
|
A common problem with particle filters is that, after multiple steps, |
|
a few particles have much larger weights than the remaining ones, |
|
effectively reducing the sample size in the population well below the actual |
|
number of particles, a phenomenon known as \emph{sample impoverishment}. To ameliorate |
|
this problem, particle filters introduce additional \emph{resample} operations |
|
after each step in the sequence, which constructs a new population by sampling |
|
with replacement from the old one. The new population has uniform weights |
|
across its particles. In the setting of probabilistic |
|
programming, we use suspended computations as particles, and their |
|
associated weight is their currently accumulated likelihood. |
|
|
|
We show how to decompose a particle filter into a stack of two |
|
transformers: a representation to conditioning transformer for |
|
representing a population of particles, and a conditioning to conditioning |
|
transformer that allows us to run a particle until its |
|
next conditioning operation. We define each step of the SMC algorithm |
|
as an inference transformation on this stack. We can then apply this |
|
stack of transformers to a sampling representation to obtain a correct |
|
by construction variation of SMC. The algorithm we obtain is known as |
|
the particle filter with multinomial resampling \citep{doucet-johansen:smc-tutorial11} |
|
that uses the prior as the proposal distribution, but throughout |
|
this paper we refer to it simply as SMC. |
|
|
|
\subsection{The population transformer} |
|
Given a representation $\ir$, we define a representation structure |
|
over $\Pop \ir\, X \definedby \uir (\List (\reals+ \t* X))$. We further |
|
deconstruct this representation transformer as the composition of two |
|
transformers: the continuous weighting transformer $\Writer$ from |
|
\exampleref{cont weighting trans}, and Haskell's notorious $\ListT$ |
|
transformer. |
|
|
|
The negative reputation associated to the transformer |
|
$\ListT \ir\, X \definedby \uir (\List X)$ stems from its failure to |
|
validate the monad laws when $\ir$ is not |
|
commutative.\footnotemark\ However, it is a perfectly valid |
|
representation transformer, described in \figref{listT}, since we do not |
|
require that representations satisfy monad laws. |
|
|
|
|
|
\footnotetext{For a list transformer ``done right'', see |
|
\citepos*{jaskelioff:thesis}{thesis}, and its |
|
generalisations~\cite{pirogy:em-monoids, fiore-saville:list-objects}.} |
|
|
|
To prove the meaning function preserves $\return$, simply |
|
calculate. For $\bind$ preservation, show: |
|
\[ |
|
a_s : \List(\uir X) \tinf |
|
\mean^{\ListT \ir} (\sequence a_s) = \sum_{a \in a_s} \mean^{\ir}(a) |
|
\] |
|
and proceed via straightforward calculation using the linearity of the |
|
Kock integral and the commutative ($\sigma$-)monoid structure on measures. |
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{minipage}[b]{.5\linewidth} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}} |
|
\text{Auxiliary functions:} \\ |
|
\sequence : \List (TX) \to T(\List X) \\ |
|
\sequence \definedby \begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
\foldlist &(\return \lst-) \\ |
|
&(\fun {\tpair ar} |
|
\expdomon\ir{\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
x &\<- a; \\ |
|
x_s &\<- r;\\ |
|
\multicolumn{2}{@{}l@{}}{ |
|
\sreturn (x :: x_s)}} |
|
\end{array}\\ |
|
\end{array} |
|
\\ |
|
\concat : \List(\List X) \to \List X\\ |
|
\concat \definedby \foldlist {\lst-} \++ |
|
\\ |
|
\sum_{x \in x_s}f(x) \definedby |
|
\foldlist 0 |
|
\parent{\fun {\tpair xs}f(x)+s}\ x_s |
|
\\\\ |
|
\RepTrans{Rep}{Rep}{\ListT}{ |
|
\sreturn_{\ListT \ir} x &{}= \return^{\ir} \lst x |
|
}{ |
|
a \bind_{\ListT \ir} f &{}= |
|
\expdomon\ir{\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}} |
|
x_s \<- a; \\ |
|
\letin {b_{s}} |
|
{\tmap f\ x_s} \\ |
|
y_{ss} \<- \sequence{b_s}; \\ |
|
\sreturn (\concat y_{ss}) |
|
} |
|
\end{array} |
|
}{ |
|
\mean_{\ListT \ir}a &= \qint_{\List X} |
|
\mean^{\ir}(a)(\dif x_s) |
|
\sum_{x \in x_s}\qdelta_x |
|
}{ |
|
\slift_{\ListT \ir} a &= \expdomon\ir{\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}} |
|
x \<- a; |
|
\sreturn{\lst{x}}} |
|
\end{array} |
|
}{ |
|
(\stmap \tfm)_X &= \tfm_{\List X} |
|
} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{The list transformer}\figlabel{listT} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
~~ |
|
\begin{minipage}[b]{.5\linewidth} |
|
\( |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}} |
|
\RepTrans{Rep}{Cond}{\Pop}{ |
|
\sreturn_{\Pop\ir}{} &= \sreturn_{(\Writer \compose \ListT) \ir} |
|
}{ |
|
\bind_{\Pop\ir} &= {\bind_{(\Writer \compose \ListT) \ir}} |
|
}{ |
|
\slift_{\Pop\ir} &= \slift_{\Writer (\ListT \ir)} \compose \slift_{\ListT \ir} |
|
}{ |
|
\stmap_{\Pop\ir} &= \stmap_{\Writer (\ListT \ir)} \compose \stmap_{\ListT\ir} |
|
}{ |
|
\mean_{\Pop\ir} &= \mean_{(\Writer\compose\ListT)\ir}\\& |
|
&= \fun a |
|
\sqint\limits_{\mathclap{\List(\reals+\times X)}} |
|
\mean^{\uir}(a)(\dif x_s) |
|
\sum_{\pair rx\in x_s}r\odot \qdelta_x |
|
\\[3ex]& |
|
\sscore_{\Pop\ir} &= \sscore_{(\Writer\compose\ListT) \ir} |
|
} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\) |
|
\subcaption{The population transformer}\figlabel{population} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}} |
|
\replicate : \naturals \t* X \to \List X \\ |
|
\replicate \tpair nx \definedby \tfold\naturals |
|
\pfun{ |
|
\Inj{Zero} &\To \lst- \\\vor |
|
\Inj{Succ} x_s &\To x::x_s |
|
\}\ n\gobble} |
|
\\ |
|
\spark : \naturals_+ \To \Pop \ir\, \Unit \\ |
|
\spark \definedby \return^{\ir} |
|
\parent{\replicate \tpair {n}{\tpair {\tfrac 1{n}}\tUnit}} |
|
\\ |
|
\spawn : \naturals_+ \t* \Pop \ir\, X \to \Pop \ir\, X \\ |
|
\spawn \tpair na \definedby |
|
\expdomon{\Pop\ir}{ |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}} |
|
\spark n; |
|
a |
|
} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{Spawning new particles} |
|
\figlabel{spawning} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
\caption{Representing populations} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
By composing the two representation transformers, we obtain the |
|
representation to conditioning transformer $\Pop$, given explicitly in |
|
\figref{population}. |
|
|
|
\figref{spawning} presents a $\naturals_+$-indexed family of inference |
|
transformations. Fix any $n \in \naturals$. The $\spark$ function |
|
generates a population of particles with the unit value, and |
|
the same weight $\tfrac 1n$. Thus, $\spawn\pair na$ takes a |
|
distribution $a$ over particle populations, sparks $n$ equally |
|
weighted particles, and for each of them, samples a population based |
|
on $a$. A straightforward calculation confirms that the meaning of |
|
$\spark$ is $1$, and so $\spawn\pair n- : \Pop \ir \to \Pop \ir$ is an |
|
inference transformation. In the version of SMC we consider below, we |
|
will only pass to $\spawn$ a distribution $a$ over uniformly-weighted |
|
single-particle populations. |
|
|
|
We use $\spawn$ to \emph{resample} a new population. Thinking |
|
operationally, we have a population of weighted particles and we |
|
obtain a new population by sampling with replacement from the |
|
current one, where the probability of selecting a given particle is |
|
proportional to its weight. Doing so is equivalent to simulating a |
|
discrete weighted sample using a uniform one. |
|
\begin{lemma}\lemmalabel{randomisation} |
|
There is a $\Qbs$-morphism |
|
$\dwrand : \List(\reals+\t* X)\t*\I \to \Variant |
|
{\Inj{Take}X \vor \Inj{Fail}}$ such that: |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item For all $x_s$ for which $\sum_{\tpair r\_ \in x_s}r = 0$, we |
|
have $\dwrand(x_s, -)_*\Uniform = \qdelta_{\Inj[]{Fail}}$. |
|
\item For all $x_s$ for which $w := \sum_{\tpair r\_ \in x_s}r > 0$, |
|
we have |
|
$\dwrand(x_s, -)_*\Uniform = \sum_{\tpair rx \in x_s} \tfrac |
|
{r_i}w\odot \qdelta_{\Inj{Take}x}$. |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
\figref{dwrand} presents one such morphism, though its precise |
|
implementation does not matter to our development. As a consequence, |
|
for every sampling representation $\ir$ for which we have an element |
|
$\fail : TX$ such that $\mean^{\ir}(\fail) = 0$, we can define a |
|
discrete weighted sampler $\dwsampler^{\ir}(x_s) : \List(\ereals+\*X) \to TX$ in \figref{dwsampler} which will then |
|
satisfy $\mean^{\ir}(\dwsampler^{\ir}(x_s)) = \sum_{\tpair rx \in x_s}r\odot \qdelta_x$. |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{minipage}[b]{.5\linewidth} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}} |
|
\dwrand(x_s, r) \definedby \\ |
|
\quad\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}} |
|
\letin {w}{\sum_{\tpair r\_ \in x_s}r}\\ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
\tif{&w = 0\\} |
|
{{}&\Inj[]{Fail}\\} |
|
&\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{}} \foldlist &{\tpair{w\cdot r}{\Inj[]{Fail}}}\\ |
|
&(\fun {\tpair{\tpair sx}{\tpair\fuel\result}} \\ |
|
&\begin{array}{@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
\tif{&0 \leq \fuel < s\\} |
|
{&\tpair{-1}{\Inj{Take}x}\\} |
|
{&\ \scomment{potential underflow}}\\&\tpair{\fuel - s}{\result}) |
|
\\x_s |
|
\end{array} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\]\\\bigskip |
|
\subcaption{A discrete weighted randomiser} |
|
\figlabel{dwrand} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
~~ |
|
\begin{minipage}[b]{.5\linewidth} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}} |
|
\dwsampler^{\ir}(x_s) |
|
\definedby\\ |
|
\quad |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
\expdomon\ir{&\score (\sum_{\tpair r\_ \in x_s}r); \\ |
|
&r \<- \ssample; \\ |
|
&\imatch{\dwrand\pair {x_s}r} |
|
{\Inj[]{Fail} & \fail \\ |
|
\mathllap{\vor{}}\Inj{Take}x & \sreturn x\}}\gobble} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{A discrete weighted sampler} |
|
\figlabel{dwsampler} |
|
|
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}} |
|
\resample : \naturals_+ \t* \Pop\ir\, X \to \Pop\ir\, X \\ |
|
\resample\tpair na \definedby \\ |
|
\qquad |
|
\expdomon\ir{\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}} |
|
x_s \<- a;\\ |
|
\spawn \tpair n {\dwsampler^{\Pop\ir} x_s} |
|
} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{Resampling}\figlabel{resampling} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
\caption{The resampling transformation} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
The resampling step in \figref{resampling} operationally takes the |
|
current population, creates a computation/thunk that samples a single |
|
particle from this population, and then spawns $n$ new particles that |
|
are initialised with this thunk. The morphism $\resample\pair n- : \Pop \ir \to \Pop \ir$ is an |
|
inference transformation because, as we know, |
|
$\spawn\pair n- $ is one and $\dwsampler^{\Pop\ir}: \Pop \ir \to \Pop \ir$ samples |
|
a population consisting of just a single unit weight particle with |
|
a probability proportional to its renormalised weight in the original population. |
|
|
|
\subsection{The suspension transformer} \label{sec:sus} |
|
The second transformer in the SMC algorithm allows us to suspend |
|
computation after each conditioning. The suspension transformer equips |
|
the standard \emph{resumption} monad transformer |
|
$\Sus \ir\, X \definedby \uir \Variant { \Inj{Return} X \vor \Inj{Yield} |
|
(\Sus \ir\, X)}$, presented in \figref{suspend}, with inference transformations. |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{minipage}[t]{.5\linewidth} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}} |
|
\RepTrans{Cond}{Cond}{\Sus}{ |
|
\sreturn_{\Sus\ir}x &{}= \return_{\ir} (\Inj{Return}x) |
|
}{ |
|
a \bind_{\Sus\ir} f &{}=\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
&\fold {}( |
|
\fun b |
|
\expdomon{\ir}{\\ |
|
&t \<- b;\\ |
|
&\imatch t{ |
|
\Inj{Return}x & f(x)\\ |
|
\mathllap{\vor{}}\Inj{Yield}c & \Inj{Yield}c |
|
\})} |
|
\gobble} |
|
\\&a |
|
\end{array} |
|
}{ |
|
\slift_{\Sus\ir} a &= \expdomon\ir{x \<- a; \return_{\Sus\ir}x} |
|
}{ |
|
(\stmap_{\Sus\ir} \tfm)_X&= \tfold{\Sus\ir X}(\fun b \mean_{\ir[2]}(b)) |
|
}{ |
|
\mean_{\Sus\ir} a &= m_{\ir}(\finish_{\Sus\ir}(a)) |
|
|
|
\\ |
|
&\sscore r &= \return_{\ir}({\Inj{Yield}\lift_{\Sus\ir}(\sscore r)}) |
|
} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{The suspension transformer} |
|
\figlabel{suspend} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
~\quad |
|
\begin{minipage}[t]{.5\linewidth} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
\adva_{\ir} &: \Sus \ir X \to \Sus \ir X \\ |
|
\adva_{\ir} a &{}= |
|
\expdomon\ir{\\ |
|
&\qquad t \<- a;\\ |
|
&\qquad\imatch t { |
|
\Inj{Return}x & \return_{\ir}x \\ |
|
\mathllap{\vor{}}\Inj{Yield} t & t |
|
\}}\gobble} |
|
\\ |
|
\finish_{\ir} &: \Sus \ir X \to \ir X \\ |
|
\finish_{\ir}a &{}= |
|
\fold \fun b \expdomon\ir{\\ |
|
&\qquad t \<- b;\\ |
|
&\qquad \imatch t{ |
|
\Inj{Return}x & \return x \\ |
|
\mathllap{\vor{}} \Inj{Yield} b & b\} |
|
}\gobble |
|
} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{Suspension operations}\figlabel{suspension ops} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
\caption{The suspension transformation} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
The two transformations on suspended computations in |
|
\figref{suspension ops} take one step, and complete the computation, |
|
accordingly. As the meaning function for the transformed representation |
|
returns the meaning the computation would have if it was allowed to |
|
run to completion, these two operations do not change the meaning and |
|
so form inference transformations. |
|
|
|
We can now put all the components together: |
|
\begin{theorem} |
|
Let $\ir$ be a sampling representation. For every pair of natural |
|
numbers $n$, $k$, the following composite forms an inference transformation: |
|
\begin{multline*} |
|
\smc^{\ir}_{n, k} \definedby |
|
(\Sus\compose \Pop) \ir |
|
\xto{\stmap_{\Sus}\spawn\tpair n-} |
|
(\Sus\compose \Pop) \ir |
|
\\ \xto{(\adva \compose \stmap_{\Sus}\resample(n, -))^{\compose k}} |
|
(\Sus\compose \Pop) \ir |
|
\xto{\finish} |
|
\Pop \ir |
|
\end{multline*} |
|
\end{theorem} |
|
In the above $(-)^{\compose -} : X^X\times \naturals \to X^X$ |
|
denotes $n$-fold composition. |
|
The transformation $\smc^{\ir}_{n,k}$ amounts to running the SMC |
|
algorithm with $n$ particles for $k$ steps. |
|
If the representation |
|
$\ir$ is operational in nature, such as the continuous sampler $\Sam$, |
|
we get a sequence of weighted values over the return type when we run |
|
the resulting representation. By construction, the distribution on the |
|
results, rescaled according to their final weights, would be identical |
|
to the desired posterior distribution. |
|
|
|
When the representation $\ir$ is not a commutative monad, like the |
|
continuous sampler $\Sam$, the resulting representation $\Pop \ir$ is |
|
not a monad: the monad laws do not hold. Therefore, to encompass |
|
representations of $\Pop \ir$ one must generalise beyond monads. |
|
|
|
\section{Trace Markov Chain Monte Carlo}\seclabel{MHG} |
|
Markov Chain Monte Carlo (MCMC) algorithms operate by repeatedly using |
|
a transition kernel to generate a new sample from a current one. |
|
Thus they can be thought of as performing a |
|
random walk around the space they are exploring. If the transition |
|
kernel is well-behaved, they are guaranteed to preserve the |
|
distribution. |
|
A popular MCMC algorithm used for Bayesian inference is Metropolis-Hastings (MH), |
|
where the transition kernel consists of a proposal kernel followed by a decision |
|
to either accept the proposed sample or keep the old one. |
|
The accept or reject step is used to correct for bias introduced by the |
|
proposal kernel, thus producing a valid MCMC algorithm for a rich family |
|
of proposal kernels. |
|
|
|
MH is a general inference method, but it requires |
|
specialised knowledge about the space on which they operate on. In the |
|
context of a probabilistic programming language, the \emph{Trace MH} |
|
algorithm replaces the unknown target space with the space of program |
|
\emph{traces}, which are shared by all probabilistic programs. Thus, |
|
Trace MH allows probabilistic programming language designers to |
|
devise general-purpose kernels to effectively explore traces. |
|
|
|
We analyse the the Trace MH as follows. First, we prove a |
|
quasi-Borel space counterpart of the \emph{Metropolis-Hastings-Green |
|
(MHG) Theorem}, that forms the theoretical foundation for the |
|
correctness of MH. We then present the \emph{tracing} representation |
|
and show its validity. We present the Trace MH algorithm, |
|
parameterised by a proposal kernel for traces, and give sufficient |
|
conditions on this kernel for the resulting transformation to be |
|
valid. We then give a concrete proposal kernel and show that it |
|
satisfies these general conditions. |
|
|
|
\subsection{Abstract Metropolis-Hastings-Green} |
|
In the abstract, the key ingredient in MH is the |
|
\emph{Metropolis-Hastings-Green (MHG)} morphism $\mh[]$ presented in |
|
\figref{mh update}, formulated in terms of an arbitrary inference |
|
representation $\ir$. This transformation is usually known as the |
|
\emph{update step} of the MH algorithm. It is parameterised by a |
|
(representation of a) \emph{proposal} kernel $\psi : X \to \uir X$, and by |
|
a chosen (representation of a) Radon-Nikodym derivative |
|
$\rho : X\times X \to \ereals+$. |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{minipage}[b]{.375\linewidth} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{\qquad}} |
|
\psi : (&\uir X)^{X}, {}\rho : \ereals+^{X\times X}, a : \uir X \tinf\\ |
|
&\expdomon\ir{ |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{\,}l@{}} |
|
x \<- a; \\ |
|
y \<- \psi(x); \\ |
|
r \<- \ssample; \\ |
|
\tif {r < \min(1,\rho(x,y))\\}{ |
|
\sreturn y \\}{ |
|
\sreturn x}} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{The Metropolis-Hastings-Green\\morphism $\mh[{\psi, \rho}](a)$}\figlabel{mh update} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
~ |
|
\begin{minipage}[b]{.625\linewidth} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
p \in t {}= \vmatch{\tpair pt}{ |
|
\begin{array}[t]{*4{@{}l}@{\quad}l@{}} |
|
\tpair{\lst{\ }&}{\Inj{Return}x&} &\To \tru \\ |
|
\tpair{r :: r_s&}{\Inj{Sample}f&} &\To [r_s \in f(r)] \\ |
|
\multicolumn{2}{@{}c@{}}{\scomment{ any other case: }}\\ |
|
\tpair{\_ &}{\_ &} &\To \fls} & |
|
\end{array} |
|
\\ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{\quad}l@{}} |
|
\weight \placeholder : \sum_{t \in \WSam X} \paths t \to \reals+ |
|
& |
|
\valuate\placeholder : \sum_{t \in \WSam X} \paths t \to X\\ |
|
\weight {\Inj{Return} \tpair rx}(\lst{\ }) = r & |
|
\valuate{\Inj{Return} \tpair rx}(\lst{\ }) = x\\ |
|
\weight {\Inj{Sample}{t_{\placeholder}}}(s :: r_s) = \weight {t_s}(r_s) |
|
& |
|
\valuate{\Inj{Sample}{t_{\placeholder}}}(s :: r_s) = \valuate{t_s}(r_s) |
|
\end{array} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{Traces through a probabilistic program}\figlabel{traces} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
\caption{Basic notions in Trace MH} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
To use $\mh[]$ in an inference transformation, we need to provide |
|
well-behaved parameters $\psi, \rho$, and their behaviour may depend |
|
on the representation of the input distribution $a$. In particular, |
|
the parameter $\rho$ should represent a well-behaved appropriate |
|
Radon-Nikodym derivative. To simplify our proofs, we also require that |
|
the proposal kernel $\psi$ is Markov, which suffices for our |
|
application. |
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{theorem}[Metropolis-Hastings-Green]\theoremlabel{MHG update} |
|
Let $X$ be a qbs, $a \in TX$ a distribution, $\psi : X \to TX$ a |
|
kernel, and $\rho : X\times X \to \ereals+$ a $\Qbs$-morphism. Set |
|
$k \definedby m^{\ir} \compose \psi$ and |
|
$\qmu \definedby [\rho\neq 0] \odot (m^{\ir}(a) \bprod k)$. |
|
|
|
Assume that: |
|
\begin{enumerate*} |
|
\item $k$ is Markov; |
|
\item $[1 = \parent{\rho \circ \braid[]} \cdot \rho]$ holds |
|
$\qmu$-a.e.; |
|
\item $\rho$ is a Radon-Nikodym derivative of |
|
$\braid[]_*\qmu$ |
|
with respect to $\qmu$; and |
|
\item $\rho(x,y) = 0 \iff \rho(y,x) = 0$ for all $x,y \in X$. |
|
\end{enumerate*} |
|
|
|
Then $(m^{\ir} \compose \mh[\psi,\rho])(a) = m^{\ir}(a)$. |
|
\end{theorem} |
|
|
|
Using Kock's synthetic measure theory, we were able to follow closely |
|
standard measure-theoretic proofs of MHG \cite{geyer:intro-mcmc}. The |
|
synthetic setting highlights the different roles each of the three |
|
abstractions: a.e.-equality, a.e.-properties, and Radon-Nykodim |
|
derivatives play in the proof that our formulation exposes |
|
(cf.~\subsubsecref{Radon-Nikodym}). |
|
|
|
\subsection{Tracing representation} |
|
A sampling \emph{trace} is a sequence of samples that occur during the |
|
execution of a probabilistic program. We represent such programs as |
|
elements of the continuous weighted sampler $\Writer \Sam$ from |
|
(cf.~\figref{cont weight sampler}). Consequently, the collection of |
|
traces through a program $t \in \Writer \Sam X$ is a subset of |
|
$\List\I$. \figref{traces} defines a measurable predicate |
|
$[\in] : \Writer \Sam X \times \List \I \to \boolty$ that tests whether |
|
a given sequence $p$ of probabilistic choice forms a complete trace in |
|
the program $t$. Consequently, we can define the set of \emph{paths} |
|
through a given program $t$ by |
|
$\paths t \definedby \set{p \in \List \I \suchthat p \in t} \subset |
|
\List\I$, and equip it with the subspace structure it inherits from |
|
$\List \I$. We can therefore define the set: \[ |
|
\sum_{t \in \WSam X}\paths t := \set{\tpair tp \in \WSam X \times |
|
\List \I \suchthat p \in t} \subset \WSam X \times \List \I |
|
\] |
|
which we can also equip with a subspace structure. We can now define |
|
the \emph{weight} $\weight-$ and \emph{valuation} $\valuate-$ |
|
morphisms in \figref{traces} that retrieve the likelihood and value at |
|
the end of a trace. |
|
|
|
We can now define the tracing inference representation. It is |
|
parameterised by an inference representation $\ir$ and given for $X$ |
|
as the following subspace of $\WSam X \times T(\List \I)$: |
|
\[ |
|
\Trace \ir\ X \definedby |
|
\set{ \tpair t a \in \WSam X \times \uir(\List \I) |
|
\suchthat |
|
\begin{aligned}[<{\textstyle}c] |
|
&\text{$[{}\in t]$ $\mean_{\ir}(a)$-a.e., and} |
|
\\&\textstyle |
|
m_{\WSam}(t) |
|
= |
|
\qint_{\List\I} |
|
\qdelta_{\valuate{t}(p)} \mean_{\ir}(a)(\dif p) |
|
\end{aligned} |
|
}. |
|
\] |
|
Thus, a representation consists of a program representation $t$, |
|
together with a distribution $a$ on all lists, but maintaining two |
|
invariants. First, the lists are $\mean_{\ir}(a)$-almost-everywhere paths |
|
through $t$, and so we can indeed think of $a$ as a representation |
|
of a distribution over traces. Second, if we calculate the posterior |
|
of the paths through $t$ according to $\mean_{\ir}(a)$, it should have the |
|
same meaning as the original program. |
|
|
|
We stress that an implementation need \emph{not} compute the meaning |
|
of the program. But this representation guarantees that the meaning |
|
will be preserved by the inference operations. |
|
|
|
Note that the integrand in the definition of |
|
$\tpair ta \in \Trace T\ X$ is only partially defined. This partiality |
|
is not an issue because the first condition guarantees it is |
|
$m^T(a)$-a.e.~defined. We can then choose the constantly $0$ |
|
distribution when $p \notin t$. |
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{minipage}[b]{.5\linewidth} |
|
\[ |
|
\GenMonad{Inf \implies Inf\ Monad}{}{\Trace\ir}{ |
|
&\sreturn x &{}= \tpair{\return_{\WSam}x}{\return_{\ir}\lst-} |
|
\\ |
|
&\tpair ta\bind \tpair{f}{g} &{}= \pair*{t \bind_{\WSam}f}{ |
|
\expdomon{\ir}{ \begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}} |
|
p \<- a; \\ |
|
q \<- g\compose \valuate t(p); \\ |
|
\sreturn (p \++ q)) |
|
|
|
}}\end{array} |
|
\\ |
|
&\mean\tpair ta &{}= \mean_{\WSam}(t) |
|
= \qint_{\List\I} |
|
\qdelta_{\valuate{t}(p)} \mean_{\ir}(a)(\dif p) |
|
|
|
\\ |
|
&\stmap \tfm &{}= \id\times \tfm_{\List\I} |
|
\\ |
|
&\ssample &{}= \tpair{\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}} |
|
\sample_{\WSam}} |
|
{\\\expdomon\ir{r \<- \ssample; \sreturn \lst r}} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\\ |
|
&\sscore r &{}=\tpair{\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}} |
|
\sscore_{\WSam}} |
|
{\\\expdomon\ir{\sscore r; \sreturn \lst-}} |
|
\end{array} |
|
} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{The tracing inference}\figlabel{tracing rep} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
~ |
|
\begin{minipage}[b]{.5\linewidth} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}} |
|
\mh[\psi, \rho]^{\Trace T} : \Trace T\, X \to \Trace T\, X |
|
\\ |
|
\mh[\psi, \rho]^{\Trace T}\pair ta \definedby |
|
\pair t{\mh[\psi_t, \rho_t](a)} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{Trace MH update-step}\figlabel{trace mh} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}} |
|
\iprior_{\ir} : \WSam X \to \uir(\List(\I)) \\ |
|
\iprior_{\ir}(t) \definedby \fold \\\pfun{ |
|
&\Inj{Return}\tpair rx &\To \return_{\ir} \lst- \\ |
|
\vor & \Inj{Sample}k &\To\expdomon\ir{\\&&r \<- \sample_{\ir};\\ |
|
&&k(r)}} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\subcaption{Prior representation}\figlabel{prior} |
|
\end{minipage} |
|
\caption{Building blocks of Trace MH} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
\figref{tracing rep} presents the inference representation structure |
|
of $\Trace \ir$. Most of the proof revolves around preseving the |
|
invariant, i.e., that these definitions define set-theoretic |
|
functions. |
|
|
|
The inference transformation |
|
$\marginal_{\ir} : \Trace \ir X \to \ir X$ \emph{marginalises} the |
|
trace transformer once it is no longer useful. It first samples a path |
|
and then uses it to run the program discarding the weight: |
|
\( \marginal \ \tpair ta = \domon{ x \<- a; \sreturn \ \valuate{t} (x) |
|
} \). Its correctness is precisely the invariant. |
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Inference with MHG} |
|
The transition from $\ir$ to $\Trace \ir$ still requires a proposal |
|
kernel and a representation of the appropriate derivative, but these |
|
can now be given in terms of concrete traces. |
|
|
|
Given an inference representation $\ir$, a \emph{trace proposal |
|
kernel} is a transformation representing a kernel |
|
\( \psi : \parent{\sum_{t \in \WSam X} \paths t} \to T(\List \I) \). |
|
A \emph{trace derivative} is a transformation representing the |
|
derivative |
|
\( \rho : \parent{\sum_{t \in \WSam X} \paths t \times \paths t} \to |
|
\ereals+ \). Given a trace proposal kernel $\psi$ and a trace |
|
derivative $\rho$, \figref{trace mh} presents the trace MHG update |
|
transformation using the corresponding MHG update on $T(\List\I)$. |
|
|
|
The Trace MH update step requires some assumptions to form an |
|
inference transformation: |
|
\begin{theorem}[Trace Metropolis-Hastings-Green]\theoremlabel{Correctness of Trace MH} |
|
Let $T$ be an inference representation, $\psi$ a trace proposal |
|
kernel, and $\rho$ a trace derivative. Assume that, for every |
|
$\pair ta \in \Trace T\, X$, letting |
|
$k \definedby m^T\compose \psi_t$ and |
|
$\qmu \definedby [\rho_t\neq 0] \odot (m^T(a)\bprod k)$: |
|
\begin{enumerate*} |
|
\item $k$ is Markov; |
|
\item $[1 = \rho_t\cdot (\rho_t\compose \braid[])]$ holds |
|
$\qmu$-a.e.; |
|
\item $\rho_t$ is a Radon-Nikodym derivative |
|
of $\braid[]_*\qmu$ |
|
with respect to $\qmu$; and |
|
\item $\rho_t(p,q)=0 \iff \rho_t(q,p) = 0$ for all $p,q \in \List(\I)$. |
|
\end{enumerate*} |
|
Then $\mh[\psi, \rho]^{\Trace T} : \Trace T \to \Trace T$ is a valid |
|
inference transformation. |
|
\end{theorem} |
|
|
|
We will now demonstrate such a simple and generic trace proposal kernel |
|
and trace derivative that implement a MHG update step of a popular |
|
lightweight Metropolis-Hastings algorithm in several probabilistic |
|
programming language systems |
|
\cite{goodman_uai_2008, HurNRS15, wood-aistats-2014, Goodman2014}. |
|
|
|
For any inference representation $\ir$, \figref{prior} defines the |
|
morphism $\iprior_{\ir}$ that maps a representation $t \in \WSam X$ to |
|
its prior distribution on paths over $t$. Let |
|
$\UD(n) \in \Mea(\naturals)$ be the measure for the uniform discrete |
|
distribution with support $\{0,1,\ldots,n\}$. Intuitively, it assigns |
|
a probability $\frac{1}{n+1}$ to every element in the support. It be |
|
easily defined from $\sample_{\Mea}$, which denotes the uniform |
|
distribution on $\I$, as in \lemmaref{randomisation}. |
|
|
|
We now define our concrete proposal $\psi_t$ and derivative, a.k.a.~ratio, $\rho_t$: |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}} |
|
\psi_t : \List(\I) \to T(\List(\I)) \\ |
|
\psi_t(p) \definedby |
|
\expdomon\ir{\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{}} |
|
i\<- \UD^{\ir}(|p|) |
|
\\ |
|
q\<-\iprior^T(\isubterm(t,\itake(i,p))) |
|
\\ |
|
\sreturn(\itake(i,p)+ q)} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\mspace{150mu} |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{}} |
|
\rho_t : \List(\I) \times \List(\I) \to \ereals+ \\ |
|
\rho_t(p,q) \definedby \frac{\weight{t}(q) \cdot (|p|+1)}{\weight{t}(p) \cdot (|q|+1)} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
where $\isubterm(t, x)$ selects a subterm of a given term by following |
|
the list $x$ and $\itake(i, p)$ retrieves the $i$-th prefix of |
|
$p$. This proposal and derivative/ratio satisfy the condition in the Trace MH. |
|
|
|
Our approach lets us combine MH updates with other inference building |
|
block. For example, recall the SMC algorithm from Section |
|
\ref{sec:sus}. Each time it performs resampling, multiple particles |
|
are given the same values, which results in inadequate coverage of the |
|
space, a phenomenon known as \emph{degeneracy}. One way to ameliorate |
|
this problem is to apply multiple MH transitions to each particle |
|
after resampling in order to spread them across the space, resulting |
|
in an algorithm known as resample-move SMC |
|
\cite{doucet-johansen:smc-tutorial11}. |
|
|
|
The implemnetation of resample-move SMC is very similar to that of SMC from |
|
Section \ref{sec:sus}, except we introduce an additional layer $\Trace$ between |
|
$\Sus$ and $\Pop$: |
|
\begin{theorem} |
|
Let $\ir$ be a sampling representation. For every pair of natural |
|
numbers $n$, $k$, $\ell$ the following composite forms an inference trasnformation: |
|
\begin{multline*} |
|
\rmsmc^{\ir}_{n,k,\ell}\definedby |
|
(\Sus\compose \Trace\compose \Pop) \ir |
|
\xto{\stmap_{\Sus}\stmap_{\Trace}\spawn\tpair n-} |
|
(\Sus\compose \Trace\compose \Pop) \ir \\ |
|
\xto{(\adva \compose \ \stmap_{\Sus}\mh[]^{\compose \ell} \ \compose \stmap_{\Sus}\stmap_{\Trace}\resample(n,-))^{\compose k}} |
|
(\Sus\compose \Trace\compose \Pop) \ir |
|
\xto{\marginal \compose \finish} |
|
\Pop \ir |
|
\end{multline*} |
|
\end{theorem} |
|
In the above we apply $\ell$ MH transitions after each resampling. |
|
Our compositional correctness criterion corresponds |
|
to a known result that resample-move SMC is an unbiased importance sampler. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\section{Related work and concluding remarks}\seclabel{conclusion} |
|
The idea of developing a programming language for machine learning and |
|
statistics is old, and was explored at least in the early |
|
2000s~\cite{BUGS,Ramsey-popl02,Park-popl05} as an interesting yet |
|
niche research topic. In the past five years, however, designing such |
|
a language and building its runtime system has become an active |
|
research area, and lead to practical programming languages and |
|
libraries~\cite{Stan,wood-aistats-2014,Goodman2014,Mansinghka-venture14,goodman_uai_2008,InferNet,Hakaru,Tran2017,Tabular,Murray2013} |
|
. Most of these research efforts have focussed on developing efficient |
|
inference algorithms and |
|
implementations~\cite{Wingate2013,Le2017,Tran2017,Kucukelbir2015}. |
|
Only a smaller amount of work has been dedicated to justifying the |
|
algorithms or other runtime systems of those |
|
languages~\cite{HurNRS15,BorgstromLGS-corr15}. Our work contributes to |
|
this less-explored line of research by providing novel denotational |
|
techniques and tools for specifying and verifying key components of |
|
inference algorithms, in particular, those for expressive higher-order |
|
probabilistic programming languages. Such specifications can then be |
|
combined to construct the correctness argument of a complex |
|
inference algorithm, as we have shown in the paper. |
|
|
|
The idea of constructing inference algorithms by composing |
|
transformations of an intermediate representations is, to the best of |
|
our knowledge, relatively recent. In previous work with |
|
Gordon~\cite{Scibior2015}, we manipulated a free monad representation |
|
to obtain an implementation of SMC. However, we did not implement MH, |
|
did not break down SMC further into resampling and suspension, and our |
|
semantics was not compositional. \citet{Zinkov2016} directly |
|
manipulate syntax trees of a small language Hakaru. Their semantics is |
|
only first-order and they focus on local program transformations |
|
corresponding to solving integrals analytically, which is orthogonal |
|
to our global transformations relating to sampling algorithms. |
|
|
|
Our approach does not yet deal with two important aspects of |
|
inference. In practice, one wants \emph{convergence} guarantees for |
|
the inference algorithm, estimating the results within an error margin |
|
after a given number of inference steps. As any purely-measure |
|
theoretic approach, ours does not express such properties. Additionally, |
|
we can not express algorithms that rely on derivatives of the density function |
|
for the program traces, such as Hamiltonian Monte Carlo or |
|
\emph{variational} inference. Developing a theory of differentiation over |
|
quasi-Borel spaces might enable us to express such algorithms. |
|
|
|
Another interesting direction for future work |
|
is to develop a denotational account of some probabilistic programming |
|
languages that allow users to select or compose parts of inference |
|
algorithms~\cite{Mansinghka-venture14,Tran2017}. The exposure of an |
|
inference algorithm in such languages breaks the usual abstraction of |
|
probabilistic programs as distributions, and causes difficulties of |
|
applying existing semantic techniques to such programs. Our more |
|
intensional semantics may be able to overcome these difficulties. |
|
Finally, it would be interesting to consider indexed or effect-annotated |
|
versions of inference representations, transformations and |
|
transformers, where indices or annotations ensure that inference |
|
components are applied to a certain type of programs. Such a refined |
|
version of our results may lead to a way of selectively applying |
|
Hamiltonian Monte Carlo or other algorithms that assume the presence |
|
of differentiable densities and a fixed length of all paths through the program. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\bibliography{references} |
|
|
|
|
|
\appendix |
|
\pagebreak |
|
\section{A Toolbox for Synthetic Measure Theory} |
|
\seclabel{kock-equations} |
|
In this section, we list some equations that allow us to work in synthetic measure theory much as if we would in classical measure theory. In fact, the validity of these equations lets us port many classical measure theory proofs to our setting. Figure \ref{fig:kock properties} lists some basic equations that hold in synthetic measure theory. |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}*3{l@{}}} |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, a : Y^X &{}\tinf \qint_X \qdelta_{a(x)}\qmu(\dif x) &{}= a_*\qmu |
|
\\ |
|
x_0 : X, f : (\Mea\!Y)^X &{}\tinf \qint_X f(x)\qdelta_{x_0}(\dif x)&{}= f(x_0) |
|
\\ |
|
x_0 : X, f : \carrier\alg^X&{}\tinf |
|
\Exp_{x \sampled \qdelta_{x_0}}[f(x)]&{}= f(x_0) |
|
\\ |
|
r : \Mea \terminal, \qmu : \Mea X |
|
&{}\tinf |
|
\qint_{\terminal} \qmu\, r(\dif \xi)&{}= r\odot \qmu |
|
\end{array} |
|
\mspace{120mu} |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}*3{l@{}}} |
|
f : Y^X &{}\tinf f_*\qdelta_x = \qdelta_{f(x)} |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X &{}\tinf \qint_X \qdelta_x\qmu(\dif x) = \qmu |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X &{}\tinf \qmu(X)=\qint_X 1\qmu(\dif x) |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}*3{l@{}}} |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, a : Y^X, f : (\Mea Z)^Y &{}\tinf \qint_X (f\compose a)(x)\qmu(\dif x) &{}= \qint_Y f(y)(a_*\qmu)(\dif y) |
|
\\ |
|
x_0 : X, w : R^X, f : (TY)^X &{}\tinf |
|
\qint_Xf(x)(w\odot |
|
\qdelta_{x_0})(\dif x) &{}= w(x_0)\odot f(x_0) |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, w : R^X, f : (TY)^X &{}\tinf |
|
\qint_Xf(x)(w\odot \qmu)(\dif x) &{}= \qint_X w(x) \odot f(x)\qmu(\dif x) |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, f : (\Mea Y)^X |
|
&{}\tinf |
|
\Exp_{x \sampled \qmu}^{\pair{KY}{\bind}}[f(x)] &{}= \qint_X f(x)\qmu(\dif x) |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, a : Y^X, f : \carrier\alg^Y |
|
&{}\tinf |
|
\Exp_{y \sampled a_*\qmu}[f(y)] &{}= \Exp_{x \sampled |
|
\qmu}[(f\compose a)(x)] |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
|
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}*3{l@{}}} |
|
\qmu : \Mea (X_1\times X_2), f : (\Mea Y)^{X_i} |
|
&{}\tinf |
|
\qiint_{X_1\times X_2}f(x)\qmu(\dif x,\dif y) |
|
&{}= |
|
\qint_{X}f(x)((\projection_i)_*\qmu)(\dif x) |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, f : (\Mea Y)^X, g : (\Mea Z)^Y |
|
&{}\tinf |
|
\qint_X\qmu(\dif x)\qint_Y g(y)f(x)(\dif y) |
|
&{}= |
|
\qint_Y g(y)\left(\qint_X f(x)\qmu(\dif x)\right)(\dif y) |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, |
|
\qmu[2] : \Mea Y, |
|
g : (\Mea Z)^Y |
|
&{}\tinf |
|
\qint_{Y}(\qmu\tensor g(y))\qmu[2](\dif y) |
|
&{}= |
|
\qmu \tensor |
|
\qint_{Y}g(y)\qmu[2](\dif y) |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
|
|
|
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}[t]{@{}l@{}l@{}r@{}l@{}} |
|
\multicolumn{4}{@{}l@{}}{ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}l@{\quad}c@{\quad}c@{}} |
|
\fbox{$\ctx \definedby \qmu_1 : X_1, \qmu_2 : X_2$},{i=1,2:} |
|
&\ctx {}\tinf |
|
(\projection_i)_*(\qmu_1\tensor\qmu_2) {}= \qmu_{3-i}(X_{3-i})\odot \qmu_i |
|
& |
|
\qint_X \qmu_1\ \qmu_2(\dif x) = \qmu_2(X_2) \odot \qmu_1 |
|
\end{array} |
|
}\\[1ex] |
|
\ctx, f : (\Mea Y)^{X_i} {}&{}\tinf{}& |
|
\qiint_{X_1\times X_2}f(x_i)(\qmu_1\tensor\qmu_2)(\dif x_1,\dif x_2) &{}= {\qmu_{3-i}(X_{3-i})\odot\qint_{X_i}f(x_i)\qmu_i(\dif x_i)} |
|
\\ |
|
\ctx, f^1 : Y_1^{X_1}, f^2 : Y_2^{X_2} |
|
&{}\tinf{}& |
|
(f^1\times f^2)_*(\qmu_1\tensor\qmu_2) &{}= (f^1_*\qmu_1)\tensor(f^2_*\qmu_2) |
|
\\ |
|
\multicolumn{4}{@{}c@{}}{ |
|
\qint_{X_1\times X_2} \parent{f^1(x_1)\tensor f^2(x_2)} (\qmu_1\!\tensor\qmu_2)(\dif x_1,\dif x_2) |
|
= |
|
\parent{\qint_{X_1} f^1(x_1) \qmu_1(\dif x_1)}\tensor |
|
\parent{\qint_{X_2} f^2(x_2) \qmu_2(\dif x_2)}} |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\caption{Toolbox for synthetic measure theory} |
|
\figlabel{kock properties} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
Additionally, we have the following theorem which makes precise the statement that integration and expectation act as $R$-module homomorphisms. |
|
|
|
\begin{theorem}[$\sigma$-linearity]\theoremlabel{sigma linearity} |
|
For all objects $X$, $Y$ in a measure category |
|
$\pair \cat{\monad\Mea}$ and $\monad\Mea$-algebras $\alg$: |
|
\[ |
|
\begin{array}{@{}*4{>{\displaystyle}l@{}}} |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, r_{-} : R^{\naturals}, f_{-} : (\Mea Y)^{\naturals \times X} |
|
&{}\tinf{}& |
|
\qint_X\qmu(\dif x)\sum_{n \in \naturals}r_n\odot f_n(x) |
|
&{}= |
|
\sum_{n \in \naturals}r_n\odot \qint_X\qmu(\dif x)f_n(x) |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu_- : (\Mea X)^{\naturals}, r_- : R^{\naturals}, f : (\Mea Y)^X |
|
&{}\tinf&{} |
|
\qint_X\parent{\sum_{n \in \naturals} r_n\odot\qmu_n}(\dif x)f(x) |
|
&{}= |
|
\sum_{n \in \naturals} r_n\odot \qint_X\qmu_n(\dif x)f(x) |
|
\\ |
|
\qmu : \Mea X, r_{-} : R^{\naturals}, f_{-} : \carrier\alg^{\naturals \times X} |
|
&{}\tinf{}& |
|
\Exp[\alg]_{x \sampled \qmu}\bracks{\sum_{n \in \naturals}r_n\odot f_n(x)} |
|
&{}= |
|
\sum_{n \in \naturals}r_n\odot \Exp[\alg]_{x\sampled \qmu}\,[f_n(x)] |
|
\\\qmu_- : (\Mea X)^{\naturals}, r_- : R^{\naturals}, f : \carrier\alg^X |
|
&{}\tinf&{} |
|
\Exp[\alg]_{x \sampled \sum_{n \in \naturals}r_n\odot \qmu_n}[f(x)] |
|
&{}= |
|
\sum_{n \in \naturals}r_n\odot \Exp[\alg]_{x \sampled \qmu_n}[f(x)] |
|
\end{array} |
|
\] |
|
\end{theorem} |
|
|
|
\end{document} |
|
|