diff --git "a/resources/philosophy/Chalmers_The_Conscious_Mind.txt" "b/resources/philosophy/Chalmers_The_Conscious_Mind.txt" new file mode 100644--- /dev/null +++ "b/resources/philosophy/Chalmers_The_Conscious_Mind.txt" @@ -0,0 +1,18134 @@ + THE + +Conscious +Mind + + PHILOSOPHY OF M I N D SERIES +Series Editor: Owen Flanagan, Duke University +SELF EXPRESSIONS +Mind, Morals, and the Meaning of Life +Owen Flanagan +DECONSTRUCTING THE MIND +Stephen P. Stich +THE CONSCIOUS MIND +In Search of a Fundamental Theory +David J. Chalmers + + THE + +conscious +Mind +IN SEARCH OF +A FUNDAMENTAL THEORY + +David J. Chalmers + +OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS +New York +Oxford + + Oxford University Press +Oxford New York +Athens Auckland Bangkok Bogota +Bombay Buenos Aires Calcutta Cape Town +Dar es Salaam Delhi Florence Hong Kong Istanbul +Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madras Madrid Melbourne +Mexico City Nairobi Paris Singapore +Taipei Tokyo Toronto Warsaw +and associated companies in +Berlin Ibadan + +Copyright © 1996 by David J. Chalmers +First published by Oxford University Press, Inc., 1996 +First issued as an Oxford University Press paperback, 1997 +Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press +All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, +stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, +electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, +without the prior permission of Oxford University Press. +Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data +Chalmers, David John +The conscious mind : in search of a fundamental theory +p. cm. (Philosophy of mind series) +Includes bibliographical references and index. +ISBN 0-19-510553-2 +ISBN 0-19-511789-1 (Pbk.) +1. Philosophy of mind. 2. Consciousness. 3. Mind and body. +4. Dualism. I. Title. II. Series. +BD418.3.C43 1996 +128'.2—dc20 95-36036 + +9 10 +Printed in the United States of America +on acid-free paper. + + Acknowledgments + +I + +first became excited by consciousness and the mind-body problem as +an undergraduate studying mathematics at the University of Adelaide. +Conversations with a number of people, especially Paul Barter, Jon Baxter, Ben Hambly, and Paul McCann, helped form my ideas. Even then, the +subject seemed about as fascinating a problem as there could be. It seemed +faintly unreasonable that somebody could be occupied full-time thinking +about something that was so much fun. +Later, as a graduate student at Oxford, I found that the mind was always +occupying my thoughts where mathematics should have been, and I decided +to switch fields and eventually to switch continents. Many people were patient and supportive during this difficult time, especially Michael Atiyah, +Michael Dummett, and Robin Fletcher. Thanks also to all those who were +subjected to hearing about whatever my latest theory of consciousness happened to be; the ideas in this book are a distant descendant. +My decision to move to Indiana University to gain a grounding in philosophy, cognitive science, and artificial intelligence was one of the best that I +have made. I owe special thanks to Doug Hofstadter; it was his writing that +first introduced me to the mysteries of the mind when I was young, and it +was the stimulating and comfortable environment of his research lab, the +Center for Research on Concepts and Cognition, that allowed these ideas +to develop. Although he disagrees with many of the ideas in this book, I +would like to think that at some level what I have written remains true to +the intellectual spirit of his work. +I wrote the first version of this work (then known as Toward a Theory of +Consciousness) in a heady six-month period in 1992 and 1993.1 had useful +discussions with a number of people at Indiana around this time: everybody +at CRCC, especially Bob French and Liane Gabora, and many in other +departments, including Mike Dunn, Rob Goldstone, Anil Gupta, Jim Hettmer, Jerry Seligman, and Tim van Gelder. Thanks also to members of the +consciousness discussion group in the back room at Nick's for many enjoyable +Monday afternoon conversations. +A two-year McDonnell fellowship in philosophy, neuroscience, and psychology at Washington University has provided another stimulating environment, as well as a chance to experience Zeno's paradox in finishing this + + vi + +Acknowledgments + +book. I am grateful to the James S. McDonnell Foundation for their support, +to all the participants in my graduate seminar on consciousness for discussions that helped to refine the book, and to a number of people for conversation and comments, including Morten Christiansen, Andy Clark, Jason Clevenger, Peggy DesAutels, Pepa Toribio, and Tad Zawidzki. +In the last couple of years, I have had an enormous amount of helpful +conversation and correspondence about the material in this book. Among +many others, thanks are due to Jon Baxter, Ned Block, Alex Byrne, Francis +Crick, Dan Dennett, Eric Dietrich, Avi Elitzur, Matthew Elton, Owen Flanagan, Stan Franklin, Liane Gabora, Guven Giizeldere, Chris Hill, Terry +Horgan, Steve Horst, Frank Jackson, Jaegwon Kim, Christof Koch, Martin +Leckey, Dave Leising, Kerry Levenberg, Joe Levine, David Lewis, Barry +Loewer, Bill Lycan, Paul McCann, Daryl McCullough, Brian McLaughlin, Thomas Metzinger, Robert Miller, Andrew Milne, John O'LearyHawthorne, Joseph O'Rourke, Calvin Ostrum, Rhett Savage, Aaron Sloman, +Leopold Stubenberg, and Red Watson. I am grateful to too many others to +mention for interesting conversations about consciousness in general. A +special note of thanks to Norton Nelkin, who returned his copy of the +manuscript covered with many helpful comments not long before he died +of lymphoma. He will be missed. +My broader philosophical debts are many. I developed my initial views +on consciousness largely on my own, but these have been greatly enriched +by my reading on the subject. One discovers quickly that any given idea has +likely been expressed already by someone else. Among recent thinkers, +Thomas Nagel, Frank Jackson, and Joseph Levine have done much to emphasize the perplexities of consciousness; their work covers much of the same +territory as my early chapters. My work also overlaps with work by Ned +Block, Robert Kirk, and Michael Lockwood at a number of points. The +metaphysical framework that I develop in Chapter 2 owes much to the work +of Terry Horgan, Saul Kripke, and David Lewis, among others, and Frank +Jackson has independently developed a similar framework, presented in +his marvelous 1995 John Locke lectures. The ideas of Daniel Dennett, +Colin McGinn, John Searle, and Sydney Shoemaker have provided stimulating challenges throughout. +My greatest debts are to Gregg Rosenberg, for memorable conversations +and valuable feedback; to Lisa Thomas, for a book on zombies and moral +support; to Sharon Wahl, for expert editing and warm friendship; and above +all, to all three of my parents, for their support and encouragement. And +thanks to all my qualia, and to the environment responsible for producing +them, for constant inspiration. +As I was finishing this book, I received a fortune cookie in a restaurant, +saying "Your life will be full of delightful mysteries." So far it has been, +and I am very grateful. + + Contents + +Introduction: Taking Consciousness Seriously xi + +I +1 + +FOUNDATIONS + +Two Concepts of Mind 3 +1. What is consciousness? + +3 + +2. The phenomenal and the psychological concepts of mind 11 +3. The double life of mental terms 16 +4. The two mind-body problems 24 +2 + +5. Two concepts of consciousness + +25 + +Supervenience and Explanation + +32 + +1. Supervenience 32 +2. Reductive explanation 42 +3. Logical Supervenience and reductive explanation 47 +4. Conceptual truth and necessary truth* 52 +5. Almost everything is logically supervenient on the physical* 71 + +II +3 + +THE IRREDUCIBILITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS + +Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +93 + +1. Is consciousness logically supervenient on the physical? 93 +2. The failure of reductive explanation 106 +3. Cognitive modeling 111 +4. Neurobiological explanation 115 +5. The appeal to new physics 118 +6. Evolutionary explanation 120 +7. Whither reductive explanation? 121 + + viii + +Contents + +4 + +Naturalistic Dualism 123 +1. An argument against materialism 123 +2. Objections from a posteriori necessity* 131 +3. Other arguments for dualism* 140 +4. Is this epiphenomenalism?* 150 +5. The logical geography of the issues 161 +6. Reflections on naturalistic dualism 168 + +5 + +The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment 172 +1. Consciousness and cognition 172 +2. The paradox of phenomenal judgment 177 +3. On explaining phenomenal judgments 184 +4. Arguments against explanatory irrelevance 191 +5. The argument from self-knowledge* 192 +6. The argument from memory* 200 +7. The argument from reference* 201 +8. The content of phenomenal beliefs* 203 + +III + +TOWARD A THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS + +6 + +The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition 213 +1. Toward a nonreductive theory 213 +2. Principles of coherence 218 +3. More on the notion of awareness 225 +4. The explanatory role of coherence principles 233 +5. Coherence as a psychophysical law 242 + +7 + +Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia 247 +1. The principle of organizational invariance 247 +2. Absent qualia 251 +3. Fading qualia 253 +4. Inverted qualia 263 +5. Dancing qualia 266 +6. Nonreductive functionalism 274 + + Contents + +8 + +Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation 276 +1. Toward a fundamental theory 276 +2. Aspects of information 277 +3. Some supporting arguments 287 +4. Is experience ubiquitous? 293 +5. The metaphysics of information 301 +6. Open questions 308 + +IV +9 + +APPLICATIONS + +Strong Artificial Intelligence 309 +1. Machine consciousness 309 +2. On implementing a computation 315 +3. In defense of strong AI 320 +4. The Chinese room and other objections 322 +5. External objections 328 +6. Conclusion 331 + +10 The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics 333 +1. Two mysteries 333 +2. The framework of quantum mechanics 334 +3. Interpreting quantum mechanics 337 +4. The Everett interpretation 346 +5. Objections to the Everett interpretation 351 +6. Conclusion 356 +Notes 359 +Bibliography +Index 405 + +391 + +ix + + This page intentionally left blank + + Introduction + +Taking Consciousness Seriously + +C + +onsciousness is the biggest mystery. It may be the largest outstanding +obstacle in our quest for a scientific understanding of the universe. +The science of physics is not yet complete, but it is well understood; +the science of biology has removed many ancient mysteries surrounding the +nature of life. There are gaps in our understanding of these fields, but they +do not seem intractable. We have a sense of what a solution to these problems +might look like; we just need to get the details right. +Even in the science of the mind, much progress has been made. Recent +work in cognitive science and neuroscience is leading us to a better understanding of human behavior and of the processes that drive it. We do not +have many detailed theories of cognition, to be sure, but the details cannot +be too far off. +Consciousness, however, is as perplexing as it ever was. It still seems utterly mysterious that the causation of behavior should be accompanied by a +subjective inner life. We have good reason to believe that consciousness +arises from physical systems such as brains, but we have little idea how it +arises, or why it exists at all. How could a physical system such as a brain also +be an experiencerl Why should there be something it is like to be such a system? Present-day scientific theories hardly touch the really difficult questions +about consciousness. We do not just lack a detailed theory; we are entirely in +the dark about how consicousness fits into the natural order. +Many books and articles on consciousness have appeared in the past few +years, and one might think that we are making progress. But on a closer +look, most of this work leaves the hardest problems about consciousness untouched. Often, such work addresses what might be called the "easy" problems of consciousness: How does the brain process environmental stimula- + + xii + +Introduction + +tion? How does it integrate information? How do we produce reports on +internal states? These are important questions, but to answer them is not +to solve the hard problem: Why is all this processing accompanied by an +experienced inner life? Sometimes this question is ignored entirely; sometimes it is put off until another day; and sometimes it is simply declared +answered. But in each case, one is left with the feeling that the central +problem remains as puzzling as ever. +This puzzlement is not a cause for despair; rather, it makes the problem +of consciousness one of the most exciting intellectual challenges of our +time. Because consciousness is both so fundamental and so ill understood, +a solution to the problem may profoundly affect our conception of the +universe and of ourselves. +I am an optimist about consciousness: I think that we will eventually have +a theory of it, and in this book I look for one. But consciousness is not just +business as usual; if we are to make progress, the first thing we must do is +face up to the things that make the problem so difficult. Then we can move +forward toward a theory, without blinkers and with a good idea of the task +at hand. +In this book, I do not solve the problem of consciousness once and for all, but +I try to rein it in. I try to get clear about what the problems are, I argue that the +standard methods of neuroscience and cognitive science do not work in addressing them, and then I try to move forward. +In developing my account of consciousness, I have tried to obey a number +of constraints. The first and most important is to take consciousness seriously. +The easiest way to develop a "theory" of consciousness is to deny its existence, or to redefine the phenomenon in need of explanation as something +it is not. This usually leads to an elegant theory, but the problem does not +go away. Throughout this book, I have assumed that consciousness exists, +and that to redefine the problem as that of explaining how certain cognitive +or behavioral functions are performed is unacceptable. This is what I mean +by taking consciousness seriously. +Some say that consciousness is an "illusion," but I have little idea what +this could even mean. It seems to me that we are surer of the existence of conscious experience than we are of anything else in the world. I have tried +hard at times to convince myself that there is really nothing there, that +conscious experience is empty, an illusion. There is something seductive +about this notion, which philosophers throughout the ages have exploited, +but in the end it is utterly unsatisfying. I find myself absorbed in an orange +sensation, and something is going on. There is something that needs explaining, even after we have explained the processes of discrimination and +action: there is the experience. +True, I cannot prove that there is a further problem, precisely because I +cannot prove that consciousness exists. We know about consciousness more + + Taking Consciousness Seriously + +xiii + +directly than we know about anything else, so "proof is inappropriate. +The best I can do is provide arguments wherever possible, while rebutting +arguments from the other side. There is no denying that this involves an +appeal to intuition at some point; but all arguments involve intuition somewhere, and I have tried to be clear about the intuitions involved in mine. +This might be seen as a Great Divide in the study of consciousness. If you +hold that an answer to the "easy" problems explains everything that needs +to be explained, then you get one sort of theory; if you hold that there is a +further "hard" problem, then you get another. After a point, it is difficult +to argue across this divide, and discussions are often reduced to table pounding. To me, it seems obvious that there is something further that needs +explaining here; to others, it seems acceptable that there is not. (Informal +surveys suggest that the numbers run two or three to one in favor of the +former view, with the ratio fairly constant across academics and students in +a variety of fields.) We may simply have to learn to live with this basic division. +This book may be of intellectual interest to those who think there is not +much of a problem, but it is really intended for those who feel the problem +in their bones. By now, we have a fairly good idea of the sort of theory we +get if we assume there is no problem. In this work, I have tried to explore +what follows given that there is a problem. The real argument of the book +is that if one takes consciousness seriously, the position I lay out is where +one should end up. +The second constraint I have followed is to take science seriously. I have +not tried to dispute current scientific theories in domains where they have +authority. At the same time, I have not been afraid to go out on a limb in +areas where scientists' opinions are as ungrounded as everyone else's. For +example, I have not disputed that the physical world is causally closed or +that behavior can be explained in physical terms; but if a physicist or a +cognitive scientist suggests that consciousness can be explained in physical +terms, this is merely a hope ungrounded in current theory, and the question +remains open. So I have tried to keep my ideas compatible with contemporary +science, but I have not restricted my ideas to what contemporary scientists +find fashionable. +The third constraint is that I take consciousness to be a natural phenomenon, falling under the sway of natural laws. If so, then there should be some +correct scientific theory of consciousness, whether or not we can arrive at +such a theory. That consciousness is a natural phenomenon seems hard to +dispute: it is an extraordinarily salient part of nature, arising throughout the +human species and very likely in many others. And we have every reason +to believe that natural phenomena are subject to fundamental natural laws; +it would be very strange if consciousness were not. This is not to say that +the natural laws concerning consciousness will be just like laws in other +domains, or even that they will be physical laws. They may be quite different +in kind. + + xiv + +Introduction + +The problem of consciousness lies uneasily at the border of science and +philosophy. I would say that it is properly a scientific subject matter: it is +a natural phenomenon like motion, life, and cognition, and calls out for +explanation in the way that these do. But it is not open to investigation by +the usual scientific methods. Everyday scientific methodology has trouble +getting a grip on it, not least because of the difficulties in observing the +phenomenon. Outside the first-person case, data are hard to come by. This +is not to say that no external data can be relevant, but we first have to arrive +at a coherent philosophical understanding before we can justify the data's +relevance. So the problem of consciousness may be a scientific problem +that requires philosophical methods of understanding before we can get off +the ground. +In this book I reach conclusions that some people may think of as "antiscientific": I argue that reductive explanation of consciousness is impossible, +and I even argue for a form of dualism. But this is just part of the scientific +process. Certain sorts of explanation turn out not to work, so we need to +embrace other sorts of explanation instead. Everything I say here is compatible with the results of contemporary science; our picture of the natural world +is broadened, not overturned. And this broadening allows the possibility of +a naturalistic theory of consciousness that might have been impossible without it. It seems to me that to ignore the problems of consciousness would +be antiscientific; it is in the scientific spirit to face up to them directly. To +those who suspect that science requires materialism, I ask that you wait +and see. +I should note that the conclusions of this work are conclusions, in the +strongest sense. Temperamentally, I am strongly inclined toward materialist +reductive explanation, and I have no strong spiritual or religious inclinations. +For a number of years, I hoped for a materialist theory; when I gave up on +this hope, it was quite reluctantly. It eventually seemed plain to me that +these conclusions were forced on anyone who wants to take consciousness +seriously. Materialism is a beautiful and compelling view of the world, but +to account for consciousness, we have to go beyond the resources it provides. +By now, I have grown almost happy with these conclusions. They do not +seem to have any fearsome consequences, and they allow a way of thinking +and theorizing about consciousness that seems more satisfactory in almost +every way. And the expansion in the scientific worldview has had a positive +effect, at least for me: it has made the universe seem a more interesting place. +This book has four parts. In the first, I lay out the problems, and set up a +framework within which they can be addressed. Chapter 1 is an introduction +to consciousness, teasing apart a number of different concepts in the vicinity, +drawing out the sense in which consciousness is really interesting, and giving +a preliminary account of its subtle relation to the rest of the mind. Chapter + + Taking Consciousness Seriously + +xv + +2 develops a metaphysical and explanatory framework within which much +of the rest of the discussion is cast. What is it for a phenomenon to be +reductively explained, or to be physical? This chapter gives an account of +these things, centering on the notion of supervenience. I argue that there is +good reason to believe that almost everything in the world can be reductively +explained; but consciousness may be an exception. +With these preliminaries out of the way, the second part focuses on the +irreducibility of consciousness. Chapter 3 argues that standard methods of +reductive explanation cannot account for consciousness. I also give a critique +of various reductive accounts that have been put forward by researchers in +neuroscience, cognitive science, and elsewhere. This is not just a negative +conclusion: it follows that a satisfactory theory of consciousness must be a +new sort of nonreductive theory instead. Chapter 4 takes things a step further +by arguing that materialism is false and that a form of dualism is true, and +outlines the general shape that a nonreductive theory of consciousness might +take. Chapter 5 is largely defensive: it considers some apparent problems for +my view, involving the relationship between consciousness and OUT judgments +about consciousness, and argues that they pose no fatal difficulties. +In the third part, I move toward a positive theory of consciousness. Each +of the three chapters here develops a component of a positive theory. Chapter 6 focuses on the "coherence" between consciousness and cognitive processes, drawing a number of systematic links between the two. I use these +links to analyze and ground the central role that neuroscience and cognitive +science play in explaining human consciousness. Chapter 7 discusses the +relation between consciousness and functional organization, using thought +experiments to argue that consciousness is an "organizational invariant": +that is, that every system with the right functional organization will have the +same sort of conscious experience, no matter what it is made of. Chapter 8 +considers what a fundamental theory of consciousness might look like, and +suggests that it may involve a close relation between consciousness and +information. This is by far the most speculative chapter, but at this point +some speculation is probably needed if we are to make progress. +The last two chapters are dessert. Here, I apply what has gone before to +central questions in the foundations of artificial intelligence and quantum +mechanics. Chapter 9 argues for the thesis of "strong artificial intelligence": +that the implementation of an appropriate computer program will give rise +to a conscious mind. Chapter 10 considers the baffling question of how +quantum mechanics should be interpreted, and uses the ideas about consciousness developed in previous chapters to lend support to a "no-collapse" +interpretation of the theory. +Perhaps the negative material will provoke the most reaction, but my real +goal is positive: I want to see a theory of consciousness that works. When I +first came into philosophy, I was surprised to find that most of the debate + + xvi + +Introduction + +over consciousness focused on whether there was a problem or not, or on +whether it was physical or not, and that the business of building theories +seemed to be left to one side. The only "theories" seemed to be put forward +by those who (by my lights) did not take consciousness seriously. By now, +I have come to enjoy the intricacies of the ontological debate as much as +anyone, but a detailed theory is still my major goal. If some of the ideas in +this book are useful to others in constructing a better theory, the attempt +will have been worthwhile. +This book is intended as a serious work of philosophy, but I have tried +to make it accessible to nonphilosophers. In my notional audience at all +times has been my undergraduate self of ten years ago: I hope I have written +a book that he would have appreciated. There are a few sections that are +philosophically technical. These are marked with an asterisk (*), and readers +should feel free to skip them. The most technical material is in Chapter 2 +and Chapter 4. Section 4 of the former and sections 2 and 3 of the latter +involve intricate issues in philosophical semantics, as does the final section +of Chapter 5. Other asterisked sections might be worth at least skimming, +to get an idea of what is going on. Often, I have put especially technical +material and comments on the philosophical literature in the endnotes. The +one technical concept that is crucial to the book is that of supervenience, +introduced at the start of Chapter 2. This concept has an intimidating name +but it expresses a very natural idea, and a good understanding of it will help +central issues fall into place. Much of the material later in this chapter can +be skipped on a first reading, although one might want to return to it later +to clarify questions as they arise. +For a short tour that avoids technicalities, read Chapter 1, skim the early +parts of Chapter 2 as background material, then read all of Chapter 3 (skimming section 1 where necessary) for the central arguments against reductive +explanation, and the first and last sections of Chapter 4 for the central +considerations about dualism. The beginning of Chapter 6 is worth reading +for the basic shape of the positive approach. Of the positive material, Chapter +7 is perhaps the most self-contained chapter as well as the most fun, with +easy-to-understand thought experiments involving silicon brains; and those +who like wild and woolly speculation might enjoy Chapter 8. Finally, Chapters +9 and 10 should make sense to anyone with an interest in the issues involved. +A couple of philosophical notes. The philosophical literature on consciousness is quite unsystematic, with seemingly independent strands talking about +related issues without making contact with each other. I have attempted to +impose some structure on the sprawl by providing a unifying framework in +which the various metaphysical and explanatory issues become clear. Much +of the discussion in the literature can be translated into this framework + + Taking Consciousness Seriously + +xvii + +without loss, and I hope the structure brings out the deep relationships +between a number of different issues. +This work is perhaps unusual in largely eschewing the philosophical notion +of identity (between mental and physical states, say) in favor of the notion +of supervenience. I find that discussions framed in terms of identity generally +throw more confusion than light onto the key issues, and often allow the +central difficulties to be evaded. By contrast, supervenience seems to provide +an ideal framework within which the key issues can be addressed. To avoid +loose philosophy, however, we need to focus on the strength of the supervenience connection: Is it underwritten by logical necessity, natural necessity, +or something else? It is widely agreed that consciousness supervenes on the +physical in some sense; the real question is how tight the connection is. +Discussions that ignore these modal issues generally avoid the hardest questions about consciousness. Those skeptical of modal notions will be skeptical +of my entire discussion, but I think there is no other satisfactory way to +frame the issues. +One of the delights of working on this book, for me, has come from the way +the problem of consciousness has reached out to make contact with deep +issues in many other areas of science and philosophy. But the scope and +depth of the problem also make it humbling. I am acutely aware that at +almost every point in this book there is more that could be said, and that +in many places I have only scratched the surface. But I hope, minimally, +to have suggested that it is possible to make progress on the problem of +consciousness without denying its existence or reducing it to something it is +not. The problem is fascinating, and the future is exciting. + + No. Xia stopped, twirling toward him in slow motion. Her icy mint +eyes grew wide. You're in danger here. Panic whitened her face as +she stared toward the house. Go home now. Before it's too late. And +find me the antidote. +What kind of antidote? +Xia disappeared beyond the junipers, yet her final message burst +into Joey's mind like the pop of a firecracker: The antidote for +zombie poison. +Dian Curtis Regan, My Zombie Valentine + + PART I +Foundations + + This page intentionally left blank + + 1 +Two Concepts of Mind + +1. What Is Consciousness? +Conscious experience is at once the most familiar thing in the world and +the most mysterious. There is nothing we know about more directly than +consciousness, but it is far from clear how to reconcile it with everything +else we know. Why does it exist? What does it do? How could it possibly +arise from lumpy gray matter? We know consciousness far more intimately +than we know the rest of the world, but we understand the rest of the world +far better than we understand consciousness. +Consciousness can be startlingly intense. It is the most vivid of phenomena; +nothing is more real to us. But it can be frustratingly diaphanous: in talking +about conscious experience, it is notoriously difficult to pin down the subject +matter. The International Dictionary of Psychology does not even try to give +a straightforward characterization: +Consciousness: The having of perceptions, thoughts, and feelings; awareness. +The term is impossible to define except in terms that are unintelligible without +a grasp of what consciousness means. Many fall into the trap of confusing +consciousness with self-consciousness—to be conscious it is only necessary to +be aware of the external world. Consciousness is a fascinating but elusive phenomenon: it is impossible to specify what it is, what it does, or why it evolved. +Nothing worth reading has been written about it. (Sutherland 1989) + +Almost anyone who has thought hard about consciousness will have some +sympathy with these sentiments. Consciousness is so intangible that even +this limited attempt at a definition could be disputed: there can arguably be +perception and thought that is not conscious, as witnessed by the notions of +subliminal perception and unconscious thought. What is central to conscious- + + 4 + +Foundations + +ness, at least in the most interesting sense, is experience. But this is not +definition. At best, it is clarification. +Trying to define conscious experience in terms of more primitive notions +is fruitless. One might as well try to define matter or space in terms of something more fundamental. The best we can do is to give illustrations and characterizations that lie at the same level. These characterizations cannot qualify +as true definitions, due to their implicitly circular nature, but they can help +to pin down what is being talked about. I presume that every reader has +conscious experiences of his or her own. If all goes well, these characterizations will help establish that it is just those that we are talking about. +The subject matter is perhaps best characterized as "the subjective quality +of experience." When we perceive, think, and act, there is a whir of causation +and information processing, but this processing does not usually go on in +the dark. There is also an internal aspect; there is something it feels like to +be a cognitive agent. This internal aspect is conscious experience. Conscious +experiences range from vivid color sensations to experiences of the faintest +background aromas; from hard-edged pains to the elusive experience of +thoughts on the tip of one's tongue; from mundane sounds and smells to +the encompassing grandeur of musical experience; from the triviality of a +nagging itch to the weight of a deep existential angst; from the specificity of +the taste of peppermint to the generality of one's experience of selfhood. +All these have a distinct experienced quality. All are prominent parts of the +inner life of the mind. +We can say that a being is conscious if there is something it is like to be +that being, to use a phrase made famous by Thomas Nagel.1 Similarly, a mental state is conscious if there is something it is like to be in that mental state. +To put it another way, we can say that a mental state is conscious if it has +a qualitative feel—an associated quality of experience. These qualitative feels +are also known as phenomenal qualities, or qualia for short.2 The problem +of explaining these phenomenal qualities is just the problem of explaining +consciousness. This is the really hard part of the mind-body problem. +Why should there be conscious experience at all? It is central to a subjective viewpoint, but from an objective viewpoint it is utterly unexpected. +Taking the objective view, we can tell a story about how fields, waves, and +particles in the spatiotemporal manifold interact in subtle ways, leading to +the development of complex systems such as brains. In principle, there is +no deep philosophical mystery in the fact that these systems can process +information in complex ways, react to stimuli with sophisticated behavior, +and even exhibit such complex capacities as learning, memory, and language. +All this is impressive, but it is not metaphysically baffling. In contrast, the +existence of conscious experience seems to be a new feature from this viewpoint. It is not something that one would have predicted from the other +features alone. + + Two Concepts of Mind + +5 + +That is, consciousness is surprising. If all we knew about were the facts +of physics, and even the facts about dynamics and information processing +in complex systems, there would be no compelling reason to postulate the +existence of conscious experience. If it were not for our direct evidence in the +first-person case, the hypothesis would seem unwarranted; almost mystical, +perhaps. Yet we know, directly, that there is conscious experience .The question is, how do we reconcile it with everything else we know? +Conscious experience is part of the natural world, and like other natural +phenomena it cries out for explanation. There are at least two major targets +of explanation here. The first and most central is the very existence of consciousness. Why does conscious experience exist? If it arises from physical +systems, as seems likely, how does it arise? This leads to some more specific +questions. Is consciousness itself physical, or is it merely a concomitant of +physical systems? How widespread is consciousness? Do mice, for example, +have conscious experience? +A second target is the specific character of conscious experiences. Given +that conscious experience exists, why do individual experiences have their +particular nature? When I open my eyes and look around my office, why +do I have this sort of complex experience? At a more basic level, why is +seeing red like this, rather than like that? It seems conceivable that when +looking at red things, such as roses, one might have had the sort of color experiences that one in fact has when looking at blue things. Why is the experience one way rather than the other? Why, for that matter, do we experience +the reddish sensation3 that we do, rather than some entirely different kind +of sensation, like the sound of a trumpet? +When someone strikes middle C on the piano, a complex chain of events +is set into place. Sound vibrates in the air and a wave travels to my ear. The +wave is processed and analyzed into frequencies inside the ear, and a signal +is sent to the auditory cortex. Further processing takes place here: isolation +of certain aspects of the signal, categorization, and ultimately reaction. All +this is not so hard to understand in principle. But why should this be accompanied by an experience? And why, in particular, should it be accompanied by +that experience, with its characteristic rich tone and timbre? These are two +central questions that we would like a theory of consciousness to answer. +Ultimately one would like a theory of consciousness to do at least the following: it should give the conditions under which physical processes give +rise to consciousness, and for those processes that give rise to consciousness, +it should specify just what sort of experience is associated. And we would +like the theory to explain how it arises, so that the emergence of consciousness +seems intelligible rather than magical. In the end, we would like the theory +to enable us to see consciousness as an integral part of the natural world. +Currently it may be hard to see what such a theory would be like, but without +such a theory we could not be said to fully understand consciousness. + + 6 + +Foundations + +Before proceeding, a note on terminology. The term "consciousness" is +ambiguous, referring to a number of phenomena. Sometimes it is used to +refer to a cognitive capacity, such as the ability to introspect or to report +one's mental states. Sometimes it is used synonymously with "awakeness." +Sometimes it is closely tied to our ability to focus attention, or to voluntarily +control our behavior. Sometimes "to be conscious of something" comes to +the same thing as "to know about something." All of these are accepted +uses of the term, but all pick out phenomena distinct from the subject I am +discussing, and phenomena that are significantly less difficult to explain. I +will say more about these alternative notions of consciousness later, but for +now, when I talk about consciousness, I am talking only about the subjective +quality of experience: what it is like to be a cognitive agent. +A number of alternative terms and phrases pick out approximately the +same class of phenomena as "consciousness" in its central sense. These include "experience," "qualia," "phenomenology," "phenomenal," "subjective experience," and "what it is like." Apart from grammatical differences, +the differences among these terms are mostly subtle matters of connotation. +"To be conscious" in this sense is roughly synonymous with "to have qualia," +"to have subjective experience," and so on. Any differences in the class +of phenomena picked out are insignificant. Like "consciousness," many of +these terms are somewhat ambiguous, but I will never use these terms in +the alternative senses. I will use all these phrases in talking about the central +phenomenon of this book, but "consciousness" and "experience" are the +most straightforward terms, and it is these terms that will recur. + +A catalog of conscious experiences +Conscious experience can be fascinating to attend to. Experience comes in +an enormous number of varieties, each with its own character. A far-fromcomplete catalog of the aspects of conscious experience is given in the +following pretheoretical, impressionistic list. Nothing here should be taken +too seriously as philosophy, but it should help focus attention on the subject +matter at hand. +Visual experiences. Among the many varieties of visual experience, color +sensations stand out as the paradigm examples of conscious experience, due +to their pure, seemingly ineffable qualitative nature. Some color experiences +can seem particularly striking, and so can be particularly good at focusing +our attention on the mystery of consciousness. In my environment now, +there is a particularly rich shade of deep purple from a book on my shelf; +an almost surreal shade of green in a photograph of ferns on my wall; and +a sparkling array of bright red, green, orange, and blue lights on a Christmas + + Two Concepts of Mind + +7 + +tree that I can see through my window. But any color can be awe-provoking +if we attend to it, and reflect upon its nature. Why should it feel like that? +Why should it feel like anything at all? How could I possibly convey the +nature of this color experience to someone who has not had such an +experience? +Other aspects of visual experience include the experience of shape, of +size, of brightness, and of darkness. A particularly subtle aspect is the experience of depth. As a child, one of my eyes had excellent vision, but the other +was very poor. Because of my one good eye, the world looked crisp and +sharp, and it certainly seemed three-dimensional. One day, I was fitted with +glasses, and the change was remarkable. The world was not much sharper +than before, but it suddenly looked more three-dimensional: things that had +depth before somehow got deeper, and the world seemed a richer place. If +you cover one eye and then uncover it, you can get an idea of the change. +In my previous state, I would have said that there was no way for the depth +of my vision to improve; the world already seemed as three-dimensional as +it could be. The change was subtle, almost ineffable, but extremely striking. +Certainly there is an intellectual story one can tell about how binocular +vision allows information from each eye to be consolidated into information +about distances, thus enabling more sophisticated control of action, but +somehow this causal story does not reveal the way the experience felt. Why +that change in processing should be accompanied by such a remaking of my +experience was mysterious to me as a ten-year-old, and is still a source of +wonder today. +Auditory experiences. In some ways, sounds are even stranger than visual +images. The structure of images usually corresponds to the structure of the +world in a straightforward way, but sounds can seem quite independent. My +telephone receives an incoming call, an internal device vibrates, a complex +wave is set up in the air and eventually reaches my eardrum, and somehow, +almost magically, I hear a ring. Nothing about the quality of the ring seems +to correspond directly to any structure in the world, although I certainly +know that it originated with the speaker, and that it is determined by a +waveform. But why should that waveform, or even these neural firings, have +given rise to a sound quality like that? +Musical experience is perhaps the richest aspect of auditory experience, +although the experience of speech must be close. Music is capable of washing +over and completely absorbing us, surrounding us in a way that a visual field +can surround us but in which auditory experiences usually do not. One can +analyze aspects of musical experience by breaking the sounds we perceive +into notes and tones with complex interrelationships, but the experience +of music somehow goes beyond this. A unified qualitative experience arises + + 8 + +Foundations + +Calvin and Hobbes + +by Bill Watterson + +Figure 1.1. Effability and ineffability in olfactory experience. (Calvin and Hobbes +© Watterson. Distributed by Universal Press Syndicate. Reprinted with permission. +All rights reserved) + +from a chord, but not from randomly selected notes. An old piano and a +far-off oboe can combine to produce an unexpectedly haunting experience. +As always, when we reflect, we ask the question: why should that feel like +this? +Tactile experiences. Textures provide another of the richest quality spaces +that we experience: think of the feel of velvet, and contrast it to the texture +of cold metal, or a clammy hand, or a stubbly chin. All of these have their +own unique quality. The tactile experiences of water, of cotton candy, or of +another person's lips are different again. +Olfactory experiences. Think of the musty smell of an old wardrobe, the +stench of rotting garbage, the whiff of newly mown grass, the warm aroma +of freshly baked bread. Smell is in some ways the most mysterious of all the +senses, due to the rich, intangible, indescribable nature of smell sensations. +Ackermann (1990) calls it "the mute sense; the one without words." While +there is something ineffable about any sensation, the other senses have +properties that facilitate some description. Visual and auditory experiences +have a complex combinatorial structure that can be described. Tactile and +taste experiences generally arise from direct contact with some object, and +a rich descriptive vocabulary has been built up by reference to these objects. +Smell has little in the way of apparent structure and often floats free of any +apparent object, remaining a primitive presence in our sensory manifold. +(Perhaps animals might do better [Figure 1.1].) The primitiveness is perhaps +partly due to the slot-and-key process by which our olfactory receptors are +sensitive to various kinds of molecules. It seems arbitrary that a given sort +of molecule should give rise to this sort of sensation, but give rise it does. + + Two Concepts of Mind + +9 + +Taste experiences. Psychophysical investigations tell us that there are only +four independent dimensions of taste perception: sweet, sour, bitter, and +salt. But this four-dimensional space combines with our sense of smell to +produce a great variety of possible experiences: the taste of Turkish Delight, +of curried black-eyed pea salad,4 of a peppermint Lifesaver, of a ripe peach. +Experiences of hot and cold. An oppressively hot, humid day and a frosty +winter's day produce strikingly different qualitative experiences. Think also +of the heat sensations on one's skin from being close to a fire, and the hotcold sensation that one gets from touching ultracold ice. +Pain. Pain is a paradigm example of conscious experience, beloved by +philosophers. Perhaps this is because pains form a very distinctive class of +qualitative experiences, and are difficult to map directly onto any structure +in the world or in the body, although they are usually associated with some +part of the body. Because of this, pains can seem even more subjective than +most sensory experiences. There are a great variety of pain experiences, +from shooting pains and fierce burns through sharp pricks to dull aches. +Other bodily sensations. Pains are only the most salient kind of sensations +associated with particular parts of the body. Others include headaches +(which are perhaps a class of pain), hunger pangs, itches, tickles, and the +experience associated with the need to urinate. Many bodily sensations have +an entirely unique quality, different in kind from anything else in our experience: think of orgasms, or the feeling of hitting one's funny bone. There are +also experiences associated with proprioception, the sense of where one's +body is in space. +Mental imagery. Moving ever inward, toward experiences that are not associated with particular objects in the environment or the body but that are +in some sense generated internally, we come to mental images. There is +often a rich phenomenology associated with visual images conjured up in +one's imagination, though not nearly as detailed as those derived from direct visual perception. There are also the interesting colored patterns that +one gets when one closes one's eyes and squints, and the strong after-images +that one gets after looking at something bright. One can have similar kinds +of auditory "images" conjured up by one's imagination, and even tactile, +olfactory, and gustatory images, although these are harder to pin down and +their associated qualitative feel is usually fainter. +Conscious thought. Some of the things we think and believe do not have +any particular qualitative feel associated with them, but many do. This ap- + + 10 + +Foundations + +plies particularly to explicit, occurrent thoughts that one thinks to oneself, +and to various thoughts that affect one's stream of consciousness. It is often +hard to pin down just what the qualitative feel of an occurrent thought is, +but it is certainly there. There is something it is like to be having such thoughts. +When I think of a lion, for instance, there seems to be a whiff of leonine +quality to my phenomenology: what it is like to think of a lion is subtly +different from what it is like to think of the Eiffel tower. More obviously, +cognitive attitudes such as desire often have a strong phenomenal flavor. +Desire seems to exert a phenomenological "tug," and memory often has a +qualitative component, as with the experience of nostalgia or regret. +Emotions. Emotions often have distinctive experiences associated with +them. The sparkle of a happy mood, the weariness of a deep depression, +the red-hot glow of a rush of anger, the melancholy of regret: all of these +can affect conscious experience profoundly, although in a much less specific +way than localized experiences such as sensations. These emotions pervade +and color all of our conscious experiences while they last. +Other more transient feelings lie partway between emotions and the more +obviously cognitive aspects of mind. Think of the rush of pleasure one feels +when one gets a joke. Another example is the feeling of tension one gets +when watching a suspense movie, or when waiting for an important event. +The butterflies in one's stomach that can accompany nervousness also fall +into this class. +The sense of self. One sometimes feels that there is something to conscious +experience that transcends all these specific elements: a kind of background +hum, for instance, that is somehow fundamental to consciousness and that +is there even when the other components are not. This phenomenology of +self is so deep and intangible that it sometimes seems illusory, consisting in +nothing over and above specific elements such as those listed above. Still, +there seems to be something to the phenomenology of self, even if it is very +hard to pin down. +This catalog covers a number of bases, but leaves out as much as it puts +in. I have said nothing, for instance, about dreams, arousal and fatigue, +intoxication, or the novel character of other drug-induced experiences. There +are also rich experiences that derive their character from the combination +of two or many of the components described above. I have mentioned the +combined effects of smell and taste, but an equally salient example is the +combined experience of music and emotion, which interact in a subtle, difficult-to-separate way. I have also left aside the unity of conscious experience—the way that all of these experiences seem to be tied together as the +experience of a single experiencer. Like the sense of self, this unity sometimes + + Two Concepts of Mind + +11 + +seems illusory—it is certainly harder to pin down than any specific experiences—but there is a strong intuition that unity is there. +Sad to say, we will not again be involved this closely with the rich varieties +of conscious experience. In addressing the philosophical mysteries associated with conscious experience, a simple color sensation raises the problems +as deeply as one's experience of a Bach chorale. The deep issues cut across +these varieties in a way that renders consideration of the nature of specific +experiences not especially relevant. Still, this brief look at the rich varieties +of conscious experience should help focus attention on just what it is that +is under discussion, and provides a stock of examples that can be kept in +mind during more abstract discussion.5 + +2. The Phenomenal and the Psychological +Concepts of Mind +Conscious experience is not all there is to the mind. To see this, observe +that although modern cognitive science has had almost nothing to say about +consciousness, it has had much to say about mind in general. The aspects +of mind with which it is concerned are different. Cognitive science deals +largely in the explanation of behavior, and insofar as it is concerned with +mind at all, it is with mind construed as the internal basis of behavior, and +with mental states construed as those states relevant to the causation and +explanation of behavior. Such states may or may not be conscious. From +the point of view of cognitive science, an internal state responsible for the +causation of behavior is equally mental whether it is conscious or not. +At the root of all this lie two quite distinct concepts of mind. The first is +the phenomenal concept of mind. This is the concept of mind as conscious +experience, and of a mental state as a consciously experienced mental state. +This is the most perplexing aspect of mind and the aspect on which I will +concentrate, but it does not exhaust the mental. The second is the psychological concept of mind. This is the concept of mind as the causal or explanatory +basis for behavior. A state is mental in this sense if it plays the right sort of +causal role in the production of behavior, or at least plays an appropriate +role in the explanation of behavior. According to the psychological concept, +it matters little whether a mental state has a conscious quality or not. What +matters is the role it plays in a cognitive economy. +On the phenomenal concept, mind is characterized by the way it feels; on +the psychological concept, mind is characterized by what it does. There +should be no question of competition between these two notions of mind. +Neither of them is the correct analysis of mind. They cover different phenomena, both of which are quite real. + + 12 + +Foundations + +I will sometimes speak of the phenomenal and psychological "aspects" of +mind, and sometimes of the "phenomenal mind" and the "psychological +mind." At this early stage, I do not wish to beg any questions about whether +the phenomenal and the psychological will turn out to be the same thing. +Perhaps every phenomenal state is a psychological state, in that it plays a +significant role in the causation and explanation of behavior, and perhaps +every psychological state has an intimate relation to the phenomenal. For +now, all that counts is the conceptual distinction between the two notions: +what it means for a state to be phenomenal is for it to feel a certain way, +and what it means for a state to be psychological is for it to play an appropriate causal role. These distinct notions should not be conflated, at least at +the outset. +A specific mental concept can usually be analyzed as a phenomenal concept, a psychological concept, or as a combination of the two. For instance, +sensation, in its central sense, is best taken as a phenomenal concept: to +have a sensation is to have a state with a certain sort of feel. On the other +hand, the concepts of learning and memory might best be taken as psychological. For something to learn, at a first approximation, is for it to adapt its +behavioral capacities appropriately in response to certain kinds of environmental stimulation. In general, a phenomenal feature of the mind is characterized by what it is like for a subject to have that feature, while a psychological feature is characterized by an associated role in the causation and/or +explanation of behavior. +Of course, this usage of the term "psychological" is a stipulation: it arises +from identifying psychology with cognitive science as described above. The +everyday concept of a "psychological state" is probably broader than this, +and may well include elements of the phenomenal. But nothing will rest on +my use of the term. +A potted history +The phenomenal and the psychological aspects of mind have a long history +of being conflated. Rene Descartes may have been partly responsible for +this. With his notorious doctrine that the mind is transparent to itself, he +came close to identifying the mental with the phenomenal. Descartes held +that every event in the mind is a cogitatio, or a content of experience. To +this class he assimilated volitions, intentions, and every type of thought. In +his reply to the Fourth Set of Objections, he wrote: +As to the fact that there can be nothing in the mind, in so far as it is a thinking +thing, of which it is not aware, this seems to me to be self-evident. For there +is nothing that we can understand to be in the mind, regarded in this way, that +is not a thought or dependent on a thought. If it were not a thought nor + + Two Concepts of Mind + +13 + +dependent on a thought it would not belong to the mind qua thinking thing; +and we cannot have any thought of which we are not aware at the very moment +it is in us. + +If Descartes did not actually identify the psychological with the phenomenal, +he at least assumed that everything psychological that is worthy of being +called mental has a conscious aspect.6 To Descartes, the notion of an unconscious mental state was a contradiction. +Progress in psychological theory rather than in philosophy was responsible +for drawing the two aspects of mind apart. As recently as a century ago, +psychologists such as Wilhelm Wundt and William James were recognizably +Cartesian in that they used introspection to investigate the causes of behavior, +and developed psychological theories on the basis of introspective evidence. +In this fashion, phenomenology was made the arbiter of psychology. But +developments soon after established the psychological as an autonomous +domain. +Most notably, Sigmund Freud and his contemporaries solidified the idea +that many activities of the mind are unconscious, and that there can be such +things as unconscious beliefs and desires. The very fact that this notion +seemed coherent is evidence that a nonphenomenal analysis of thought was +being used. It appears that Freud construed the notions causally. Desire, +very roughly, was implicitly construed as the sort of state that brings about +a certain kind of behavior associated with the object of the desire. Belief +was construed according to its causal role in a similar way. Of course Freud +did not make these analyses explicit, but something along these lines clearly +underlies his use of the notions. Explicitly, he recognized that accessibility +to consciousness is not essential to a state's relevance in the explanation of +behavior, and that a conscious quality is not constitutive of something's being +a belief or a desire. These conclusions rely on a notion of mentality that is +independent of phenomenal notions. +Around the same time, the behaviorist movement in psychology had thoroughly rejected the introspectionist tradition. A new "objective" brand of +psychological explanation was developed, with no room for consciousness +in its explanations. This mode of explanation had only partial success, but +it established the idea that psychological explanation can proceed while the +phenomenal is ignored. Behaviorists differed in their theoretical positions: +some recognized the existence of consciousness but found it irrelevant to +psychological explanation, and some denied its existence altogether. Many +went further, denying the existence of any kind of mental state. The official +reason for this was that internal states were supposed to be irrelevant in the +explanation of behavior, which could be carried out entirely in external +terms. Perhaps a deeper reason is that all mental notions were tainted with +the disreputable odor of the phenomenal. + + 14 + +Foundations + +In any case, these two developments established as orthodoxy the idea +that explanation of behavior is in no way dependent on phenomenal notions. +The move from behaviorism to computational cognitive science for the +most part preserved this orthodoxy. Although the move brought back a role +for internal states, which could even be called "mental" states, there was +nothing particularly phenomenal about them. These states were admissible +precisely on the grounds of their relevance in the explanation of behavior; +any associated phenomenal quality was at best beside the point. The concept +of the mental as psychological thus had center stage. +In philosophy, the shift in emphasis from the phenomenal to the psychological was codified by Gilbert Ryle (1949), who argued that all our mental +concepts can be analyzed in terms of certain kinds of associated behavior, +or in terms of dispositions to behave in certain ways.7 This view, logical +behaviorism, is recognizably the precursor of much of what passes for orthodoxy in contemporary philosophy of psychology. In particular, it was the +most explicit codification of the link between mental concepts and the causation of behavior. +Ryle did not put this theory forward as an analysis of just some mental +concepts. He intended all of them to fall within its grasp. It seemed to many +people, as it seems to me, that this view is a nonstarter as an analysis of our +phenomenal concepts, such as sensation and consciousness itself. To many, +it seemed clear that when we talk about phenomenal states, we are certainly +not talking about our behavior, or about any behavioral disposition. But in +any case, Ryle's analysis provided a suggestive approach to many other +mental notions, such as believing, enjoying, wanting, pretending, and remembering. +Apart from its problems with phenomenal states, Ryle's view had some +technical problems. First, it is natural to suppose that mental states cause +behavior, but if mental states are themselves behavioral or behavioral dispositions, as opposed to internal states, then it is hard to see how they could +do the job. Second, it was argued (by Chisholm [1957] and Geach [1957]) that +no mental state could be defined by a single range of behavioral dispositions, +independent of any other mental states. For example, if one believes that it +is raining, one's behavioral dispositions will vary depending on whether one +has the desire to get wet. It is therefore necessary to invoke other mental +states in characterizing the behavioral dispositions associated with a given +sort of mental state. +These problems were finessed by what has become known as functionalism, which was developed by David Lewis (1966) and most thoroughly by +David Armstrong (1968).8 On this view, a mental state is defined wholly by +its causal role: that is, in terms of the kinds of stimulation that tend to +produce it, the kind of behavior it tends to produce, and the way it interacts +with other mental states. This view made mental states fully internal and + + Two Concepts of Mind + +15 + +able to stand in the right kind of causal relation to behavior, answering the +first objection, and it allowed mental states to be defined in terms of their +interaction with each other, answering the second objection. +On this view, our mental concepts can be analyzed functionally, in terms +of their actual or typical causes and effects. To give such an analysis for any +given mental concept is highly nontrivial; Armstrong (1968) gives a number +of analyses, but these are very incomplete. As an in-principle position, however, functionalism may provide a reasonable construal of many of our +mental concepts, at least insofar as they play a role in the explanation of +behavior. For instance, the notion of learning might be analyzed as the +adaptation of one's behavioral capacities in response to environmental stimulation. To take a more complex state, a belief that it is raining might be very +roughly analyzed as the sort of state that tends to be produced when it is +raining, that leads to behavior that would be appropriate if it were raining, +that interacts inferentially with other beliefs and desires in a certain sort of +way, and so on. There is a lot of room for working out the details, but many +have found the overall idea to be on the right track. +Like Ryle, however, Armstrong and Lewis did not put this forward as an +analysis of some mental concepts. Rather, it was meant as an analysis of all +mental concepts. In particular, they argued that the notions of experience, +sensation, consciousness, and so on, could be analyzed in this fashion. This +assimilation of the phenomenal to the psychological seems to me to be +as great an error as Descartes's assimilation of the psychological to the +phenomenal. It is simply a false analysis of what it means to be phenomenal. +When we wonder whether somebody is having a color experience, we are +not wondering whether they are receiving environmental stimulation and +processing it in a certain way. We are wondering whether they are experiencing a color sensation, and this is a distinct question. It is a conceptually +coherent possibility that something could be playing the causal role without +there being an associated experience. +To put the point a different way, note that this analysis of phenomenal +concepts leaves it unclear why anybody was ever bothered by the problem +in the first place.9 There is no great mystery about how a state might play +some causal role, although there are certainly technical problems there for +science. What is mysterious is why that state should feel like something; why +it should have a phenomenal quality. Why the causal role is played and why +the phenomenal quality is present are two entirely different questions. The +functionalist analysis denies the distinctness of these questions, and therefore seems to be unsatisfactory. +I will consider this matter in much more detail later, but for now we can +note that even if the functionalist account gives an unsatisfactory analysis +of phenomenal concepts, it may provide a good analysis of other mental +notions, such as learning and memory, and perhaps belief. No parallel wor- + + 16 + +Foundations + +ries come up in these cases. It seems no more mysterious that a system +should be able to learn than that a system should be able to adapt its behavior +in response to environmental stimulation; indeed, these seem to be more or +less the same question. Similarly, when we wonder whether somebody has +learned something, it seems reasonable to say that in doing this we are +wondering whether they have undergone a change that will give rise to an +improved capacity to deal with certain situations in the future. Of course, a +thorough analysis of the concept of learning will be more subtle than this +first approximation, but the further details of the analysis will be spelled out +within the same framework. +Indeed, the functionalist account corresponds precisely to the definition +I have given of psychological properties. Most nonphenomenal mental properties fall into this class, and can therefore be functionally analyzed. There +is certainly room to argue over the details of a specific functionalist analysis. +There are also significant framework questions about such matters as the +role of the environment in characterizing psychological properties, and +whether it is causation, explanation, or both that provides the defining link +between psychological properties and behavior. These details are relatively +unimportant here, though. What matters is that nonphenomenal mental +states are largely characterized by their role in our cognitive economy. +The moral of this discussion is that both the psychological and the phenomenal are real and distinct aspects of mind. At a first approximation, phenomenal concepts deal with the first-person aspects of mind, and psychological +concepts deal with the third-person aspects. One's approach to the mind will +be quite different depending on what aspects of the mind one is interested +in. If one is interested in the mind's role in bringing about behavior, one +will focus on psychological properties. If one is interested in the conscious +experience of mental states, one will focus on phenomenal properties. Neither +the phenomenal nor the psychological should be defined away in terms of +the other. Conceivably, some deep analysis might reveal a fundamental link +between the phenomenal and the psychological, but this would be a nontrivial +task, and is not something to be accomplished by prior stipulation. To assimilate the phenomenal to the psychological prior to some deep explanation +would be to trivialize the problem of conscious experience; and to assimilate +the psychological to the phenomenal would be to vastly limit the role of the +mental in explaining behavior. + +3. The Double Life of Mental Terms +It seems reasonable to say that together, the psychological and the phenomenal exhaust the mental. That is, every mental property is either a phenomenal + + Two Concepts of Mind + +17 + +property, a psychological property, or some combination of the two. Certainly, if we are concerned with those manifest properties of the mind that +cry out for explanation, we find first, the varieties of conscious experience, +and second, the causation of behavior. There is no third kind of manifest +explanandum, and the first two sources of evidence—experience and behavior—provide no reason to believe in any third kind of nonphenomenal, +nonfunctional properties (with perhaps a minor exception for relational +properties, discussed shortly). There are certainly other classes of mental +states of which we often speak—intentional states, emotional states, and so +on—but it is plausible that these can be assimilated to the psychological, the +phenomenal, or a combination of the two. +Things are complicated by the fact that many everyday mental concepts +straddle the fence, having both a phenomenal and a psychological component. Pain provides a clear example. The term is often used to name a particular sort of unpleasant phenomenal quality, in which case a phenomenal +notion is central. But there is also a psychological notion associated with +the term: roughly, the concept of the sort of state that tends to be produced +by damage to the organism, tends to lead to aversion reactions, and so on. +Both of these aspects are central to the commonsense notion of pain. We +might say that the notion of pain is ambiguous between the phenomenal +and the psychological concept, or we might say that both of these are components of a single rich concept. +One can tie oneself into all kinds of knots by worrying about whether the +phenomenal quality or the functional role is more essential to pain. For +instance, would a hypothetical system in which all the functional criteria +were satisfied but in which the conscious experience were not present be +truly in pain? One might be tempted to say no, but what of the fact that we +speak of pains that last for a day, even though there are times when they +are not conscious? There is little point trying to legislate matters one way +or the other. Nothing important rests on the semantic decision as to whether +some phenomenal quality is really essential for something to count as pain. +Instead, we can recognize the different components associated with a concept and explicitly distinguish them, speaking for example of "phenomenal +pain" and "psychological pain." Our everyday concept of pain presumably +combines the two in some subtle weighted combination, but for philosophical discussion things are clearer if we keep them separate. +The reason why phenomenal and psychological properties are often run +together is clear: it is because the relevant properties tend to co-occur. +Generally, when the processes resulting from tissue damage and leading to +aversion reaction take place, some sort of phenomenal quality is instantiated. +That is, when psychological pain is present, phenomenal pain is usually also +present. It is not a conceptual truth that the process should be accompanied + + 18 + +Foundations + +by the phenomenal quality, but it is a fact about the world. Once we have +this sort of co-occurrence of properties in everyday situations, it is natural +that our everyday concepts will bind them together. +Many mental concepts lead this sort of double life. For example, the +concept of perception can be taken wholly psychologically, denoting the +process whereby cognitive systems are sensitive to environmental stimulation in such a way that the resulting states play a certain role in directing +cognitive processes. But it can also be taken phenomenally, involving the +conscious experience of what is perceived. The possibility of subliminal +perception counts against the latter construal, but some would argue that +this qualifies as perception only in a weakened sense of the term. Once again, +however, the issue is terminological. When we want to be clear, we can +simply stipulate whether it is the psychological property, the phenomenal +property, or a combination that we are concerned with. +Still, some of these dual concepts lean more strongly toward the phenomenal, and some lean toward the psychological. Take the concept of sensation, +which is closely related to the concept of perception and which also has both +phenomenal and psychological components. The phenomenal component is +much more prominent in "sensation" than in "perception," as witnessed by +the fact that the idea of unconscious perception seems to make more sense +than that of unconscious sensation. Things are still somewhat gray—there +remains a sense of "perception" that requires conscious experience, and a +sense of "sensation" that does not—but these senses seem less central than +the alternatives. Perhaps it is most natural to use "perception" as a psychological term, and "sensation" as a phenomenal term. This way, we can see +sensation as something like perception's phenomenal counterpart. +A good test for whether a mental notion M is primarily psychological is +to ask oneself: Could something be an instance of M without any particular +associated phenomenal quality? If so, then M is likely psychological. If not, +then M is phenomenal, or at least a combined notion that centrally involves +phenomenology. The latter possibility cannot be ruled out, as some concepts +may require both an appropriate sort of phenomenal quality and an appropriate cognitive role; perhaps a central sense of "sensation" has this combined character, for example. But we can at least separate those notions that +involve phenomenology from those that do not. +The test suggests that a concept such as learning, for example, is largely +psychological. To a first approximation, to learn is just for one's cognitive +capacities to adapt in a certain way to various new circumstances and stimuli. +No particular phenomenal quality is required for a cognitive process to be +an instance of learning; such a quality may be present, but it is not what +makes the process count as an example of learning. There may be a slight +phenomenal tinge inherited from a link with concepts such as belief, dis- + + Two Concepts of Mind + +19 + +cussed below, but this is faint at best. In explaining learning, the central thing +we have to explain is how the system manages to adapt in the appropriate +way. Something similar goes for concepts such as those of categorization +and memory, which seem to be largely psychological notions, in that what +is central is the playing of an appropriate cognitive role. +Emotions have a much clearer phenomenal aspect. When we think of +happiness and sadness, a distinct variety of conscious experience comes to +mind. It is not quite obvious whether the phenomenal aspect is essential +for a state to be an emotion, however; there is clearly a strong associated +psychological property as well. As usual, we need not make any decision on +this matter. We can simply talk about the psychological and phenomenal +aspects of emotion, and observe that these exhaust the aspects of emotion +that require explanation. +The most complex case is that of mental states such as belief, often called +"propositional attitudes" because they are attitudes to propositions concerning the world. When I believe that Bob Dylan will tour Australia, for +example, I endorse a certain proposition concerning Dylan; when I hope +that Dylan will tour Australia, I have a different attitude toward the same +proposition. The central feature of these mental states is their semantic +aspect, or intentionality: the fact that they are about things in the world. That +is, a belief has semantic content: the content of my belief cited above is +something like the proposition that Dylan will tour Australia (although there +is room for debate here). +Belief is most often regarded as a psychological property. On this view, +at a rough first approximation, to believe that a proposition is true is to be +in a state wherein one acts in a way that would be appropriate if it were +true, a state that tends to be brought about by its being the case, and a +state in which one's cognitive dynamics of reasoning reflect the appropriate +interaction of the belief with other beliefs and desires. The functional criteria +for belief are very subtle, however, and no one has yet produced anything +like a complete analysis of the relevant criteria. All the same, there is reason +to believe that this view captures much of what is significant about belief. +It is related to the idea that belief is something of an explanatory construct: +we attribute beliefs to others largely in order to explain their behavior. +Some would argue that this leaves something out, and that something over +and above the relevant sort of psychological process is required for belief. +In particular, it leaves out the experiential aspects of believing, which some +have argued are essential for anything to count as a belief. For example, +Searle (1990a) has argued that the intentional content of a belief depends +entirely on the associated state of consciousness, or on a state of consciousness that the belief can bring about. Without consciousness, all that is present +is "as-if" intentionality.10 + + 20 + +Foundations + +Certainly, there is often conscious experience in the vicinity of belief: there +is something it is like when one has an occurrent (i.e., conscious) belief, and +most nonoccurrent beliefs can at least bring about a conscious belief. The +crucial questions, though, are whether this conscious quality is what makes +the state a belief, and whether it is what gives it the content it has. This may +be more plausible for some beliefs than for others: for example, one might +argue that a conscious quality is required to truly have beliefs about one's +experiences, and perhaps also certain sorts of experiences are required to +have certain sorts of perceptual beliefs about the external world (perhaps +one needs red experiences to believe that an object is red?). In other cases, +this seems more problematic. For example, when I think that Don Bradman +is the greatest cricketer of all time, it seems plausible to say that I would have +had the same belief even if I had had a very different conscious experience +associated with it. The phenomenology of the belief is relatively faint, and +it is hard to see how it could be this phenomenal quality that makes the +belief a belief about Bradman. What seems more central to the beliefs +content is the connection between the belief and Bradman, and the role it +plays in my cognitive system. +As a weaker position, it might be suggested that although no particular +phenomenal quality is required to have a particular belief, a being must at +least be capable of conscious experience to believe anything at all.11 There +is a certain plausibility in the idea that a being with no conscious inner life +would not truly be a believer; at best, it would be only a pseudobeliever. +All the same, this would make the role of the phenomenal in intentional +concepts quite thin. The most substantial requirements for having a specific +belief will lie elsewhere than in the phenomenal. One could even subtract +any phenomenal component out, leaving a concept of pseudobelief that +resembles belief in most important respects except that it does not involve +the concept of consciousness. Indeed, it is plausible that pseudobelief could +do most of the explanatory work that is done by the concept of belief. +In any case, I will not try to adjudicate these difficult issues about the +relationship between intentionality and consciousness here. We can note +that there is at least a deflationary concept of belief that is purely psychological, not involving conscious experience; if a being is in the right psychological state, then it is in a state that resembles belief in many important ways, +except with respect to any phenomenal aspects. And there is an inflationary +concept of belief, on which conscious experience is required for truly believing, and perhaps even on which a specific sort of conscious experience +is required for truly believing a specific proposition. Which of these is the +"true" concept of belief will not matter too much for my purposes. +What is central is that there is not any feature of belief that outstrips the +phenomenal and the psychological. Perhaps a small qualification needs to + + Two Concepts of Mind + +21 + +be made to this: one may need to add a relational element, to account for +the fact that certain beliefs may depend on the state of the environment as +well as the internal state of the thinker. It has been argued, for example, +that to believe that water is wet, a subject must be related in an appropriate +way to water in the environment. This relation is usually taken to be a causal +relation, so it is possible that one could build this into the characterization +of the relevant psychological property, where the causal roles in question +stretch outside the head into the environment. If so, then no extra component +would be required. But in any case, it is not much of a burden to note that +there might also be a relational component to certain mental states, over +and above the psychological and phenomenal components. Either way, no +deep further mystery arises. +To see that there is no deep further aspect over and above the phenomenal and the psychological/relational aspects of intentional states, note that +the manifest phenomena in the vicinity that need explaining fall into two +classes: those we have third-person access to, and those we have first-person +access to. Those in the former class ultimately come down to behavior, +relations to the environment, and so on, and can be subsumed into the +class of the psychological and the relational. Those in the latter class come +down to the experience associated with believing—for example, the way +our concepts seem to reach out into a phenomenal world—and thus constitute part of the problem of consciousness, not a separate mystery. The reasons for believing in any given aspect of belief (including semantic content, +"aboutness," and so on) will derive from one of these two classes; there is +no independent third class of phenomena forcing itself on us to be explained. +Another way to see this is to note that once we have fixed the psychological, +phenomenal, and relational properties of an individual, there seems to be +nothing mental that can be independently varied. We cannot even imagine +someone identical to me in the three respects mentioned above but who +believes something different, in the way that we can arguably imagine someone psychologically identical to me who experiences something different. +There is simply not enough room in conceptual space for the possibility. +Intentional concepts are in some ways less primitive than psychological +and phenomenal concepts, in that they cannot be varied independently of +the latter.12 +Everything that I have said here about belief applies equally to other +intentional states, such as desire, hope, and so on. All of these states have +a psychological and a phenomenal aspect, and we need not legislate which +is primary, although a strong case might be made for a psychological analysis. +What counts is that there is no aspect of this state that outstrips both the +psychological and the phenomenal (with perhaps a relational component + + 22 + +Foundations + +thrown in). Psychology and phenomenology together constitute the central +aspects of the mind. +The co-occurrence of phenomenal and psychological properties +It is a fact about the human mind that whenever a phenomenal property is +instantiated, a corresponding psychological property is instantiated. Conscious experience does not occur in a vacuum. It is always tied to cognitive +processing, and it is likely that in some sense it arises from that processing. +Whenever one has a sensation, for example, there is some information processing going on: a corresponding perception, if you like. Similarly, whenever +one has the conscious experience of happiness, the functional role associated +with happiness is generally being played by some internal state. Perhaps it +is logically possible that one could have the experience without the causation, +but it seems to be an empirical fact that they go together. +In the face of this co-occurrence, the faint-hearted may be tempted to +worry whether any real distinction is being made. But it is clear that there +is at least a conceptual distinction here, even if the extensions of the concepts +involved seem to go together. One can wonder how to explain the phenomenal quality, and one can wonder how to explain the playing of the causal +role, and these are two distinct wonderings. +That being said, the co-occurrence of phenomenal and psychological properties reflects something deep about our phenomenal concepts. We have no +independent language for describing phenomenal qualities. As we have +seen, there is something ineffable about them. Although greenness is a +distinct sort of sensation with a rich intrinsic character, there is very little that +one can say about it other than that it is green. In talking about phenomenal +qualities, we generally have to specify the qualities in question in terms of +associated external properties, or in terms of associated causal roles. Our +language for phenomenal qualities is derivative on our nonphenomenal language. As Ryle said, there are no "neat" sensation words. +If one looks at the catalog of conscious experience that I presented earlier, +the experiences in question are never described in terms of their intrinsic +qualities. Rather, I used expressions such as "the smell of freshly baked +bread," "the patterns one gets when closing one's eyes," and so on. Even +with a term like "green sensation," reference is effectively pinned down in +extrinsic terms. When we learn the term "green sensation," it is effectively +by ostension—we learn to apply it to the sort of experience caused by grass, +trees, and so on. Generally, insofar as we have communicable phenomenal +categories at all, they are denned with respect either to their typical external +associations or to an associated kind of psychological state. For instance, +when one speaks of the phenomenal quality of happiness, the reference of +the term "happiness" is implicitly fixed via some causal role—the state where + + Two Concepts of Mind + +23 + +one judges all to be good, jumps for joy, and so on. Perhaps this is one +interpretation of Wittgenstein's famous remark, "An inner process stands +in need of outward criteria." +This dependence of phenomenal concepts on causal criteria has led some +(including Wittgenstein and Ryle, in some of their moods) to suggest that +there is nothing to the meaning of our mental concepts beyond the associated +causal criteria. There is a certain plausibility to this: if a phenomenal property +is always picked out by invoking a psychological property, why not suppose +that there is only one property involved? But this temptation should be +resisted. When we talk of a green sensation, this talk is not equivalent simply +to talk of "a state that is caused by grass, trees, and so on." We are talking +about the phenomenal quality that generally occurs when a state is caused +by grass and trees. If there is a causal analysis in the vicinity, it is something +like "the kind of phenomenal state that is caused by grass, trees, and so +on."13 The phenomenal element in the concept prevents an analysis in purely +functional terms. +In general, when a phenomenal property is picked out with the aid of a +psychological property P, the phenomenal notion is not just "P." It is "the +sort of conscious experience that tends to accompany P." And importantly, +the very notion of "phenomenal quality" or "conscious experience" is not +defined in psychological terms. Rather, the notion of conscious experience +is something of a primitive, as we saw earlier. // there were a functional +analysis of the notion of experience or phenomenal quality, then the analysis +in question would yield functional analyses of specific phenomenal properties, but in the absence of such an analysis we cannot draw such a conclusion. +We cannot identify the notion "phenomenal P" with that of "psychological +P" for all the usual reasons: there are two distinct concepts here, as witnessed +by the fact that there are two distinct explananda. Although "phenomenal +P" is picked out as "the experience that tends to accompany psychological +P," we can coherently imagine a situation in which phenomenal P occurs +without psychological P, and vice versa. A Rolls-Royce icon can be roughly +analyzed as the kind of icon that is generally found on Rolls-Royce cars, +but this does not mean that to be a Rolls-Royce icon is to be a RollsRoyce car. +This gives us some insight into the sparseness of our specifically phenomenal vocabulary compared to our psychological vocabulary, and it also helps +us understand why phenomenal and psychological properties have so often +been conflated. For most everyday purposes this conflation does not matter: +when one claims that someone is happy, one need not be talking specifically +about either the phenomenal quality or the functional role, as they usually +go together. However, for philosophical purposes and in particular for the +purposes of explanation, to conflate these properties is fatal. The conflation + + 24 + +Foundations + +can be tempting, as collapsing the distinction makes the problem of explaining conscious experience suddenly very straightforward; but it is utterly +unsatisfactory for the same reason. The problem of consciousness cannot be +spirited away on purely verbal grounds. + +4. The Two Mind-Body Problems +The division of mental properties into phenomenal and psychological properties has the effect of dividing the mind-body problem into two: an easy +part and a hard part. The psychological aspects of mind pose many technical +problems for cognitive science, and a number of interesting puzzles for +philosophical analysis, but they pose no deep metaphysical enigmas. The +question "How could a physical system be the sort of thing that could learn, +or that could remember?" does not have the same bite as the corresponding +question about sensations, or about consciousness in general. The reason +for this is clear. By our analysis in section 3, learning and memory are +functional properties, characterized by causal roles, so the question "How +could a physical system have psychological property P?" comes to the same +thing as "How could a state of a physical system play such-and-such a causal +role?" This is a question for the sciences of physical systems. One simply +needs to tell a story about the organization of the physical system that +allows it to react to environmental stimulation and produce behavior in the +appropriate sorts of ways. While the technical problems are enormous, there +is a clearly defined research program for their answer. The metaphysical +problems are relatively few. +This is not to say that psychological properties pose no philosophical +difficulties. There are significant problems in coming up with the correct +analyses of these notions, for instance. Even if it is widely accepted that +these are functional concepts, there can be significant disagreement about +just how the requisite functional analyses should run. Intentional properties +such as belief and desire, for example, provide fertile grounds for argument. +In particular, the question of just what constitutes the content of a given +intentional state is still poorly understood. There are also technical problems +concerning just how high-level constructs such as these can play a real causal +role in the production of behavior, especially if these are partly constituted +by properties of the environment, or if there are no strict laws connecting +psychological states with behavior. Then there are semi-empirical problems in the foundations of cognitive science concerning just how these properties might be instantiated in existing cognitive systems, or even concerning +whether they are instantiated at all. +These problems are all serious, but they have the character of puzzles +rather than mysteries.The situation here is analogous to that in the philosophy + + Two Concepts of Mind + +25 + +of biology, where there is no pressing life-body problem; there are merely +a host of technical problems about evolution, selection, adaptation, fitness, +and species. Just as most of the apparent metaphysical mysteries surrounding +biology were disposed of long ago, it is fair to say that the mind-body +problem for psychological properties is for all intents and purposes dissolved. +What remains is a collection of smaller technical problems with which the +normal course of scientific and philosophical analysis can grapple. +The phenomenal aspects of mind are a different matter. Here, the mindbody problem is as baffling as it ever was. The impressive progress of the +physical and cognitive sciences has not shed significant light on the question +of how and why cognitive functioning is accompanied by conscious experience. The progress in the understanding of the mind has almost entirely +centered on the explanation of behavior. This progress leaves the question +of conscious experience untouched. +If we like, we can view the psychological-phenomenal distinction not so +much as splitting the mind-body problem as factoring it into two separate +parts. The hardest part of the mind-body problem is the question: how could +a physical system give rise to conscious experience? We might factor the +link between the physical and conscious experience into two parts: the link +between the physical and the psychological, and the link between the psychological and the phenomenal. As we saw above, we now have a pretty good idea +of how a physical system can have psychological properties: the psychological +mind-body problem has been dissolved. What remains is the question of +why and how these psychological properties are accompanied by phenomenal +properties: why all the stimulation and reaction associated with pain is accompanied by the experience of pain, for instance. Following Jackendoff (1987), +we can call this residue the mind-mind problem. Current physical explanations take us as far as the psychological mind. What remains ill understood +is the link between the psychological mind and the phenomenal mind.14 +It is conceivable that the link between the phenomenal and the physical +might be independent of that between the psychological and the physical, +so that factoring would be impossible, but it seems unlikely. The close correlation that we have seen between phenomenal and psychological properties +suggests a deep link. In later chapters, I will argue that the link is an extremely +strong one and that the factoring strategy is valuable in approaching the +mind-body problem. If so, then understanding the link between the psychological and the phenomenal is crucial to understanding conscious experience. + +5. Two Concepts of Consciousness +Given that so many mental terms have a dual nature, it will not be surprising +to learn that even "consciousness" has both phenomenal and psychological + + 26 + +Foundations + +senses. So far, I have been focusing on the phenomenal sense, which itself +subsumes all the previously mentioned phenomenal aspects of mind. To be +conscious in this sense is just to instantiate some phenomenal quality. This +is the key sense of "consciousness," or at least the one that poses the major +explanatory problems. But it is not the only sense of the term. "Consciousness" can also be used to refer to a variety of psychological properties, such +as reportability or introspective accessibility of information. We can group +psychological properties of this sort under the label of psychological consciousness, as opposed to the phenomenal consciousness on which I have +been concentrating. +This ambiguity can lead to much confusion in the discussion of consciousness. Frequently, someone putting forward an explanation of consciousness +will start by investing the problem with all the gravity of the problem of +phenomenal consciousness, but will end by giving an explanation of some +aspect of psychological consciousness, such as the ability to introspect. This +explanation might be worthwhile in its own right, but one is left with the +sense that more has been promised than has been delivered. +Varieties of psychological consciousness +There are numerous psychological notions for which the term "consciousness" is sometimes used. These include the following: +Awakeness. Sometimes we say that a person is conscious as another way +of saying that they are not asleep. It makes sense to suppose that we have +experiences while we are asleep, so this notion clearly does not coincide +with phenomenal consciousness. Awakeness can plausibly be analyzed in +functional terms—perhaps, at a first approximation, in terms of an ability +to process information about the world and deal with it in a rational fashion. +Introspection. This is the process by which we can become aware of the +contents of our internal states. If you ask me about my mental states, it is +by introspection that I determine my answer. This access to one's mental +states is an important component of the everyday concept of consciousness, +and it is at least partly a functional notion. One might analyze it in terms +of one's rational processes being sensitive to information about one's internal +states in the right sort of way, and one's being able to use this information appropriately. +Reportability. This is our ability to report the contents of our mental states. +It presupposes the ability to introspect, but is more constrained than that +ability, as it presupposes a capacity for language. This concept of consciousness has often been the central target of philosophers and psychologists of +an operationalist bent. + + Two Concepts of Mind + +27 + +Self-consciousness. This refers to our ability to think about ourselves, our +awareness of our existence as individuals and of our distinctness from others. +My self-consciousness might be analyzed in terms of my access to a selfmodel, or my possession of a certain sort of representation that is associated +in some way with myself. It may well be that self-consciousness is limited +to humans and a few species of animals. +Attention. We often say that someone is conscious of something precisely +when they are paying attention to it; that is, when a significant portion of +their cognitive resources is devoted to dealing with the relevant information.We can be phenomenally conscious of something without attending to +it, as witnessed by the fringes of a visual field. +Voluntary control. In another sense, we say that a behavioral act is conscious when that act is performed deliberately; that is, where the action is +caused in the appropriate sort of way by an element of prior thought. +Knowledge. In another everyday sense, we say that someone is conscious +of a fact precisely when they know the fact, and that they are conscious of +a thing precisely when they know about that thing. This notion is rarely the +focus of technical discussion of consciousness, but it is probably as central +to the everyday usage of the term as anything else. +That these are all largely functional notions can be seen from how one would +explain the phenomena in question. If one were to try to explain attention, +one might devise a model of the cognitive processes that lead to resources +being concentrated on one aspect of available information rather than another. If one were to try to explain introspection, one would try to explain +the processes by which one is sensitive to one's internal states in the appropriate way. Similar stories apply to explanation of the other properties. In +each case, a functional explanation seems to capture what is central. +Although these concepts have a psychological core, many or all of them +are associated with phenomenal states. There is a certain sort of phenomenal +state associated with self-consciousness, for example. The same goes for +introspection, attention, and the voluntary control of behavior. As with the +other dual-aspect terms that I have discussed, terms such as "introspection" +and "self-consciousness" are sometimes used to refer to the phenomenal +state, which can lead to confusion. Indeed, some might argue that a phenomenal aspect is required for a process to truly qualify as "introspection," "attention," or whatever. As before, however, this issue is largely verbal. It is clear +that there is a phenomenal and a psychological property in the vicinity of +each of these concepts. Those who do not like to dignify the psychological +property with a mental term such as "attention" can use the term "pseudoattention" instead. The substantial philosophical issues remain the same, no +matter what the properties are called. + + 28 + +Foundations + +The phenomenal and the psychological properties in the vicinity of these +notions tend to occur together, but as with other mental concepts, they +should not be conflated. We should also be careful not to conflate the phenomenal senses of these terms with phenomenal consciousness in general. +Consciousness and awareness +We have seen that there is a psychological property associated with the +experience of emotion, a psychological property associated with the experience of self-consciousness, a psychological property associated with the experience of sensation, and so on. It is natural to suppose that there might be a +psychological property associated with experience itself, or with phenomenal +consciousness. In fact, I think there is such a property in the vicinity; we can +call it "awareness." This is the most general brand of psychological consciousness. +Awareness can be broadly analyzed as a state wherein we have access to +some information, and can use that information in the control of behavior. +One can be aware of an object in the environment, of a state of one's body, +or of one's mental state, among other things. Awareness of information +generally brings with it the ability to knowingly direct behavior depending +on that information. This is clearly a functional notion. In everyday language, +the term "awareness" is often used synonymously with "consciousness," but +I will reserve the term for the functional notion I have described here. +In general, wherever there is phenomenal consciousness, there seems to +be awareness. My phenomenal experience of the yellow book beside me is +accompanied by my functional awareness of the book, and indeed by my +awareness of the yellow color. My experience of a pain is accompanied by +an awareness of the presence of something nasty, which tends to lead to +withdrawal and the like, where possible. The fact that any conscious experience is accompanied by awareness is made clear by the fact that a conscious +experience is reportable. If I am having an experience, I can talk about the +fact that I am having it. I may not be paying attention to it, but I at least +have the ability to focus on it and talk about it, if I choose .This reportability +immediately implies that I am aware in the relevant sense. Of course, an +animal or a prelinguistic human might have conscious experience without +the ability to report, but such a being would still plausibly have a degree of +awareness. Awareness does not entail the ability to report, although the two +tend to go together in creatures with language. +Consciousness is always accompanied by awareness, but awareness as I +have described it need not be accompanied by consciousness. One can be +aware of a fact without any particular associated phenomenal experience, +for instance. However, it may be possible to constrain the notion of awareness so that it turns out to be coextensive with phenomenal consciousness, + + Two Concepts of Mind + +29 + +or nearly so. I will not attempt that project here, but I discuss it further in +Chapter 6. +The notion of awareness subsumes most or all of the various psychological +notions of consciousness just enumerated. Introspection can be analyzed as +awareness of some internal state. Attention can be analyzed as a particularly +high degree of awareness of an object or event. Self-consciousness can be +understood as awareness of oneself. Voluntary control is trickier, although +it might be partly analyzed as requiring attention to the behavior one is +performing. Awakeness might be roughly characterized as a state in which +one is able to deal rationally with one's environment to some extent, and +so implies a particular sort of awareness. +The idea that there is a functional notion of consciousness that can be +explicated in terms of access has been fleshed out by Block (1995), who +talks about the distinction between "phenomenal consciousness" and "access +consciousness." Block's notion of access consciousness corresponds closely to +the notion of awareness that I have been describing (I discuss the relationship +further in Chapter 6). In a similar fashion, Newell (1992) explicitly distinguishes between "awareness" and "consciousness." He describes awareness +as "the ability of a subject to make its behavior depend on some knowledge," and goes on to spell out the distinction between this notion and +consciousness, which he says is a nonfunctional phenomenon. Similar distinctions have been made by other philosophers and cognitive scientists.15 +Explaining consciousness versus explaining awareness +Awareness, like other psychological properties, poses few metaphysical +problems. The problems posed by the psychological varieties of consciousness are of the same order of magnitude as those posed by memory, learning, +and belief. Certainly, the notion of awareness is not crystal-clear, so there +is room for significant philosophical analysis of just what it comes to. Further, +there is room for an enormous amount of research in cognitive science, +studying how natural and artificial cognitive systems might function in such +a way that they are aware. But the outlines of these research programs are +reasonably clear. There is little reason to suppose that the normal course of +cognitive science, backed by appropriate philosophical analysis, should not +eventually succeed. +Insofar as consciousness is the really difficult problem for a science of the +mind, it is phenomenal consciousness that is central. The problems here are +of a different order of magnitude. Even after we have explained the physical +and computational functioning of a conscious system, we still need to explain +why the system has conscious experiences. Some dispute this claim, of course, +and I will discuss it at greater length soon. For now, though, we can simply +note the prima facie difference in the problems that the phenomenal and + + 30 + +Foundations + +psychological varieties present. It is phenomenal consciousness that poses +the worrying problem of consciousness. +Given the differences between the psychological and phenomenal notions +of consciousness, it is unfortunate that they are often conflated in the literature. This conflation matters little in everyday speech, as awareness and +phenomenal consciousness usually go together. But for the purposes of explanation, the conceptual distinction is crucial. Insofar as any remotely satisfactory explanations of "consciousness" have been put forward, it is usually +a psychological aspect that is explained. The phenomenal aspects generally +go untouched. +Many recent philosophical analyses of consciousness have concerned themselves primarily with the nonphenomenal aspects. Rosenthal (1996) argues that a mental state is conscious precisely when there is a higher-order +thought about that mental state. This might be a useful analysis of introspective consciousness, and perhaps of other aspects of awareness, but it does +not appear to explain phenomenal experience.16 Similarly, Dennett (1991) +spends much of his book outlining a detailed cognitive model, which he puts +forward as an explanation of consciousness. On the face of it, the model is +centrally a model of the capacity of a subject to verbally report a mental +state. It might thus yield an explanation of reportability, of introspective +consciousness, and perhaps of other aspects of awareness, but nothing in +the model provides an explanation of phenomenal consciousness (although +Dennett would put things differently). +Armstrong (1968), confronted by consciousness as an obstacle for his +functionalist theory of mind, analyzes the notion in terms of the presence +of some self-scanning mechanism. This might provide a useful account of +self-consciousness and introspective consciousness, but it leaves the problem +of phenomenal experience to the side. Armstrong (1981) talks about both +perceptual consciousness and introspective consciousness, but is concerned +with both only as varieties of awareness, and does not address the problems +posed by the phenomenal qualities of experience. Thus the sense in which +consciousness is really problematic for his functionalist theory is sidestepped, +by courtesy of the ambiguity in the notion of consciousness. +Others writing on the topic of "consciousness" have been primarily concerned with self-consciousness or introspective consciousness. Van Gulick +(1988), in suggesting that consciousness should be analyzed as the possession of "reflexive metapsychological information," is at best providing an +analysis of these psychological notions, and indeed concedes that the phenomenal aspects may be left out by such an analysis. Similarly, Jaynes's (1976) +elaborate theory of consciousness is concerned only with our awareness of +our own thoughts. It says nothing about phenomena associated with perception and therefore could not hope to be a theory of awareness in general, +let alone a theory of phenomenal consciousness. Hofstadter (1979) has some + + Two Concepts of Mind + +31 + +interesting things to say about consciousness, but he is more concerned with +introspection, free will, and the sense of self than with experience per se. +Insofar as consciousness has been a topic for discussion among psychologists, the phenomenal and psychological notions have not often been carefully +distinguished. Usually it is some aspect of awareness, such as introspection, +attention, or self-consciousness, that psychological studies address. Even the +psychological aspects of consciousness have had something of a bad name +in psychology, at least until recently. Perhaps this is because of some unclearness in those notions, and the difficulties associated with high-level phenomena such as introspection. One might speculate that to a larger extent this +bad reputation is due to their sharing a name with phenomenal consciousness, +giving the appearance of partnership in crime. +One sometimes hears that psychological research has been "returning to +consciousness" in recent years. The reality seems to be that the psychological +aspects of consciousness have been an active subject of research, and that +researchers have not been afraid to use the term "consciousness" for the +phenomena. For the most part, however, phenomenal consciousness remains +off to the side. Perhaps this is understandable. While one can see how the +methods of experimental psychology might lead to an understanding of the +various kinds of awareness, it is not easy to see how they could explain +phenomenal experience.17 +Cognitive models are well suited to explaining psychological aspects of +consciousness. There is no vast metaphysical problem in the idea that a +physical system should be able to introspect its internal states, or that it +should be able to deal rationally with information from its environment, or +that it should be able to focus its attention first in one place and then in the +next. It is clear enough that an appropriate functional account should be +able to explain these abilities, even if discovering the correct account takes +decades or centuries. But the really difficult problem is that of phenomenal +consciousness, and this is left untouched by the explanations of psychological +consciousness that have been put forward so far. +In what follows, I revert to using "consciousness" to refer to phenomenal +consciousness alone. When I wish to use the psychological notions, I will +speak of "psychological consciousness" or "awareness." It is phenomenal +consciousness with which I will mostly be concerned. + + 2 + +Supervenience and Explanation + +What is the place of consciousness in the natural order? Is consciousness +physical? Can consciousness be explained in physical terms? To come to +grips with these issues, we need to build a framework; in this chapter, I build +one. The centerpiece of this framework is the concept of supervenience: I +give an account of this concept and apply it to clarify the idea of reductive +explanation. Using this account, I sketch a picture of the relationship between +most high-level phenomena and physical facts, one that seems to cover +everything except, perhaps, for conscious experience. + +1. Supervenience +It is widely believed that the most fundamental facts about our universe are +physical facts, and that all other facts are dependent on these. In a weak +enough sense of "dependent," this may be almost trivially true; in a strong +sense, it is controversial. There is a complex variety of dependence relations +between high-level facts and low-level facts in general, and the kind of +dependence relation that holds in one domain, such as biology, may not hold +in another, such as that of conscious experience. The philosophical notion +of supervenience provides a unifying framework within which these dependence relations can be discussed. +The notion of supervenience formalizes the intuitive idea that one set of +facts can fully determine another set of facts.1 The physical facts about the +world seem to determine the biological facts, for instance, in that once all +the physical facts about the world are fixed, there is no room for the biological facts to vary. (Fixing all the physical facts will simultaneously fix which +objects are alive.) This provides a rough characterization of the sense in + + Supervenience and Explanation + +33 + +which biological properties supervene on physical properties. In general, +supervenience is a relation between two sets of properties: B-properties—intuitively, the high-level properties—and A-properties, which are the more +basic low-level properties. +For our purposes, the relevant A-properties are usually the physical +properties: more precisely, the fundamental properties that are invoked by a +completed theory of physics. Perhaps these will include mass, charge, spatiotemporal position; properties characterizing the distribution of various spatiotemporal fields, the exertion of various forces, and the form of various waves; +and so on. The precise nature of these properties is not important. If physics +changes radically, the relevant class of properties may be quite different +from those I mention, but the arguments will go through all the same. Such +high-level properties as juiciness, lumpiness, giraffehood, and the like are +excluded, even though there is a sense in which these properties are physical. +In what follows, talk of physical properties is implicitly restricted to the class +of fundamental properties unless otherwise indicated. I will sometimes speak +of "microphysical" or "low-level physical" properties to be explicit. +The A-facts and B-facts about the world are the facts concerning the +instantiation and distribution of A-properties and B-properties.2 So the physical facts about the world encompass all facts about the instantiation of +physical properties within the spatiotemporal manifold. It is also useful to +stipulate that the world's physical facts include its basic physical laws. On +some accounts, these laws are already determined by the totality of particular +physical facts, but we cannot take this for granted. +The template for the definition of supervenience is the following: +B-properties supervene on A-properties if no two possible situations are identical with respect to their A-properties while differing in their B-properties. +For instance, biological properties supervene on physical properties insofar +as any two possible situations that are physically identical are biologically +identical. (I use "identical" in the sense of indiscernibility rather than numerical identity here. In this sense, two separate tables might be physically +identical.) More precise notions of supervenience can be obtained by filling +in this template. Depending on whether we take the "situations" in question +to be individuals or entire worlds, we arrive at notions of local and global +supervenience, respectively. And depending on how we construe the notion +of possibility, we obtain notions of logical supervenience, natural supervenience, and perhaps others. I will flesh out these distinctions in what follows. + +Local and global supervenience +B-properties supervene locally on A-properties if the A-properties of an +individual determine the B-properties of that individual—if, that is, any two + + 34 + +Foundations + +possible individuals that instantiate the same A-properties instantiate the +same B-properties. For example, shape supervenes locally on physical properties: any two objects with the same physical properties will necessarily +have the same shape. Value does not supervene locally on physical properties, +however: an exact physical replica of the Mona Lisa is not worth as much +as the Mona Lisa. In general, local supervenience of a property on the +physical fails if that property is somehow context-dependent—that is, if an +object's possession of that property depends not only on the object's physical +constitution but also on its environment and its history. The Mona Lisa +is more valuable than its replica because of a difference in their historical context: the Mona Lisa was painted by Leonardo, whereas the replica +was not.3 +B-properties supervene globally on A-properties, by contrast, if the Afacts about the entire world determine the B-facts: that is, if there are no +two possible worlds identical with respect to their A-properties, but differing +with respect to their B-properties.4 A world here is to be thought of as +an entire universe; different possible worlds correspond to different ways a +universe might be. +Local supervenience implies global supervenience, but not vice versa. For +example, it is plausible that biological properties supervene globally +on physical properties, in that any world physically identical to ours would +also be biologically identical. (There is a small caveat here, which I discuss +shortly.) But they probably do not supervene locally. Two physically identical organisms can arguably differ in certain biological characteristics. One +might be fitter than the other, for example, due to differences in their environmental contexts. It is even conceivable that physically identical organisms +could be members of different species, if they had different evolutionary +histories. +The distinction between global and local supervenience does not matter +too much when it comes to conscious experience, because it is likely that +insofar as consciousness supervenes on the physical at all, it supervenes locally. If two creatures are physically identical, then differences in environmental and historical contexts will not prevent them from having identical +experiences. Of course, context can affect experience indirectly, but only by +virtue of affecting internal structure, as in the case of perception. Phenomena such as hallucination and illusion illustrate the fact that it is internal +structure rather than context that is directly responsible for experience. +Logical and natural supervenience +A more important distinction for our purposes is between logical (or conceptual) supervenience, and mere natural (or nomic, or empirical) supervenience. + + Supervenience and Explanation + +35 + +B-properties supervene logically on A-properties if no two logically possible situations are identical with respect to their A-properties but distinct +with respect to their B-properties. I will say more about logical possibility +later in this chapter. For now, one can think of it loosely as possibility in +the broadest sense, corresponding roughly to conceivability, quite unconstrained by the laws of our world. It is useful to think of a logically possible +world as a world that it would have been in God's power (hypothetically!) +to create, had he so chosen.5 God could not have created a world with +male vixens, but he could have created a world with flying telephones. In +determining whether it is logically possible that some statement is true, the +constraints are largely conceptual. The notion of a male vixen is contradictory, +so a male vixen is logically impossible; the notion of a flying telephone is +conceptually coherent, if a little out of the ordinary, so a flying telephone +is logically possible. +It should be stressed that the logical supervenience is not defined in terms +of deducibility in any system of formal logic. Rather, logical supervenience +is defined in terms of logically possible worlds (and individuals), where the +notion of a logically possible world is independent of these formal considerations. This sort of possibility is often called "broadly logical" possibility in +the philosophical literature, as opposed to the "strictly logical" possibility +that depends on formal systems.6 +At the global level, biological properties supervene logically on physical properties. Even God could not have created a world that was physically identical to ours but biologically distinct. There is simply no logical space for the biological facts to independently vary. When we fix all the +physical facts about the world—including the facts about the distribution of +every last particle across space and time—we will in effect also fix the +macroscopic shape of all the objects in the world, the way they move and +function, the way they physically interact. If there is a living kangaroo in +this world, then any world that is physically identical to this world will contain a physically identical kangaroo, and that kangaroo will automatically +be alive. +We can imagine that a hypothetical superbeing—Laplace's demon, say, +who knows the location of every particle in the universe—would be able +to straightforwardly "read off' all the biological facts, once given all the +microphysical facts. The microphysical facts are enough for such a being to +construct a model of the microscopic structure and dynamics of the world +throughout space and time, from which it can straightforwardly deduce the +macroscopic structure and dynamics. Given all that information, it has all +the information it needs to determine which systems are alive, which systems +belong to the same species, and so on. As long as it possesses the biological +concepts and has a full specification of the microphysical facts, no other +information is relevant. + + 36 + +Foundations + +In general, when B-properties supervene logically on A-properties, we +can say that the A-facts entail the B-facts, where one fact entails another if +it is logically impossible for the first to hold without the second. In such +cases, Laplace's demon could read off the B-facts from a specification of the +A-facts, as long as it possesses the B-concepts in question. (I will say much +more about the connections between these different ways of understanding +logical supervenience later in the chapter; the present discussion is largely +for illustration.) In a sense, when logical supervenience holds, all there is to +the B-facts being as they are is that the A-facts are as they are. +There can be supervenience without logical supervenience, however. The +weaker variety of supervenience arises when two sets of properties are +systematically and perfectly correlated in the natural world. For example, +the pressure exerted by one mole of a gas systematically depends on its +temperature and volume according to the law pV = KT, where Kis a constant +(I pretend for the purposes of illustration that all gases are ideal gases). In +the actual world, whenever there is a mole of gas at a given temperature +and volume, its pressure will be determined: it is empirically impossible that +two distinct moles of gas could have the same temperature and volume, but +different pressure. It follows that the pressure of a mole of gas supervenes +on its temperature and volume in a certain sense. (In this example, I am +taking the class of A-properties to be much narrower than the class of physical properties, for reasons that will become clear.) But this supervenience +is weaker than logical supervenience. It is logically possible that a mole of +gas with a given temperature and volume might have a different pressure; +imagine a world in which the gas constant K is larger or smaller, for example. +Rather, it is just a fact about nature that there is this correlation. +This is an example of natural supervenience of one property on others: +in this instance, pressure supervenes naturally on temperature, volume, and +the property of being a mole of gas. In general, B-properties supervene +naturally on A-properties if any two naturally possible situations with the +same A-properties have the same B-properties. +A naturally possible situation is one that could actually occur in nature, +without violating any natural laws. This is a much stronger constraint than +mere logical possibility. The scenario with a different gas constant is logically +possible, for example, but it could never occur in the real world, so it is not +naturally possible. Among naturally possible situations, any two moles of +gas with the same temperature and volume will have the same pressure. +Intuitively, natural possibility corresponds to what we think of as real +empirical possibility—a naturally possible situation is one that could come +up in the real world, if the conditions were right. These include not just +actual situations but counterfactual situations that might have come up in +the world's history, if boundary conditions had been different, or that might +come up in the future, depending on how things go. A mile-high skyscraper + + Supervenience and Explanation + +37 + +is almost certainly naturally possible, for example, even though none has +actually been constructed. It is even naturally possible (although wildly improbable) that a monkey could type Hamlet. We can also think of a naturally +possible situation as one that conforms to the laws of nature of our world.7 +For this reason, natural possibility is sometimes called nomic or nomological +possibility,8 from the Greek term nomos for "law." +There are a vast number of logically possible situations that are not naturally +possible. Any situation that violates the laws of nature of our world falls into +this class: a universe without gravity, for example, or with different values +of fundamental constants. Science fiction provides many situations of this +sort, such as antigravity devices and perpetual-motion machines. These are +easy to imagine, but almost certainly could never come to exist in our world. +In the reverse direction, any situation that is naturally possible will be +logically possible. The class of natural possibilities is therefore a subset of +the class of logical possiblities. To illustrate this distinction: both a cubic +mile of gold and a cubic mile of uranium-235 seem to be logically possible, +but as far as we know, only the first is naturally possible—a (stable) cubic +mile of uranium-235 could not exist in our world. +Natural supervenience holds when, among all naturally possible situations, those with the same distribution of A-properties have the same distributon of B-properties: that is, when the A-facts about a situation naturally +necessitate the B-facts. This happens when the same clusters of A-properties +in our world are always accompanied by the same B-properties, and when +this correlation is not just coincidental but lawful: that is, when instantiating +the A-properties will always bring about the B-properties, wherever and +whenever this happens. (In philosophical terms, the dependence must support counterfactuals.) This co-occurrence need not hold in every logically +possible situation, but it must hold in every naturally possible situation. +It is clear that logical supervenience implies natural supervenience. If any +two logically possible situations with the same A-properties have the same +B-properties, then any two naturally possible situations will also. The reverse +does not hold, however, as the gas law illustrates. The temperature and +volume of a mole of gas determine pressure across naturally but not logically +possible situations, so pressure depends naturally but not logically on temperature and volume. Where we have natural supervenience without logical +supervenience, I will say that we have mere natural supervenience. +For reasons that will become clear, it is hard to find cases of natural supervenience on the set of physical properties without logical supervenience, +but consciousness itself can provide a useful illustration. It seems very likely +that consciousness is naturally supervenient on physical properties, locally +or globally, insofar as in the natural world, any two physically identical creatures will have qualitatively identical experiences. It is not at all clear +that consciousness is logically supervenient on physical properties, however. + + 38 + +Foundations + +It seems logically possible, at least to many, that a creature physically identical to a conscious creature might have no conscious experiences at all, or +that it might have conscious experiences of a different kind. (Some dispute +this, but I use it for now only as an illustration.) If this is so, then conscious +experience supervenes naturally but not logically on the physical. The necessary connection between physical structure and experience is ensured only +by the laws of nature, and not by any logical or conceptual force. +The distinction between logical and natural supervenience is vital for our +purposes.9 We can intuitively understand the distinction as follows. If Bproperties supervene logically on A-properties, then once God (hypothetically) creates a world with certain A-facts, the B-facts come along for free +as an automatic consequence. If B-properties merely supervene naturally on +A-properties, however, then after making sure of the A-facts, God has to +do more work in order to make sure of the B-facts: he has to make sure +there is a law relating the A-facts and the B-facts. (I borrow this image from +Kripke 1972.) Once the law is in place, the relevant A-facts will automatically +bring along the B-facts; but one could, in principle, have had a situation +where they did not. +One also sometimes hears talk of metaphysical supervenience, which is +based on neither logical nor natural necessity, but on "necessity tout court," +or "metaphysical necessity" as it is sometimes known (drawing inspiration +from Kripke's [1972] discussion of a posteriori necessity). I will argue later +that the metaphysically possible worlds are just the logically possible worlds +(and that metaphysical possibility of statements is logical possibility with an +a posteriori semantic twist), but for now it is harmless to assume there is a +notion of metaphysical supervenience, to be spelled out by analogy with the +notions of logical and natural supervenience above. A notion of "weak" +supervenience is also mentioned occasionally, but seems too weak to express +an interesting dependence relation between properties.10 +The logical-natural distinction and the global-local distinction cut across +each other. It is reasonable to speak of both global logical supervenience +and local logical supervenience, although I will more often be concerned +with the former. When I speak of logical supervenience without a further +modifier, global logical supervenience is intended. It is also coherent to +speak of global and local natural supervenience, but the natural supervenience relations with which we are concerned are generally local or at least +localizable, for the simple reason that evidence for a natural supervenience +relation generally consists in local regularities between clusters of properties.11 +A problem with logical supervenience* +A technical problem with the notion of logical supervenience needs to be +dealt with. This problem arises from the logical possibility of a world physi- + + Supervenience and Explanation + +39 + +cally identical to ours, but with additional nonphysical stuff that is not present +in our own world: angels, ectoplasm, and ghosts, for example. There is a +conceivable world just like ours except that it has some extra angels hovering +in a non-physical realm, made of ectoplasm. These angels might have biological properties of their own, if they reproduced and evolved. Presumably the +angels could have all sorts of beliefs, and their communities might have +complex social structure. +The problem these examples pose is clear. The angel world is physically +identical to ours, but it is biologically distinct. If the angel world is logically +possible, then according to our definition biological properties are not supervenient on physical properties. But we certainly want to say that biological +properties are supervenient on physical properties, at least in this world if +not in the angel world (assuming there are no angels in the actual world!). +Intuitively, it seems undesirable for the mere logical possibility of the angel +world to stand in the way of the determination of biological properties by +physical properties in our own world. +This sort of problem has caused some (e.g., Haugeland 1982; Petrie 1987) +to suggest that logical possibility and necessity are too strong to serve as the +relevant sort of possibility and necessity in supervenience relations, and that +a weaker variety such as natural possibility and necessity should be used +instead. But this would render useless the very useful distinction between +logical and natural supervenience outlined above, and would also ignore the +fact that there is a very real sense in which the biological facts about our +world are logically determined by the physical facts. Others (e.g., Teller +1989) have bitten the bullet by stipulating that worlds with extra nonphysical +stuff are not logically or metaphysically possible, despite appearances, but +this makes logical and metaphysical possibility seem quite arbitrary. Fortunately, such moves are not required. It turns out that it is possible to retain +a useful notion of logical supervenience compatible with the possibility of +these worlds, as long as we fix the definition appropriately.12 +The key to the solution is to turn supervenience into a thesis about our +world (or more generally, about particular worlds). This accords with the +intuition that biological facts are logically determined by the physical facts +in our world, despite the existence of bizarre worlds where they are not so +determined. According to a revised definition, B-properties are logically +supervenient on A-properties if the B-properties in our world are logically +determined by the A-properties in the following sense: in any possible world +with the same A-facts, the same B-facts will hold.13 The existence of possible +worlds with extra B-facts will thus not count against logical supervenience +in our world, as long as at least the B-facts true in our world are true in all +physically identical worlds. And this they generally will be (with an exception +discussed below). If there is a koala eating in a gum tree in this world, there +will be an identical koala eating in a gum tree in any physically identical +world, whether or not that world has any angels hanging around. + + 40 + +Foundations + +There is a minor complication. There is a certain sort of biological fact +about our world that does not hold in the angel world: the fact that our +world has no living ectoplasm, for example, and the fact that all living +things are based on DNA. Perhaps the angel world might even be set up +with ectoplasm causally dependent on physical processes, so that wombat +copulation on the physical plane sometimes gives rise to baby ectoplasmic wombats on the nonphysical plane. If so, then there might be a wombat that is childless (in a certain sense) in our world, with a counterpart +that is not childless in the physically identical angel world. It follows that +the property of being childless does not supervene according to our definition, and nor do the world-level properties such as that of having no living +ectoplasm. Not all the facts about our world follow from the physical +facts alone. +To analyze the problem, note that these facts all involve negative existence +claims, and so depend not only on what is going on in our world but on +what is not. We cannot expect these facts to be determined by any sort of +localized facts, as they depend not just on local goings-on in the world but +on the world's limits. Supervenience theses should apply only to positive +facts and properties, those that cannot be negated simply by enlarging a +world. We can define a positive fact in W as one that holds in every world +that contains W as a proper part;14 a positive property is one that if instantiated in a world W, is also instantiated by the corresponding individual in all +worlds that contain W as a proper part.15 Most everyday facts and properties +are positive—think of the property of being a kangaroo, or of being six feet +tall, or of having a child. Negative facts and properties will always involve +negative existence claims in one form or another. These include explicitly +negative existential facts such as the nonexistence of ectoplasm, universally +quantified facts such as the fact that all living things are made of DNA, +negative relational properties such as childlessness, and superlatives such as +the property of being the most fecund organism in existence. +In future, the supervenience relations with which we are concerned should +be understood to be restricted to positive facts and properties. When claiming +that biological properties supervene on physical properties, it is only the +positive biological properties that are at issue. All the properties with which +we are concerned are positive—local physical and phenomenal properties, +for instance—so this is not much of a restriction. +The definition of global logical supervenience of B-properties on A-properties therefore comes to this: for any logically possible world W that is Aindiscernible from our world, then the B-facts true of our world are true of +W. We need not build in a clause about positiveness, but it will usually be +understood that the only relevant B-facts and properties are positive facts +and properties. Similarly, B-properties supervene locally and logically on Aproperties when for every actual individual x and every logically possible + + Supervenience and Explanation + +41 + +individual y, if y is A-indiscernible from x, then the B-properties instantiated +by x are instantiated by y. More briefly and more generally: B-properties +supervene logically on A-properties if the B-facts about actual situations +are entailed by the A-facts, where situations are understood as worlds and +individuals in the global and local cases respectively. This definition captures +the idea that supervenience claims are usually claims about our world, while +retaining the key role of logical necessity.16 +Supervenience and materialism +Logical and natural supervenience have quite different ramifications for +ontology: that is, for the matter of what there is in the world. If B-properties +are logically supervenient on A-properties, then there is a sense in which +once the A-facts are given, the B-facts are a free lunch. Once God (hypothetically) made sure that all the physical facts in our world held, the biological +facts came along for free. The B-facts merely redescribe what is described +by the A-facts. They may be different facts (a fact about elephants is not a +microphysical fact), but they are not further facts. +With mere natural supervenience, the ontology is not so straightforward. +Contingent lawful connections connect distinct features of the world. In +general, if B-properties are merely naturally supervenient on A-properties +in our world, then there could have been a world in which our A-facts held +without the B-facts. As we saw before, once God fixed all the A-facts, in +order to fix the B-facts he had more work to do. The B-facts are something +over and above the A-facts, and their satisfaction implies that there is something new in the world. +With this in mind we can formulate precisely the widely held doctrine of +materialism (or physicalism), which is generally taken to hold that everything +in the world is physical, or that there is nothing over and above the physical, +or that the physical facts in a certain sense exhaust all the facts about the +world. In our language, materialism is true if all the positive facts about the +world are globally logically supervenient on the physical facts. This captures +the intuitive notion that if materialism is true, then once God fixed the +physical facts about the world, all the facts were fixed. +(Or at least, all the positive facts were fixed. The restriction to positive +facts is needed to ensure that worlds with extra ectoplasmic facts do not +count against materialism in our world. Negative existential facts such as +"There are no angels" are not strictly logically supervenient on the physical, +but their nonsupervenience is quite compatible with materialism. In a sense, +to fix the negative facts, God had to do more than fix the physical facts; he +also had to declare, "That's all." If we wanted, we could add a second-order +"That's all" fact to the supervenience base in the definition of materialism, +in which case the positive-fact constraint could be removed.) + + 42 + +Foundations + +According to this definition, materialism is true if all the positive facts +about our world are entailed by the physical facts.17 That is, materialism is +true if for any logically possible world W that is physically indiscernible from +our world, all the positive facts true of our world are true of W. This is +equivalent in turn to the thesis that any world that is physically indiscernible +from our world contains a copy of our world as a (proper or improper) part, +which seems an intuitively correct definition.18 (This matches the definition +of physicalism given by Jackson [1994], whose criterion is that every minimal +physical duplicate of our world is a duplicate simpliciter of our world.19) +I will discuss this matter at much greater length in Chapter 4, where this +definition of materialism will be further justified. Some may object to the +use of logical possibility rather than possibility tout court or "metaphysical possibility." Those people may substitute metaphysical possibility for +logical possibility in the definition above. Later, I will argue that it comes +to the same thing. + +2. Reductive Explanation +The remarkable progress of science over the last few centuries has given us +good reason to believe that there is very little that is utterly mysterious +about the world. For almost every natural phenomenon above the level of +microscopic physics, there seems in principle to exist a reductive explanation: +that is, an explanation wholly in terms of simpler entities. In these cases, +when we give an appropriate account of lower-level processes, an explanation +of the higher-level phenomenon falls out. +Biological phenomena provide a clear illustration. Reproduction can be +explained by giving an account of the genetic and cellular mechanisms that +allow organisms to produce other organisms. Adaptation can be explained +by giving an account of the mechanisms that lead to appropriate changes in +external function in response to environmental stimulation. Life itself is +explained by explaining the various mechanisms that bring about reproduction, adaptation, and the like. Once we have told the lower-level story in +enough detail, any sense of fundamental mystery goes away: the phenomena +that needed to be explained have been explained. +One can tell a similar story for most natural phenomena. In physics, we +explain heat by telling an appropriate story about the energy and excitation +of molecules. In astronomy, we explain the phases of the moon by going +into the details of orbital motion and optical reflection. In geophysics, earthquakes are explained via an account of the interaction of subterranean +masses. In cognitive science, to explain a phenomenon such as learning, all +we have to do is explain various functional mechanisms—the mechanisms +that give rise to appropriate changes in behavior in response to environmen- + + Supervenience and Explanation + +43 + +tal stimulation, at a first approximation (any worries about the experience +of learning aside). Many of the details of these explanations currently evade +our grasp, and are likely to prove very complex, but we know that if we find +out enough about the low-level story, the high-level story will eventually +come along. +I will not precisely define the notion of reductive explanation until later. +For now, it remains characterized by example. However, I can issue some +caveats about what reductive explanation is not. A reductive explanation of +a phenomenon need not require a reduction of that phenomenon, at least +in some senses of that ambiguous term. In a certain sense, phenomena +that can be realized in many different physical substrates—learning, for +example—might not be reducible in that we cannot identify learning with +any specific lower-level phenomenon. But this multiple realizability does not +stand in the way of reductively explaining any instance of learning in terms +of lower-level phenomena.20 Reductive explanation of a phenomenon should +also not be confused with a reduction of a high-level theory. Sometimes a +reductive explanation of a phenomenon will provide a reduction of a preexisting high-level theory, but other times it will show such theories to be on +the wrong track. Often there might not even be a high-level theory to reduce. +Reductive explanation is not the be-all and end-all of explanation. There +are many other sorts of explanation, some of which may shed more light on +a phenomenon than a reductive explanation in a given instance. There are +historical explanations, for instance, explaining the genesis of a phenomenon +such as life, where a reductive explanation only gives a synchronic account of +how living systems function. There are also ail sorts of high-level explanations, +such as the explanation of aspects of behavior in terms of beliefs and desires. +Even though this behavior might in principle be explainable reductively, a +high-level explanation is often more comprehensible and enlightening. Reductive explanations should not be seen as displacing these other sorts of +explanation. Each has its place. +Reductive explanation via functional analysis +What is it that allows such diverse phenomena as reproduction, learning, +and heat to be reductively explained? In all these cases, the nature of the +concepts required to characterize the phenomena is crucial. If someone +objected to a cellular explanation of reproduction, "This explains how a +cellular process can lead to the production of a complex physical entity that +is similar to the original entity, but it doesn't explain reproduction," we +would have little patience—for that is all that "reproduction" means. In +general, a reductive explanation of a phenomenon is accompanied by some +rough-and-ready analysis of the phenomenon in question, whether implicit +or explicit. The notion of reproduction can be roughly analyzed in terms of + + 44 + +Foundations + +the ability of an organism to produce another organism in a certain sort of +way. It follows that once we have explained the processes by which an +organism produces another organism, we have explained that instance of +reproduction. +The point may seem trivial, but the possibility of this kind of analysis +undergirds the possibility of reductive explanation in general. Without such +an analysis, there would be no explanatory bridge from the lower-level +physical facts to the phenomenon in question. With such an analysis in hand, +all we need to do is to show how certain lower-level physical mechanisms +allow the analysis to be satisfied, and an explanation will result. +For the most interesting phenomena that require explanation, including +phenomena such as reproduction and learning, the relevant notions can +usually be analyzed functionally. The core of such notions can be characterized in terms of the performance of some function or functions (where +"function" is taken causally rather than teleologically), or in terms of the +capacity to perform those functions. It follows that once we have explained +how those functions are performed, then we have explained the phenomena +in question. Once we explain how an organism performs the function of +producing another organism, we have explained reproduction, for all it +means to reproduce is to perform that function. The same goes for an +explanation of learning. All it means for an organism to learn, roughly, is for +its behavioral capacities to adapt appropriately in response to environmental +stimulation. If we explain how the organism is able to perform the relevant +functions, then we have explained learning. +(At most, we may have failed to explain any phenomenal aspects of learning, which I leave aside here for obvious reasons. If there is a phenomenal +element to the concept of learning, then that part of learning may go unexplained; but I concentrate on the psychological aspects of learning here, +which are plausibly the core of the concept.) +Explaining the performance of these functions is quite straightforward, in +principle. As long as the results of such functions are themselves characterizable physically, and all physical events have physical causes, then there +should be a physical explanation for the performance of any such function. +One need only show how certain sorts of states are responsible for the +production of appropriate resultant states, by a causal process in accord with +the laws of nature. Of course the details of this kind of physical explanation +can be nontrivial. Indeed, the details constitute the vast bulk of any reductive +explanation, while the analysis component is often trivial. But once the +relevant details are in, a story about low-level physical causation will explain +how the relevant functions are performed, and will therefore explain the +phenomenon in question. +Even a physical notion such as heat can be construed functionally: roughly, +heat is the kind of thing that expands metals, is caused by fire, leads to a + + Supervenience and Explanation + +45 + +particular sort of sensation, and the like. Once we have an account of how +these various causal relations are fulfilled, then we have an account of heat. +Heat is a causal-role concept, characterized in terms of what it is typically +caused by and of what it typically causes, under appropriate conditions. Once +empirical investigation shows how the relevant causal role is played, the +phenomenon is explained. +There are some technical complications here, but they are inessential. For +example, Kripke (1980) has pointed out a difference between a term such +as "heat" and the associated description of a causal role: given that heat is +realized by the motion of molecules, then the motion of molecules might +qualify as heat in a counterfactual world, whether or not those molecules +play the relevant causal role. It remains the case, however, that explaining +heat involves explaining the fulfillment of the causal role, rather than +explaining the motion of molecules. To see this, note that the equivalence +of heat with the motion of molecules is known a posteriori: we know this as +a result of explaining heat. The concept of heat that we had a priori—before +the phenomenon was explained—was roughly that of "the thing that plays +this causal role in the actual world." Once we discover how that causal role +is played, we have an explanation of the phenomenon. As a bonus, we know +what heat is. It is the motion of molecules, as the motion of molecules is +what plays the relevant causal role in the actual world. +A second minor complication is that many causal-role concepts are somewhat ambiguous between the state that plays a certain causal role and the +actual performance of that role. "Heat" can be taken to denote either the +molecules that do the causal work or the causal process (heating) itself. +Similarly, "perception" can be used to refer to either the act of perceiving +or the internal state that arises as a result. Nothing important turns on this +ambiguity, however. An explanation of how the causal role is played will +explain heat or perception in either of these senses. +A third complication is that many causal-role concepts are partly characterized in terms of their effect on experience: for example, heat is naturally +construed as the cause of heat sensations. Does this mean that we have to +explain heat sensations before we can explain heat? Of course, we have no +good account of heat sensations (or of experience generally), so what happens +in practice is that that part of the phenomenon is left unexplained. If we +can explain how molecular motion comes about in certain conditions, and +causes metals to expand, and stimulates our skin in certain ways, then the +observation that this motion is correlated with heat sensations is good enough. +From the correlation, we infer that there is almost certainly a causal connection. To be sure, no explanation of heat will be complete until we have an +account of how that causal connection works, but the incomplete account is +good enough for most purposes. It is somewhat paradoxical that we end up +explaining almost everything about a phenomenon except for the details of + + 46 + +Foundations + +how it affects our phenomenology, but it is not a problem in practice. It +would not be a happy state of affairs if we had to put the rest of science on +hold until we had a theory of consciousness. +Reductive explanations in cognitive science +The paradigm of reductive explanation via functional analysis works beautifully in most areas of cognitive science, at least in principle. As we saw in +the previous chapter, most nonphenomenal mental concepts can be analyzed +functionally. Psychological states are characterizable in terms of the causal +role they play. To explain these states, we explain how the relevant causation +is performed. +In principle, one can do this by giving an account of the underlying neurophysiology. If we explain how certain neurophysiological states are responsible for the performance of the functions in question, then we have explained +the psychological state. We need not always descend to the neurophysiological level, however. We can frequently explain some aspect of mentality by +exhibiting an appropriate cognitive model—that is, by exhibiting the details +of the abstract causal organization of a system whose mechanisms are sufficient to perform the relevant functions, without specifying the physiochemical substrate in which this causal organization is implemented. In this way, +we give a how-possibly explanation of a given aspect of psychology, in that +we have shown how the appropriate causal mechanisms might support the +relevant mental processes. If we are interested in explaining the mental states +of an actual organism or type of organism (e.g., learning in humans, as +opposed to the possibility of learning in general), this sort of explanation +must be supplemented with a demonstration that the causal organization of +the model mirrors the causal organization of the organism in question. +To explain the possibility of learning, we can exhibit a model whose +mechanisms lead to the appropriate changes in behavioral capacity in response to various kinds of environmental stimulation—a connectionist learning model, for example. To explain human learning, we must also demonstrate that such a model reflects the causal organization responsible for the +performance of such functions in humans. The second step is usually difficult: +we cannot exhibit such a correspondence directly, due to our ignorance of +neurophysiology, so we usually have to look for indirect evidence, such as +qualitative similarities in patterns of response, measurements of timing, and +the like. This is one reason why cognitive science is currently in an undeveloped state. But as usual, the in-principle possibility of such explanation is +a straightforward consequence of the functional nature of psychological +concepts. +Unfortunately, the kind of functional explanation that works so well for +psychological states does not seem to work in explaining phenomenal states. + + Supervenience and Explanation + +47 + +The reason for this is straightforward. Whatever functional account of human +cognition we give, there is a further question: Why is this kind of functioning +accompanied by consciousness? No such further question arises for psychological states. If one asked about a given functional model of learning, "Why +is this functioning accompanied by learning?" the appropriate answer is a +semantic answer: "Because all it means to learn is to function like this." +There is no corresponding analysis of the concept of consciousness. Phenomenal states, unlike psychological states, are not defined by the causal roles +that they play. It follows that explaining how some causal role is played +is not sufficient to explain consciousness. After we have explained the performance of a given function, the fact that consciousness accompanies the +performance of the function (if indeed it does) remains quite unexplained. +One can put the point the following way. Given an appropriate functional +account of learning, it is simply logically impossible that something could +instantiate that account without learning (except perhaps insofar as learning +requires consciousness). However, no matter what functional account of +cognition one gives, it seems logically possible that that account could be +instantiated without any accompanying consciousness. It may be naturally +impossible—consciousness may in fact arise from that functional organization in the actual world—but the important thing is that the notion is logically coherent. +If this is indeed logically possible, then any functional and indeed any +physical account of mental phenomena will be fundamentally incomplete. +To use a phrase coined by Levine (1983), there is an explanatory gap between +such accounts and consciousness itself. Even if the appropriate functional +organization always gives rise to consciousness in practice, the question of +why it gives rise to consciousness remains unanswered. This point will be +developed at length later. +If this is so, it follows that there will be a partial explanatory gap for any +mental concept that has a phenomenal element. If conscious experience is +required for belief or learning, for example, we may not have a fully reductive explanation for belief or learning. But we at least have reason to believe +that the psychological aspects of these mental features—which are arguably +at the core of the relevant concepts—will be susceptible to reductive explanation in principle. If we leave worries about phenomenology aside, cognitive +science seems to have the resources to do a good job of explaining the mind. + +3. Logical Supervenience and Reductive Explanation +The epistemology of reductive explanation meets the metaphysics of supervenience in a straightforward way. A natural phenomenon is reductively +explainable in terms of some low-level properties precisely when it is logically + + 48 + +Foundations + +supervenient on those properties. It is reductively explainable in terms of +physical properties—or simply "reductively explainable"—when it is logically supervenient on the physical. +To put things more carefully: A natural phenomenon is reductively explainable in terms of some lower-level properties if the property of instantiating that phenomenon is globally logically supervenient on the low-level +properties in question. A phenomenon is reductively explainable simpliciter +if the property of instantiating that phenomenon is globally logically supervenient on physical properties. +This can be taken as an explication of the notion of reductive explanation, +with perhaps an element of stipulation. That our prior notion of reductive +explanation implies (global) logical supervenience should be clear from the +earlier discussion. If the property of exemplifying a phenomenon fails to +supervene logically on some lower-level properties, then given any lowerlevel account of those properties, there will always be a further unanswered +question: Why is this lower-level process accompanied by the phenomenon? +Reductive explanation requires some kind of analysis of the phenomenon +in question, where the low-level facts imply the realization of the analysis. +So reductive explanation requires a logical supervenience relation. For example, it is precisely because reproduction is logically supervenient on lowerlevel facts that it is reductively explainable in terms of those facts. +That logical supervenience suffices for reductive explainability is somewhat +less clear. If a phenomenon P supervenes logically on some lower-level +properties, then given an account of the lower-level facts associated with an +instance of P, the exemplification of P is a logical consequence. An account +of the lower-level facts will therefore automatically yield an explanation of +P. Nevertheless, such an explanation can sometimes seem unsatisfactory, for +two reasons. First, the lower-level facts might be a vast hotchpotch of arbitrary-seeming details without any clear explanatory unity. An account of all +the molecular motions underlying an instance of learning might be like this, +for example. Second, it is possible that different instances of P might be accompanied by very different sets of low-level facts, so that explanations of particular +instances do not yield an explanation of the phenomenon as a type. +One option is to hold that logical supervenience is merely necessary for +reductive explanation, rather than sufficient. This is all that is required for +my arguments about consciousness in the next chapter. But it is more useful +to note that there is a useful notion of reductive explanation such that logical +supervenience is both necessary and sufficient. Instead of taking the problems +above as indicating that the accounts in question are not explanations, we can +instead take them to indicate that a reductive explanation is not necessarily +an illuminating explanation. Rather, a reductive explanation is a mysteryremoving explanation. + + Supervenience and Explanation + +49 + +As I noted earlier, reductive explanation is not the be-all and end-all of +explanation. Its chief role is to remove any deep sense of mystery surrounding a high-level phenomenon. It does this by reducing the bruteness and +arbitrariness of the phenomenon in question to the bruteness and arbitrariness of lower-level processes. Insofar as the low-level processes may themselves be quite brute and arbitrary, a reductive explanation may not give us +a deep understanding of a phenomenon, but it at least eliminates any sense +that there is something "extra" going on. +The gap between a reductive explanation and an illuminating explanation +can generally be closed much further than this, however. This is due to +two basic facts about the physics of our world: autonomy and simplicity, +Microphysical causation and explanation seem to be autonomous, in that +every physical event has a physical explanation; the laws of physics are +sufficient to explain the events of physics on their own terms. Further, the +laws in question are reasonably simple, so that the explanations in question +have a certain compactness. Both of these things might have been otherwise. We might have lived in a world in which there were brutely emergent +fundamental laws governing the behavior of high-level configurations such +as organisms, with an associated downward causation that overrides any +relevant microphysical laws. (The British emergentists, such as Alexander +[1920] and Broad [1925], believed our world to be something like this.) +Alternatively, our world might have been a world in which the behavior of +microphysical entities is governed only by a vast array of baroque laws, or +perhaps a world in which microphysical behavior is lawless and chaotic. In +worlds like these, there would be little hope of achieving an illuminating +reductive explanation, as the bruteness of low-level accounts might never +be simplified. +But the actual world, with its low-level autonomy and simplicity, seems +to allow that sense can generally be made even of complex processes. The +low-level facts underlying a high-level phenomenon often have a basic unity +that allows for a comprehensible explanation. Given an instance of highlevel causation, such as a released trigger causing a gun to fire, we can not +only isolate a bundle of lower-level facts that fix this causation; we can also +tell a fairly simple story about how the causation is enabled, by encapsulating +those facts under certain simple principles. This may not always work. It +may be the case that some domains, such as those of sociology and economics, are so far removed from the simplicity of low-level processes that +illuminating reductive explanation is impossible, even if the phenomena are +logically supervenient. If so, then so be it: we can content ourselves with highlevel explanations of those domains, while noting that logical supervenience +implies that there is a reductive explanation in principle, although perhaps +one that only a superbeing could understand. + + 50 + +Foundations + +Note also that on this account reductive explanation is fundamentally +particular, accounting for particular instances of a phenomenon, without +necessarily accounting for all instances together. This is what we should +expect. If a property can be instantiated in many different ways, we cannot +expect a single explanation to cover all the instances. Temperature is instantiated quite differently in different media, for example, and there are different +explanations for each. At a much higher level, it is most unlikely that there +should be a single explanation covering all instances of murder. Still, there +is frequently a certain unity across the explanation of particulars, in that a +good explanation of one is often an explanation of many. This is again a +consequence of the underlying simplicity of our world, rather than a necessary property of explanation. In our world, the simple unifying stories that +one can tell about lower-level processes often apply across the board, or at +least across a wide range of particulars. It is also frequently the case, especially +in the biological sciences, that the particulars have a common ancestry that +leads to a similarity in the low-level processes involved. So the second problem mentioned, that of unifying the explanations of specific instances of a +phenomenon, is not as much of a problem as it might be. In any case, it is +the explanation of particulars that is central. +There is much more that could be said about closing the gap between +reductive explanation and illuminating explanation, but the matter deserves +a lengthy treatment in its own right and is not too important for my purposes. +What is most important is that if logical supervenience fails (as I will argue +it does for consciousness), then any kind of reductive explanation fails, even +if we are generous about what counts as explanation. Also important is that +logical supervenience removes any residual metaphysical mystery about a +high-level phenomenon, by reducing any brutality in that phenomenon to +brutality in lower-level facts. Of secondary importance is that if logical supervenience holds, then some sort of reductive explanation is possible. Although such explanations can fail to be illuminating or useful, this failure is +not nearly as fundamental as the failure of explanation in domains where +logical supervenience does not hold. +Further notes on reductive explanation +A few further notes: First, a practical reductive explanation of a phenomenon does not usually go all the way to the microphysical level. To do this +would be enormously difficult, giving rise to all the brutality problems just +discussed. Instead, high-level phenomena are explained in terms of some +properties at a slightly more basic level, as when reproduction is explained +in terms of cellular mechanisms, or the phases of the moon are explained +in terms of orbital motion. In turn, one hopes that the more basic phenomena + + Supervenience and Explanation + +51 + +will themselves be reductively explainable in terms of something more basic +still. If all goes well, biological phenomena may be explainable in terms of +cellular phenomena, which are explainable in terms of biochemical phenomena, which are explainable in terms of chemical phenomena, which are +explainable in terms of physical phenomena. As for the physical phenomena, +one tries to unify these as far as possible, but at some level physics has to +be taken as brute: there may be no explanation of why the fundamental laws +or boundary conditions are the way they are. This ladder of explanation is +little more than a pipe dream at the moment, but significant progress has +been made. Given logical supervenience, along with the simplicity and autonomy of the lowest level, this sort of explanatory connection between the +sciences ought to be possible in principle. Whether the complexities of reality +will make it practically infeasible is an open question. +Second, it is at least conceivable that a phenomenon might be reductively +explainable in terms of lower-level properties without being reductively +explainable simpliciter. This might happen in a situation where C-properties +are logically supervenient on B-properties, and are therefore explainable in +terms of B-properties, but where B-properties themselves are not logically +supervenient on the physical. There is clearly one sense in which such an +explanation is reductive and another sense in which it is not. For the most +part, I will be concerned with reductive explanation in terms of the physical, +or in terms of properties that are themselves explainable in terms of the +physical, and so on. Even if the C-properties here are reductively explainable +in a relative sense, their very existence implies the failure of reductive +explanation in general. +Third, local logical supervenience is too stringent a requirement for reductive explanation. One can reductively explain even context-dependent properties of an individual by giving an account of how relevant environmental +relations come to be satisfied. As long as a phenomenon is globally supervenient, it will be reductively explainable in terms of some lower-level facts, +even if these are spread widely in space and time. +Fourth, in principle there are two projects in reductive explanation of a +phenomenon such as life, learning, or heat. There is first a project of explication, where we clarify just what it is that needs to be explained, by means +of analysis. Learning might be analyzed as a certain kind of adaptational +process, for example. Second, there is a project of explanation, where we +see how that analysis comes to be satisfied by the low-level facts. The first +project is conceptual, and the second is empirical. For many or most phenomena, the conceptual stage will be quite trivial. For some phenomena, however, +such as belief, explication can be a major hurdle in itself. In practice, of +course, there is never a clean separation between the projects, as explication +and explanation take place in parallel. + + 52 + +Foundations + +4. Conceptual Truth and Necessary Truth* +In my account of supervenience and explanation, I have relied heavily on +the notions of logical possibility and necessity. It is now time to say something +more about this. The basic way to understand the logical necessity of a +statement is in terms of its truth across all logically possible worlds. This +requires some care in making sense of both the relevant class of worlds and +the way that statements are evaluated in worlds; I will discuss this at some +length later in this section. It is also possible to explicate the logical necessity +of a statement as truth in virtue of meaning: a statement is logically necessary +if its truth is ensured by the meaning of the concepts involved. But again, +this requires care in understanding just how the "meanings" should be +taken. I will discuss both of these ways of looking at things, and their relation, +later in this section. +(As before, the notion of logical necessity is not to be identified with a +narrow notion involving derivability in first-order logic, or some other syntactic formalism. Indeed, it is arguable that the justification of the axioms and +rules in these formalisms depends precisely on their logical necessity in the +broader, more primitive sense.) +All this requires taking seriously, at least to some extent, the notion of +conceptual truth—that is, the notion that some statements are true or false +simply by virtue of the meanings of the terms involved. Key elements of my +discussion so far have depended on characterizations of various concepts. I +have accounted for the reductive explanation of reproduction, for example, +by arguing that low-level details entail that certain functions are performed, +and that performance of these functions is all there is to the concept of +reproduction. +The notion of conceptual truth has had a bad name in some circles since +the critique by Quine (1951), who argued that there is no useful distinction +between conceptual truths and empirical truths. The objections to these notions usually cluster around the following points: +1. Most concepts do not have definitions giving necessary and sufficient +conditions (this observation has been made many times but is often +associated with Wittgenstein 1953). +2. Most apparent conceptual truths are in fact revisable, and could be +withdrawn in the face of sufficient empirical evidence (a point raised +by Quine). +3. Considerations about a posteriori necessity, outlined by Kripke +(1972), show that application-conditions of many terms across possible worlds cannot be known a priori. +These considerations count against an overly simplistic view of conceptual +truth, but not against the way I am using these notions. In particular, it turns + + Supervenience and Explanation + +53 + +out that the class of supervenience conditionals—"If the A-facts about a +situation are X, then the B-facts are Y," where the A-facts fully specify a +situation at a fundamental level—are unaffected by these considerations. +These are the only conceptual truths that my arguments need, and we will +see that none of the considerations above count against them. I will also +analyze the relationship between conceptual truth and necessary truth in +more detail, and spell out the role these play in understanding logical +supervenience. + +Definitions +The absence of cut-and-dried definitions is the least serious of the difficulties +with conceptual truth. None of my arguments depend on the existence of +such definitions. I occasionally rely on analyses of various notions, but these +analyses need only be rough and ready, without any pretense at providing +precise necessary and sufficient conditions. Most concepts (e.g., "life") are +somewhat vague in their application, and there is little point trying to remove +that vagueness by arbitrary precision. Instead of saying "A system is alive +if and only if it reproduces, adapts with utility 800 or greater, and metabolizes +with efficiency 75 percent, or exhibits these in a weighted combination with +such-and-such properties," we can simply note that if a system exhibits these +phenomena to a sufficient degree then it will be alive, by virtue of the +meaning of the term. If an account of relevant low-level facts fixes the facts +about a system's reproduction, utility, metabolism, and so on, then it also +fixes the facts about whether the system is alive, insofar as that matter is +factual at all. +We can sum this up with a schematic diagram (Figure 2.1) showing how +a high-level property P might depend on two low-level parameters A and +B, each of which can take on a range of values. If we had a crisp definition +in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions, then we would have something +like the picture at left, where the dark rectangle represents the region in +which property P is instantiated. Instead, the dependence is invariably something like the picture at right, where the boundaries are vague and there is +a large area in which the matter of P-hood is indeterminate, but there is +also an area in which the matter is clear. (It may be indeterminate whether +bacteria or computer viruses are alive, but there is no doubt that dogs are +alive.) Given an example in the determinate area, exemplifying A and B to +sufficient degrees that P is exemplified, the conditional "If x is A and B to +this degree, then x is P" is a conceptual truth, despite the lack of a clean +definition of P. Any indeterminacy in such conditionals, in the gray areas, +will reflect indeterminacy in the facts of the matter, which is as it should be. +The picture can straightforwardly be extended to dependence of a property + + 54 + +Foundations + +Figure 2,1. Two ways in which a property P might depend on properties A and B. + +on an arbitrary number of factors, and to supervenience conditionals in +general. +Importantly, then, one set of facts can entail another set without there +being a clean definition of the latter notions in terms of the former. The +above case provides an example: there is no simple definition of P in terms +of A and B, but the facts about A and B in an instance entail the facts about +P. For another example, think about the roundness of closed curves in twodimensional space (Figure 2.2). There is certainly no perfect definition of +roundness in terms of simpler mathematical notions. Nevertheless, take the +figure at left, specified by the equation 2x2 + 3y2 = 1. There is a fact of the +matter—this figure is round—insofar as there are ever facts about roundness +at all (compare to the figure at right, which is certainly not round). Further, +this fact is entailed by the basic description of the figure in mathematical +terms—given that description, and the concept of roundness, the fact that +the figure is round is determined. Given that A-facts can entail B-facts +without a definition of B-facts in terms of A-facts, the notion of logical +supervenience is unaffected by the absence of definitions. (In thinking about +more complex issues and objections concerning logical supervenience, it may +be worthwhile to keep this example in mind.) +We can put the point by saying that the sort of "meaning" of a concept +that is relevant in most cases is not a definition, but an intension: a function +specifying how the concept applies to different situations. Sometimes an +intension might be summarizable in a definition, but it need not be, as these +cases suggest. But as long as there is a fact of the matter about how concepts +apply in various situations, then we have an intension; and as I will discuss +shortly, this will generally be all the"meaning" that my arguments will need. + + Supervenience and Explanation + +Figure 2.2, + +55 + +The round curve 2x2 + 3y2 = I and nonround friend. + +Revisabitity +The second objection, raised by Quine (1951), is that purported conceptual +truths are always subject to revision in the face of sufficient empirical evidence. For instance, if evidence forces us to revise various background statements in a theory, it is possible that a statement that once appeared to be +conceptually true might turn out to be false. +This is so for many purported conceptual truths, but it does not apply to +the supervenience conditionals that we are considering, which have the form +"If the low-level facts turn out like this, then the high-level facts will be like +that." The facts specified in the antecedent of this conditional effectively +include all relevant empirical factors. Empirical evidence could show us that +the antecedent of the conditional is false, but not that the conditional is +false. In the extreme case, we can ensure that the antecedent gives a full +specification of the low-level facts about the world. The very comprehensiveness of the antecedent ensures that empirical evidence is irrelevant to the +conditional's truth-value. (This picture is somewhat complicated by the existence of a posteriori necessities, which I discuss shortly. Here, I am only +concerned with epistemic conditionals about ways the actual world might +turn out.) +While considerations about revisability provide a plausible argument that +there are not many short conceptual truths, nothing in these considerations +counts against the constrained, complex sort of conceptual truth that I have +been concerned with. The upshot of these observations is that the truthconditions of a high-level statement may not be easily localizable, as all sorts +of factors might have some kind of indirect relevance; but the global truth +conditions provided by a supervenience conditional are not threatened. Indeed, if meaning determines a function from possible worlds to reference +classes (an intension), and if possible worlds are finitely describable (in + + 56 + +Foundations + +terms of arrangement of basic qualities in those worlds, say), then there will +automatically be a vast class of conceptually true conditionals that result. +A posteriori necessity +It has traditionally been thought that all conceptual truths are knowable a +priori, as are all necessary truths, and that the classes of a priori truths, +necessary truths, and conceptual truths are closely related or even coextensive. Saul Kripke's book Naming and Necessity (1972) threw a wrench into +this picture by arguing that there is a large class of necessarily true statements +whose truth is not knowable a priori. An example is the statement "Water +is H2O." We cannot know this to be true a priori; for all we know (or for +all we knew at the beginning of inquiry), water is made out of something +else, perhaps XYZ. Kripke argues that nevertheless, given that water is H2O +in the actual world, then water is H2O in all possible worlds. It follows that +"Water is H2O" is a necessary truth despite its a posteriori nature. +This raises a few difficulties for the framework I have presented. For +example, on some accounts these necessary truths are conceptual truths, +implying that not all conceptual truths are knowable a priori. On alternative +accounts, such statements are not conceptual truths, but then the link between +conceptual truth and necessity is broken. At various points in this book, I +use a priori methods to gain insight into necessity; this is the sort of thing +that Kripke's account is often taken to challenge. +On analysis, I think it can be seen that these complications do not change +anything fundamental to my arguments; but it is worth taking the trouble to +get clear about what is going on. I will spend some time setting up a systematic framework for dealing with these issues, which will recur. In particular, I will present a natural way of capturing Kripke's insights in a twodimensional picture of meaning and necessity. This framework is a synthesis +of ideas suggested by Kripke, Putnam, Kaplan, Stalnaker, Lewis, Evans, +Davies and Humberstone, and others who have addressed these two-dimensional phenomena. +On the traditional view of reference, derived from Frege although cloaked +here in modern terminology, a concept determines a function f: W —> R +from possible worlds to referents. Such a function is often called an intension; +together with a specification of a world w, it determines an extension f(w). +In Frege's own view, every concept had a sense, which was supposed to +determine the reference of the concept depending on the state of the world; +so these senses correspond closely to intensions. The sense was often thought +of as the meaning of the concept in question. +More recent work has recognized that no single intension can do all the +work that a meaning needs to do. The picture developed by Kripke complicates things by noting that reference in the actual world and in counterfactual + + Supervenience and Explanation + +57 + +possible worlds is determined by quite different mechanisms. In a way, the +Kripkean picture can be seen to split the Fregean picture into two separate levels. +Kripke's insight can be expressed by saying that there are in fact two +intensions associated with a given concept. That is, there are two quite +distinct patterns of dependence of the referent of a concept on the state of +the world. First, there is the dependence by which reference is fixed in the +actual world, depending on how the world turns out: if it turns out one way, +a concept will pick out one thing, but if it turns out another way, the concept +will pick out something else. Second, there is the dependence by which +reference in counterfactual worlds is determined, given that reference in the +actual world is already fixed. Corresponding to each of these dependencies +is an intension, which I will call the primary and secondary intensions, +respectively. +The primary intension of a concept is a function from worlds to extensions +reflecting the way that actual-world reference is fixed. In a given world, it +picks out what the referent of the concept would be if that world turned out +to be actual. Take the concept "water." If the actual world turned out to +have XYZ in the oceans and lakes, then "water" would refer to XYZ,21 but +given that it turns out to have H2O in the oceans and lakes, "water" refers +to H2O. So the primary intension of "water" maps the XYZ world to XYZ, +and the H2O world to H2O. At a rough approximation, we might say that +the primary intension picks out the dominant clear, drinkable liquid in the +oceans and lakes; or more briefly, that it picks out the watery stuff in a world. +However, given that "water" turns out to refer to H2O in the actual world, +Kripke notes (as does Putnam [1975]) that it is reasonable to say that water +is H2O in every counterfactual world. The secondary intension of "water" +picks out the water in every counterfactual world; so if Kripke and Putnam +are correct, the secondary intension picks out H2O in all worlds.22 +It is the primary intension of a concept that is most central for my purposes: for a concept of a natural phenomenon, it is the primary intension +that captures what needs explaining. If someone says, "Explain water," long +before we know that water is in fact H2O, what they are asking for is more +or less an explanation of the clear, drinkable liquid in their environment. It +is only after the explanation is complete that we know that water is H2O. +The primary intension of a concept, unlike the secondary intension, is independent of empirical factors: the intension specifies how reference depends +on the way the external world turns out, so it does not itself depend on the +way the external world turns out. +Of course, any brief characterization of the primary intension of a concept +along the lines of "the dominant clear, drinkable liquid in the environment" +will be a simplification. The true intension can be determined only from +detailed consideration of specific scenarios: What would we say if the world + + 58 + +Foundations + +turned out this way? What would we say if it turned out that way? For +example, if it had turned out that the liquid in lakes was H2O and the liquid +in oceans XYZ, then we probably would have said that both were water; if +the stuff in oceans and lakes was a mixture of 95 percent A and 5 percent +B, we would probably have said that A but not B was water; if it turned out +that a substance neither clear nor drinkable bore an appropriate microphysical relation to the clear, drinkable liquid in our environment, we would +probably call that substance "water" too (as we do in the case of ice or of +"dirty water"). The full conditions for what it takes to qualify as "water" +will be quite vague at the edges and need not be immediately apparent on +reflection, but none of this makes much difference to the picture I am describing. I will use "watery stuff" as a term of art to encapsulate the primary intension, whatever it is.23 +In certain cases, the decision about what a concept refers to in the actual +world involves a large amount of reflection about what is the most reasonable thing to say; as, for example, with questions about the reference of +"mass" when the actual world turned out to be one in which the theory of +general relativity is true,24 or perhaps with questions about what qualifies as +"belief" in the actual world. So consideration of just what the primary +intension picks out in various actual-world candidates may involve a corresponding amount of reflection. But this is not to say that the matter is not a +priori: we have the ability to engage in this reasoning independently of how +the world turns out. Perhaps the reports of experiments confirming relativity +are disputed, so we are not sure whether the actual world has turned out to +be a relativistic world: either way, we have the ability to reason about what +"mass" will refer to if that state of affairs turns out to be actual. +(Various intricacies arise in analyzing the primary intensions of concepts +used by individuals within a linguistic community. These might be handled +by noting that an individual's concept may have a primary intension that +involves deference to a surrounding community's concept—so my concept +"elm" might pick out what those around me call "elms"; but in any case +this sort of problem is irrelevant to the issues I will be concerned with, for +which we might as well assume that there is just one person in the community, +or that all individuals are equally well informed, or even that the community +is a giant individual. There are also a few technical problems that might +come up in using primary intensions to build a general semantic theory—for +example, is the reference of a concept essential to the concept? Might different speakers associate different primary intensions with the same word? But +I am not trying to build a full semantic theory here, and we can abstract +away from this sort of concern. +Sometimes philosophers are suspicious of entities such as primary intensions because they see them as reminiscent of a "description" theory of +reference. But descriptions play no essential part in this framework; I use + + Supervenience and Explanation + +59 + +them merely to flesh out some of the character of the relevant functions +from possible worlds to extensions. It is the function itself, rather than any +summarizing description, that is truly central. This picture is quite compatible +with the "causal" theory of reference: we need simply note that the primary +intension of a concept such as "water" may require an appropriate causal +connection between the referent and the subject. Indeed, we are led to believe in a causal theory of reference in the first place precisely by considering +various ways the actual world might turn out, and noting what the referent +of the concept would turn out to be in those cases; that is, by evaluating the +primary intension of a concept at those worlds.) +Given that the actual-world reference of "water" is fixed by picking out +the watery stuff, one might think that water is watery stuff in all possible +worlds. Kripke and Putnam pointed out that this is not so: if water is H2O +in the actual world, then water is H2O in all possible worlds. In a world +(Putnam's "Twin Earth") in which the dominant clear, drinkable liquid is +XYZ rather than H2O, this liquid is not water; it is merely watery stuff. All +this is captured by the secondary intension of "water," which picks out the +water in all worlds: that is, it picks out H2O in all worlds. +The secondary intension of a concept such as "water" is not determined +a priori, as it depends on how things turn out in the actual world. But it still +has a close relation to the primary intension above. In this case, the secondary +intension is determined by first evaluating the primary intension at the actual +world, and then rigidifying this evaluation so that the same sort of thing is +picked out in all possible worlds. Given that the primary intension ("watery +stuff") picks out H2O in the actual world, it follows from rigidification that +the secondary intension picks out H2O in all possible worlds. +We can sum this up by saying "water" is conceptually equivalent to "dthat +(watery stuff)," where dthat is a version of Kaplan's rigidifying operator, +converting an intension into a rigid designator by evaluation at the actual +world (Kaplan 1979).The single Fregean intension has fragmented into two: +a primary intension ("watery stuff') that fixes reference in the actual world, +and a secondary intension ("H2O ") that picks out reference in counterfactual possible worlds, and which depends on how the actual world turned out. +(There is sometimes a tendency to suppose that a posteriori necessity +makes a priori conceptual analysis irrelevant, but this supposition is ungrounded. Before we even get to the point where rigid designation and the +like become relevant, there is a story to tell about what makes an actualworld X qualify as the referent of "A™ in the first place. This story can only +be told by an analysis of the primary intension. And this project is an a +priori enterprise, as it involves questions about what our concept would refer +to if the actual world turned out in various ways. Given that we have the +ability to know what our concepts refer to when we know how the actual +world turns out, then we have the ability to know what our concepts would + + 60 + +Foundations + +refer to if the actual world turned out in various ways. Whether or not the +actual world does turn out a certain way makes little difference in answering +this question, except in focusing our attention.) +Both the primary and secondary intensions can be seen as functions f: +W —> R from possible worlds to extensions, where the possible worlds in +question are seen in subtly different ways. We might say that the primary +intension picks out the referent of a concept in a world when it is considered +as actual—that is, when it is considered as a candidate for the actual world +of the thinker—whereas the secondary intension picks out the referent of a +concept in a world when it is considered as counterfactual, given that the actual +world of the thinker is already fixed. When the XYZ world is considered as +actual, my term "water" picks out XYZ in the world, but when it is considered as counterfactual, "water" picks out H2O. +The distinction between these two ways of looking at worlds corresponds +closely to Kaplan's (1989) distinction between the context of utterance of an +expression and the circumstances of evaluation. When we consider a world +w as counterfactual, we keep the actual world as the context of utterance, +but use w as a circumstance of evaluation. For example, if I utter "There is +water in the ocean" in this world and evaluate it in the XYZ world, "water" +refers to H2O and the statement is false. But when we consider w as actual, +we think of it as a potential context of utterance, and wonder how things +would be if the context of the expression turned out to be w. If the context +of my sentence "There is water in the ocean" turned out to be the XYZ +world, then the statement would be true when evaluated at that world. +The primary intension is therefore closely related to what Kaplan calls the +character of a term, although there are a few differences,25 and the secondary +intension corresponds to what he calls a term's content. +There is a slight asymmetry in that a context of utterance but not the +circumstance of evaluation is what Quine (1969) calls a centered possible +world. This is an ordered pair consisting of a world and a center representing +the viewpoint within that world of an agent using the term in question: the +center consists in (at least) a "marked" individual and time. (This suggestion +comes from Lewis 1979; Quine suggests that the center might be a point in +space-time.) Such a center is necessary to capture the fact that a term like +"water" picks out a different extension for me than for my twin on Twin +Earth, despite the fact that we live in the same universe.26 It is only our +position in the universe that differs, and it is this position that makes a +relevant difference to the reference-fixing process. +This phenomenon arises in an especially obvious way for indexical terms +such as "I", whose reference clearly depends on who is using the term and +not just on the overall state of the world: the primary intension of "I" picks +out the individual at the center of a centered world. (The secondary intension of my concept "I" picks out David Chalmers in all possible worlds.) + + Supervenience and Explanation + +61 + +There is a less overt indexical element in notions such as "water," however, +which can be roughly analyzed as "dthat(the dominant clear, drinkable liquid +in our environment)."27 It is this indexical element that requires primary +intensions to depend on centered worlds. Once actual-world reference is +fixed, however, no center is needed to evaluate reference in a counterfactual +world. The circumstance of evaluation can therefore be represented by a +simple possible world without a center. +All this can be formalized by noting that the full story about reference in +counterfactual worlds is not determined a priori by a singly indexed function +f: W -> R. Instead, reference in a counterfactual world depends both on +that world and on the way the actual world turns out. That is, a concept +determines a doubly indexed function + +where W* is the space of centered possible worlds, and W is the space of +ordinary possible worlds. The first parameter represents contexts of utterance, or ways the actual world might turn out, whereas the second parameter represents circumstances of evaluation, or counterfactual possible worlds. +Equivalently, a concept determines a family of functions + +for each v G W* representing a way the actual world might turn out, where +Fv(w) = F(v, w). For "water," if a is a world in which watery stuff is H2O, +then Fa picks out H2O in any possible world. Given that in our world water +did turn out to be H2O, this Fa specifies the correct application conditions +for "water" across counterfactual worlds. If our world had turned out to be +a different world b in which watery stuff was XYZ, then the relevant application conditions would have been specified by Fb ,a different intension which +picks out XYZ in any possible world. +The function F is determined a priori, as all a posteriori factors are included in its parameters. From F we can recover both of our singly indexed +intensions. The primary intension is the function f : W* -> R determined by +the "diagonal" mapping f : w -> F(w, w'), where w' is identical to w except that the center is removed. This is the function whereby reference in +the actual world is fixed. The secondary intension is the mapping Fa : w \—> +F(a, w), where a is our actual world. This intension picks out reference +in counterfactual worlds. An immediate consequence is that the primary +intension and secondary intension coincide in their application to the actual +world: f(a) = Fa(a'} = F(a, a'). +In the reverse direction, the doubly indexed function F and therefore the +secondary intension Fa can usually be derived from the primary intension f, + + 62 + +Foundations + +with the aid of a "rule" about how the secondary intension depends on the +primary intension and the actual world a. This rule depends on the type of +concept. For a concept that is a rigid designator, the rule is that in a world +w, the secondary intension picks out in w whatever the primary intension +picks out in a (or perhaps, for natural-kind terms, whatever has the same +underlying structure as what the primary intension picks out in a). More +formally, let D : R X W —> R be a "projection" operator that goes from +a class picked out in some world to members of "that" class in another +possible world. Then the secondary intension Fa is just the function D(f(a),-), +which we can think of as dthat applied to the intension given by /. +For other concepts, derivation of the secondary intension from the primary +intension will be easier. With "descriptive" expressions such as "doctor," +"square," and "watery stuff," rigid designation plays no special role: they +apply to counterfactual worlds independently of how the actual world turns +out. In these cases, the secondary intension is a simple copy of the primary +intension (except for differences due to centering). The framework I have +outlined can handle both sorts of concepts. +Property terms, such as "hot," can be represented in one of two ways in +an intensional framework. We can see the intension of a property as a +function from a world to a class of individuals (the individuals that instantiate +the property), or from a world to properties themselves. Either way of doing +things is compatible with the current framework: we can easily find a primary +and a secondary intension in either case, and it is easy to move back and +forth between the two frameworks. I will usually do things the first way, +however, so that the primary intension of "hot" picks out the entities that +qualify as "hot" things in the actual world, depending on how it turns out, +and the secondary intension picks out the hot things in a counterfactual +world, given that the actual world has turned out as it has. +Both the primary and the secondary intensions can be thought of as candidates for the "meaning" of a concept. I think there is no point choosing one +of these to qualify as the meaning; the term "meaning" here is largely an +honorific. We might as well think of the primary and secondary intensions +as the a priori and a posteriori aspects of meaning, respectively. +If we make this equation, both of these intensions will back a certain kind +of conceptual truth, or truth in virtue of meaning. The primary intension +backs a priori truths, such as "Water is watery stuff." Such a statement will +be true no matter how the actual world turns out, although it need not hold +in all nonactual possible worlds. The secondary intension does not back a +priori truths, but backs truths that hold in all counterfactual possible worlds, +such as "Water is H2O." Both varieties qualify as truths in virtue of meaning; +they are simply true in virtue of different aspects of meaning. + + Supervenience and Explanation + +63 + +It is also possible to see both as varieties of necessary truth. The latter +corresponds to the more standard construal of a necessary truth. The former, +however, can also be construed as truth across possible worlds, as long as +these possible worlds are construed as contexts of utterance, or as ways the +actual world might turn out. On this subtly different construal, a statement +S is necessarily true if no matter how the actual world turns out, it would +turn out that S was true. If the actual world turns out to be a world in which +watery stuff is XYZ, then my statement "XYZ is water" will turn out to be +true. So, according to this construal on which possible worlds are considered +as actual, "Water is watery stuff" is a necessary truth. +This kind of necessity is what Evans (1979) calls "deep necessity," as +opposed to "superficial" necessities like "Water is H2O." It is analyzed in +detail by Davies and Humberstone (1980) by means of a modal operator +they call "fixedly actually." Deep necessity, unlike superficial necessity, is +unaffected by a posteriori considerations. These two varieties of possibility +and necessity apply always to statements. There is only one relevant kind of +possibility of worlds; the two approaches differ on how the truth of a statement is evaluated in a world. +We can see this in a different way by noting that there are two sets of +truth conditions associated with any statement. If we evaluate the terms in +a statement according to their primary intensions, we arrive at the primary +truth conditions of the statement; that is, a set of centered possible worlds +in which the statement, evaluated according to the primary intensions of the +terms therein, turns out to be true. The primary truth conditions tell us how +the actual world has to be for an utterance of the statement to be true in +that world; that is, they specify those contexts in which the statement would +turn out to be true. For instance, the primary truth conditions of "Water is +wet" specify roughly that such an utterance will be true in the set of worlds +in which watery stuff is wet. +If instead we evaluate the terms involved according to their secondary +intensions, we arrive at the more familiar secondary truth conditions. These +conditions specify the truth-value of a statement in counterfactual worlds, +given that the actual world has turned out as it did. For instance, the secondary +truth conditions of "Water is wet" (uttered in this world) specifies those +worlds in which water is wet: so given that water is H2O, it specifies those +worlds in which H2O is wet. Note that there is no danger of an ambiguity +in actual-world truth: the primary and secondary truth conditions will always +specify the same truth-value when evaluated at the actual world. +If we see a proposition as a function from possible worlds to truth-values, +then these two sets of truth conditions yield two propositions associated with +any statement. Composing the primary intensions of the terms involved +yields a primary proposition, which holds in precisely those contexts of + + 64 + +Foundations + +utterance in which the statement would turn out to express a truth. (This is the +"diagonal proposition" of Stalnaker 1978. Strictly speaking, it is a centered +proposition, or a function from centered worlds to truth-values.) The secondary intensions yield a secondary proposition, which holds in those counterfactual circumstances in which the statement, as uttered in the actual world, +is true. The secondary proposition is Kaplan's "content" of an utterance +and is more commonly seen as the proposition expressed by a statement, +but the primary proposition is also central. +The two kinds of necessary truth of a statement correspond precisely to +the necessity of the two kinds of associated proposition. A statement is +necessarily true in the first (a priori) sense if the associated primary proposition holds in all centered possible worlds (that is, if the statement would +turn out to express a truth in any context of utterance). A statement is +necessarily true in the a posteriori sense if the associated secondary proposition holds in all possible worlds (that is, if the statement as uttered in the +actual world is true in all counterfactual worlds). The first corresponds to +Evans's deep necessity, and the second to the more familiar superficial +necessity. +To illustrate, take the statement "Water is H2O." The primary intensions +of "water" and "H2O" differ, so that we cannot know a priori that water is +H2O; the associated primary proposition is not necessary (it holds in those +centered worlds in which the watery stuff has a certain molecular structure). +Nevertheless, the secondary intensions coincide, so that "Water is H2O" +is true in all possible worlds when evaluated according to the secondary +intensions—that is, the associated secondary proposition is necessary. Kripkean a posteriori necessity arises just when the secondary intensions in a +statement back a necessary proposition, but the primary intensions do not. +Consider by contrast the statement "Water is watery stuff." Here the +associated primary intensions of "water" and "watery stuff' are the same, +so that we can know this statement to be true a priori, as long as we possess +the concepts. The associated primary proposition is necessary, so that this +statement is necessarily true in Evans's "deep" sense. However, the secondary intensions differ, as "water" is rigidified but "watery stuff is not: in a +world where XYZ is the clear, drinkable liquid, the secondary intension of +"watery stuff" picks out XYZ but that of "water" does not. The associated +secondary proposition is therefore not necessary, and the statement is not +a necessary truth in the more familiar sense; it is an example of Kripke's +"contingent a priori." +In general, many apparent "problems" that arise from these Kripkean +considerations are a consequence of trying to squeeze the doubly indexed +picture of reference into a single notion of meaning or of necessity. Such +problems can usually be dissolved by explicitly noting the two-dimensional + + Supervenience and Explanation + +65 + +character of reference, and by taking care to explicitly distinguish the notion +of meaning or of necessity that is in question.28 +It is also possible to use this two-dimensional framework to give an account +of the semantics of thought, as well as of language. I do this at much greater +length elsewhere (Chalmers 1994c). This aspect of the framework will not +be central here, but it is worth mentioning, as it will come up in one or two +minor places. The basic idea is very similar: given an individual's concept in +thought, we can assign a primary intension corresponding to what it will +pick out depending on how the actual world turns out, and a secondary intension corresponding to what it picks out in counterfactual worlds, given +that the actual world turns out as it has. Given a belief, we can assign a +primary proposition and a secondary proposition in a similar way (what I +elsewhere call the "notional" and "relational" content of the belief). +For example, concepts such as "Hesperus" and "Phosphorus" will have +different primary intensions (one picks out the evening star in a given centered world, the other picks out the morning star), but the same secondary +intensions (both pick out Venus in all worlds). The thought "Hesperus is +Phosphorus" will have a primary proposition true in all centered worlds in +which the evening star is the morning star: the fact that this thought is +informative rather than trivial corresponds to the fact that the primary proposition is contingent, as the primary intensions of the two terms differ. +The primary proposition, more than the secondary proposition, captures +how things seem from the point of view of the subject: it delivers the set of +centered worlds which the subject, in having the belief, is endorsing as +potential environments in which he or she might be living (in believing that +Hesperus is Phosphorus, I endorse all those centered worlds in which the +evening star and the morning star around the center are identical). It is also +fairly easy to argue that the primary proposition, rather than the secondary +proposition, governs the cognitive and rational relations between thoughts. +For this reason it is natural to think of the primary proposition as the cognitive content of a thought.29 +Logical necessity, conceptual truth, and conceivability +With this framework in hand, we can spell out the relationships among +logical necessity, conceptual truth, and conceivability. Starting with logical +necessity: this is just necessity as explicated above. A statement is logically +necessary if and only if it is true in all logically possible worlds. Of course +we have two varieties of logical necessity of statements, depending on +whether we evaluate truth in a possible world according to primary and +secondary intensions. We might call these varieties 1-necessity and 2-necessity, respectively. + + 66 + +Foundations + +This analysis explicates the logical necessity and possibility of a statement +in terms of (a) the logical possibility of worlds, and (b) the intensions determined by the terms involved in the statement. I have already discussed the +intensions. As for the notion of a logically possible world, this is something +of a primitive: as before, we can intuitively think of a logically possible +world as a world that God might have created (questions about God himself +aside). I will not engage the vexed question of the ontological status of these +worlds, but simply take them for granted as a tool, in the same way one +takes mathematics for granted.30 As for the extent of the class, the most +important feature is that every conceivable world is logically possible, a +matter on which I will say more in a moment. +As for conceptual truth, if we equate meaning with intension (primary or +secondary), it is easy to make the link between truth in virtue of meaning +and logical necessity. If a statement is logically necessary, its truth will be +an automatic byproduct of the intensions of the terms (and the compositional structure of the statement). We do not need to bring in the world in +any further role, as the intensions in question will be satisfied in every +possible world. Similarly, if a statement is true in virtue of its intensions, it +will be true in every possible world. +As before, there are two varieties of conceptual truth, depending on +whether we equate the "meanings" with primary or secondary intensions, +paralleling the two varieties of necessary truth. As long as one makes parallel +decisions in the two cases, a statement is conceptually true if and only if it +is necessarily true. "Water is watery stuff is conceptually true and necessarily +true in the first sense; and "Water is H2O" is conceptually true and necessarily true in the second. Only the first variety of conceptual truth will in +general be accessible a priori. The second variety will include many a posteriori truths, as the secondary intension depends on the way the actual world +turns out. +(I do not claim that intensions are the correct way to think of meanings. +Meaning is a many-faceted notion, and some of its facets may not be perfectly +reflected by intensions, so one could resist the equation of the two at least +in some cases.31 Rather, the equation of meaning and intension should here +be thought of as stipulative: if one makes the equation, then one can make +various useful connections. Not much rests on the use of the word "meaning." +In any case, truth in virtue of intension is the only sort of truth in virtue of +meaning that I will need.) +We can also make a link between the logical possibility of statements and +the conceivability of statements, if we are careful. Let us say that a statement +is conceivable (or conceivably true) if it is true in some conceivable world. +This should not be confused with other senses of "conceivable." For example, +there is a sense according to which a statement is conceivable if for all we +know it is true, or if we do not know that it is impossible. In this sense, both + + Supervenience and Explanation + +67 + +Goldbach's conjecture and its negation are conceivable. But the false member +of the pair will not qualify as conceivable in the sense I am using, as there +is no conceivable world in which it is true (it is false in every world). +On this view of conceivability, the conceivability of a statement involves +two things: first, the conceivability of a relevant world, and second, the truth +of the statement in that world.32 It follows that in making conceivability judgments, one has to make sure that one describes the world that +one is conceiving correctly, by properly evaluating the truth of a statement +in the world. One might at first glance think it is conceivable that Goldbach's conjecture is false, by conceiving of a world where mathematicians +announce it to be so; but if in fact Goldbach's conjecture is true, then one +is misdescribing this world; it is really a world in which the conjecture is true +and some mathematicians make a mistake. +In practice, to make a conceivability judgment, one need only consider a +conceivable situation—a small part of a world—and then make sure that one +is describing it correctly. If there is a conceivable situation in which a statement is true, there will obviously be a conceivable world in which the statement is true, so this method will give reasonable results while straining our +cognitive resources less than conceiving of an entire world! +Sometimes it is said that examples such as "Water is XYZ" show that +conceivability does not imply possibility, but I think the situation is subtler +than this. In effect, there are two varieties of conceivability, which we might +call 1-conceivability and 2-conceivability, depending on whether we evaluate +a statement in a conceivable world according to the primary or secondary +intensions of the terms involved. "Water is XYZ" is 1-conceivable, as there +is a conceivable world in which the statement (evaluated according to primary intensions) is true, but it is not 2-conceivable, as there is no conceivable +world in which the statement (evaluated according to secondary intension) +is true. These two sorts of conceivability precisely mirror the two sorts of +logical possibility mentioned previously. +Often, the conceivability of a statement is equated with 1-conceivability +(the sense in which "Water is XYZ" is conceivable), as it is this sort of +conceivability that is accessible a priori. And most often, the possibility of +a statement is equated with 2-possibility (the sense in which "Water is +XYZ" is impossible). Taken this way, conceivability does not imply possibility. But it remains the case that 1-conceivability implies 1-possibility, and +2-conceivability implies 2-possibility. One simply has to be careful not to +judge 1-conceivability when 2-possibility is relevant. That is, one has to be +careful not to describe the world that one is conceiving (the XYZ world, +say) according to primary intensions, when secondary intensions would be +more appropriate.33 +It follows from all this that the oft-cited distinction between "logical" and +"metaphysical" possibility stemming from the Kripkean cases—on which it + + 68 + +Foundations + +is held to be logically possible but not metaphysically possible that water is +XYZ—is not a distinction at the level of worlds, but at most a distinction +at the level of statements. A statement is "logically possible" in this sense +if it is true in some world when evaluated according to primary intensions; +a statement is "metaphysically possible" if it is true in some world when +evaluated according to secondary intensions. The relevant space of worlds +is the same in both cases.34 +Most importantly, none of the cases we have seen give reason to believe +that any conceivable worlds are impossible. Any worries about the gap +between conceivability and possibility apply at the level of statements, not +worlds: either we use a statement to misdescribe a conceived world (as in +the Kripkean case, and the second Goldbach case), or we claim that a +statement is conceivable without conceiving of a world at all (as in the first +Goldbach case). So there seems to be no reason to deny that conceivability +of a world implies possibility. I will henceforth take this for granted as a +claim about logical possibility; any variety of possibility for which conceivability does not imply possibility will then be a narrower class. Someone +might hold that there is a narrower variety of "metaphysically possible +worlds," but any reason for believing in such a class would have to be quite +independent of the standard reasons I have considered here. In any case, it +is logical possibility that is central to the issues about explanation. (A stronger +"metaphysical" modality might at best be relevant to issues about ontology, +materialism, and the like; I will discuss it when those issues become relevant +in Chapter 4.) +An implication in the other direction, from logical possibility to conceivability, is trickier in that limits on our cognitive capacity imply that there +are some possible situations that we cannot conceive, perhaps due to their +great complexity. However, if we understand conceivability as conceivability-in-principle—perhaps conceivability by a superbeing—then it is plausible +that logical possibility of a world implies conceivability of the world, and +therefore that logical possibility of a statement implies conceivability of the +statement (in the relevant sense). In any case, I will be more concerned with +the other implication. +If a statement is logically possible or necessary according to its primary +intension, the possibility or necessity is knowable a priori, at least in principle. Modality is not epistemically inaccessible: the possibility of a statement +is a function of the intensions involved and the space of possible worlds, +both of which are epistemically accessible in principle, and neither of which +is dependent on a posteriori facts in this case. So matters of 1-possibility and +1-conceivability are in principle accessible from the armchair. By contrast, +matters of 2-possibility and 2-conceivability will in many cases be accessible +only a posteriori, as facts about the external world may play a role in determining the secondary intensions. + + Supervenience and Explanation + +69 + +The class of 1-necessary truths corresponds directly to the class of a priori +truths. If a statement is true a priori, then it is true no matter how the actual +world turns out; that is, it is true in all worlds considered as actual, so it is +1-necessary. And conversely, if a statement is 1-necessary, then it will be +true no matter how the actual world turns out, so it will be true a priori. In +most such cases, the statement's truth will be knowable by us a priori; the +exceptions may be certain mathematical statements whose truth we cannot +determine, and certain statements that are so complex that we cannot comprehend them. Even in these cases, it seems reasonable to say that they are +knowable a priori at least in principle, although they are beyond our limited +cognitive capacity. (I will return to this matter when it becomes relevant +later.) +Logical necessity and logical supervenience +We obtain two slightly different notions of logical supervenience depending +on whether we use the primary or secondary brands of logical necessity. If +"gloop" has both a primary and a secondary intension associated with it, +then gloopiness may supervene logically on physical properties according to +either the primary or the secondary intension of "gloop". Supervenience +according to secondary intension—that is, supervenience with a posteriori +necessity as the relevant modality—corresponds to what some call "metaphysical supervenience," but we have now seen how this can be regarded +as a variety of logical supervenience. +(There is really only one kind of logical supervenience of properties, just +as there is only one kind of logical necessity of propositions. But we have +seen that terms or concepts effectively determine two properties, one via a +primary intension ["watery stuff'] and the other via a secondary intension +["H2O"]. So for a given concept ["water"], there are two ways in which +properties associated with that concept might supervene. I will sometimes +talk loosely of the primary and secondary intensions associated with a property, and of the two ways in which a property might supervene.) +I will discuss both the primary and secondary versions of logical supervenience in specific cases, but the former will be more central. Especially +when considering questions about explanation, primary intensions are more +important than secondary intensions. As noted before, we have only the +primary intension to work with at the start of inquiry, and it is this intension +that determines whether or not an explanation is satisfactory. To explain +water, for example, we have to explain things like its clarity, liquidity, and +so on. The secondary intension ("H2O") does not emerge until after an +explanation is complete, and therefore does not itself determine a criterion +for explanatory success. It is logical supervenience according to a primary +intension that determines whether reductive explanation is possible. Where + + 70 + +Foundations + +I do not specify otherwise, it is logical supervenience according to primary +intension that I will generally be discussing. +If we choose one sort of intension—say, the primary intension—and stick +with it, then we can see that various ways of formulating logical supervenience are equivalent. According to the definition given at the start of this +chapter, B-properties are logically supervenient on A-properties if for any +logically possible situation Y that is A-indiscernible from an actual situation +X, then all the B-facts true of X are true of Y. Or more simply, B-properties +are logically supervenient on A-properties if for any actual situation X, the +A-facts about Xentail the B-facts about X (where "P entails Q" is understood +as "It is logically impossible that P and not Q"). +Sticking to global supervenience, this means that B-properties supervene +logically on A-facts if the B-facts about the actual world are entailed by the +A-facts. Similarly, B-properties supervene logically on A-properties if there +is no conceivable world with the same A-properties as our world but different B-properties. We can also say that logical supervenience holds if, given +the totality of A-facts .A* and any B-fact B about our world W, "A*(W) —> +B(W)" is true in virtue of the meanings of the A-terms and the B-terms +(where meanings are understood as intensions). +Finally, if B-properties are logically supervenient on A-properties according to primary intensions, then the implication from A-facts to B-facts +will be a priori. So in principle, someone who knows all the A-facts about +an actual situation will be able to ascertain the B-facts about the situation +from those facts alone, given that they possess the B-concepts in question. +This sort of inference may be difficult or impossible in practice, due to the +complexity of the situations involved, but it is at least possible in principle. +For logical supervenience according to secondary intensions, B-facts about +a situation can also be ascertained from the A-facts in principle, but only a +posteriori. The A-facts will have to be supplemented with contingent facts +about the actual world, as those facts will play a role in determining the +B-intensions involved. +There are therefore at least three avenues to establishing claims of logical +supervenience: these involve conceivability, epistemology, and analysis. To +establish that B-properties logically supervene on A-properties, we can +(1) argue that instantiation of A-properties without instantiation of the Bproperties is inconceivable; (2) argue that someone in possession of the Afacts could come to know the B-facts (at least in cases of supervenience +via primary intension); or (3) analyze the intensions of the B-properties in +sufficient detail that it becomes clear that B-statements follow from Astatements in virtue of these intensions alone. The same goes for establishing +the failure of logical supervenience. I will use all three methods in arguing +for central claims involving logical supervenience. + + Supervenience and Explanation + +71 + +Not everybody may be convinced that the various formulations of logical +supervenience are equivalent, so when arguing for important conclusions +involving logical supervenience I will run versions of the arguments using +each of the different formulations. In this way it will be seen that the arguments are robust, with nothing depending on a subtle equivocation between +different notions of supervenience. + +5. Almost Everything is Logically Supervenient +on the Physical* +In the following chapter I will argue that conscious experience does not +supervene logically on the physical, and therefore cannot be reductively +explained. A frequent response is that conscious experience is not alone +here, and that all sorts of properties fail to supervene logically on the physical. It is suggested that such diverse properties as tablehood, life, and economic prosperity have no logical relationship to facts about atoms, electromagnetic fields, and so on. Surely those high-level facts could not be logically +entailed by the microphysical facts? +On a careful analysis, I think that it is not hard to see that this is wrong, +and that the high-level facts in question are (globally) logically supervenient +on the physical insofar as they are facts at all.35 Conscious experience is +almost unique in its failure to supervene logically. The relationship between +consciousness and the physical facts is different in kind from the standard +relationship between high-level and low-level facts. +There are various ways to make it clear that most properties supervene +logically on physical properties. Here I will only be concerned with properties that characterize natural phenomena—that is, contingent aspects of the +world that need explaining. The property of being an angel might not supervene logically on the physical, but angels are not something that we have +reason to believe in, so this failure need not concern us. I will also not +concern myself with facts about abstract entities such as mathematical entities +and propositions, which need to be treated separately.36 +It should be noted that in claiming that most high-level properties supervene on the physical, I am not suggesting that high-level facts and laws are +entailed by microphysical laws, or even by microphysical laws in conjunction +with microphysical boundary conditions. That would be a strong claim, and +although it might have some plausibility if qualified appropriately, the evidence is not yet in. I am making the much weaker claim that highlevel facts are entailed by all the microphysical facts (perhaps along with +microphysical laws). This enormously comprehensive set includes the facts + + 72 + +Foundations + +about the distribution of every last particle and field in every last corner of +space-time: from the atoms in Napoleon's hat to the electromagnetic fields +in the outer ring of Saturn. Fixing this set of facts leaves very little room +for anything else to vary, as we shall see. +Before moving to the arguments I should note some harmless reasons +why logical supervenience on the physical sometimes fails. First, some highlevel properties fail to supervene logically because of a dependence on conscious experience. Perhaps conscious experience is partly constitutive of a +property like love, for example. The primary (although not the secondary) +intensions associated with some external properties such as color and heat +may also be dependent on phenomenal qualities, as we will see. If so, then +love and perhaps heat do not supervene logically on the physical. These +should not be seen as providing counterexamples to my thesis, as they introduce no new failure of logical supervenience. Perhaps the best way to phrase +the claim is to say that all facts supervene logically on the combination of physical facts and phenomenal facts, or that all facts supervene +logically on the physical facts modulo conscious experience. Similarly, a +dependence on conscious experience may hinder the reductive explainability +of some high-level phenomena, but we can still say that they are reductively +explainable modulo conscious experience. +Second, an indexical element enters into the application of some primary +intensions, although not secondary intensions, as we saw earlier. The primary +intension of "water," for example, is something like "the clear, drinkable +liquid in our environment," so that if there is watery H2O and watery XYZ +in the actual universe, which of them qualifies as "water" depends on which +is in the environment of the agent using the term. In principle we therefore +need to add a center representing the location of an agent to the supervenience base in some cases. This yields logical supervenience and reductive +explanation modulo conscious experience and indexicality. +Finally, cases where the high-level facts are indeterminate do not count +against logical supervenience. The claim is only that insofar as the high-level +facts are determinate, they are determined by the physical facts. If the world +itself does not suffice to fix the high-level facts, we cannot expect the physical +facts to. Some might suggest that logical supervenience would fail if there +were two equally good high-level theories of the world that differed in their +description of the high-level facts. One theory might hold that a virus is +alive, for instance, whereas another might hold that it is not, so the facts about +life are not determined by the physical facts. This is not a counterexample, +however, but a case in which the facts about life are indeterminate. Given +indeterminacy, we are free to legislate the terms one way or the other where +it is convenient. If the facts are determinate—for example, if it is true that +viruses are alive—then one of the descriptions is simply wrong. Either way, + + Supervenienee and Explanation + +73 + +insofar as the facts about the situation are determinate at all, they are entailed +by the physical facts. +I will argue for the ubiquity of logical supervenience using arguments that +appeal to conceivability, to epistemological considerations, and to analysis +of the concepts involved. +Conceivability. The logical supervenience of most high-level facts is most +easily seen by using conceivability as a test for logical possibility. What kind +of world could be identical to ours in every last microphysical fact but be +biologically distinct? Say a wombat has had two children in our world. The +physical facts about our world will include facts about the distribution of +every particle in the spatiotemporal hunk corresponding to the wombat, and +its children, and their environments, and their evolutionary histories. If a +world shared those physical facts with ours, but was not a world in which +the wombat had two children, what could that difference consist in? Such a +world seems quite inconceivable. Once a possible world is fixed to have all +those physical facts the same, then the facts about wombathood and parenthood are automatically fixed. These biological facts are not the sort of thing +that can float free of their physical underpinnings even as a conceptual +possibility. +The same goes for architectural facts, astronomical facts, behavioral facts, +chemical facts, economic facts, meteorological facts, sociological facts, and +so on. A world physically identical to ours, but in which these sort of facts +differ, is inconceivable. In conceiving of a microphysically identical world, +we conceive of a world in which the location of every last particle throughout space and time is the same. It follows that the world will have the +same macroscopic structure as ours, and the same macroscopic dynamics. +Once all this is fixed there is simply no room for the facts in question to +vary (apart, perhaps, from any variation due to variations in conscious +experience). +Furthermore, this inconceivability does not seem to be due to any contingent limits in our cognitive capacity. Such a world is inconceivable in principle. +Even a superbeing, or God, could not imagine such a world. There is simply +not anything for them to imagine. Once they imagine a world with all the +physical facts, they have automatically imagined a world in which all the +high-level facts hold. A physically identical world in which the high-level +facts are false is therefore logically impossible, and the high-level properties +in question are logically supervenient on the physical. +Epistemology. Moving beyond conceivability intuitions, we can note that +if there were a possible world physically identical to ours but biologically +distinct, then this would raise radical epistemological problems. How would + + 74 + +Foundations + +we know that we were not in that world rather than this one? How would +we know that the biological facts in our world are as they are? To see this, +note that if I were in the alternative world, it would certainly look the same +as this one. It instantiates the same distribution of particles found in the +plants and animals in this world; indistinguishable patterns of photons are +reflected from those entities; no difference would be revealed under even +the closest examination. It follows that all the external evidence we possess +fails to distinguish the possibilities. Insofar as the biological facts about our +world are not logically supervenient, there is no way we can know those +facts on the basis of external evidence. +In actuality, however, there is no deep epistemological problem about +biology. We come to know biological facts about our world on the basis of +external evidence all the time, and there is no special skeptical problem that +arises. It follows that the biological facts are logically supervenient on the +physical. The same goes for facts about architecture, economics, and meteorology. There is no special skeptical problem about knowing these facts on +the basis of external evidence, so they must be logically supervenient on +the physical. +We can back up this point by noting that in areas where there are epistemological problems, there is an accompanying failure of logical supervenience, +and that conversely, in areas where logical supervenience fails, there are +accompanying epistemological problems. +Most obviously, there is an epistemological problem about consciousness—the problem of other minds. This problem arises because it seems +logically compatible with all the external evidence that beings around us are +conscious, and it is logically compatible that they are not. We have no way +to peek inside a dog's brain, for instance, and observe the presence or absence +of conscious experience. The status of this problem is controversial, but +the mere prima facie existence of the problem is sufficient to defeat an +epistemological argument, parallel to those above, for the logical supervenience of consciousness. By contrast, there is not even a prima facie problem of other biologies, or other economies. Those facts are straightforwardly +publically accessible, precisely because they are fixed by the physical facts. +(Question: Why doesn't a similar argument force us to the conclusion that +if conscious experience fails to supervene logically, then we can't know about +even our own consciousness? Answer: Because conscious experience is +at the very center of our epistemic universe. The skeptical problems about +nonsupervenient biological facts arise because we only have access to biological facts by external, physically mediated evidence; external nonsupervenient +facts would be out of our direct epistemic reach. There is no such problem +with our own consciousness.) +Another famous epistemological problem concerns facts about causation. +As Hume argued, external evidence only gives us access to regularities of + + Supervenience and Explanation + +75 + +succession between events; it does not give us access to any further fact of +causation. So if causation is construed as something over and above the +presence of a regularity (as I will assume it must be), it is not clear that we +can know that it exists. Once again, this skeptical problem goes hand in hand +with a failure of logical supervenience. In this case, facts about causation +fail to supervene logically on matters of particular physical fact. Given all +the facts about distribution of physical entities in space-time, it is logically +possible that all the regularities therein arose as a giant cosmic coincidence +without any real causation. At a smaller scale, given the particular facts +about any apparent instance of causation, it is logically possible that it is a +mere succession. We infer the existence of causation by a kind of inference +to the best explanation—to believe otherwise would be to believe in vast, +inexplicable coincidences—but belief in causation is not forced on us in the +direct way that belief in biology is forced on us. +I have sidestepped problems about the supervenience of causation by +stipulating that the supervenience base for our purposes includes not just +particular physical facts but all the physical laws. It is reasonable to suppose +that the addition of laws fixes the facts about causation. But of course there +is a skeptical problem about laws paralleling the problem about causation: +witness Hume's problem of induction, and the logical possibility that any +apparent law might be an accidental regularity. +As far as I can tell, these two problems exhaust the epistemological problems that arise from failure of logical supervenience on the physical. There +are some other epistemological problems that in a sense precede these, +because they concern the existence of the physical facts themselves. First, +there is Descartes's problem about the existence of the external world. It is +compatible with our experiential evidence that the world we think we are +seeing does not exist; perhaps we are hallucinating, or we are brains in vats. +This problem can be seen to arise precisely because the facts about the +external world do not supervene logically on the facts about our experience. +(Idealists, positivists, and others have argued controversially that they do. +Note that if these views are accepted the skeptical problem falls away.) +There is also an epistemological problem about the theoretical entities postulated by science—electrons, quarks, and such. Their absence would be logically compatible with the directly observable facts about objects in our +environment, and some have therefore raised skeptical doubts about them. +This problem can be analyzed as arising from the failure of theoretical facts +to supervene logically on observational facts. In both these cases, skeptical +doubts are perhaps best quelled by a form of inference to the best explanation, just as in the case of causation, but the in-principle possibility that we +are wrong remains. +In any case, I am bypassing this sort of skeptical problem by giving myself +the physical world for free, and fixing all physical facts about the world in + + 76 + +Foundations + +the supervenience base (thereby assuming that the external world exists, +and that there are electrons, and so on). Given that those facts are known, +there is no room for skeptical doubts about most high-level facts, precisely +because they are logically supervenient. To put the matter the other way +around: All our sources of external evidence supervene logically on the +microphysical facts, so that insofar as some phenomenon does not supervene +on those facts, external evidence can give us no reason to believe in it. +One might wonder whether some further phenomena might be posited via +inference to the best explanation, as above, to explain the microphysical +facts. Indeed, this process takes us from particular facts to simple underlying +laws (and hence yields causation), but then the process seems to stop. It is +in the nature of fundamental laws that they are the end of the explanatory +chain (except, perhaps, for theological speculation). This leaves phenomena +that we have internal evidence for—namely conscious experience—and that +is all. Modulo conscious experience, all phenomena are logically supervenient +on the physical. +We can also make an epistemological case for logical supervenience more +directly, by arguing that someone in possession of all the physical facts could +in principle come to know all the high-level facts, given that they possess +the high-level concepts involved. True, one could never in practice ascertain +the high-level facts from the set of microphysical facts. The vastness of the +latter set is enough to rule that out. (Even less am I suggesting that one +could perform a formal derivation; formal systems are irrelevant for reasons +canvased earlier.) But as an in-principle point, there are various ways to see +that someone (a superbeing?) armed with only the microphysical facts and +the concepts involved could infer the high-level facts. +The simplest way is to note that in principle one could build a big mental +simulation of the world and watch it in one's mind's eye, so to speak. Say +that a man is carrying an umbrella. From the associated microphysical facts, +one could straightforwardly infer facts about the distribution and chemical +composition of mass in the man's vicinity, giving a high-level structural +characterization of the area. One could determine the existence of a male +fleshy biped straightforwardly enough. For instance, from the structural information one could note that there was an organism atop two longish legs that +were responsible for its locomotion, that the creature has male anatomy, +and so on. It would be clear that he was carrying some device that was +preventing drops of water, otherwise prevalent in the neighborhood, from +hitting him. Doubts that this device is really an umbrella could be assuaged +by noting from its physical structure that it can fold and unfold; from its +history that it was hanging on a stand that morning, and was originally made +in a factory with others of a similar kind, and so on. Doubts that the fleshy +biped is really a human could be assuaged by noting the composition of his +DNA, his evolutionary history, his relation to other beings, and so on. We + + Supervenience and Explanation + +77 + +need only assume that the being possesses enough of the concept involved +to be able to apply it correctly to instances (that is, the being possesses the +intension). If so, then the microphysical facts will give it all the evidence it +needs to apply the concepts, and to determine that there really is a person +carrying an umbrella here. +The same goes for almost any sort of high-level phenomena: tables, life, +economic prosperity. By knowing all the low-level facts, a being in principle +can infer all the facts necessary to determine whether or not this is an instance of the property involved. Effectively, what is happening is that a +possible world compatible with the microphysical facts is constructed, and +the high-level facts are simply read off that world using the appropriate +intension (as the relevant facts are invariant across physically identical possible worlds). Hence the high-level facts are logically supervenient on the +physical. +Analyzability. So far, I have argued that microphysical facts fix high-level +facts without saying much explicitly about the high-level concepts involved. +In any specific case, however, this entailment relationship relies on a concept's intension. If microphysical facts entail a high-level fact, this is because +the microphysical facts suffice to fix those features of the world in virtue of +which the high-level intension applies. That is, we should be able to analyze +what it takes for an entity to satisfy the intension of a high-level concept, +at least to a sufficient extent that we can see why those conditions for +satisfaction could be satisfied by fixing the physical facts. It is therefore useful +to look more closely at the intensions of high-level concepts, and to examine +the features of the world in virtue of which they apply. +There are some obstacles to elucidating these intensions and to summarizing them in words. As we saw earlier, application conditions of a concept +are often indeterminate in places. Is a cup-shaped object made of tissues a +cup? Is a computer virus alive? Is a booklike entity that coagulates randomly +into existence a book? Our ordinary concepts do not give straightforward +answers to these questions. In a sense, it is a matter for stipulation. Hence +there will not be determinate application conditions for use in the entailment process. But as we saw earlier, this indeterminacy precisely mirrors an +indeterminacy about the facts themselves. Insofar as the intension of "cup" +is a matter for stipulation, the facts about cups are also a matter for stipulation. What counts for our purposes is that the intension together with the +microphysical facts determines the high-level facts insofar as they are really +factual. Vagueness and indeterminacy can make discussion awkward, but +they affect nothing important to the issues. +A related problem is that any short analysis of a concept will invariably +fail to do justice to it. As we have seen, concepts do not usually have crisp +definitions. At a first approximation, we can say something is a table if it + + 78 + +Foundations + +has a flat horizontal surface with legs as support; but this lets in too many +things (Frankenstein's monster on stilts?) and omits others (a table with no +legs, sticking out from a wall?). One can refine the definition, adding further +conditions and clauses, but we quickly hit the problems with indeterminacy, +and in any case the product will never be perfect. But there is no need to +go into all the details required to handle every special case: after a point +the details are just more of the same. As long as we know what sort of +properties the intension applies in virtue of, we will have enough to make +the point. +As we saw before, we do not need a definition of B-properties in terms +of A-properties in order for A-facts to entail B-facts. Meanings are fundamentally represented by intensions, not definitions. The role of analysis here +is simply to characterize the intensions in sufficient detail that the existence +of an entailment becomes clear. For this purpose, a rough-and-ready analysis +will suffice. Intensions generally apply to individuals in a possible world in +virtue of some of their properties and not others; the point of such an analysis +is to see what sort of properties the intension applies in virtue of, and to +make the case that properties of this sort are compatible with entailment by +physical properties. +A third problem stems from the division between the a priori and a +posteriori application conditions of many concepts. As long as we keep +primary and secondary intensions separate, however, this is not much of a +problem. The secondary intension associated with "water" is something like +"H2O," which is obviously logically supervenient on the physical. But the +primary intension, something like "the clear, drinkable liquid in our environment" is equally logically supervenient, as the clarity, drinkability, and liquidity of water is entailed by the physical facts.37 We can run things either +way. As we have seen, it is the primary intension that enters into reductive +explanation, so it is this that we are most concerned with. In general, if a +primary intension / is logically supervenient on the physical, then so is a +rigidified secondary intension dthat(I), as it will generally consist in a projection of some intrinsic physical structure across worlds. +Considerations about a posteriori necessity have led some to suppose that +there can be no logical entailment from low-level facts to high-level facts. +Typically one hears something like "Water is necessarily H2O, but that is +not a truth of meaning, so there is no conceptual relation." But this is a vast +oversimplification. For a start, the secondary intension "H2O" can be seen +as part of the meaning of "water" in some sense, and it certainly supervenes logically. But more importantly, the primary intension ("the clear, +drinkable liquid ...") which fixes reference also supervenes, perhaps modulo +experience and indexicality. It is precisely in virtue of its satisfying this +intension that we deemed that H2O was water in the first place. Given the +primary intension I, the high-level facts are derivable unproblematically + + Supervenience and Explanation + +79 + +from the microphysical facts (modulo the contribution of experience and +indexicality). The Kripkean observation that the concept is better represented as dthat(I) affects this derivability not at all. The semantic phenomenon of rigidification does not alone make an ontological difference. +With these obstacles out of the way, we can look at the intensions associated with various high-level concepts. In most cases these are characterizable +in functional or structural terms, or as a combination of the two. For example, +the sorts of things relevant to something's being a table include (1) that it +have a flat top and be supported by legs, and (2) that people use it to support +various objects. The first of these is a structural condition: that is, a condition +on the intrinsic physical structure of the object. The second is a functional +condition: that is, it concerns the external causal role of an entity, characterizing the way it interacts with other entities. Structural properties are clearly +entailed by microphysical facts. So are functional properties in general, although this is slightly less straightforward. Such properties depend on a +much wider supervenience base of microphysical facts, so that facts about +an object's environment will often be relevant; and insofar as such properties +are characterized dispositionally (something is soluble if it would dissolve if +immersed in water), one needs to appeal to counterfactuals. But the truthvalues of those counterfactuals are fixed by the inclusion of physical laws in +the antecedent of our supervenience conditionals, so this is not a problem. +To take another example, the conditions on life roughly come down to +some combination of the ability to reproduce, to adapt, and to metabolize, +among other things (as usual, we need not legislate the weights, or all other +relevant factors). These properties are all characterizable functionally, in +terms of an entity's relation to other entities, its ability to convert external +resources to energy, and its ability to react appropriately to its environment. +These functional properties are all derivable, in principle, from the physical +facts. As usual, even if there is no perfect definition of life in functional +terms, this sort of characterization shows us that life is a functional property, +whose instantiation can therefore be entailed by physical facts. +A complication is raised by the fact that functional properties are often +characterized in terms of a causal role relative to other high-level entities. +It follows that logical supervenience of the properties depends on the logical +supervenience of the other high-level notions involved, where these notions +may themselves be characterized functionally. This is ultimately not a problem, as long as causal roles are eventually cashed out by nonfunctional +properties: typically either by structural or phenomenal properties. There +may be some circularity in the interdefinability of various functional properties—-perhaps it is partly constitutive of a stapler that it deliver staples, +and partly constitutive of staples that they are delivered by staplers. This +circularity can be handled by cashing out the causal roles of all the properties simultaneously,38 as long as the analyses have a noncircular part that is + + 80 + +Foundations + +ultimately grounded in structural or phenomenal properties. (The appeal to +phenomenal properties may seem to count against logical supervenience +on the physical, but see below. In any case, it is compatible with logical +supervenience modulo conscious experience.) +Many properties are characterized relationally, in terms of relations to an +entity's environment. Usually such relations are causal, so that the properties +in question are functional, but this is not always so: witness the property of +being on the same continent as a duck. Similarly, some properties are dependent on history (although these can usually be construed causally); to be a +kangaroo, a creature must have appropriate ancestors. In any case these +properties pose no problems for logical supervenience, as the relevant historical and environmental facts will themselves be fixed by the global physical +facts. +Even a complex social fact such as "There was economic prosperity in +the 1950s"39 is characterizable in mostly functional terms, and so can be seen +to be entailed by the physical facts. A full analysis would be very complicated +and would be made difficult by the vagueness of the notion of prosperity, +but to get an idea how it might go, one can ask why we say that there was +economic prosperity in the 1950s? At a first approximation, because there +was high employment, people were able to purchase unusually large amounts +of goods, there was low inflation, much development in housing, and so on. +We can in turn give rough-and-ready analyses of the notion of housing (the +kind of place people sleep and eat in), of employment (organized labor +for reward), and of monetary notions (presumably money will be roughly +analyzable in terms of the systematic ability to exchange for other items, +and its value will be analyzable in terms of how much one gets in exchange). +All these analyses are ridiculously oversimplified, but the point is clear +enough. These are generally functional properties that can be entailed by +physical facts. +Many have been skeptical of the possibility of conceptual analysis. Often +this has been for reasons that do not make any difference to the arguments +I am making—because of indeterminacy in our concepts, for example, or +because they lack crisp definitions. Sometimes this skepticism may have +arisen for deeper reasons. Nevertheless, if what I have said earlier in this +chapter is correct, and if the physical facts about a possible world fix the +high-level facts, we should expect to be able to analyze the intension of the +high-level concept in question, at least to a good approximation, in order +to see how its application can be determined by physical facts. This is +what I have tried to do in the examples given here. Other examples can be +treated similarly.40 +I am not advocating a program of performing such analyses in general. +Concepts are too complex and unruly for this to do much good, and any +explicit analysis is usually a pale shadow of the real thing. What counts is + + Supervenience and Explanation + +81 + +the general point that most high-level concepts are not primitive, unanalyzable notions. They are generally analyzable to the extent that their intensions can be seen to specify functional or structural properties. It is in virtue +of this analyzability that high-level facts are in principle derivable from +microphysical facts and reductively explainable in terms of physical facts. + +Some problem cases +There are some types of properties that might be thought to provide particular difficulties for logical supervenience, and therefore for reductive explanation. I will examine a number of such candidates, paying particular attention +to the question of whether the associated phenomena pose problems for +reductive explanation analogous to the problems posed by consciousness. It +seems to me that with a couple of possible exceptions, no significant new +problems arise here. +Consciousness-dependent properties. As discussed already, some concepts' +primary intensions involve a relation to conscious experience. An obvious +example is redness, taken as a property of external objects. On at least some +accounts, the primary intension associated with redness requires that for +something to be red, it must be the kind of thing that tends to cause red +experiences under appropriate conditions.41 So in its primary intension, redness is not logically supervenient on the physical, although it supervenes +modulo conscious experience. On the other hand, its secondary intension +almost certainly supervenes. If it turns out that in the actual world, the sort +of thing that tends to cause red experience is a certain surface reflectance, +then objects with that reflectance are red even in worlds in which there is +no conscious being to see them. Redness is identified a posteriori with that +reflectance, which is logically supervenient on the physical alone. +We saw earlier that failure of a primary intension to supervene logically +is associated with a failure of reductive explanation. So, does reductive +explanation fail for redness? The answer is yes, in a weak sense. If redness +is construed as the tendency to cause red experiences, then insofar as experience is not reductively explainable, neither is redness. But one can come +close. One can note that a certain physical quality causes red experiences; +and one can even explain the causal relation between the quality and redjudgments. It is just the final step to experience that goes unexplained. In +practice, our strictures on explanation are weak enough that this sort of +thing counts. To explain a phenomenon to which reference is fixed by some +experience, we do not require an explanation of experience. Otherwise we +would wait a long time. +The same goes for phenomena such as heat, light, and sound. Although +their secondary intensions determine structural properties (molecular mo- + + 82 + +Foundations + +tion, the presence of photons, waves in air), their primary intensions involve a relation to conscious experience: heat is the thing that causes heat +sensations, light causes visual experiences, and so on. But as Nagel (1974) +and Searle (1992) have noted, we do not require an explanation of heat +sensations when explaining heat. Explanation modulo experience is good +enough. +Other properties depend even more directly on conscious experience, in +that experience not only plays a role in reference fixation but is partly +constitutive of the a posteriori notion as well. The property of standing next +to a conscious person is an obvious example. On some accounts, mental +properties such as love and belief, although not themselves phenomenal +properties, have a conceptual dependence on the existence of conscious +experience. If so, then in a world without consciousness, such properties +would not be exemplified. Such properties therefore are not logically supervenient even a posteriori, and reductive explanation fails even more strongly +than in the above cases. But they are logically supervenient and reductively +explainable modulo conscious experience, so no further failure of reductive +explanation arises here. +Intentionality. It is worth separately considering the status of intentionality, as this is sometimes thought to pose problems analogous to those posed +by consciousness. It is plausible, however, that any failure of intentional +properties to supervene logically is derivative on the nonsupervenience of +consciousness. As I noted in Chapter 1, there seems to be no conceivable +world that is physically and phenomenally identical to ours, but in which +intentional contents differ.42 If phenomenology is partly constitutive of intentional content, as some philosophers suggest, then intentional properties may +fail to supervene logically on the physical, but they will supervene modulo +conscious experience. The claim that consciousness is partly constitutive of +content is controversial, but in any case there is little reason to believe that +intentionality fails to supervene in a separate, nonderivative way. +Leaving any phenomenological aspects aside, intentional properties are +best seen as a kind of third-person construct in the explanation of human +behavior, and should therefore be analyzable in terms of causal connections to behavior and the environment. If so, then intentional properties are +straightforwardly logically supervenient on the physical. Lewis (1974) makes +a thorough attempt at explicating the entailment from physical facts to +intentional facts by giving an appropriate functional analysis. More recent +accounts of intentionality, such as those by Dennett (1987), Dretske (1981), +and Fodor (1987) can be seen as contributing to the same project. None of +these analyses are entirely compelling, but it may be that a more sophisticated +descendant might do the job. There is no argument analogous to the arguments against the supervenience of consciousness showing that intentionality + + Supervenience and Explanation + +83 + +cannot supervene logically on physical and phenomenal properties.43 Indeed, +conceivability arguments indicate that intentional properties must be logically supervenient on these if such properties are instantiated at all, and +epistemological arguments lead us to a similar conclusion. So there is no +separate ontological problem of intentionality. +Moral and aesthetic properties. It is often held that there is no conceptual +connection from physical properties to moral and aesthetic properties. According to Moore (1922), nothing about the meaning of notions such as +"goodness" allows that facts about goodness should be entailed by physical +facts. In fact, Moore claimed that there is no conceptual connection from +natural facts to moral facts, where the natural may include the mental as +well as the physical (so supervenience modulo conscious experience does +not help here). Does this mean that moral properties are as problematic as +conscious experience? +There are two disanalogies, however. First, there does not seem to be a +conceivable world that is naturally identical to ours but morally distinct, so +it is unlikely that moral facts are further facts in any strong sense. Second, +moral facts are not phenomena that force themselves on us. When it comes +to the crunch, we can deny that moral facts exist at all. Indeed, this reflects +the strategy taken by moral antirealists such as Blackburn (1971) and Hare +(1984). These antirealists argue that because moral facts are not entailed +by natural facts and are not plausibly "queer" further facts, they have no +objective existence and morality should be relativized into a construct or +projection of our cognitive apparatus. The same strategy cannot be taken +for phenomenal properties, whose existence is forced upon us. +For moral properties, there are at least two reasonable alternatives available. The first is antirealism of some sort, perhaps relativizing "objective +moral facts" into "subjective moral facts,"44 or embracing a view on which +moral discourse does not state facts at all. The second is to claim that there +is an a priori connection from natural facts to moral facts, one that (contra Moore) can be seen to hold in virtue of an analysis and explication of +moral concepts. If a concept such as "good" determines a stable nonindexical +primary intension, then the second position follows: we will have an a priori +function from naturally specified worlds to moral facts. If it only determines +an indexical primary intension, or if different subjects can equally reasonably +associate different primary intensions with the concept, or if it determines +no primary intension at all, then a version of the first position will follow. +Some other positions are sometimes taken, but none seem tenable. Moore +held that there is a nonconceptual a priori connection between natural and +moral facts that we obtain through a mysterious faculty of "moral intuition," +but this view is widely rejected (it is hard to see what could ground such +intuitions' truth or falsity). A position on which moral properties supervene + + 84 + +Foundations + +by a fundamental nomic link seems out of the question, as there is no +conceivable world in which the natural facts are the same as ours but in +which the moral facts are different. A popular position among contemporary +moral realists (see, e.g., Boyd 1988; Brink 1989) is that moral facts supervene +on natural facts with a posteriori necessity; that is, they supervene according +to the secondary but not the primary intensions of moral concepts. This +position is difficult to maintain, however, given that even a posteriori equivalences must be grounded in a priori reference fixation. Even though it is +a posteriori that water is H2O, the facts about water follow from the microphysical facts a priori. Similarly, if moral concepts have a primary intension +and if naturally identical centered worlds are morally identical, an a priori +link from natural facts to moral facts would seem to follow. (Horgan and +Timmons [1992a; 1992b] provide a critique along these lines.) +Aesthetic properties can be treated in a similar way. If anything, an antirealist treatment is even more plausible here. In the final analysis, although +there are interesting conceptual questions about how the moral and aesthetic domains should be treated, they do not pose metaphysical and explanatory problems comparable to those posed by conscious experience. +Names. On many accounts (e.g., Kaplan 1989), there is no analysis associated with a name such as "Rolf Harris," which simply picks out its referent +directly. Does this mean that the property of being Rolf Harris fails to +supervene logically on the physical? There is no problem about the supervenience of the secondary intension (e.g., Rolf might be the person conceived +from a given sperm and egg in all possible worlds), but the absence of a +primary intension might be thought to pose problems for reductive explanation. Still, it is plausible that even though there is no primary intension that +is shared across the community, every individual use of the name has a +primary intension attached. When I use the name "Rolf Harris," there is +some systematic way in which its referent depends on the way the world +turns out; for me, the primary intension might be something like "the man +called 'Rolf Harris' who bangs around on paint cans, and who bears the +appropriate causal relation to me."45 Such an intension will supervene logically. Rather than justifying this in detail, however, it is easier to note that +any failure of logical supervenience will not be accompanied by an explanatory mystery. The property of being Rolf Harris does not constitute a phenomenon in need of explanation, as opposed to explication. What needs +explaining is the existence of a person named "Rolf Harris" who bangs +around on paint cans, and so on. These properties certainly supervene, and +are explainable in principle in the usual way. +Indexicals. Reference fixation of many concepts, from "water" to "my +dog," involves an indexical element. The reference of these notions is fixed + + Supervenience and Explanation + +85 + +on the basis of both physical facts and an agent-relative "indexical fact" +representing the location of an agent using the term in question. Such a fact +is determinate for any given agent, so reference fixation is determinate. +Supervenience and explanation succeed modulo that indexical fact. +Does indexicality pose a problem for reductive explanation? For arbitrary +speakers, perhaps not, as the "fact" in question can be relativized away. But +for myself, it is not so easy. The indexical fact expresses something very +salient about the world as I find it: that David Chalmers is me. How could +one explain this seemingly brute fact? Indeed, is there really a fact here to +be explained, as opposed to a tautology? The issue is extraordinarily difficult to get a grip on, but it seems to me that even if the indexical is not +an objective fact about the world, it is a fact about the world as I find it, +and it is the world as I find it that needs explanation. The nature of the +brute indexical is quite obscure, though, and it is most unclear how one +might explain it.46 (Of course, we can give a reductive explanation of why +David Chalmers's utterance of "I am David Chalmers" is true. But this +nonindexical fact seems quite different from the indexical fact that I am +David Chalmers.) +It is tempting to look to consciousness. But while an explanation of consciousness might yield an explanation of "points of view" in general, it is +hard to see how it could explain why a seemingly arbitrary one of those +points of view is mine, unless solipsism is true. The indexical fact may have +to be taken as primitive. If so, then we have a failure of reductive explanation distinct from and analogous to the failure with consciousness. Still, the +failure is less worrying than that with consciousness, as the unexplained fact +is so "thin" by comparison to the facts about consciousness in all its glory. +Admitting this primitive indexical fact would require far less revision of our +materialist worldview than would admitting irreducible facts about conscious experience. +Negative facts. As we saw earlier, certain facts involving negative existentials and universal quantifiers are not logically determined by the physical +facts, or indeed by any set of localized facts. Consider the following facts +about our world: there are no angels; Don Bradman is the greatest cricketer; +everything alive is based on DNA. All these could be falsified, consistently +with all the physical facts about our world, simply by the addition of some +new nonphysical stuff: cricket-playing angels made of ectoplasm, for instance. +Even addition of facts about conscious experience or indexicality cannot +help here.47 +Does this mean that these facts are not reductively explainable? It seems +so, insofar as there is no physical explanation of why there is no extra +nonphysical stuff in our world. That is indeed a further fact. The best way +to deal with this situation is to introduce a second-order fact that says of + + 86 + +Foundations + +the set of basic particular facts, be they microphysical, phenomenal, indexical, or whatever: That's all This fact says that all the particular facts about +the world are included in or entailed by the given set of facts. From this +second-order fact, in conjunction with all the basic particular facts, all the +negative facts will follow. +This does not constitute a very serious failure of reductive explanation. +Presumably there will be such a "That's all" fact true of any world, and +such a fact will never be entailed by the particular facts. It simply expresses +the bounded nature of our world, or of any world. It is a cheap way to bring +all the negative existential and universally quantified facts within our +grasp. +Physical laws and causation. On the most plausible accounts of physical +laws, these are not logically supervenient on the physical facts, taken as a +collection of particular facts about a world's spatiotemporal history. One +can see this by noting the logical possibility of a world physically indiscernible from ours over its entire spatiotemporal history, but with different laws. +For example, it might be a law of that world that whenever two hundred +tons of pure gold are assembled in a vacuum, it will transmute into lead. +Otherwise its laws are identical, with minor modifications where necessary. +As it happens, in the spatiotemporal history of our world, two hundred tons +of gold are never assembled in a vacuum. It follows that our world and the +other world have identical histories, but their laws differ nevertheless. +Arguments like this suggest that the laws of nature do not supervene +logically on the collection of particular physical facts.48 By similar arguments +one can see that a causal connection between two events is something over +and above a regularity between the events. Holders of various Humean +views dispute these conclusions, but it seems to me that they have the worse +of the arguments here.49 There is something irreducible in the existence of +laws and causation. +I have bypassed these problems elsewhere by including physical laws in +the supervenience base, but this steps over the metaphysical puzzle rather +than answering it. It is true that laws and causation lead to less significant +failure of reductive explanation than consciousness. The laws and causal relations are themselves posited to explain existing physical phenomena, +namely the manifold regularities present in nature, whereas consciousness +is a brute explanandum. Nevertheless the very existence of such irreducible +further facts raises deep questions about their metaphysical nature. Apart +from conscious experience and perhaps indexicality, these constitute the only +such further facts in which we have any reason to believe. It is not unnatural +to speculate that these two nonsupervenient kinds, consciousness and causation, may have a close metaphysical relation. + + Supervenience and Explanation + +87 + +Recap +The position we are left with is that almost all facts supervene logically on +the physical facts (including physical laws), with possible exceptions for +conscious experience, indexicality, and negative existential facts. To put the +matter differently, we can say that the facts about the world are exhausted +by (1) particular physical facts, (2) facts about conscious experience, (3) laws +of nature, (4) a second-order "That's all" fact, and perhaps (5) an indexical +fact about my location. (The last two are minor compared to the others, and +the status of the last is dubious, but I include them for completeness.) Modulo +conscious experience and indexicality, it seems that all positive facts are +logically supervenient on the physical. To establish this conclusively would +require a more detailed examination of all kinds of phenomena, but what +we have seen suggests that the conclusion is reasonable. We can sum up +the ontological and epistemological situations with a couple of fables. Perhaps there is a grain of truth in the shape of these stories, if not in the +details. +Creation myth. Creating the world, all God had to do was fix the facts +just mentioned. For maximum economy of effort, he first fixed the laws +of nature—the laws of physics, and any laws relating physics to conscious +experience. Next, he fixed the boundary conditions: perhaps a time-slice of +physical facts, and maybe the values in a random-number generator. These +combined with the laws to fix the remaining physical and phenomenal facts. +Last, he decreed, "That's all." +Epistemological myth. At first, I have only facts about my conscious +experience. From here, I infer facts about middle-sized objects in the world, +and eventually microphysical facts. From regularities in these facts, I infer +physical laws, and therefore further physical facts. From regularities between +my conscious experience and physical facts, I infer psychophysical laws, and +therefore facts about conscious experience in others. I seem to have taken +the abductive process as far as it can go, so I hypothesize: that's all. The +world is much larger than it once seemed, so I single out the original conscious +experiences as mine. +Note the very different order involved from the two perspectives. One +could almost say that epistemology recapitulates ontology backward. Note +also that it seems beyond God's powers to fix my indexical fact. Perhaps +this is another reason to be skeptical about it. +The logical supervenience of most high-level phenomena is a conclusion that +has not been as widely accepted as it might have been, even among those +who discuss supervenience. Although the matter is often not discussed, many +have been wary about invoking the conceptual modality as relevant to super- + + 88 + +Foundations + +venience relations. As far as I can tell there have been a number of separate +reasons for this hesitation, none of which are ultimately compelling. +First, the problem with logically possible physically identical worlds with +extra nonphysical stuff (angels, ectoplasm) has led some to suppose that +supervenience relations cannot be logical (Haugeland 1982; Petrie 1987); +but we have seen how to fix this problem. Second, many have supposed that +considerations about a posteriori necessity demonstrate that supervenience +relations cannot be underwritten by meanings (Brink 1989; Teller 1984); but +we have seen that supervenience relations based on a posteriori necessity +can be seen as a variety of logical supervenience. Third, there is a general +skepticism about the notion of conceptual truth, deriving from Quine; but +we have seen that this is a red herring here. Fourth, worries about "reducibility" have led some to suppose that supervenience is not generally a conceptual relation (Hellman and Thompson 1975); but it is unclear that there +are any good arguments against reducibility that are also good arguments +against logical supervenience. Fifth, the very phenomenon of conscious experience is sometimes invoked to demonstrate that supervenience relations +cannot be logical in general (Seager 1988); but we have seen that conscious +experience is almost unique in its failure to supervene logically. Finally, the +claim that supervenience relations are not generally logical is often stated +without argument, presumably as something that any reasonable person must +believe (Bacon 1986; Heil 1992).50 +It is plausible that every supervenience relation of a high-level property +upon the physical is ultimately either (1) a logical supervenience relation of +either the primary or secondary variety, or (2) a contingent natural supervenience relation. If neither of these holds for some apparent supervenience +relation, then we have good reason to believe that there are no objective +high-level facts of the kind in question (as, perhaps, for moral facts). I will +argue further in Chapter 4 that there is no deep variety of supervenience +intermediate between the logical and the natural. +This provides a unified explanatory picture, in principle. Almost every +phenomenon is reductively explainable, in the weak sense outlined earlier, +except for conscious experience and perhaps indexicality, along with the +rock-bottom microphysical facts and laws, which have to be taken as +fundamental. +It is worth taking a moment to answer a query posed by Blackburn (1985) +and Horgan (1993); How do we explain the supervenience relations themselves? For a logical supervenience relation based on the primary intension +of a concept, this is a simple matter of giving an appropriate analysis of the +concept, perhaps in functional or structural terms, and noting that its reference is invariant across physically identical worlds. Here, the supervenience +conditional is itself an a priori conceptual truth. For a logical supervenience +relation based on a secondary intension, the supervenience can be explained + + Supervenience and Explanation + +89 + +by noting that the primary intension of the concept picks out some actualworld referent that is projected (by rigidification) invariantly across physically identical worlds. All we need here for an explanation is an a priori +conceptual analysis combined with contingent facts about the actual world.51 +On the other hand, a mere natural supervenience relation will itself be a +contingent law. At best it will be explainable in terms of more fundamental +laws; at worst, the supervenience law will itself be fundamental. In either +case, one explains certain regularities in the world by invoking fundamental +laws, just as one does in physics, and as always, fundamental laws are where +explanation must stop. Mere natural supervenience is ontologically expensive, as we have seen, so it is fortunate that logical supervenience is the rule +and natural supervenience the exception. + + This page intentionally left blank + + PART II +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + + This page intentionally left blank + + 3 + +Can Consciousness +Be Reductively Explained? + +1. Is Consciousness Logically Supervenient +on the Physical? +Almost everything in the world can be explained in physical terms; it is +natural to hope that consciousness might be explained this way, too. In this +chapter, however, I will argue that consciousness escapes the net of reductive explanation. No explanation given wholly in physical terms can ever +account for the emergence of conscious experience. This may seem to be a +negative conclusion, but it leads to some strong positive consequences that +I will bring out in later chapters. +To make the case against reductive explanation, we need to show that +consciousness is not logically supervenient on the physical. In principle, +we need to show that it does not supervene globally—that is, that all the +microphysical facts in the world do not entail the facts about consciousness. In +practice, it is easier to run the argument locally, arguing that in an individual, +microphysical facts do not entail the facts about consciousness. When it +comes to consciousness, local and global supervenience plausibly stand and +fall together, so it does not matter much which way we run the argument: +if consciousness supervenes at all, it almost certainly supervenes locally. If +this is disputed, however, all the arguments can be run at the global level +with straightforward alterations. +How can we argue that consciousness is not logically supervenient on the +physical? There are various ways. We can think about what is conceivable, +in order to argue directly for the logical possibility of a situation in which +the physical facts are the same but the facts about experience are different. +We can appeal to epistemology, arguing that the right sort of link between + + 94 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +knowledge of physical facts and knowledge of consciousness is absent. And +we can appeal directly to the concept of consciousness, arguing that there +is no analysis of the concept that could ground an entailment from the physical to the phenomenal. In what follows I will give arguments using all three +of these strategies. The first two are essentially arguments from conceivability, the second two are arguments from epistemology, and the fifth is an +argument from analysis. There is some element of redundancy among the +five arguments, but together they make a strong case. +One can also do things more directly, making the case against reductive +explanation without explicitly appealing to logical supervenience. I have +taken that route elsewhere, but here I will give the more detailed analysis +to allow a fuller case. All the same, the case against reductive explanation +and the critique of existing reductive accounts (in section 2 onward) should +make sense even without this analysis. Some readers might like to proceed +there directly, at least on a first reading. +(A technical note: The burden of this chapter is to argue, in effect, that +there is no a priori entailment from physical facts to phenomenal facts. The +sort of necessity that defines the relevant supervenience relation is the a +priori version of logical necessity, where primary intensions are central. As +we saw in Chapter 2, this is the relation that is relevant to issues about +explanation; matters of a posteriori necessity can be set to one side. In the +next chapter, issues of ontology rather than explanation are central, and I +argue separately that there is no a posteriori necessary connection between +physical facts and phenomenal facts.) +Argument 1: The logical possibility of zombies +The most obvious way (although not the only way) to investigate the logical +supervenience of consciousness is to consider the logical possibility of a +zombie: someone or something physically identical to me (or to any other +conscious being), but lacking conscious experiences altogether.1 At the global +level, we can consider the logical possibility of a zombie world: a world +physically identical to ours, but in which there are no conscious experiences +at all. In such a world, everybody is a zombie. +So let us consider my zombie twin. This creature is molecule for molecule +identical to me, and identical in all the low-level properties postulated by a +completed physics, but he lacks conscious experience entirely. (Some might +prefer to call a zombie "it," but I use the personal pronoun; I have grown +quite fond of my zombie twin.) To fix ideas, we can imagine that right now +I am gazing out the window, experiencing some nice green sensations from +seeing the trees outside, having pleasant taste experiences through munching +on a chocolate bar, and feeling a dull aching sensation in my right shoulder. + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +95 + +Figure 3.1. Calvin and Hobbes on zombies. (Calvin and Hobbes © Watterson. +Distributed by Universal Press Syndicate. Reprinted with permission. All rights +reserved) + +What is going on in my zombie twin? He is physically identical to me, +and we may as well suppose that he is embedded in an identical environment. He will certainly be identical to me functionally: he will be processing +the same sort of information, reacting in a similar way to inputs, with his +internal configurations being modified appropriately and with indistinguishable behavior resulting. He will be psychologically identical to me, in the +sense developed in Chapter 1. He will be perceiving the trees outside, in the +functional sense, and tasting the chocolate, in the psychological sense. All +of this follows logically from the fact that he is physically identical to me, +by virtue of the functional analyses of psychological notions. He will even +be "conscious" in the functional senses described earlier—he will be awake, +able to report the contents of his internal states, able to focus attention in +various places, and so on. It is just that none of this functioning will be +accompanied by any real conscious experience. There will be no phenomenal +feel. There is nothing it is like to be a zombie. +This sort of zombie is quite unlike the zombies found in Hollywood movies, which tend to have significant functional impairments (Figure 3.1). The +sort of consciousness that Hollywood zombies most obviously lack is a psychological version: typically, they have little capacity for introspection and +lack a refined ability to voluntarily control behavior. They may or may not +lack phenomenal consciousness; as Block (1995) points out, it is reasonable +to suppose that there is something it tastes like when they eat their victims. +We can call these psychological zombies', I am concerned with phenomenal +zombies, which are physically and functionally identical, but which lack +experience. (Perhaps it is not surprising that phenomenal zombies have +not been popular in Hollywood, as there would be obvious problems with +their depiction.) + + 96 + +The Irredudbility of Consciousness + +The idea of zombies as I have described them is a strange one. For a start, +it is unlikely that zombies are naturally possible. In the real world, it is likely +that any replica of me would be conscious. For this reason, it is most natural +to imagine unconscious creatures as physically different from conscious +ones—exhibiting impaired behavior, for example. But the question is not +whether it is plausible that zombies could exist in our world, or even whether +the idea of a zombie replica is a natural one; the question is whether the notion of a zombie is conceptually coherent. The mere intelligibility of the +notion is enough to establish the conclusion. +Arguing for a logical possibility is not entirely straightforward. How, for +example, would one argue that a mile-high unicycle is logically possible? +It just seems obvious. Although no such thing exists in the real world, the +description certainly appears to be coherent. If someone objects that it is +not logically possible—it merely seems that way—there is little we can +say, except to repeat the description and assert its obvious coherence. It +seems quite clear that there is no hidden contradiction lurking in the description. +I confess that the logical possibility of zombies seems equally obvious to +me. A zombie is just something physically identical to me, but which has no +conscious experience—all is dark inside. While this is probably empirically +impossible, it certainly seems that a coherent situation is described; I can +discern no contradiction in the description. In some ways an assertion of +this logical possibility comes down to a brute intuition, but no more so than +with the unicycle. Almost everybody, it seems to me, is capable of conceiving +of this possibility. Some may be led to deny the possibility in order to make +some theory come out right, but the justification of such theories should ride +on the question of possibility, rather than the other way around. +In general, a certain burden of proof lies on those who claim that a given +description is logically impossible. If someone truly believes that a mile-high +unicycle is logically impossible, she must give us some idea of where a contradiction lies, whether explicit or implicit. If she cannot point out something +about the intensions of the concepts "mile-high" and "unicycle" that might +lead to a contradiction, then her case will not be convincing. On the other +hand, it is no more convincing to give an obviously false analysis of the +notions in question—to assert, for example, that for something to qualify as +a unicycle it must be shorter than the Statue of Liberty. If no reasonable +analysis of the terms in question points toward a contradiction, or even +makes the existence of a contradiction plausible, then there is a natural +assumption in favor of logical possibility. +That being said, there are some positive things that proponents of logical +possibility can do to bolster their case. They can exhibit various indirect +arguments, appealing to what we know about the phenomena in question +and the way we think about hypothetical cases involving these phenomena, + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +97 + +in order to establish that the obvious logical possibility really is a logical +possibility, and really is obvious. One might spin a fantasy about an ordinary +person riding a unicycle, when suddenly the whole system expands a thousandfold. Or one might describe a series of unicycles, each bigger than the +last. In a sense, these are all appeals to intuition, and an opponent who +wishes to deny the possibility can in each case assert that our intuitions have +misled us, but the very obviousness of what we are describing works in our +favor, and helps shift the burden of proof further onto the other side. +For example, we can indirectly support the claim that zombies are logically +possible by considering nonstandard realizations of my functional organization.2 My functional organization—that is, the pattern of causal organization embodied in the mechanisms responsible for the production of my +behavior—can in principle be realized in all sorts of strange ways. To use a +common example (Block 1978), the people of a large nation such as China +might organize themselves so that they realize a causal organization isomorphic to that of my brain, with every person simulating the behavior of a +single neuron, and with radio links corresponding to synapses. The population +might control an empty shell of a robot body, equipped with sensory transducers and motor effectors. +Many people find it implausible that a set-up like this would give rise to +conscious experience—that somehow a "group mind" would emerge from +the overall system. I am not concerned here with whether or not conscious +experience would in fact arise; I suspect that in fact it would, as I argue in +Chapter 7. All that matters here is that the idea that such a system lacks +conscious experience is coherent A meaningful possibility is being expressed, +and it is an open question whether consciousness arises or not. We can make +a similar point by considering my silicon isomorph, who is organized like +me but who has silicon chips where I have neurons. Whether such an isomorph would in fact be conscious is controversial, but it seems to most people +that those who deny this are expressing a coherent possibility. From these +cases it follows that the existence of my conscious experience is not logically +entailed by the facts about my functional organization. +But given that it is conceptually coherent that the group-mind set-up or +my silicon isomorph could lack conscious experience, it follows that my +zombie twin is an equally coherent possibility. For it is clear that there is +no more of a conceptual entailment from biochemistry to consciousness +than there is from silicon or from a group of homunculi. If the silicon +isomorph without conscious experience is conceivable, we need only substitute neurons for silicon in the conception while leaving functional organization constant, and we have my zombie twin. Nothing in this substitution could +force experience into the conception; these implementational differences are +simply not the sort of thing that could be conceptually relevant to experience. +So consciousness fails to logically supervene on the physical. + + 98 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +The argument for zombies can be made without an appeal to these nonstandard realizations, but these have a heuristic value in eliminating a source +of conceptual confusion. To some people, intuitions about the logical possibility of an unconscious physical replica seem less than clear at first, perhaps +because the familiar co-occurrence of biochemistry and consciousness can +lead one to suppose a conceptual connection. Considerations of the less +familiar cases remove these empirical correlations from the picture, and +therefore make judgments of logical possibility more straightforward.3 But +once it is accepted that these nonconscious functional replicas are logically +possible, the corresponding conclusion concerning a physical replica cannot +be avoided. +Some may think that conceivability arguments are unreliable. For example, +sometimes it is objected that we cannot really imagine in detail the many +billions of neurons in the human brain. Of course this is true; but we do not +need to imagine each of the neurons to make the case. Mere complexity +among neurons could not conceptually entail consciousness; if all that neural +structure is to be relevant to consciousness, it must be relevant in virtue of +some higher-level properties that it enables. So it is enough to imagine the +system at a coarse level, and to make sure that we conceive it with appropriately sophisticated mechanisms of perception, categorization, high-bandwidth access to information contents, reportability, and the like. No matter +how sophisticated we imagine these mechanisms to be, the zombie scenario +remains as coherent as ever. Perhaps an opponent might claim that all the +unimagined neural detail is conceptually relevant in some way independent +of its contribution to sophisticated functioning; but then she owes us an +account of what that way might be, and none is available. Those implementational details simply lie at the wrong level to be conceptually relevant to +consciousness. +It is also sometimes said that conceivability is an imperfect guide to possibility. The main way that conceivability and possibility can come apart is +tied to the phenomenon of a posteriori necessity: for example, the hypothesis +that water is not H2O seems conceptually coherent, but water is arguably +H2O in all possible worlds. But a posteriori necessity is irrelevant to the +concerns of this chapter. As we saw in the last chapter, explanatory connections are grounded in a priori entailments from physical facts to highlevel facts. The relevant kind of possibility is to be evaluated using the primary intensions of the terms involved, instead of the secondary intensions +that are relevant to a posteriori necessity. So even if a zombie world is conceivable only in the sense in which it is conceivable that water is not H2O, +that is enough to establish that consciousness cannot be reductively explained. +Those considerations aside, the main way in which conceivability arguments can go wrong is by subtle conceptual confusion: if we are insufficiently + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +99 + +reflective we can overlook an incoherence in a purported possibility, by taking a conceived-of situation and misdescribing it. For example, one might +think that one can conceive of a situation in which Fermat's last theorem is +false, by imagining a situation in which leading mathematicians declare that +they have found a counterexample. But given that the theorem is actually +true, this situation is being misdescribed: it is really a scenario in which +Fermat's last theorem is true, and in which some mathematicians make a +mistake. Importantly, though, this kind of mistake always lies in the a priori +domain, as it arises from the incorrect application of the primary intensions +of our concepts to a conceived situation. Sufficient reflection will reveal that +the concepts are being incorrectly applied, and that the claim of logical possibility is not justified. +So the only route available to an opponent here is to claim that in describing +the zombie world as a zombie world, we are misapplying the concepts, and +that in fact there is a conceptual contradiction lurking in the description. +Perhaps if we thought about it clearly enough we would realize that by +imagining a physically identical world we are thereby automatically imagining a world in which there is conscious experience. But then the burden is +on the opponent to give us some idea of where the contradiction might lie +in the apparently quite coherent description. If no internal incoherence can +be revealed, then there is a very strong case that the zombie world is logically possible. +As before, I can detect no internal incoherence; I have a clear picture of +what I am conceiving when I conceive of a zombie. Still, some people find +conceivability arguments difficult to adjudicate, particularly where strange +ideas such as this one are concerned. It is therefore fortunate that every +point made using zombies can also be made in other ways, for example by +considering epistemology and analysis. To many, arguments of the latter +sort (such as arguments 3-5 below) are more straightforward and therefore +make a stronger foundation in the argument against logical supervenience. +But zombies at least provide a vivid illustration of important issues in the +vicinity. +Argument 2: The inverted spectrum +Even in making a conceivability argument against logical supervenience, it +is not strictly necessary to establish the logical possibility of zombies or a +zombie world. It suffices to establish the logical possibility of a world physically identical to ours in which the facts about conscious experience are +merely different from the facts in our world, without conscious experience +being absent entirely. As long as some positive fact about experience in our +world does not hold in a physically identical world, then consciousness does +not logically supervene. + + 100 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +It is therefore enough to note that one can coherently imagine a physically +identical world in which conscious experiences are inverted, or (at the local +level) imagine a being physically identical to me but with inverted conscious +experiences. One might imagine, for example, that where I have a red experience, my inverted twin has a blue experience, and vice versa. Of course he +will call his blue experiences "red," but that is irrelevant. What matters is +that the experience he has of the things we both call "red"—blood, fire +engines, and so on—is of the same kind as the experience I have of the +things we both call "blue," such as the sea and the sky. +The rest of his color experiences are systematically inverted with respect +to mine, in order that they cohere with the red-blue inversion. Perhaps +the best way to imagine this happening with human color experiences is +to imagine that two of the axes of our three-dimensional color space are +switched—the red-green axis is mapped onto the yellow-blue axis, and vice +versa.4 To achieve such an inversion in the actual world, presumably we +would need to rewire neural processes in an appropriate way, but as a logical +possibility, it seems entirely coherent that experiences could be inverted +while physical structure is duplicated exactly. Nothing in the neurophysiology +dictates that one sort of processing should be accompanied by red experiences +rather than by yellow experiences. +It is sometimes objected (Harrison 1973; Hardin 1987) that human color +space is asymmetrical in a way that disallows such an inversion. For instance, +certain colors have a warmth or coolness associated with them, and warmth +and coolness appear to be directly associated with different functional roles +(e.g., warmth is perceived as "positive," whereas coolness is perceived +as "negative"). If a warm color and a cool color were switched, then the +"warm" phenomenal feel would become dissociated from the "warm" functional role—a "cool" green experience would be reported as positive rather +than negative, and so on. In a similar way, there seem to be more discriminable shades of red than of yellow, so swapping red experiences with yellow +experiences directly might lead to the odd situation in which a subject could +functionally discriminate more shades of yellow than are distinguishable +phenomenologically. Perhaps there are enough asymmetries in color space +that any such inversion would lead to a strange dissociation of phenomenal +feel from the "appropriate" functional role. +There are three things we can say in response to this. First, there does +not seem to be anything incoherent about the notion of such a dissociation +(e.g., cool phenomenology with warm reactions), although it is admittedly +an odd idea.5 Second, instead of mapping red precisely onto blue and vice +versa, one can imagine that these are mapped onto slightly different colors. +For example, red might be mapped onto a "warm" version of blue (as Levine +[1991] suggests), or even onto color not in our color space at all. In the + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +101 + +red-yellow case, we might imagine that red is mapped onto an extended +range of yellow experiences, in which more discrimination is available. There +is no reason why spectrum inversion scenarios must involve colors drawn +from the usual color space. Third, perhaps the most compelling response +is to argue (with Shoemaker [1982]) that even if our own color space is +asymmetrical, there certainly could be creatures whose color space is symmetrical. For example, there is probably a naturally possible creature who +sees (and experiences) precisely two colors, A and B, which correspond +to distinct, well-separated ranges of light wavelengths, and for which the +distinction between the two exhausts the structure of the color space. It +seems entirely coherent to imagine two such creatures that are physically +identical, but whose experiences of A and B are inverted. That is enough +to make the point. +Even many reductive materialists (e.g., Shoemaker [1982]) have conceded +that it is coherent that one's color experiences might be inverted while +one's functional organization stays constant. It is allowed that a system with +different underlying neurophysiological properties, or with something like +silicon in place of neurobiology, might have different color experiences. But +once this is granted, it follows automatically that inversion of experiences +in a physical replica is at least conceptually coherent. The extra neurophysiological properties that are constrained in such a case are again not the +kind of thing that could logically determine the nature of the experience. +Even if there is some sort of a posteriori identification between certain neurophysiological structures and certain experiences (as Shoemaker believes), +we must still allow that a different pattern of associations is conceivable, in +the sense of conceivability that is relevant to reductive explanation. +While the possibility of inverted spectra and the possibility of zombies +both establish that consciousness fails to supervene logically, the first establishes a conclusion strictly weaker than the second. Somebody might conceivably hold that inverted spectra but not zombies are logically possible. If +this were the case, then the existence of consciousness could be reductively +explained, but the specific character of particular conscious experiences could +not be. +Argument 3: From epistemic asymmetry +As we saw earlier, consciousness is a surprising feature of the universe. Our +grounds for belief in consciousness derive solely from our own experience +of it. Even if we knew every last detail about the physics of the universe—the +configuration, causation, and evolution among all the fields and particles in +the spatiotemporal manifold—that information would not lead us to postulate the existence of conscious experience. My knowledge of consciousness, + + 102 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +in the first instance, comes from my own case, not from any external observation. It is my first-person experience of consciousness that forces the problem +on me. +From all the low-level facts about physical configurations and causation, +we can in principle derive all sorts of high-level facts about macroscopic +systems, their organization, and the causation among them. One could determine all the facts about biological function, and about human behavior and +the brain mechanisms by which it is caused. But nothing in this vast causal +story would lead one who had not experienced it directly to believe that +there should be any consciousness. The very idea would be unreasonable; almost mystical, perhaps. +It is true that the physical facts about the world might provide some +indirect evidence for the existence of consciousness. For example, from these +facts one could ascertain that there were a lot of organisms that claimed to +be conscious, and said they had mysterious subjective experiences. Still, this +evidence would be quite inconclusive, and it might be most natural to draw +an eliminativist conclusion—that there was in fact no experience present in +these creatures, just a lot of talk. +Eliminativism about conscious experience is an unreasonable position +only because of our own acquaintance with it. If it were not for this direct +knowledge, consciousness could go the way of the vital spirit. To put it +another way, there is an epistemic asymmetry in our knowledge of consciousness that is not present in our knowledge of other phenomena.6 Our knowledge that conscious experience exists derives primarily from our own case, +with external evidence playing at best a secondary role. +The point can also be made by pointing to the existence of a problem of +other minds. Even when we know everything physical about other creatures, +we do not know for certain that they are conscious, or what their experiences +are (although we may have good reason to believe that they are). It is striking that there is no problem of "other lives," or of "other economies," or +of "other heights." There is no epistemic asymmetry in those cases, precisely +because those phenomena are logically supervenient on the physical. +The epistemic asymmetry in knowledge of consciousness makes it clear +that consciousness cannot logically supervene. If it were logically supervenient, there would be no such epistemic asymmetry; a logically supervenient property can be detected straightforwardly on the basis of external evidence, and there is no special role for the first-person case. To be sure, there +are some supervenient properties—memory, perhaps—that are more easily +detected in the first-person case. But this is just a matter of how hard one +has to work. The presence of memory is just as accessible from the third +person, in principle, as from the first person. The epistemic asymmetry associated with consciousness is much more fundamental, and it tells us that no + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +103 + +collection of facts about complex causation in physical systems adds up to +a fact about consciousness. +Argument 4: The knowledge argument +The most vivid argument against the logical supervenience of consciousness +is suggested by Jackson (1982), following related arguments by Nagel (1974) +and others. Imagine that we are living in an age of a completed neuroscience, +where we know everything there is to know about the physical processes +within our brain responsible for the generation of our behavior. Mary has +been brought up in a black-and-white room and has never seen any colors +except for black, white, and shades of gray.7 She is nevertheless one of the +world's leading neuroscientists, specializing in the neurophysiology of color +vision. She knows everything there is to know about the neural processes +involved in visual information processing, about the physics of optical processes, and about the physical makeup of objects in the environment. But +she does not know what it is like to see red. No amount of reasoning from +the physical facts alone will give her this knowledge. +It follows that the facts about the subjective experience of color vision +are not entailed by the physical facts. If they were, Mary could in principle +come to know what it is like to see red on the basis of her knowledge of +the physical facts. But she cannot. Perhaps Mary could come to know what +it is like to see red by some indirect method, such as by manipulating her +brain in the appropriate way. The point, however, is that the knowledge +does not follow from the physical knowledge alone. Knowledge of all the +physical facts will in principle allow Mary to derive all the facts about +a system's reactions, abilities, and cognitive capacities; but she will still be +entirely in the dark about its experience of red. +A related way to make this point is to consider systems quite different +from ourselves, perhaps much simpler—such as bats or mice—and note that +the physical facts about these systems do not tell us what their conscious +experiences are like, if they have any at all (Nagel focuses on this sort of +issue). Once all the physical facts about a mouse are in, the nature of its +conscious experience remains an open question: it is consistent with the +physical facts about a mouse that it has conscious experience, and it is +consistent with the physical facts that it does not. From the physical facts +about a bat, we can ascertain all the facts about a bat, except the facts about +its conscious experiences. Knowing all the physical facts, we still do not know +what it is like to be a bat. +Along similar lines we can consider a computer, designed as a simple +cognitive agent (perhaps it has the intelligence of a dog), but similar to us +in certain respects, such as its capacity for perceptual discrimination. In + + 104 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +particular it categorizes color stimuli in a manner quite similar to ours, +grouping things that we would call "red" under one category and things we +would call "green" under another. Even if we know every detail about +the computer's circuits, questions remain: (1) Is the computer experiencing +anything at all when it looks at roses?; (2) If it is, is it experiencing the same +sensory color quality that we have when we look at a rose, or some quite +different quality? These are entirely meaningful questions, and knowing all +the physical facts does not force one answer rather than another onto us. +The physical facts therefore do not logically entail the facts about conscious experience. +Jackson put his argument forward as an argument against materialism +rather than against reductive explanation. There have been many replies +to the argument; I will discuss them in the next chapter, where materialism +rather than reductive explanation will be at issue. But for now it is interesting +to note that most of the objections to the argument against materialism +have conceded the point that is relevant to the argument against reductive +explanation: that knowledge of what red is like is factual knowledge that is +not entailed a priori by knowledge of the physical facts. The only way that +the conclusion can be evaded is to deny that knowing what red experience +is like gives knowledge of a fact at all. This is the strategy taken by Lewis +(1990) and Nemirow (1990), who argue that all Mary is lacking is an ability, +such as the ability to recognize red things. I discuss this suggestion in the +next chapter; here, I simply note that insofar as it seems clear that when she +sees red for the first time, Mary is discovering something about the way the +world is, it seems clear that the knowledge she is gaining is knowledge of +a fact. +Argument 5: From the absence of analysis +If proponents of reductive explanation are to have any hope of defeating +the arguments above, they will have to give us some idea of how the existence +of consciousness might be entailed by physical facts. While it is not fair to +expect all the details, one at least needs an account of how such an entailment +might possibly go. But any attempt to demonstrate such an entailment is +doomed to failure. For consciousness to be entailed by a set of physical facts, +one would need some kind of analysis of the notion of consciousness—the +kind of analysis whose satisfaction physical facts could imply—and there is +no such analysis to be had. +The only analysis of consciousness that seems even remotely tenable for +these purposes is a functional analysis. Upon such an analysis, it would be +seen that all there is to the notion of something's being conscious is that it +should play a certain functional role. For example, one might say that all +there is to a state's being conscious is that it be verbally reportable, or that + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +105 + +it be the result of certain kinds of perceptual discrimination, or that it make +information available to later processes in a certain way, or whatever. But +on the face of it, these fail miserably as analyses. They simply miss what it +means to be a conscious experience. Although conscious states may play +various causal roles, they are not defined by their causal roles. Rather, what +makes them conscious is that they have a certain phenomenal feel, and this +feel is not something that can be functionally defined away. +To see how unsatisfactory these analyses are, note how they trivialize the +problem of explaining consciousness. Suddenly, all we have to do to explain +consciousness is explain our ability to make certain verbal reports, or to +perform certain sorts of discrimination, or to manifest some other capacity. +But on the face of it, it is entirely conceivable that one could explain all +these things without explaining a thing about consciousness itself; that is, +without explaining the experience that accompanies the report or the discrimination. To analyze consciousness in terms of some functional notion is either +to change the subject or to define away the problem. One might as well +define "world peace" as "a ham sandwich." Achieving world peace becomes +much easier, but it is a hollow achievement. +Functional analyses of consciousness can also be argued against on more +specific grounds. For example, any functionally analyzed concept will have +a degree of semantic indeterminancy. Does a mouse have beliefs? Do bacteria +learn? Is a computer virus alive? The best answer to these questions is usually +in a sense yes, in a sense no. It all depends on how we draw the boundaries +in the concepts, and in any high-level functional concepts the boundaries +will be vague. But compare: Does a mouse have conscious experience? Does +a virus? These are not matters for stipulation. Either there is something that +it is like to be a mouse or there is not, and it is not up to us to define the +mouse's experience into or out of existence. To be sure, there is probably +a continuum of conscious experience from the very faint to the very rich; +but if something has conscious experience, however faint, we cannot stipulate +it away. This determinacy could not be derived from any functional analysis +of the concepts in the vicinity of consciousness, as the functional concepts +in the vicinity are all somewhat vague. If so, it follows that the notion of +consciousness cannot be functionally analyzed. +Another objection is that the functionalist analysis collapses the important distinction, outlined in Chapter 1, between the notions of awareness +and consciousness. Presumably if consciousness is to be functionally analyzed, +it will be analyzed roughly as we analyzed awareness then: in terms of a +certain accessibility of information in later processing and in the control of +behavior. Awareness is a perfectly good concept, but it is quite distinct from +the concept of conscious experience. The functionalist treatment collapses +the two notions of consciousness and awareness into one, and therefore does +not do justice to our conceptual system. + + 106 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +The alternatives to functional analysis look even worse. It is most unclear +that there could be any other kind of analysis appropriate for reductive +explanation. The only alternative might be a structural analysis—perhaps +consciousness could be analyzed as some sort of biochemical structure—but +that analysis would be even more clearly inadequate. Whether or not consciousness is a biochemical structure, that is not what "consciousness" means. +To analyze consciousness that way again trivializes the explanatory problem +by changing the subject. It seems that the concept of consciousness is irreducible, being characterizable only in terms of concepts that themselves involve consciousness. +Note that this is quite unlike the sort of irreducibility that is sometimes +supposed to hold for high-level concepts in general. We have seen that many +high-level notions have no crisp definitions, and no manageable analyses in +terms of necessary and sufficient conditions. Nevertheless, as we saw in the +last chapter, these concepts at least have rough-and-ready analyses that get +us into the ballpark, although they will inevitably fail to do justice to the +details. Most importantly, it is easy to see that properties such as life, learning, +and so on can be analyzed as functional properties, even if spelling out the +details of just which functional property is a difficult matter. Even though +these properties lack crisp functional definitions, they are nevertheless quite +compatible with entailment by the physical facts. +The problems with consciousness are in a different league. Here, the +purported analyses do not even get into the ballpark. In a much starker way, +they completely fail to characterize what needs to be explained. There is no +temptation to even try to add epicycles to a purported functional analysis +of consciousness in order to make it satisfactory, as there is with similar +analyses of life and of learning. Consciousness is simply not to be characterized as a functional property in the first place. The same goes for analyses +of consciousness as a structural property, or in other reductive terms. There +is therefore no way for an entailment from physical facts to consciousness +to get off the ground. + +2. The Failure of Reductive Explanation +The failure of consciousness to logically supervene on the physical tells us that +no reductive explanation of consciousness can succeed. Given any account of +the physical processes purported to underlie consciousness, there will always +be a further question: Why are these processes accompanied by conscious +experience? For most other phenomena, such a question is easily answered: +the physical facts about those processes entail the existence of the phenomena. For a phenomenon such as life, for example, the physical facts imply that +certain functions will be performed, and the performance of those functions is + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +107 + +all we need to explain in order to explain life. But no such answer will suffice +for consciousness. +Physical explanation is well suited to the explanation of structure and of +function. Structural properties and functional properties can be straightforwardly entailed by a low-level physical story, and so are clearly apt for reductive explanation. And almost all the high-level phenomena that we +need to explain ultimately come down to structure or function: think of the +explanation of waterfalls, planets, digestion, reproduction, language. But the +explanation of consciousness is not just a matter of explaining structure and +function. Once we have explained all the physical structure in the vicinity +of the brain, and we have explained how all the various brain functions are +performed, there is a further sort of explanandum: consciousness itself. Why +should all this structure and function give rise to experience? The story about +the physical processes does not say. +We can put this in terms of the thought experiments given earlier. Any +story about physical processes applies equally to me and to my zombie twin. +It follows that nothing in that story says why, in my case, consciousness +arises. Similarly, any story about physical processes applies equally to my +inverted twin, who sees blue where I see red: it follows that nothing in that +story says why my experience is of one variety rather than another. The very +fact that it is logically possible that the physical facts could be the same +while the facts about consciousness are different shows us that as Levine +(1983) has put it, there is an explanatory gap between the physical level and +conscious experience. +If this is right, the fact that consciousness accompanies a given physical +process is a further fact, not explainable simply by telling the story about +the physical facts. In a sense, the accompaniment must be taken as brute. +We might try to systematize and explain these brute facts in terms of some +simple underlying pattern, but there will always remain an element here that +is logically independent of the physical story. Perhaps we might get some +kind of explanation by combining the underlying physical facts with certain +further bridging principles that link the physical facts with consciousness, +but this explanation will not be a reductive one. The very need for explicit +bridging principles shows us that consciousness is not being explained reductively, but is being explained on its own terms. +Of course nothing I have said implies that physical facts are irrelevant to +the explanation of consciousness. We can still expect physical accounts to +play a significant role in a theory of consciousness, giving information about +the physical basis of consciousness, for example, and perhaps yielding a detailed correspondence between various aspects of physical processing and +aspects of conscious experience. Such accounts may be especially useful in +helping to understand the structure of consciousness: the patterns of similarity and difference between experiences, the geometric structure of phenome- + + 108 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +nal fields, and so on. I say much more about these and other things that +physical explanation can tell us about experience in a nonreductive framework in Chapter 6. But a physical account, alone, is not enough. +At this point, a number of objections naturally arise. +Objection 1: Are we setting the standards too high? +Some might argue that explanation of any high-level phenomena will postulate "bridge laws" in addition to a low-level account, and that it is only with +the aid of these bridge laws that the details of the high-level phenomena are +derived. However, as the discussion in the last chapter suggests (and as is +carefully argued by Horgan [1978]), in such cases the bridge laws are not +further facts about the world. Rather, the connecting principles themselves +are logically supervenient on the low-level facts. The extreme case of such +a bridging principle is a supervenience conditional, which we have seen is +usually a conceptual truth. Other more "localized" bridging principles, such +as the link between molecular motion and heat, can at least be derived from +the physical facts. For consciousness, by contrast, such bridging principles +must be taken as primitive. +It is interesting to see how a typical high-level property—such as life, +say���evades the arguments put forward in the case of consciousness. First, +it is straightforwardly inconceivable that there could be a physical replica +of a living creature that was not itself alive. Perhaps a problem might arise +due to context-dependent properties (would a replica that forms randomly +in a swamp be alive, or be human?), but fixing environmental facts eliminates +even that possibility. Second, there is no "inverted life" possibility analogous +to the inverted spectrum. Third, when one knows all the physical facts about +an organism (and possibly about its environment), one has enough material +to know all the biological facts. Fourth, there is no epistemic asymmetry +with life; facts about life in others are as accessible, in principle, as facts +about life in ourselves. Fifth, the concept of life is plausibly analyzable in +functional terms: to be alive is roughly to possess certain capacities to adapt, +reproduce, and metabolize. As a general point, most high-level phenomena come down to matters of physical structure and function, and we have +good reason to believe that structural and functional properties are logically +supervenient on the physical. +Objection 2: Couldn't a vitalist have said +the same thing about life? +All this notwithstanding, a common reaction to the sort of argument I have +given is to reply that a vitalist about life might have said the same things.8 +For example, a vitalist might have claimed that it is logically possible that +a physical replica of me might not be alive, in order to establish that life + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +109 + +cannot be reductively explained. And a vitalist might have argued that life +is a further fact, not explained by any account of the physical facts. But the +vitalist would have been wrong. By analogy, might not the opponent of +reductive explanation for consciousness also be wrong? +I think this reaction misplaces the source of vitalist objections. Vitalism was +mostly driven by doubt about whether physical mechanisms could perform all +the complex functions associated with life: adaptive behavior, reproduction, +and the like. At the time, very little was known about the enormous sophistication of biochemical mechanisms, so this sort of doubt was quite natural. +But implicit in these very doubts is the conceptual point that when it comes +to explaining life, it is the performance of various functions that needs to +be explained. Indeed, it is notable that as physical explanation of the relevant +functions gradually appeared, vitalist doubts mostly melted away. With consciousness, by contrast, the problem persists even when the various functions +are explained. +Presented with a full physical account showing how physical processes +perform the relevant functions, a reasonable vitalist would concede that life +has been explained. There is not even conceptual room for the performance +of these functions without life. Perhaps some ultrastrong vitalist would deny +even this, claiming that something is left out by a functional account of +life—the vital spirit, perhaps. But the obvious rejoinder is that unlike experience, the vital spirit is not something we have independent reason to believe +in. Insofar as there was ever any reason to believe in it, it was as an explanatory construct—"We must have such a thing in order to be able to +do such amazing stuff." But as an explanatory construct, the vital spirit can +be eliminated when we find a better explanation of how the functions are +performed. Conscious experience, by contrast, forces itself on one as an +explanandum and cannot be eliminated so easily. +One reason a vitalist might think something is left out of a functional +explanation of life is precisely that nothing in a physical account explains +why there is something it is like to be alive. Perhaps some element of belief +in a "vital spirit" was tied to the phenomena of one's inner life. Many have +perceived a link between the concepts of life and experience, and even today +it seems reasonable to say that one of the things that needs to be explained +about life is the fact that many living creatures are conscious. But the existence of this sort of vitalist doubt is of no comfort to the proponent of reductive explanation of consciousness, as it is a doubt that has never been +overturned. +Objection 3: Is conceivability a guide to possibility? +Philosophers are often suspicious of arguments that give a key role to conceivability, frequently responding that conceivability does not suffice for +possibility. This is a subtle issue that I have discussed earlier and will dis- + + 110 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +cuss again: but here, the subtleties are not especially relevant. When it +comes to matters of explanation, it is clear that conceivability is central. If +on reflection we find it conceivable that all these physical processes could +take place in the absence of consciousness, then no reductive explanation +of consciousness will be satisfactory: the further question of why we exist +and not zombies will always arise. Even if conceivability is tied to the limits +of human capacity, explanation is tied to the limits of human capacity in a +similar way. +Another way to put the point is to note that reductive explanation of a +phenomenon in terms of the physical requires an a priori implication from +the physical facts to the relevant high-level facts (logical supervenience according to primary intension, as I put it earlier). If such a connection does +not hold, then we will always be able to raise the further question of why +the physical processes give rise to consciousness. We have seen that in almost +all domains, the right sort of connection holds, making reductive explanation +possible; but it does not seem to hold for conscious experience. One can +question whether ontological views such as materialism turn on these a +priori links—I discuss that matter in the next chapter—but when it comes +to reductive explanation, such links are crucial. + +Objection 4: Isn't this a collection of circular intuitions? +It might be further objected that the arguments I have given consist, at +bottom, in a collection of intuitions. There is certainly a sense in which all +these arguments are based on intuition, but I have tried to make clear just +how natural and plain these intuitions are, and how forced it is to deny them. +The main intuition at work is that there is something to be explained—some +phenomenon associated with first-person experience that presents a problem +not presented by observation of cognition from the third-person point of +view. Given the premise that some explanandum is forced on us by firstperson experience that is not forced on us by third-person observation, most +of the arguments above fall out. It follows immediately, for example, that +what needs to be explained cannot be analyzed as the playing of some +functional role, for the latter phenomenon is revealed to us by third-person +observation and is much more straightforward. +The "intuition" at work here is the very raison d'etre of the problem of +consciousness. The only consistent way to get around the intuitions is to +deny the problem and the phenomenon altogether. One can always, at least +when speaking "philosophically," deny the intuitions altogether, and deny +that there is anything (apart from the performance of various functions) that +needs explaining. But if one takes consciousness seriously, the conclusions +for which I am arguing must follow. + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +111 + +Objection 5: Doesn't all explanation have to stop somewhere? +A final objection is that no explanation gives one something for nothing: all +explanation has to stop somewhere. In explaining the motion of the planets, +for example, one takes the laws of gravity and the existence of mass for +granted. Perhaps we should simply take something for granted in this case, +too? I am sympathetic with this point; I think we do have to take something +for granted in explaining consciousness. But in doing so we inevitably move +beyond a reductive explanation. Indeed, this sort of analogy lends support +to the nonreductive position I am advocating. We take the laws of physics +for granted because they are fundamental laws. If we take a link between +physical processes and conscious experience for granted, this suggests that +the link should be taken as fundamental in the same way. I return to this +point in the next chapter. + +3. Cognitive Modeling +In this and the sections that follow, I illustrate the failure of reductive +explanation by giving a critique of a number of accounts of consciousness +that have been proposed by researchers in various disciplines. Not all of +these proposals have been put forward as reductive explanations of conscious +experience, although they have often been interpreted this way; but in any +case, it is instructive to see just what these accounts can and cannot achieve. +Along the way, it is interesting to note these researchers' varying attitudes +to the hard questions about conscious experience. +First, I will consider accounts based on cognitive modeling. Cognitive +modeling works well for most problems in cognitive science. By exhibiting +a model of the causal dynamics involved in cognitive processes, one can +explain the causation of behavior in a cognitive agent. This provides a valuable kind of explanation for psychological phenomena, such as learning, +memory, perception, control of action, attention, categorization, linguistic +behavior, and so on. If we have a model that captures the causal dynamics +of someone who is learning, for example, it follows that anything instantiating +those dynamics in the right environment will be learning. From the model +we can see how certain functions are performed, and this is all we have to +explain to explain learning. But this is insufficient to explain consciousness. +For any model we exhibit, it remains a further question why realization of +the model should be accompanied by consciousness. This is not a question +that description and analysis of the model alone can answer. +It is sometimes objected that purported models of consciousness are untestable, as there is no way to verify whether or not instantiations of the model +are conscious. This is a problem, but there is a deeper problem. Even if we + + 112 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +had (per impossible) an "experience meter" that could peek in and tell us +whether an instantiation was conscious, this would only establish a correlation. We would know that whenever the model is instantiated, consciousness +goes along with it. But it would not explain consciousness, in the way that +such models explain other mental phenomena. +Such models can certainly explain "consciousness" in the psychological +senses thereof, where it is construed as some kind of cognitive or functional +capacity. Many existing "models of consciousness" can be most charitably +interpreted in this light. We can see these as providing explanations of +reportability, or of attention, or of introspective abilities, and so on. None +of them, however, gives us anything close to an explanation of why these +processes should be accompanied by conscious experience. Some examples +will illustrate this. +The first example is the cognitive model presented by Bernard Baars +(1988), as part of a book-length treatment of consciousness from the standpoint of cognitive psychology. Baars brings all sorts of experimental evidence +to bear in establishing his main thesis: consciousness is a kind of global +workspace in a distributed system of intelligent information processors. When +processors gain access to the global workspace, they broadcast a message to +the entire system, as if they had written it on a blackboard. The contents of +the global workspace are the contents of consciousness. +Baars uses this model to explain a remarkable number of properties of +human processing. The model provides a very suggestive framework for +explaining a subject's access to information, and its role in attention, reportability, voluntary control, and even the development of a self-concept. The +global workspace framework is therefore well suited to explaining consciousness in its whole bundle of psychological senses. There is at least a general +theory of awareness on offer. +But there is no reductive explanation of experience to be found here. The +question of why these processes should give rise to experience is simply not +addressed. One might suppose that according to the theory, the contents of +experience are precisely the contents of the workspace. But even if this is +so, nothing internal to the theory explains why it is that the information +within the global workspace is experienced. The best the theory can do is +to say that the information is experienced because it is globally accessible. +But now the question arises in a different form: Why should global accessibility give rise to conscious experience? This bridging question is not addressed +in Baars's work. +Baars mentions this sort of worry briefly: "A skeptical reader may ... +wonder whether we are truly describing conscious experience, or whether, +instead, we can only deal with incidental phenomena associated with it" (p. +27). His response is to note that scientific theories tend to at least approach + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +113 + +the "thing itself"; for instance, biology explains inheritance itself, and not +just associated phenomena. But this is simply to ignore the ways in which +consciousness is different in kind from these phenomena, as we have seen. +With inheritance, various functions are all there is to explain. With consciousness, there is a further explanandum: experience itself. Baars's theory can +therefore be seen as an interesting approach to the cognitive processes +underlying consciousness, and one that gives us much indirect insight into +consciousness, but it leaves the key questions—why is there consciousness +and how does it arise from cognitive processing?—untouched. +Daniel Dennett has also put forward a cognitive model of consciousness. +In fact, he has put forward at least two of them. The first (Dennett 1978c) +is a "box-and-lines" model, consisting in an account of the flow of information between various modules (Figure 3.2). Central to the model are (1) +a perceptual module, (2) a short-term memory store M, which receives + +Figure 3.2. Dennett's cognitive model of consciousness. (Redrawn from Figure 9.1, +p. 155, from Daniel C. Dennett, Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and +Psychology, The MIT Press. Copyright © 1987 by Bradford Books, Publishers. By +permission of The MIT Press) + + 114 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +information from the perceptual module, (3) a control system, which interacts +with the memory store by a question-and-answer-process, and which can +direct attention to the contents of the perceptual module, and (4) a "public +relations" unit, which receives speech act commands from the control system +and converts them into public-language utterances. +What might this model explain? Although it is in a very simplified form +(as Dennett would concede), it might be fleshed out to provide an explanation +of reportability; that is, of our ability to report the contents of our internal +states. It also provides the skeleton of an explanation of our ability to bring +perceptual information to bear on the control of behavior, to introspect our +internal states, and so on. But it tells us nothing about why there should be +something it is like to be a system undergoing these processes. +In Consciousness Explained (1991), Dennett puts forward a more sophisticated account that draws on much recent work in cognitive science. The +model proposed here is essentially a "pandemonium" model, consisting in +many small agents competing for attention, with the agent that shouts the +loudest playing the primary role in the direction of later processing. On this +model there is no central "headquarters" of control, but multiple channels +exerting simultaneous influence. Dennett supplements this account with appeals to neuroscience, evolutionary biology, and connectionist models and +production systems in artificial intelligence. +The complexity of this account notwithstanding, it is directed at largely +the same phenomena as the earlier account. If successful, it would provide +an explanation of reportability, and more generally of the influence of various +sorts of information on the control of behavior. It also provides a potential +explanation of the focus of attention. It gives a provocative account of some +of our cognitive capacities, but it goes no further than the previous model +in telling us why there should be conscious experience in the vicinity of +these capacities. +Unlike most authors who put forward cognitive models, Dennett claims +explicitly that his models are the sort of thing that could explain everything +about experience that needs explaining. In particular, he thinks that to explain +consciousness, one only needs to explain such functional phenomena as reportability and control; any phenomenon that is apparently omitted is a +chimera. Sometimes he seems to take it as a basic premise that once one +has explained the various functions, one has explained everything (see, e.g., +Dennett [1993a], p. 210), but he occasionally puts forward arguments, some +of which I will consider later.9 +The same sort of critique could be directed at cognitive-model approaches +to consciousness by Churchland (1995), Johnson-Laird (1988), Shallice (1972, +1988a, 1988b), and many others. All provide intriguing accounts of the performance of cognitive functions, but all leave the really hard questions +untouched. + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +115 + +4. Neurobiologieal Explanation +Neurobiological approaches to consciousness have recently become popular. +Like cognitive models, these have much to offer in explaining psychological +phenomena, such as the varieties of awareness. They can also tell us something about the brain processes that are correlated with consciousness. But +none of these accounts explains the correlation: we are not told why brain +processes should give rise to experience at all. From the point of view of +neuroscience, the correlation is simply a brute fact. +From a methodological standpoint, it is not obvious how one can begin +to develop a neuroscientific theory. How does one perform the experiments +that detect a correlation between some neural process and consciousness? +What usually happens is that theorists implicitly rely on some psychological +criterion for consciousness, such as the focus of attention, the control of +behavior, and most frequently the ability to make verbal reports about an +internal state. One then notes that some neurophysiological property is +instantiated when these criteria are present, and one's theory of consciousness is off the ground. +The very fact that such indirect criteria are relied upon, however, makes +it clear that no reductive explanation of consciousness is being given. At +best, a neurophysiological account might be able to explain why the relevant +psychological property is instantiated. The question of why the psychological property in question should be accompanied by conscious experience is +left unanswered. Because these theories gain their purchase by assuming a +link between psychological properties and conscious experience, it is clear +that they do nothing to explain that link. We can see this by examining some +recent neuroscientific accounts of consciousness. +Much recent attention in neuroscience has focused on certain 40-hertz +oscillations in the visual cortex and elsewhere. Francis Crick and Christof +Koch (1990) have hypothesized that this sort of oscillation may be the fundamental neural feature responsible for conscious experience, and have advocated the development of a neurobiological theory along these lines.10 +Why 40-hertz oscillations? Primarily because evidence suggests that these +oscillations play an important role in the binding of various kinds of information into a unified whole. Two different kinds of information about a +scene—the shape and location of an object, for instance—may be represented +quite separately, but this theory suggests that the separate neural representations may have a common frequency and phase in their oscillations, allowing +the information to be bound together by later processes and stored in working +memory. In this way all sorts of disparate information might be integrated +into the "contents of consciousness." +Such a theory might indeed provide neurobiological insight into binding +and working memory, and perhaps eventually could be elaborated into an + + 116 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +account of how information is brought to bear in an integrated way in the +control of behavior. But the key question remains unanswered: Why should +these oscillations be accompanied by conscious experience? The theory provides a partial answer: because these oscillations are responsible for binding. +But the question of why binding itself should be accompanied by experience +is not addressed. The theory gains its purchase by assuming a link between +binding and consciousness, and therefore does nothing to explain it. +Crick and Koch seem sympathetic with the "big" problem of consciousness, calling it the "major puzzle confronting the neural view of the mind." +They argue that pure cognitive-level approaches are doomed to be unsuccessful, and that neural-level theories are required. But they give us no reason +to believe that their theory is better suited than cognitive theories when it +comes to answering the really difficult questions. Indeed, they do not claim +that their project handles the problem of experience. In a published interview, Koch is quite clear about the limitations of the approach: +Well, let's first forget about the really difficult aspects, like subjective feelings, +for they may not have a scientific solution. The subjective state of play, of pain, +of pleasure, of seeing blue, of smelling a rose—there seems to be a huge jump +between the materialistic level, of explaining molecules and neurons, and the +subjective level. Let's focus on things that are easier to study—like visual awareness. You're now talking to me, but you're not looking at me, you're looking at the cappuccino, and so you are aware of it. You can say, "It's a cup +and there's some liquid in it." If I give it to you, you'll move your arm and +you'll take it—you'll respond in a meaningful manner. That's what I call awareness.11 + +Another neurophysiological theory of consciousness has been outlined by +Gerald Edelman in The Remembered Present (1989) and other books and +articles. The central element of his theory involves re-entrant neural circuits +by which perceptual signals can be conceptually categorized before they +contribute to memory. Perceptual information and internal state interact in +a subtle way (as depicted in Figure 3.3) to give rise to "primary consciousness." His model of "higher-order consciousness" brings in a new memory +element through "semantic bootstrapping," which yields concepts of the self, +past, and, future. All this is linked to language production through Broca's +and Wernicke's areas. +Much of Edelman's work is devoted to the explanation of perception, +memory, and language, rather than of consciousness. Insofar as it is devoted +to consciousness, the discussion is often vague, but it seems that what ultimately might be explained by this sort of model is perceptual awareness— +that is, the effects of perceptual processing on later processes and on the +control of behavior—and aspects of self-consciousness, especially the origin +of the concept of the self. + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +117 + +PRIMARY +CONSCIOUSNESS +Reentrant Loop +Connecting ValueCategory Memory to +Current Perceptual +Categorization + +Figure 3.3. Edelman's scheme for higher-order consciousness. (Redrawn from +Figure 12-4, p. 132, from Bright Air, Brilliant Fire by Gerald M. Edelman. Copyright +© 1992 by BasicBooks, Inc. By permission of BasicBooks, a division of +HarperCollins, Inc.) + +Edelman gives no account of how all this processing should give rise to +conscious experience. He simply takes it that there is a correlation. He is +up-front about this, noting that phenomenal experience is the hardest problem for a theory of consciousness, and that no physical theory will take us +all the way to qualia: +This suggests an approach to the problem of qualia. As a basis for a theory of +consciousness, it is sensible to assume that, just as in ourselves, qualia exist in +other conscious human beings, whether they are considered as scientific observers or as subjects +We can then take human beings to be the best canonical +referent for the study of consciousness. This is justified by the fact that human +subjective reports (including those about qualia), actions, and brain structures +and function can all be correlated. After building a theory based on the assumption that qualia exist in human beings, we can then look anew at some of the +properties of qualia based on these correlations. It is our ability to report and +correlate while individually experiencing qualia that opens up the possibility of +a scientific investigation of consciousness. (Edelman 1992, p. 115) + + 118 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +As before, because this theory is based on the assumption of correlation, +it is clear that a reductive explanation of experience is not on offer. Most +of the time Edelman claims only to be explaining the processes that underlie conscious experience; he does not claim to be explaining experience +itself.12 + +5. The Appeal to New Physics +Sometimes it is held that the key to the explanation of consciousness may +lie in a new sort of physical theory. Perhaps, in arguing that consciousness +is not entailed by the physics of our world, we have been tacitly assuming +that the physics of our world is something like physics as we understand it +today, consisting in an arrangement of particles and fields in the spatiotemporal manifold, undergoing complex processes of causation and evolution. An +opponent might agree that nothing in this sort of physics entails the existence of consciousness, but argue that there might be a new kind of physical +theory from which consciousness falls out as a consequence. +It is not easy to evaluate this claim in the absence of any detailed proposal. +One would at least like to see an example of how such a new physics might +possibly go. Such an example need not be plausible in the light of current +theories, but there would have to be a sense in which it would recognizably +be physics. The crucial question is: How could a theory that is recognizably +a physical theory entail the existence of consciousness? If such a theory consists in a description of the structure and dynamics of fields, waves, particles, +and the like, then all the usual problems will apply. And it is unclear that +any sort of physical theory could be different enough from this to avoid +the problems. +The trouble is that the basic elements of physical theories seem always to +come down to two things: the structure and dynamics of physical processes. +Different theories invoke different sorts of structure. Newtonian physics +invokes a Euclidean space-time; relativity theory invokes a non-Euclidean +differential manifold; quantum theory invokes a Hilbert space for wave +functions. And different theories invoke different kinds of dynamics within +those structures: Newton's laws, the principles of relativity, the wave equations of quantum mechanics. But from structure and dynamics, we can only +get more structure and dynamics. This allows the possibility of satisfying +explanations of all sorts of high-level structural and functional properties, but +conscious experience will remain untouched. No set of facts about physical +structure and dynamics can add up to a fact about phenomenology. +Of course, there is a sense in which the physics of the universe must entail +the existence of consciousness, if one defines physics as the fundamental +science from whose facts and laws everything else follows. This construal of +physics, however, trivializes the question involved. If one allows physics to + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +119 + +include theories developed specifically to deal with the phenomenon of +consciousness, unmotivated by more basic considerations, then we may get +an "explanation" of consciousness, but it will certainly not be a reductive +one. For our purposes, it is best to take physics to be the fundamental science developed to explain observations of the external world. If this kind +of physics entailed the facts about consciousness, without invoking consciousness itself in a crucial role, then consciousness would truly be reductively +explained. For the reasons I have given, however, there is good reason to +believe that no such reductive explanation is possible. +Almost all existing proposals concerning the use of physics to explain +consciousness focus on the most puzzling part of physics, namely quantum +mechanics. This is understandable: for physics to explain consciousness would +take something extraordinary, and quantum mechanics is by far the most +extraordinary part of contemporary physics. But in the end it does not seem +to be extraordinary enough. +For example, Penrose (1994) suggests that the key to understanding consciousness may lie in a theory that reconciles quantum theory with the theory +of general relativity. He suggests that gravitational effects not yet understood +may be responsible for the collapse of the quantum wave function, leading +to a nonalgorithmic element in the laws of nature. Drawing on the ideas of +Hameroff (1994), he suggests that human cognition may depend on quantum +collapses in microtubules, which are protein structures found in the skeleton +of a neuron. Indeed, Penrose and Hameroff suggest that quantum collapse +in microtubules may be the physical basis of conscious experience. +These ideas are extremely speculative, but they could at least conceivably +help to explain certain elements of human cognitive functioning. Penrose +suggests that the nonalgorithmic element in collapse could explain certain +aspects of our mathematical insight, which he believes goes beyond the +capacity of any algorithmic system. Hameroff suggests that the collapse of +a superposed wave function might help explain certain aspects of human +decision making. But nothing here seems to help with the explanation of +conscious experience. Why should quantum processes in microtubules give +rise to consciousness? The question here is just as hard as the corresponding +question about classical processes in a classical brain. When it comes to the +problem of experience, nonalgorithmic and algorithmic processes are in the +same boat. +Some have suggested that the nonlocality of quantum mechanics, as suggested by recent experiments bearing on the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell's theorem, might be the key to a theory of consciousness (see +Lahav and Shanks 1992 for suggestions along these lines). But even if physics +is nonlocal, it is hard to see how this should help in the explanation of +consciousness. Even given a nonlocal physical process, it remains logically +possible that the process could take place in the absence of consciousness. +The explanatory gap is as wide as ever. + + 120 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +The most frequently noted connection between consciousness and quantum mechanics lies in the fact that on some interpretations of the latter, +measurement by a conscious observer is required to bring about the collapse +of the wave function. On this sort of interpretation, consciousness plays a +central role in the dynamics of the physical theory. These interpretations are highly controversial, but in any case it is notable that they do nothing to provide an explanation of consciousness. Rather, they simply assume +the existence of consciousness, and use it to help explain certain physical +phenomena. Theories of consciousness that exploit this relationship are occasionally put forward (e.g., Hodgson 1988; Stapp 1993), but they are certainly not reductive theories.13 +One cannot rule out the possibility that fundamental physical theories +such as quantum mechanics will play a key role in a theory of consciousness. +For example, perhaps consciousness will turn out to be associated with certain +fundamental physical properties, or with certain configurations of those +properties, or perhaps there will be a more subtle link. But all the same, +there is little hope that this sort of theory will provide a wholly physical +explanation of consciousness. When it comes to reductive explanation, physics-based theories are no better off than neurobioiogical and cognitive +theories. + +6. Evolutionary Explanation +Even those who take consciousness seriously are often drawn to the idea of +an evolutionary explanation of consciousness. After all, consciousness is such +a ubiquitous and central feature that it seems that it must have arisen during +the evolutionary process for a reason. In particular, it is natural to suppose +that it arose because there is some function that it serves that could not be +achieved without it. If we could get a clear enough idea of the relevant function, then we would have some idea of why consciousness exists. +Unfortunately, this idea overestimates what an evolutionary explanation +can provide us. The process of natural selection cannot distinguish between +me and my zombie twin. Evolution selects properties according to their +functional role, and my zombie twin performs all the functions that I perform +just as well as I do; in particular he leaves around just as many copies of his +genes. It follows that evolution alone cannot explain why conscious creatures +rather than zombies evolved. +Some may be tempted to respond, "But a zombie couldn't do all the things +that I can." But my zombie twin is by definition physically identical to me +over its history, so it certainly produces indistinguishable behavior. Anyone +wishing to question zombie capacity must therefore find something wrong +with the arguments at the start of this chapter, rather than raising the objection here. + + Can Consciousness Be Reductively Explained? + +121 + +To see the point in a different way, note that the real problem with +consciousness is to explain the principles in virtue of which consciousness +arises from physical systems. Presumably these principles—whether they are +conceptual truths, metaphysical necessities, or natural laws—are constant +over space-time: if a physical replica of me had popped into existence a +million years ago, it would have been just as conscious as I am. The connecting principles themselves are therefore independent of the evolutionary process. While evolution can be very useful in explaining why particular physical systems have evolved, it is irrelevant to the explanation of +the bridging principles in virtue of which some of these systems are conscious. + +7. Whither Reductive Explanation? +It is not uncommon for people to agree with critiques of specific reductive +accounts, but to qualify this agreement: "Of course that doesn't explain +consciousness, but if we just wait a while, an explanation will come along." +I hope the discussion here has made it clear that the problems with this +kind of explanation of consciousness are more fundamental than that. The +problems with the models and theories presented here do not lie in the +details; at least, we have not needed to consider the details in order to see +what is wrong with them. The problem lies in the overall explanatory strategy. +These models and theories are simply not the sort of thing that could explain consciousness. +It is inevitable that increasingly sophisticated reductive "explanations" of +consciousness will be put forward, but these will only produce increasingly +sophisticated explanations of cognitive functions. Even such "revolutionary" +developments as the invocation of connectionist networks, nonlinear dynamics, artificial life, and quantum mechanics will provide only more powerful +functional explanations. This may make for some very interesting cognitive +science, but the mystery of consciousness will not be removed. +Any account given in purely physical terms will suffer from the same +problem. It will ultimately be given in terms of the structural and dynamical +properties of physical processes, and no matter how sophisticated such an +account is, it will yield only more structure and dynamics. While this is +enough to handle most natural phenomena, the problem of consciousness +goes beyond any problem about the explanation of structure and function, +so a new sort of explanation is needed. +It might be supposed that there could eventually be a reductive explanatory +technique that explained something other than structure and function, but +it is very hard to see how this could be possible, given that the laws of physics +are ultimately cast in terms of structure and dynamics. The existence of + + 122 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +consciousness will always be a further fact relative to structural and dynamic +facts, and so will always be unexplained by a physical account. +For an explanation of consciousness, then, we must look elsewhere. We +certainly need not give up on explanation; we need only give up on reductive +explanation. The possibility of explaining consciousness nonreductively remains open. This would be a very different sort of explanation, requiring +some radical changes in the way we think about the structure of the world. +But if we make these changes, the beginnings of a theory of consciousness +may become visible in the distance. + + 4 + +Naturalistic Dualism + +1. An Argument Against Materialism +In the last chapter, I was concerned with the explanatory question, "Can +consciousness be explained by physical theories?" rather than the ontological question, "Is consciousness itself physical?" But the two questions are +closely related, and in this chapter I will draw out the ontological consequences of the arguments in the last chapter. In particular, the failure of +logical supervenience directly implies that materialism is false: there are +features of the world over and above the physical features. The basic argument for this goes as follows. +1. In our world, there are conscious experiences. +2. There is a logically possible world physically identical to ours, in +which the positive facts about consciousness in our world do not hold. +3. Therefore, facts about consciousness are further facts about our +world, over and above the physical facts. +4. So materialism is false. +If a physically identical zombie world is logically possible, it follows that +the presence of consciousness is an extra fact about our world, not guaranteed +by the physical facts alone. The character of our world is not exhausted +by the character supplied by the physical facts; there is extra character +due to the presence of consciousness. To use a phrase due to Lewis +(1990), consciousness carries phenomenal information. The physical facts incompletely constrain the way the world is; the facts about consciousness constrain it further. + + 124 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +A similar conclusion can be drawn from the logical possibility of a world +with inverted conscious experiences. Such a world is physically identical to +ours, but some of the facts about conscious experience in our world do not +hold in that world. It follows that the facts about conscious experience in +our world are further facts over and above the physical facts, and that +materialism is false. +Either way, if consciousness is not logically supervenient on the physical, +then materialism is false. The failure of logical supervenience implies that +some positive fact about our world does not hold in a physically identical +world, so that it is a further fact over and above the physical facts. As in +Chapter 2, I take materialism to be the doctrine that the physical facts about +the world exhaust all the facts, in that every positive fact is entailed by the +physical facts. If zombie worlds or inverted worlds are possible, the physical +facts do not entail all the positive facts about our world, and materialism +is false. +We can use Kripke's image here. When God created the world, after +ensuring that the physical facts held, he had more work to do. He had to +ensure that the facts about consciousness held. The possibility of zombie +worlds or inverted worlds shows that he had a choice. The world might have +lacked experience, or it might have contained different experiences, even if +all the physical facts had been the same. To ensure that the facts about +consciousness are as they are, further features had to be included in the +world. + +What sort of dualism? +This failure of materialism leads to a kind of dualism: there are both physical +and nonphysical features of the world. The falsity of logical supervenience +implies that experience is fundamentally different in kind from any physical +feature. But there are many varieties of dualism, and it is important to see +just where the argument leads us. +The arguments in the last chapter establish that consciousness does not +supervene logically on the physical, but this is not to say that it does not +supervene at all. There appears to be a systematic dependence of conscious +experience on physical structure in the cases with which we are familiar, and +nothing in the arguments of the last chapter suggests otherwise. It remains +as plausible as ever, for example, that if my physical structure were to be +replicated by some creature in the actual world, my conscious experience +would be replicated, too. So it remains plausible that consciousness supervenes naturally on the physical. It is this view—natural supervenience without logical supervenience—that I will develop. +The arguments do not lead us to a dualism such as that of Descartes, with +a separate realm of mental substance that exerts its own influence on physi- + + Naturalistic Dualism + +125 + +cal processes. The best evidence of contemporary science tells us that the +physical world is more or less causally closed: for every physical event, there +is a physical sufficient cause. If so, there is no room for a mental "ghost in +the machine" to do any extra causal work. A small loophole may be opened +by the existence of quantum indeterminacy, but I argue later that this probably cannot be exploited to yield a causal role for a nonphysical mind. In any +case, for all the arguments in the previous chapter, it remains plausible that +physical events can be explained in physical terms, so a move to a Cartesian +dualism would be a stronger reaction than is warranted. +The dualism implied here is instead a kind of property dualism: conscious +experience involves properties of an individual that are not entailed by the +physical properties of that individual, although they may depend lawfully +on those properties. Consciousness is a feature of the world over and above +the physical features of the world. This is not to say it is a separate "substance"; the issue of what it would take to constitute a dualism of substances +seems quite unclear to me. All we know is that there are properties of individuals in this world—the phenomenal properties—that are ontologically +independent of physical properties. +There is a weaker sort of property dualism with which this view should +not be confused. It is sometimes said that property dualism applies to any +domain in which the properties are not themselves properties invoked by +physics, or directly reducible to such properties. In this sense, even biological fitness is not a physical property. But this sort of "dualism" is a very +weak variety. There is nothing fundamentally ontologically new about properties such as fitness, as they are still logically supervenient on microphysical +properties. Property dualism of this variety is entirely compatible with materialism. By contrast, the property dualism that I advocate involves fundamentally new features of the world. Because these properties are not even logically supervenient on microphysical properties, they are nonphysical in a +much stronger sense. When I speak of property dualism and nonphysical +properties, it is this stronger view and the stronger sense of nonphysicality +that I have in mind. +It remains plausible, however, that consciousness arises from a physical +basis, even though it is not entailed by that basis. The position we are left +with is that consciousness arises from a physical substrate in virtue of certain +contingent laws of nature, which are not themselves implied by physical +laws. This position is implicitly held by many people who think of themselves +as materialists. It is common to hear, "Of course I'm a materialist; the mind +certainly arises from the brain." The very presence of the word "arises" +should be a tip-off here. One tends not to say "learning arises from the +brain," for instance—and if one did, it would be in a temporal sense of +"arises." Rather, one would more naturally say that learning is a process in +the brain. The very fact that the mind needs to arise from the brain indi- + + 126 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +cates that there is something further going on, over and above the physical +facts.1 +Some people will think that the view should count as a version of materialism rather than dualism, because it posits such a strong lawful dependence +of the phenomenal facts on the physical facts, and because the physical +domain remains autonomous. Of course there is little point arguing over a +name, but it seems to me that the existence of further contingent facts over +and above the physical facts is a significant enough modification to the received materialist world view to deserve a different label. Certainly, if all +that is required for materialism is that all facts be lawfully connected to the +physical facts, then materialism becomes a weak doctrine indeed. +Although it is a variety of dualism, there is nothing antiscientific or supernatural about this view. The best way to think about it is as follows. Physics +postulates a number of fundamental features of the world: space-time, massenergy, charge, spin, and so on. It also posits a number of fundamental laws +in virtue of which these fundamental features are related. Fundamental +features cannot be explained in terms of more basic features, and fundamental laws cannot be explained in terms of more basic laws; they must simply +be taken as primitive. Once the fundamental laws and the distribution of +the fundamental features are set in place, however, almost everything about +the world follows. That is why a fundamental theory in physics is sometimes +known as a "theory of everything." But the fact that consciousness does +not supervene on the physical features shows us that this physical theory is +not quite a theory of everything. To bring consciousness within the scope of +a fundamental theory, we need to introduce new fundamental properties +and laws. +In his book Dreams of a Final Theory (1992), physicist Steven Weinberg +notes that what makes a fundamental theory in physics special is that it leads +to an explanatory chain all the way up, ultimately explaining everything. But +he is forced to concede that such a theory may not explain consciousness. +At best, he says, we can explain the "objective correlates" of consciousness. +"That may not be an explanation of consciousness, but it will be pretty +close" (p. 45). But it is not close enough, of course. It does not explain +everything that is happening in the world. To be consistent, we must acknowledge that a truly final theory needs an additional component. +There are two ways this might go. Perhaps we might take experience itself +as a fundamental feature of the world, alongside space-time, spin, charge, +and the like. That is, certain phenomenal properties will have to be taken +as basic properties. Alternatively, perhaps there is some other class of novel +fundamental properties from which phenomenal properties are derived. Previous arguments have shown that these cannot be physical properties, but +perhaps they are nonphysical properties of a new variety, on which phenomenal properties are logically supervenient. Such properties would be related + + Naturalistic Dualism + +127 + +to experience in the same way that basic physical properties are related to +nonbasic properties such as temperature. We could call these properties +protophenomenal properties, as they are not themselves phenomenal but +together they can yield the phenomenal. Of course it is very hard to imagine +what a protophenomenal property could be like, but we cannot rule out the +possibility that they exist. Most of the time, however, I will speak as if the +fundamental properties are themselves phenomenal. +Where we have new fundamental properties, we also have new fundamental laws. Here the fundamental laws will be psychophysical laws, specifying +how phenomenal (or protophenomenal) properties depend on physical properties. These laws will not interfere with physical laws; physical laws already +form a closed system. Instead, they will be supervenience laws, telling us +how experience arises from physical processes. We have seen that the dependence of experience on the physical cannot be derived from physical laws, +so any final theory must include laws of this variety. +Of course, at this stage we have very little idea what the relevant fundamental theory will look like, or what the fundamental psychophysical laws will +be. But we have reason to believe that such a theory exists. There is good +reason to believe that there is a lawful relationship between physical processes and conscious experience, and any lawful relationship must be supported by fundamental laws. The case of physics tells us that fundamental +laws are typically simple and elegant; we should expect the same of the +fundamental laws in a theory of consciousness. Once we have a fundamental theory of consciousness to accompany a fundamental theory in physics, +we may truly have a theory of everything. Given the basic physical and +psychophysical laws, and given the distribution of the fundamental properties, we can expect that all the facts about the world will follow. Developing such a theory will not be straightforward, but it ought to be possible +in principle. +In a way, what is going on here with consciousness is analogous to what +happened with electromagnetism in the nineteenth century. There had been +an attempt to explain electromagnetic phenomena in terms of physical laws +that were already understood, involving mechanical principles and the like, +but this was unsuccessful. It turned out that to explain electromagnetic +phenomena, features such as electromagnetic charge and electromagnetic +forces had to be taken as fundamental, and Maxwell introduced new fundamental electromagnetic laws. Only this way could the phenomena be explained. In the same way, to explain consciousness, the features and laws of +physical theory are not enough. For a theory of consciousness, new fundamental features and laws are needed. +This view is entirely compatible with a contemporary scientific worldview, +and is entirely naturalistic. On this view, the world still consists in a network +of fundamental properties related by basic laws, and everything is to be + + 128 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +ultimately explained in these terms. All that has happened is that the inventory of properties and laws has been expanded, as happened with Maxwell. +Further, nothing about this view contradicts anything in physical theory; +rather, it supplements that theory. A physical theory gives a theory of physical +processes, and a psychophysical theory tells us how those processes give rise +to experience. +To capture the spirit of the view I advocate, I call it naturalistic dualism. +It is naturalistic because it posits that everything is a consequence of a +network of basic properties and laws, and because it is compatible with all +the results of contemporary science. And as with naturalistic theories in +other domains, this view allows that we can explain consciousness in terms +of basic natural laws. There need be nothing especially transcendental about +consciousness; it is just another natural phenomenon. All that has happened +is that our picture of nature has expanded. Sometimes "naturalism" is taken +to be synonymous with "materialism," but it seems to me that a commitment +to a naturalistic understanding of the world can survive the failure of materialism. (If a reader doubts this, I point to the rest of this work as evidence.) +Some might find a certain irony in the name of the view, but what is most +important is that it conveys the central message: to embrace dualism is not +necessarily to embrace mystery. +In some ways, those who hold this sort of dualism may be temperamentally +closer to materialists than to dualists of other varieties. This is partly because +of its avoidance of any transcendental element and its commitment to natural +explanation, and partly because of its commitment to the physical causation +of behavior. Conversely, by avoiding any commitment to a ghost in the +machine, this view avoids the worst implausibilities of the traditional dualist +views. One often hears that the successes of cognitive science and neuroscience make dualism implausible, but not all varieties of dualism are affected +equally. These successes are all grounded in physical explanations of behavior +and of other physical phenomena, and so do not distinguish between the +materialist and the naturalistic dualist view. +Two final notes. Some will wonder why, if experience is fundamental, it +does not qualify as a physical property. After all, is not physics just the +science of what is truly fundamental? In reply: Certainly if we define physics +that way, experience will indeed qualify as a physical property, and the +supervenience laws will count as laws of physics. But on a more natural +reading of "physics" and "physical," experience does not qualify. Experience is not a fundamental property that physicists need to posit in their +theory of the external world; physics forms a closed, consistent theory even +without experience. Given the possibility of a zombie world, there is a clear +sense in which experience is superfluous to physics as it is usually understood. +It is therefore more natural to consider experience as a fundamental property + + Naturalistic Dualism + +129 + +that is not a physical property, and to consider the psychophysical laws as +fundamental laws of nature that are not laws of physics. But nothing much +turns on the terminological issue, as long as the shape of the view is clear. +I should also note that although I call the view a variety of dualism, it is +possible that it could turn out to be a kind of monism. Perhaps the physical +and the phenomenal will turn out to be two different aspects of a single +encompassing kind, in something like the way that matter and energy turn +out to be two aspects of a single kind. Nothing that I have said rules this +out, and in fact I have some sympathy with the idea. But it remains the case +that if a variety of monism is true, it cannot be a materialist monism. It must +be something broader. +Objections +There are a number of objections that might be raised to the argument +against materialism at the beginning of this chapter. Some of these are +objections to premise (2), the denial of logical supervenience; I have dealt +with objections of that sort in the previous chapter. Here, I will deal with +objections to the step from the failure of logical supervenience to the falsity +of materialism. The most serious objections of this sort are those that invoke +a posteriori necessity. I will deal with these in the next section. Here I will +deal with some more minor objections. +Sometimes it is argued that consciousness might be an emergent property, +in a sense that is still compatible with materialism. In recent work on complex +systems and artificial life, it is often held that emergent properties are unpredictable from low-level properties, but that they are physical all the same. +Examples are the emergence of self-organization in biological systems, or +the emergence of flocking patterns from simple rules in simulated birds (Langton 1990; Reynolds 1987). But emergent properties of this sort are not +analogous to consciousness. What is interesting about these cases is that the +relevant properties are not obvious consequences of low-level laws; but they +are still logically supervenient on low-level facts. If all the physical facts +about such a system over time are given, then the fact that self-organization +is occurring will be straightforwardly derivable. This is just what we would +expect, as properties such as self-organization and flocking are straightforwardly functional and structural. +If consciousness is an emergent property, it is emergent in a much stronger +sense. There is a stronger notion of emergence, used by the British emergentists (e.g., Broad [1925]), according to which emergent properties are not +even predictable from the entire ensemble of low-level physical facts. It is +reasonable to say (as the British emergentists did) that conscious experience +is emergent in this sense. But this sort of emergence is best counted as a + + 130 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +variety of property dualism. Unlike the more "innocent" examples of emergence given above, the strong variety requires new fundamental laws in +order that the emergent properties emerge. +Another objection is that consciousness and the physical might be two +aspects of the same thing, in the way that the morning star and the evening +star are two aspects of Venus. If so, consciousness might in a sense be +physical. But again, we have to ask: Is the phenomenal aspect entailed by +the physical aspect? If it is, we have a variety of materialism, but we are +back to the arguments in Chapter 3. If it is not, then the phenomenal aspect +provides further contingency in the world over and above the physical aspect, +and the duality of the aspects gives us a kind of property dualism. Perhaps +it may turn out that the duality of the physical and the phenomenal can be +subsumed under a grander monism, but this will not be a monism of the +physical alone. +A third objection is suggested by the work of Searle (1992). Like me, +Searle holds that consciousness is merely naturally supervenient on the +physical. He allows that a zombie replica is logically possible, holding that +consciousness is merely caused by states of the brain. But he denies that this +is a variety of dualism, even property dualism. This might seem to be a +mere terminological issue, but Searle insists that the ontological status of +consciousness is the same as that of physical features such as liquidity, so +the issue is not merely terminological. Searle's argument that the view is not +dualistic is that a similar story holds elsewhere: for example, H2O causes +liquidity, but no one is a dualist about liquidity. +It seems clear that this is a false analogy, however. Given all the microphysical facts about a particular batch of H2O, it is logically impossible that +those facts could hold without liquidity being instantiated. The notion of a +nonliquid replica of a batch of liquid H2O is simply incoherent. It follows +that the relation between the microphysical facts and liquidity is much tighter +than a simple causal relation. The microphysical features do not cause liquidity; they constitute it. This is entirely different from what is going on in the +case of consciousness, so the analogy fails. Consciousness is ontologically +novel in a much more significant way than liquidity.2 +Finally, some will find the argument for dualism that I have given reminiscent of the argument given by Descartes. Descartes argued that he could +imagine his mind existing separately from his body, so his mind could not +be identical to his body. This sort of argument is generally regarded to be +flawed: just because one can imagine that A and B are not identical, it does +not follow that A and B are not identical (think of the morning star and the +evening star, for example). Might not my argument make a similar mistake? +The zombie world only shows that it is conceivable that one might have a +physical state without consciousness; it does not show that a physical state +and consciousness are not identical. + + Naturalistic Dualism + +131 + +This is to misunderstand the argument, however. It is crucial that the +argument as I have put it does not turn on questions of identity but of +supervenience. The form of the argument is not, "One can imagine physical +state P without consciousness, therefore consciousness is not physical state +P." The form of the argument is rather, "One can imagine all the physical +facts holding without the facts about consciousness holding, so the physical +facts do not exhaust all the facts." This is an entirely different sort of argument. In general, modal arguments for dualism that are cast in terms of +identity are less conclusive than modal arguments cast in terms of supervenience; this is one reason why I have put things in terms of supervenience +throughout, and avoided talk of identity almost entirely. It seems to me that +the issues about supervenience are the most fundamental here. +One might nevertheless try to reply to this argument with a strategy analogous to the reply to Descartes. For example, one might note that my strategy +still relies on a sort of inference from conceivability to possibility that might +be questioned. I consider strategies along these lines in the next section. + +2. Objections From A Posteriori Necessity* +A popular response to this sort of argument is to object that it only establishes +that a zombie world is logically possible, which is quite different from being +metaphysically possible. Whereas conceptual coherence suffices for logical +possibility, metaphysical possibility is more constrained. The point is also +often made by suggesting that there is a difference between conceivability +and true possibility. Although it may be the case that a zombie world is +conceivable, something more is required in order to show that it is possible +in the metaphysical sense relevant to the falsity of materialism. +This objection is most often accompanied by an appeal to Kripke's Naming +and Necessity (1980), which demonstrates the existence of necessary truths +such as "Water is H2O" whose necessity is only knowable a posteriori. In +the terms of these objectors, it is logically possible that water is not H2O, +but it is not metaphysically possible. It is not unnatural to suppose that +zombies might be logically possible but metaphysically impossible in a similar +way. If so, this would arguably be enough to save materialism. +This is by far the most common strategy of materialists who are persuaded +that there is no entailment between physical and phenomenal concepts. On +this view, there can be a conceptual gap without a metaphysical gap. The +view offers the enticing prospect of taking consciousness seriously while +nevertheless holding on to materialism. Unfortunately, upon close examination the view can be seen quite straightforwardly to fail. The notion of a +posteriori necessity cannot carry the burden that this argument requires, and +in fact is something of a red herring in this context.3 + + 132 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +We can best see this by using the two-dimensional framework for dealing +with a posteriori necessity developed in Chapter 2, section 4. Recall that in +this framework there are two intensions (functions from possible worlds to +referents) associated with any concept: a primary intension (determined a +priori) that fixes reference in the actual world, and a secondary intension +(determined a posteriori) that picks out reference in counterfactual worlds. +The primary intension associated with "water" is something like "watery +stuff." The secondary intension is "H2O," which is derived from the primary +intension by applying Kaplan's dthat operator: "dthat(watery stuff)" picks +out H2O in all possible worlds, as watery stuff is H2O in the actual world. +"Logical possibility" comes down to the possible truth of a statement +when evaluated according to the primary intensions involved (what I called +1-possibility in Chapter 2). The primary intensions of "water" and "H2O" +differ, so it is logically possible in this sense that water is not H2O. "Metaphysical possibility" comes down to the possible truth of a statement when evaluated according to the secondary intensions involved (that is, 2-possibility). +The secondary intensions of "water" and "H2O" are the same, so it is +metaphysically necessary that water is H2O. +The objection therefore comes down to the point that in using arguments +from conceivability and the like, we have demonstrated the possibility of a +zombie world using the primary intensions of the notions involved, but not +using the more appropriate secondary intensions. While the primary intension of phenomenal notions may not correspond to that of any physical +notion, the secondary intensions may be the same. If so, then phenomenal +and physical/functional concepts may pick out the same properties a posteriori despite the a priori distinction. Such an objection might be made by an +advocate of "psychofunctionalism" (see Block 1980), which equates phenomenal properties with functional properties a posteriori, or by an advocate +of a view that equates phenomenal properties with certain neurophysiological +properties a posteriori. +The easiest way to see that none of this affects the argument for dualism +is to note that the argument I have given goes through if we concentrate on +the primary intension throughout and ignore the secondary intension. We +saw in Chapter 2 that it is the primary intension that is most relevant +to explanation, but it also serves us well in the argument for dualism. For +note that whether or not the primary and secondary intensions coincide, the +primary intension determines a perfectly good property of objects in possible +worlds. The property of being watery stuff is a perfectly reasonable property, +even though it is not the same as the property of being H2O. If we can show +that there are possible worlds that are physically identical to ours but in +which the property introduced by the primary intension is lacking, then +dualism will follow. +This is just what has been done with consciousness. We have seen that there +are worlds physically just like ours that lack consciousness, according to the + + Naturalistic Dualism + +133 + +primary intension thereof. This difference in worlds is sufficient to show that +there are properties of our world over and above the physical properties. +By analogy, if we could show that there were worlds physically identical to +ours in which there was no watery stuff, we would have established dualism +about water just as well as if we had established that there were worlds +physically identical to ours in which there was no H2O. And importantly, +the difference with respect to the primary intension can be established independently of a posteriori factors, so that considerations about a posteriori +necessity are irrelevant. +(Two technical notes here: Strictly speaking, a primary intension determines a center-relative property of an object in a possible world (or a relation +between objects and centers), as the primary intension applies to centered +possible worlds. But this relativity cannot be exploited to help our objector. +Once the location of a center is specified, a primary intension determines a +perfectly good nonindexical property; and all the arguments of Chapter 3 +go through even when the location of the center is included in the supervenience base. For example, even if Mary's facts about the world include facts +about where she is located, this will not enable her to know what it is like +to see red. +One might also be worried by the fact that the concept of consciousness +is arguably not present at the center of the zombie world, whereas the application of a primary intension might require the presence of the relevant +concept at the center of the world. (One might even start worrying about +the application of the zombie's concept!) I think the situation is more subtle +than this—primary intensions need not require the presence of the original +concept—but in any case, we can bypass this worry altogether simply by +considering a partial zombie world: one in which I am at the center, conscious, +with all the relevant concepts, but in which some other people are zombies.) +The irrelevance of a posteriori necessity can be further supported by the +observation that with consciousness, the primary and secondary intensions +coincide. What it takes for a state to be a conscious experience in the actual +world is for it to have a phenomenal feel, and what it takes for something +to be a conscious experience in a counterfactual world is for it to have a +phenomenal feel. The difference between the primary and secondary intensions for the concept of water reflects the fact that there could be something +that looks and feels like water in some counterfactual world that in fact is +not water, but merely watery stuff. But if something feels like a conscious +experience, even in some counterfactual world, it is a conscious experience. +All it means to be a conscious experience, in any possible world, is to have +a certain feel. (Kripke makes a similar point, although he puts the point in +terms of essential properties rather than in terms of meaning.) +Even if someone insists that the primary and the secondary intensions +differ, however, the argument still goes through. We simply focus on +the primary intension used to fix reference, as above. For instance, if "con- + + 134 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +sciousness" comes to "dthat (has a phenomenal feel)", then we simply focus +on the intension "has a phenomenal feel." The arguments in Chapter 3 +establish that there is a possible world in which my replica lacks a phenomenal feel, so the property of having a phenomenal feel is a fact over and +above the physical facts, and the argument for dualism is successful.4 +The most general way to make the point is to note that nothing about +Kripke's a posteriori necessity renders any logically possible worlds impossible. It simply tells us that some of them are misdescribed, because we +are applying terms according to their primary intensions rather than the +more appropriate secondary intensions. One might have thought it possible +a priori that water is XYZ, rather than H2O. In conceiving this, one imagines +something like a world in which XYZ is the liquid found in oceans and lakes. +However, Kripke's analysis shows us that due to the way the actual world +turns out, we are misdescribing this world as one in which XYZ is water, as +we are describing it with the primary intension instead of the more appropriate secondary intension. Strictly speaking, it is a world in which XYZ is +watery stuff. These considerations cannot show the impossibility of this +apparently possible world; they simply show us the correct way to describe it. +As we saw in Chapter 2, Kripkean considerations show us that the secondary intension Fa: W — R sometimes differs from the primary intension +/ : W* — R. This puts some a posteriori constraints on the application +conditions of concepts, but the relevant space of worlds stays constant +throughout; the only difference between the arguments of the two functions +involves the location of a center. So although there may be two kinds of +possibility of statements, there is only one relevant kind of possibility of +worlds. +It follows that if there is a conceivable world that is physically identical +to ours but which lacks certain positive features of our world, then no +considerations about the designation of terms such as "consciousness" can +do anything to rule out the metaphysical possibility of the world. We can +simply forget the semantics of these terms, and note that the relevant possible world clearly lacks something, whether or not we call it "consciousness." +The Kripkean considerations might tell us at best how this world and the +relevant features should be appropriately described, but they have no effect +on its possibility; and the mere possibility of such a world, no matter how +it is described, is all the argument for dualism needs to succeed. +An alternative strategy +There is a quite different way in which one might appeal to a posteriori +necessity in order to avoid dualism. It might be argued that to claim that +the zombie world is physically identical to ours is to misdescribe it. Just as +the XYZ world seems to contain water but does not, the zombie world seems + + Naturalistic Dualism + +135 + +physically identical while being physically different. This may sound strange, +but there is a way to cash it out. An opponent might argue that there are +properties essential to the physical constitution of the world that are not +accessible to physical investigation. In conceiving of a "physically identical" +world, we are really only conceiving of a world that is identical from the +standpoint of physical investigation, while differing in the inaccessible essential properties, which are also the properties that guarantee consciousness. +For example, it might be that for something to qualify as an electron in +a counterfactual world, it is not sufficient that it be causally related to other +physical entities in the way that an electron is. Some hidden essence of +electronhood might also be required. On this view, the concept of an electron +is something like "dthat(the entity that plays the electron role)." Reference +to electrons is fixed by an extrinsic characterization, but is then rigidified so +that entities with the same intrinsic nature are picked out in counterfactual +worlds, regardless of whether they play the appropriate role, and so that +entities that play the role in those worlds do not qualify as electrons unless +they have the appropriate intrinsic nature. The same might go for properties +such as mass, which might be understood as "dthat(the property that plays +the mass role)." The essential nature of electrons or of mass would then +be hidden to physical theory, which characterizes electrons and mass only +extrinsically. If so, it might be that the relevant essential properties are +themselves phenomenal or protophenomenal properties, so that their instantiation could guarantee the existence of consciousness in our world. +If this were the case, the zombie world that we are conceiving would lack +these hidden essential properties and would therefore fail to be physically +identical to our world. The zombie world would give the same results as +our world when evaluated according to the primary intensions of physical +predicates, which apply on the basis of extrinsic relations, but not when +evaluated according to the secondary intensions, which require the hidden +essence. Given this, conscious experience might supervene "metaphysically" +on physical properties after all. (An argument very much like this is given +by Maxwell [1978], and is also suggested by the approach in Lockwood +[1989]. As Maxwell puts it, the basic idea is that even though phenomenal +concepts cannot be given topic-neutral analyses that pick out underlying +physical properties, physical concepts can be given topic-neutral analyses +that might pick out underlying phenomenal properties.5) +This is in many ways a more interesting objection than the previous one. +It certainly relies on a speculative metaphysics, but this does not prevent it +from being a coherent position. A more direct reply is that it relies on an +incorrect view of the semantics of physical terms. Arguably, physical predicates apply even a posteriori on the basis of extrinsic relations between +physical entities, irrespective of any hidden properties. This is a purely conceptual question: if electrons in our world have hidden protophenomenal + + 136 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +properties, would we call an otherwise identical counterfactual entity that +lacks those properties an electron? I think we would. Not only is reference +to electrons fixed by the role that electrons play in a theory; the very concept +of an electron is defined by that role, which determines the application of +the concept across all worlds. The notion of an electron that has all the +extrinsic properties of actual protons does not appear to be coherent, and +neither does the notion that there is a world in which mass plays the role +that charge actually plays. The semantic account given above predicts +that these notions should be coherent, and so gives a false account of the +concepts. +Semantic intuitions may differ, but as usual there is a reply that runs +deeper than the semantic intuitions. Even if we allow that certain hidden +properties could be constitutive of physical properties, the difference between +this view and the property dualism that I have advocated is small. It remains +the case that the world has phenomenal properties that are not fixed by the +properties that physics reveals. After ensuring that a world is identical to +ours from the standpoint of our physical theories, God has to expend further +effort to make that world identical to ours across the board. The dualism of +"physical" and "nonphysical" properties is replaced on this view by a dualism +of "accessible" and "hidden" physical properties, but the essential point +remains. +The view that physical entities have an intrinsic protophenomenal nature +is one to which I will return, but the metaphysics of the view remains much +the same regardless of the approach we take to the semantics of physical +predicates. As before, secondary intensions and a posteriori necessity make +only a semantic and not a metaphysical difference. However the view is +spelled out, it admits phenomenal or protophenomenal properties as fundamental, and so remains closer to a version of dualism (or perhaps an idealism +or a neutral monism, as I discuss later) than to a version of materialism. +Strong metaphysical necessity +The two-dimensional analysis just discussed establishes that an invocation +of Kripkean a posteriori necessity has no force against the argument from +supervenience. This sort of necessity does not put a posteriori constraints +on the space of possible worlds, but merely constrains the way in which +certain terms are used to describe them; so if there is a logically possible +world that is identical to ours in all physical respects but not in all positive +respects, then these considerations cannot count against the world's metaphysical possibility. +Some may claim, however, that the relevant worlds might be metaphysically impossible nevertheless. It could be held that there is a modality of +metaphysical possibility that is distinct from and more constrained than + + Naturalistic Dualism + +137 + +logical possibility, and that arises for reasons independent of the Kripkean +considerations. On this view, there are fewer metaphysically possible worlds +than there are logically possible worlds, and the a posteriori necessity of +certain statements can stem from factors quite independent of the semantics +of the terms involved. We can call this hypothesized modality strong metaphysical necessity, as opposed to the weak metaphysical necessity introduced +by the Kripkean framework. +On this view, there are worlds that are entirely conceivable, even according +to the strongest strictures on conceivability, but which are not possible at +all. This is a gap between conceivability and possibility much stronger than +any gap found elsewhere. There is a sense in which the truth of statements +such as "Water is XYZ" is conceivable but not possible, but these examples +never rule out the possibility of any conceivable world, They are merely +instances in which such a world is misdescribed. Strong metaphysical necessity goes beyond this. On this position, "zombie world" may correctly describe the world that we are conceiving, even according to a secondary +intension. It is just that the world is not metaphysically possible.6 +The short answer to this objection is that there is no reason to believe that +such a modality exists. Such "metaphysical necessities" will put constraints on +the space of possible worlds that are brute and inexplicable. It may be +reasonable to countenance brute, inexplicable facts about our world, but the +existence of such facts about the space of possible worlds would be quite +bizarre. The realm of the possible (as opposed to the realm of the natural) +has no room for this sort of arbitrary constraint. +The position cannot be supported by analogy, as no analogies are available.7 We have already seen that analogies with the necessity of "Water is +H2O," "Hesperus is Phosphorus," and so on fail, as these examples require +only a single space of worlds. Indeed, if some worlds are logically possible +but metaphysically impossible, it seems that we could never know it. By +assumption the information is not available a priori, and a posteriori information only tells us about our world. This can serve to locate our world in +the space of possible worlds, but it is hard to see how it could give information +about the extent of that space. Any claims about the added constraints of +metaphysical possibility would seem to be a matter of arbitrary stipulation; +one might as well stipulate that it is metaphysically impossible that a stone +could move upward when one lets go of it. +Further, the position leads to an ad hoc proliferation of modalities. If it +were accepted, we would have to countenance four kind of possibility and +necessity of statements, even leaving the natural modality aside: possibility +and necessity according to primary or secondary intensions, over the space +of logically possible or metaphysically possible worlds. And considering the +possibility of worlds rather than statements, we would now have three objective classes of possible worlds: logically possible worlds, metaphysically pos- + + 138 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +sible worlds, and naturally possible worlds. We have good reason to believe +in the first and the last of these classes, but we have very little reason to +believe in a third, distinct class as a metaphysical given. +Someone who holds that a zombie world is logically possible but metaphysically impossible has to answer the key question: Why couldn't God have +created a zombie world? Presumably it is in God's powers, when creating +the world, to do anything that is logically possible. Yet the advocate of +metaphysical necessity must say either the possibility is coherent, but God +could not have created it, or God could have created it, but it is nevertheless +metaphysically impossible. The first is quite unjustified, and the second is +entirely arbitrary. If the second holds, in any case, an argument against materialism still goes through; after fixing the physical facts about the world, +God still had more work to do. +Even if this view were accepted, it would look very much like the property +dualism I advocate, in many crucial respects. On this view, it would still be +the case that the existence of consciousness cannot be derived from physical knowledge, so that consciousness cannot be reductively explained. And +it would remain the case that we would need certain primitive connecting +principles to explain the supervenience of the phenomenal on the physical. +The only difference between the views is that the relevant psychophysical +principles are deemed to be brute "laws of necessity" rather than laws of +nature. For all explanatory purposes in constructing a theory, we are left in +the same position in which property dualism leaves us; the main difference +is in an ontological stipulation. +The only real motivation for this view would seem to be to save materialism at all costs, perhaps because of perceived problems with dualism. But +this sort of materialism seems far more mysterious than the dualist alternative. The invocation of brute "metaphysically necessary" principles constraining the space of possible worlds introduces an element much more +problematic, and indeed far less naturalistic, than the mere invocation of +further natural laws postulated by property dualism. In the end, the invocation of a new degree of necessity is a sort of solution by ad hoc stipulation +that raises as many problems as it answers. The view saves materialism +only at the cost of making it entirely mysterious how consciousness could +be physical.8 +Cognitive limitations +There is a final position that might be taken by a materialist who finds the +zombie world conceivable but still wants to save materialism. In the position +discussed above, the materialist accepts that the zombie notion is entirely +coherent, even to a maximally rational being, but nevertheless denies its +metaphysical possibility, thus leading to a "two-layered" picture of logically + + Naturalistic Dualism + +139 + +and metaphysically possible worlds. But a materialist might also argue that +the apparent conceivability arises from some sort of impaired rationality, so +that if we were only more intelligent we would see that the description of +the world is not coherent after all. On this view, .the world is not really even +logically possible; it is just that the limitations of human cognitive faculties +mislead us into believeing that it is. (This may be one interpretation of the +position of McGinn [1989].) +One might try to support this position by analogy with the necessity of +certain complex mathematical truths that lie beyond our powers of mathematical insight. If our mathematical powers are computable, such truths must +exist (by Godel's theorem), and even if not, they may well exist all the same. +(Perhaps Goldbach's conjecture is an example, or perhaps the continuum +hypothesis or its negation.) These truths are necessary even though they are +not knowable a priori by us, nor are they grounded in a combination of +a priori knowable and empirical factors in the manner of Kripkean necessities. Perhaps the implication from physical facts to phenomenal facts is a +necessity of this form, somehow beyond our powers of modal comprehension?9 +The analogy is imperfect, however. In the mathematical case, our modal +reasoning leaves the matter open; our conceivability intuitions do not tell +us anything one way or the other. There may be some weak sense in which +it is "conceivable" that the statements are false—for example, they are false +for all we know—but this is not a sense that delivers a conceivable world +where they fail. In the zombie case, by contrast, the matter is not left open: +there seems to be a clearly conceivable world in which the implication is +false. To save materialism, the possibility of this world has to be ruled out +despite the best evidence of our modal powers; but nothing in the mathematical case comes close to providing an example whereby an apparently possible +world is ruled out in this way. Once again, any gap between conceivability +and possibility that the materialist might invoke here must be sui generis, +unsupported by relevant analogies elsewhere.10 +Of course, a materialist might bite the bullet and make a case for a sui +generis cognitive impairment. To do this, she would have to hold that the +arguments in Chapter 3 all go wrong in ways that we cannot appreciate. Apart +from requiring that imperfect rationality leads our conceivability intuitions +to go massively astray, the view also requires that a smarter version of Mary +really could know what it is like to see red on the basis of physical information, and that there is an analysis of phenomenal concepts to support the +implication from physical to phenomenal facts (perhaps a structural or functional analysis), although one whose correctness lies beyond our powers +of appreciation. +While it must be conceded that any philosophical argument could go wrong +because of cognitive impairment, in the absence of any substantial reason + + 140 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +to believe this, this sort of objection seems quite ad hoc. As before, the main +motivation would seem to be a desire to hang onto materialism at all costs. +Such an option should always be the last option considered, only after we +have given up on both substantial arguments pointing out where we have +gone wrong and substantial attempts to develop an alternative to materialism. +If we find a substantial alternative that is satisfactory, then any motivation +for this view will disappear.11 + +3. Other Arguments for Dualism* +I am not the first to use the argument from logical possibility against materialism.12 Indeed, I think that in one form or another it is the fundamental +antimaterialist argument in the philosophy of mind. Nevertheless, it has not +received the careful attention it deserves. More attention has focused on +two antimaterialist arguments by Jackson (1982) and Kripke (1972). These +arguments strike me as related, but as perhaps less fundamental. Jackson's +argument is important for the entry it provides to the argument from logical +supervenience, and the most compelling portion of Kripke's argument depends on the argument from logical supervenience, as we will see. +Jackson's argument +I have already discussed Jackson's argument, the knowledge argument, in +the context of establishing the failure of logical supervenience, where it +plays a supporting role. Recall that the argument is concerned with Mary, +a neuroscientist brought up in a black-and-white room, who knows all the +physical facts about color processing in the brain. Later, when she first sees +a red object, she learns some new facts. In particular, she learns what it is +like to see red. The argument concludes that the physical facts do not exhaust +all the facts, and that materialism is false. +This argument is closely related to the arguments from zombies or inverted +spectra, in that both revolve around the failure of phenomenal facts to be +entailed by physical facts. In a way, they are flip sides of the same argument. +As a direct argument against materialism, however, Jackson's argument +is often seen as vulnerable due to its use of the intensional notion of knowledge. Many attacks on the argument have centered on this intensionality— +arguing, for example, that the same fact can be known in two different ways. +These attacks fail, I think, but the most straightforward way to see this is +to proceed directly to the failure of supervenience, which is cast in terms of +metaphysics rather than epistemology. The framework I have developed +helps bring out just why the various objections do not succeed. I will discuss +some of these objections in what follows. + + Naturalistic Dualism + +141 + +First, various respondents have argued that although Mary gains new +knowledge upon seeing red, this knowledge does not correspond to any new +fact. She simply comes to know an old fact in a new way, under a new "mode +of presentation," due to the intensionality of knowledge (Churchland 1985; +Morgan 1984b; Lycan 1995; McMullen 1985; Papineau 1993; Teller 1992; Tye +1986). For example, Tye and Lycan appeal to the intensional difference +between "This liquid is water" and "This liquid is H2O": in a sense these +express the same fact, but one can be known without the other. Similarly, +Churchland appeals to the gap between knowledge of temperature and +knowledge of mean kinetic energy, Morgan discusses the difference between +knowledge of Clark Kent and knowledge of Superman, while McMullen +points to Mark Twain and Samuel Clemens. +These gaps arise precisely because of the difference between primary and +secondary intensions. One can know things about water without knowing +things about H2O because the primary intensions differ—there is no a priori +connection between water thoughts and H2O thoughts. Nevertheless, in a +sense there is only one set of facts about the two: because of the a posteriori +identity between water and H2O, the relevant secondary intensions coincide. +(It is not obvious that one has to individuate facts this way, so that water +facts and H2O facts are the same facts, but I will go along with this for the +sake of argument.13) In the terminology used earlier, "If this is water, it is +H2O" is logically contingent but metaphysically necessary. This objection +therefore comes to precisely the same thing as the objection from the distinction between logical necessity and (Kripkean) metaphysical necessity discussed earlier, and the discussion there of primary and secondary intensions +is sufficient to refute it. +We can also put the point a more direct way. Whenever one knows a fact +under one mode of presentation but not under another, there will always +be a different fact that one lacks knowledge of—a fact that connects the two +modes of presentation.14 If one knows that Hesperus is visible but not that +Phosphorus is visible (because one does not know that Hesperus is Phosphorus), then one does not know that one object is both the brightest star in +the morning sky and the brightest star in the evening sky. This is a separate +fact that one lacks knowledge of entirely. Similarly, if one knows that Superman can fly but not that Clark Kent can fly, then one does not know that +there is an individual who is both the lead reporter at the Daily Planet and +who wears a cape. If one knows that water is wet but not that H2O is wet, +one does not know that the stuff in the lakes is made out of H2O molecules. +And so on. +More formally: Say that "a is G" and "6 is G" are the same fact in this +sense, but one cannot connect the two facts a priori. This must be because +a = b and the secondary intensions are the same, but the primary intensions +are different: perhaps a is equivalent to dthat(P) and b to dthat(Q). If one + + 142 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +knows that a is G but not that b is G, then one lacks the factual knowledge +that something is both P and Q. More generally, one lacks the factual +knowledge that something is both P' and Q', where these are any identifying +descriptions such that one knows that a is P' and that b is Q'. This fact is quite +separate from the facts that one initially possessed. Even when interpreted +according to secondary intensions, there will be a possible world in which +a is Fbut in which nothing is both P and Q (or both P' and Q'). +(As in section 2, there is the complication that P and Q may be indexrelative properties, but this changes nothing fundamental. To make the +unknown novel fact strictly nonindexical, one need only move to the fact +"There exists a point [with property X] from which P and Q pick out the +same thing." X is a backup just in case one knows of some other location +from which P and Q pick out the same thing; in such a case, we simply make +X specific enough to distinguish oneself from those other locations. The +extreme case where one lacks any distinguishing self-knowledge reduces to +the pure indexical case, discussed below.) +It follows that if Mary gains any factual knowledge that she previously +lacked—even if it is only knowledge of an old fact under a different mode of +presentation—then there must be some truly novel fact that she gains knowledge of. In particular, she must come to know a new fact involving that +mode of presentation. Given that she already knew all the physical facts, it +follows that materialism is false. The physical facts are in no sense exhaustive. +This rejoinder may seem less straightforward than the corresponding rejoinder to the argument from logical possibility. The supervenience framework eliminates the less clear-cut question of how to individuate pieces of +knowledge, and so makes discussion less confusing. All the same, close +analysis shows that water-H2O analogies and related objections fail equally +either way. Despite the fact that this is easily the most popular response to +the knowledge argument, it is also easily the weakest of the major replies. +It simply does not hold up to scrutiny. +A second, more sophisticated objection, due to Loar (1990), also holds +that Mary gains new knowledge of old facts because of intensionality, but +explicitly goes beyond the usual water-H2O analogies. Loar recognizes that +analogies with the usual examples cannot do the job for the materialist, as +(in our terminology) such analogies allow that physical and phenomenal +notions have distinct primary intensions, and the antimaterialist can simply +apply the argument to the property corresponding to the primary intension. +As Loar puts it, even though "heat" and some statistical-mechanical predicate designate the same property (secondary intension), they nevertheless +introduce distinct properties (primary intension). So he takes the argument +further, and argues that two predicates can introduce the same property—that is, share the same primary intension—even when this sameness +is not knowable a priori. If so, then Mary's knowledge of phenomenal proper- + + Naturalistic Dualism + +143 + +ties may just be knowledge of physical/functional properties, even though +she could not have connected the two beforehand. +But how can two primary intensions coincide without our being able to +know it a priori! Only if the space of possible worlds is smaller than we +would have thought a priori. We think the intensions differ because we +conceive of a world where they have different reference, such as a zombie +world. Loar's position therefore requires that this world is not really possible, +despite the fact that we cannot rule it out on conceptual grounds, and despite +the fact that Kripkean a posteriori necessity cannot do any work for us. +This position therefore comes to precisely the same thing as the "strong +metaphysical necessity" objection considered above. Like that objection, +Loar's position requires that a conditional from physical facts to phenomenal facts be metaphysically necessary despite being logically contingent, +where this gap cannot be explained by a difference in primary intensions. +Like that objection, Loar's position requires a brute and arbitrary restriction +on possible worlds. Loar offers no argument for this restriction, and his +position is subject to precisely the same criticisms.15 +One might expect there to be a third objection analogous to the intermediate "alternative strategy" from section 2. This would be cashed out in the +claim that Mary does not really know all the physical facts. She knows all +the facts couched in the terms of physics, but she lacks knowledge about +the hidden (phenomenal or protpphenomenal) essences of physical entities. +If she had this knowledge, she would thereby know the phenomenal facts. +As before, however, this view has only a very tenuous claim to the name +"materialism." Like my own view, this view must take phenomenal or protophenomenal properties to be fundamental properties. +A fourth objection draws a connection between Mary's plight and a lack of +indexical knowledge (Bigelow and Pargetter 1990; McMullen 1985; Papineau +1993). Although Mary gains new knowledge, it is argued that this is no +more puzzling than other cases where someone who knows all the relevant +objective facts discovers something new: for example, an omniscient amnesiac who discovers "I am Rudolf Lingens," or a well-informed insomniac +who does not know that it is 3:49 A.M. now (see Perry 1979 and Lewis +1979). In these cases, there is gap between physical knowledge and indexical +knowledge, just as there is a gap between physical knowledge and phenomenal knowledge in Mary's case. +The connection might be drawn in two ways. First, an objector might try +to reduce phenomenal knowledge to indexical knowledge, arguing that all +that Mary lacks is indexical knowledge. Second, one might try to draw an +analogy between the two cases, arguing that in the indexical case the epistemic gap does not lead to an ontological gap (indexicality does not falsify +materialism), so that the phenomenal case need not lead to an ontological +gap either. + + 144 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +The reduction strategy clearly fails. As we saw in Chapter 2, indexicals +accompany .facts about conscious experience in their failure to supervene +logically on physical facts, but they are all settled by the addition of a thin +"indexical fact" about the location of the agent in question. But even when +we give Mary perfect knowledge about her indexical relation to everything +in the physical world, her knowledge of red experiences will not be improved +in the slightest. In lacking phenomenal knowledge, she lacks far more than +someone lacking indexical knowledge. +The analogy strategy is more interesting. One might respond by arguing +for an ontological gap even in the indexical case (see, e.g., Nagel 1983), but +a more straightforward response is available. To see this, note that in the +indexical case, an argument analogous to that in section 1 does not get off +the ground: there is no conceivable uncentered world in which the physical +facts are the same as ours, but in which the indexical facts differ. In +uncentered worlds, indexical facts do not even apply. There is a relevant +conceivable centered world, to be sure, but it is uncentered worlds that are +relevant to the ontological question. (If not, there is an ontological gap in +the indexical case as well, so the objector's argument does not get started.16) +So in this case alone we can explain away the epistemic gap by noting +that epistemic connections are determined by centered primary intensions, +whereas ontological connections are determined by properties corresponding +to uncentered intensions. Indeed, this is reflected in the single loophole that +was found in the argument of section 2, and in the analogous argument in +this section: the fact that primary intensions determine only center-relative +properties. This loophole allows through a single piece of irreducible indexical knowledge (the location of a centered world's center) without ontological cost, but nothing further. Once the location of a center is specified, the +loophole is closed. The phenomenal facts remain unsettled even when the +location of a center is specified, so conscious experience remains out in +the cold.17 +If a materialist is to hold on to materialism, she really needs to deny that +Mary makes any discovery about the world at all. Materialism requires logical +supervenience, which requires that Mary can gain no new factual knowledge +of any sort when she first experiences red. Thus, in a fifth strategy, Lewis +(1990) and Nemirow (1990) argue that at most Mary gains a new ability. For +example, she gains the ability to imagine the sight of red things, and to +recognize them when she sees them. But this is only knowledge how, not +knowledge that When she first experiences red, she learns no facts about +the world.18 +Unlike the previous options, this strategy does not suffer from internal +problems. Its main problem is that it is deeply implausible. No doubt Mary +does gain some abilities when she first experiences red, as she gains some +abilities when she learns to ride a bicycle. But it certainly seems that she + + Naturalistic Dualism + +145 + +learns something else: some facts about the nature of experience. For all she +knew before, the experience of red things might have been like this, or it +might have been like that, or it might even have been like nothing at all. +But now she knows that it is like this. She has narrowed down the space +of epistemic possibilities. No such new knowledge comes along when an +omniscient mechanic learns to ride a bicycle (except perhaps for knowledge +about the phenomenology of bicycle riding). So this reply fails to come to +grips with what goes on when Mary learns what it is like to see red. +We can also use more indirect methods to see that Mary's discovery +involves factual knowledge. For example, Loar (1990) points out that this +sort of knowledge can be embedded in conditionals: "If seeing red things is +like this and seeing blue things is like this, then seeing purple things is +probably like that"; "If it is like this for dogs to see red, then such-and-such +follows"; and so on. Another example: as Lycan (1995) points out,19 what +we imagine can turn out to be right or wrong; thus, after seeing a few colors, Mary might imagine what it is like to see another one, and her imagination +might be correct or incorrect. If so, then to know what something is like is +to know a truth about the world, and the ability analysis fails. +Dennett (1991) takes a related but more extreme position, arguing that +Mary learns nothing at all. He notes that Mary could use her neurophysiological knowledge to recognize that a red object is red when she sees it, by +noticing its effects on her reactions, which may differ from the effects of +something blue. (If a team of experimenters tries to fool her by holding up +a blue apple, she might not be fooled.) Perhaps this is so, but all that follows +is that contra Lewis and Nemirow, Mary had certain abilities to recognize +even before she had her first experience of red. It does nothing to show that +she had the crucial knowledge: knowledge of what seeing red would be like. +That would only follow if we had already accepted the ability analysis of +"knowing what it is like"; but if we had accepted that analysis, the argument +against materialism would already have been defeated. So Dennett's argument is a red herring here. +Ultimately, the strategy that a materialist must take is to deny that Mary +gains knowledge about the world. And the only tenable way to do this seems +to be via an ability analysis of "knowing what it is like." This is the only +position with the internal coherence to ensure that it is not defeated by +technical objections, just as analytic functionalism is ultimately the most +coherent way for a materialist to resist the argument from logical supervenience. But contraposing, the very implausibility of the denial that Mary +gains knowledge about the world is evidence that materialism is doomed.20 +We have seen that the modal argument (the argument from logical possibility) and the knowledge argument are two sides of the same coin. I think +that in principle each succeeds on its own, but in practice they work best in +tandem.21 Taking the knowledge argument alone: most materialists find it + + 146 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +hard to deny that Mary gains knowledge about the world, but often deny +the step from there to the failure of materialism. Taking the modal argument +alone: most materialists find it hard to deny the argument from the conceivability of zombies or inverted spectra to the failure of materialism, but often +deny the premise. But taking the two together, the modal argument buttresses the knowledge argument where help is needed, and vice versa. In +perhaps the most powerful combination of the two arguments, we can use +the knowledge argument to compellingly establish the failure of logical supervenience, and the modal argument to compellingly make the step from that +failure to the falsity of materialism. +Kripke's argument +Kripke's argument was directed at the identity thesis put forward by Place +(1957) and Smart (1959), but it can be seen to have a broad force against +all forms of materialism. I will discuss the strengths and weaknesses of this +argument in some detail, to support the conclusion that the parts that succeed are precisely those parts that correspond to the argument from logical +supervenience. +The argument goes roughly as follows: According to the identity thesis, +certain mental states (such as pains) and brain states (such as C-fibers firing) +are identical, even though "pain" and "C-fibers firing" do not mean the +same thing. The identity here was originally supposed to be contingent rather +than necessary, just as the identity between water and H2O is contingent. +Against this, Kripke argues that all identities are necessary: If X is Y, then +X is necessarily Y, as long as the terms X and Y designate rigidly, picking +out the same individual or kind across worlds. Water is necessarily H2O, he +argues; that is, water is H2O in every possible world. The identity may seem +contingent—that is, it might seem that there is a possible world in which +water is not H2O but XYZ—but this is illusory. In fact, the possible world +that one is imagining contains no water at all. It is just a world in which +there is some watery stuff—stuff that looks and behaves like water—made +out of XYZ. In asserting that this watery stuff is water, one is misdescribing it. +Similarly, Kripke argues, if pains are identical to the firing of C-fibers, +then this identity must be necessary. But the identity does not seem to be +necessary. On the face of it, one can imagine a possible world where a pain +occurs without any brain state whatsoever (disembodied pain), and one can +imagine a world in which C-fibers fire without any accompanying pain (in a +zombie, say). Further, he argues, these possibilities cannot be explained away +as merely apparent possibilities, in the way that the possibility of water +without H2O was explained away. For that to be the case, we would have +to be misdescribing the "disembodied pain" world as one in which pain +occurred, when really there was just "painy stuff (something that feels like + + Naturalistic Dualism + +147 + +pain) going on. Similarly, we would have to be misdescribing the zombie as +lacking pain, when all it really lacks is painy stuff. On such an account, the +zombie would presumably have real pain, which is the firing of C-fibers; it +is just that it doesn't feel like real pain. +But this cannot be the case, according to Kripke: all it is for something +to be pain is for it to feel like pain. There is no distinction between pain +and painy stuff, in the way that there is a distinction between water and +watery stuff. One could have something that felt like water without it being +water, but one could not have something that felt like pain without it being +pain. Pain's feel is essential to it. So the possibility of the pains without the +brain states (and vice versa) cannot be dismissed as before. Those possible +worlds really are possible, and mental states are not necessarily identical to +brain states. It follows that they cannot be identical to brain states at all. +Kripke runs the argument in two different ways, once against token-identity theories and once against type-identity theories. Token-identity theories hold that particular pains (such as my pain now) are identical to particular brain states (such as the C-fibers firing in my head now). Kripke argues +in the above fashion that a particular pain could occur without the particular associated brain state, and vice versa, so they cannot be identical. Typeidentity theories hold that mental states and brain states are identical as +types: pain, for example, might be identical as a type to the firing of C-fibers. +Kripke holds that this is straightforwardly refuted by the fact that one could +instantiate the mental-state type without the brain-state type, and vice versa. +Overall, we can count four separate arguments here, divided according to +the target (token- or type-identity theories) and according to the method of +argument (from the possibility of disembodiment or from the possibility +of zombies). +There are some obvious differences between Kripke's argument and the +argument I have given. For a start, Kripke's argument is couched entirely +in terms of identity, whereas I have relied on the notion of supervenience. +Second, Kripke's argument is closely tied to his theoretical apparatus involving rigid designators and a posteriori necessity, whereas that apparatus +plays only a secondary role in my argument, in answering certain objections. +Third, Kripke's argument is usually seen to rely on a certain essentialism +about various states, whereas no such doctrine is invoked in my argument. +Fourth, my argument nowhere appeals to the possibility of disembodiment, +as Kripke's does. Nevertheless there are obvious similarities. Both are modal +arguments, involving necessity and possibility in key roles. And both appeal +to the logical possibility of dissociating physical states from the associated +phenomenal states. +I will now discuss what succeeds and what fails in Kripke's arguments, +starting with those against token identity. These are generally held to be +inconclusive. This is largely because they rely on intuitions about what counts + + 148 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +as that very thing across possible worlds, and such intuitions are notoriously +unreliable. Kripke's claim that one could have that very pain state without +that very brain state relies on the claim that what is essential to that pain +state is its feel, and only its feel. But such claims about the essential properties of individuals are hard to justify. The token-identity theorist can respond +by arguing that it is just as plausible that the firing of C-fibers is an essential +property of the state. Of course, C-fiber firing does not seem to be essential +to pain as a type, but who is to say that it is not essential to this particular +pain token, especially if that token is identical to a brain state? If it is, +then one simply could not have the particular pain in question without the +particular brain state. (A line like this is taken by Feldman [1974], who +argues that painfulness need not be essential to a particular pain, and by +McGinn [1977], who in effect argues that both painfulness and C-fiber firing +might be essential to a particular pain.) If so, then in imagining a disembodied version of my pain, one is not imagining that very pain but a separate, +numerically distinct pain. The same goes for imagining my C-fiber firing +without pain. So the arguments against token identity are inconclusive, although the arguments against type identity may survive. +Next, the argument from disembodiment does not establish a conclusive +case against materialism. It might refute a type-identity thesis of the kind +put forward by Place and Smart, but materialism does not require such a +thesis.22 As Boyd (1980) notes, the materialist need not hold that mental states are physical states in all possible worlds—it is compatible with materialism that in some worlds mental states are constituted out of nonphysical +stuff, as long as in this world they are physically constituted. The possibility +of disembodiment only establishes the possibility of dualism, rather than its +truth.23 To illustrate this, we can note that that few would argue that the +possibility of nonphysical life implies dualism about biology. An argument +against the identity thesis may be all that Kripke intended, but in any case +the more general version of materialism survives. +This leaves the argument from the possibility of instantiating physical states +without the corresponding phenomenal states—essentially an argument from +the possibility of zombies. Curiously, this is the part of Kripke's argument +that has received the least critical attention, with most commentators focusing +on the possibility of disembodiment. As before, the argument that zombies +yield against strong type-identity theses may be irrelevant, due to the fact +that materialism does not require such a thesis, but there is a more general +argument lurking here. The possibility of instantiating the relevant physical +states without pain, Kripke argues (pp. 153-54), shows that even after God +created all the physical stuff going on when one has a pain—perhaps a brain +with C-fibers firing—he had to do more work in order that those firings be +felt as pain. This is enough to establish that materialism is false.24 + + Naturalistic Dualism + +149 + +This argument from physical states without phenomenal states corresponds +directly to the argument I have given against materialism. Even the further +maneuvers correspond. To the objection that this situation is merely conceivable and not truly possible, Kripke will respond: One cannot explain away +the conceived situation as one that lacks the feeling of pain but not pain +itself, as to be a pain is to feel like pain in any possible world. (That is, the +secondary intension and the primary intension of "pain" coincide.) To this +we might add (with Jackson [1980]) that even if the equivalence is disputed, +the argument against materialism will succeed when applied to feelings of +pain rather than pain. (That is, even if the intensions differ, the argument +still goes through using the primary intension.) These are isomorphic to the +responses that I gave to the same sort of objection earlier in this chapter. +(Note that with his thesis that an apparently-conceivable-but-impossible +situation should be explained away as an epistemically possible situation +that is misdescribed, Kripke is in effect endorsing the "weak" treatment of +a posteriori necessity: the spaces of conceivable and possible worlds are the +same, but a posteriori factors put constraints on their correct description.25 +To see this, note that an advocate of "strong" metaphysical necessity, on +which the space of possible worlds is a proper subset of the space of conceivable worlds, would not advocate such a thesis. On such a view, we might +correctly describe an epistemically possible situation, but it might still be +(brutely) metaphysically impossible. Kripke's reliance on the misdescription +strategy, by contrast, suggests an implicit endorsement of the two-dimensional framework: indeed, all his examples of misdescription can be seen as +cases in which a world is described under primary rather than secondary +intensions.) +This argument from physical states without phenomenal states strikes me +as the most conclusive part of Kripke's discussion. It is frequently overlooked +amidst the discussion of identity theses, disembodiment, and the like; even +Kripke assigns this aspect of his discussion a noncentral role. All the same, +I think it is this part of the discussion that ultimately carries the burden of +Kripke's argument. +To summarize, it seems to me that insofar as Kripke's argument against +materialism succeeds, (1) the possibility of disembodiment is inconclusive +as an argument against materialism but inessential to the case; (2) arguments +phrased in terms of identity are similarly inconclusive but inessential; (3) an +essentialist metaphysics is inessential, except insofar as the feel of pain is +essential to pain as a type—but that is just a fact about what "pain" means; +and (4) Kripke's apparatus of rigid designation and the like is not central, although it is required to answer a certain sort of objection.26 But his +argument contains a sound core, in what is essentially an argument from the +failure of logical supervenience. + + 150 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +4. Is This Epiphenomenalism?* +A problem with the view I have advocated is that if consciousness is merely +naturally supervenient on the physical, then it seems to lack causal efficacy. +The physical world is more or less causally closed, in that for any given +physical event, it seems that there is a physical explanation (modulo a small +amount of quantum indeterminacy). This implies that there is no room for +a nonphysical consciousness to do any independent causal work. It seems +to be a mere epiphenomenon, hanging off the engine of physical causation, +but making no difference in the physical world. It exists, but as far as the +physical world is concerned it might as well not. Huxley (1874) advocated +such a view, but many people find it counterintuitive and repugnant. Indeed, +this consequence has been enough to cause some (e.g., Kirk [1979]; Seager +[1991]) to question the conclusions of their arguments against materialism, +and to consider the possibility that consciousness might be logically supervenient on the physical after all. +This argument has been formalized in different but related ways by Kirk +(1979), Morgan (1987), and Seager (1991). If we assume that the physical +world is causally closed and that consciousness causes some physical events, +then it follows under certain natural assumptions about causation that consciousness must supervene logically (or metaphysically) on the physical.27 If +so, then given that the physical world is causally closed, the mere natural +supervenience of consciousness implies that consciousness is epiphenomenal. +The basic shape of the argument is clear: if it is possible to subtract the +phenomenal from our world and still retain a causally closed world Z, then +everything that happens in Z has a causal explanation that is independent +of the phenomenal, as there is nothing phenomenal in Z. But everything +that happens in Z also happens in our world, so the causal explanation that +applies in Z applies equally here. So the phenomenal is causally irrelevant. +Even if conscious experience were absent, the behavior might have been +caused in exactly the same way. +In responding to this, I will pursue a two-pronged strategy. First, it is not +obvious that mere natural supervenience must imply epiphenomenalism in +the strongest sense. It is clear that the picture it produces looks something +like epiphenomenalism. Nevertheless, the very nature of causation itself is +quite mysterious, and it is possible that when causation is better understood +we will be in a position to understand a subtle way in which conscious +experience may be causally relevant. (In effect, it may turn out that background assumptions in arguments above are false.) I will outline some ways +in which such an analysis might be made below. On the second prong, I will +consider the reasons why epiphenomenalism might be found unpalatable, +and analyze their force as arguments. If these intuitions do not translate into +compelling arguments, it may turn out the sort of epiphenomenalism that + + Naturalistic Dualism + +151 + +this position implies is only counterintuitive, and that ultimately a degree of +epiphenomenalism can be accepted. +Strategies for avoiding epiphenomenalism +There are a number of ways in which one might try to preserve the failure +of logical supervenience while nevertheless avoiding epiphenomenalism. The +most obvious of these is to deny the causal closure of the physical, and to +embrace a strong form of interactionist dualism in which the mental fills +causal gaps in physical processing. I think this strategy should be avoided, +for reasons I discuss shortly. However, there are a number of more subtle +options that depend on an appropriate view of metaphysics and especially +of causation. I discuss four such options. +1. Regularity-based causation. The first option is to accept a strong Humean account of causation, upon which all it is for A to cause B is for there +to be a uniform regularity between events of type A and events of type B, +Such a view would allow a "causal" role for the phenomenal: the mere fact +that pain sensations are generally followed by withdrawal reactions would +imply that pain causes withdrawal reactions. +A related non-Humean option identifies a causal connection with any +nomic (or lawful) connection, even if a nomic regularity is something more +than a uniform regularity. The natural supervenience view is entirely compatible with the existence of a nomic connection between experience and behavior (for example, there might be a lawful connection between experience +and an underlying brain state, and a lawful connection between that brain +state and behavior). One might claim that this is enough for causation. This +might be supported by noting that the counterfactual "Behavior would have +been the same even in the absence of experience" is false on the most natural +interpretation: if the experience were absent, the brain state would have been +different, and behavior would have been different. Here, the counterfactual +is assessed by considering naturally possible worlds, rather than logically +possible worlds. +I find both of these positions implausible. I have argued against Humean +views of causation in Chapter 2, and even on the non-Humean view it is +implausible that just any nomic connection suffices for causation—think +of the correlation between the hair color of identical twins, for instance. +Nevertheless, considerations like these at least give us an idea of why consciousness appears to play a causal role. There are all sorts of systematic +regularities between conscious experiences and later physical events, each +of which leads us to infer a causal connection. Faced with such regularities, +we would expect people to infer a causal relation for broadly Humean +reasons. This can therefore explain away some of our intuitions that con- + + 152 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +sciousness is causally efficacious, thus supporting the second prong of the +strategy. +2. Causal overdetermination. Perhaps we might claim that a physical state +and a phenomenal state, though wholly distinct, might both qualify as causing +a later physical state. If physical state PI is associated with phenomenal state +Qi, then perhaps it is true both that PI causes a later physical state P2 and +that Q1 causes P2. This is counterintuitive: P1 is already a sufficient cause of +P2, so Q1 would seem to be causally redundant. But it is not obvious that +Q1 could not stand in a causal relation to P1 nevertheless. This may be +especially reasonable if we adopt a nonreductive view of causation (of the sort +advocated by Tooley 1987). Perhaps there is an irreducible causal connection +between the two physical states, and a separate irreducible causal connection +between the phenomenal state and the physical state. +This sort of causal overdetermination of events is often regarded with +suspicion, but it is hard to demonstrate conclusively that there is something +wrong with it. The nature of causation is sufficiently ill understood that +overdetermination cannot yet be ruled out. I will not pursue this line myself, +but it nevertheless deserves to be taken seriously. +3. The nonsupervenience of causation. A third strategy rests with the very +nature of causation itself. We saw in Chapter 2 that there are two classes of +facts that do not supervene logically on particular physical facts: facts about +consciousness and facts about causation. It is natural to speculate that these +two failures might be intimately related, and that consciousness and causation +have some deep metaphysical tie. Both are quite mysterious, after all, and +two mysteries might be more neatly wrapped into one. Perhaps, for instance, +experience itself is a kind of causal nexus; perhaps it somehow realizes +Hume's "unknowable causal relation"; or perhaps the relationship is more +complex. A relationship like this might suggest a role for experience in +causation that is more subtle than the usual sort of causation, but nevertheless +avoids the strongest form of epiphenomenalism. +A proposal like this has been developed by Rosenberg (1996), who argues +that many of the problems of consciousness are precisely paralleled by problems about causation. He argues that because of these parallels, it may be +that experience realizes causation, or some aspects of causation, in the actual world. On this view, causation needs to be realized by something in +order to support its many properties, and experience is a natural candidate. +If this is so, it may be that it is the very existence of experience that allows +for causal relations to exist, so that there is a subtle sort of relevance for +experience in causation. +Of course, this proposal is extremely speculative, and faces some problems. For a start, it seems to lead to a version of panpsychism, the view + + Naturalistic Dualism + +153 + +that everything is conscious, which many find counterintuitive. Further, the +zombie world is still a problem—it seems that we can imagine all that causation going on without experience, so that experience might still seem epiphenomenal. A response might be that causation has to be realized by something; +in the zombie world it is realized by something else, but experience is still +relevant in this world in virtue of realizing causation here. It is not obvious +to me that causation has to be realized by something with any further properties; if it need not be, then the phenomenal nature of causation might still +be redundant. But again, the metaphysics of causation is as yet far from +clear, and this proposal is certainly worth investigating. +4. The intrinsic nature of the physical. The strategy to which I am most +drawn stems from the observation that physical theory only characterizes +its basic entities relationally, in terms of their causal and other relations to +other entities. Basic particles, for instance, are largely characterized in terms +of their propensity to interact with other particles. Their mass and charge +is specified, to be sure, but all that a specification of mass ultimately comes +to is a propensity to be accelerated in certain ways by forces, and so on. +Each entity is characterized by its relation to other entities, and these entities are characterized by their relations to other entities, and so on forever +(except, perhaps, for some entities that are characterized by their relation +to an observer). The picture of the physical world that this yields is that of +a giant causal flux, but the picture tells us nothing about what all this +causation relates. Reference to the proton is fixed as the thing that causes +interactions of a certain kind, that combines in certain ways with other +entities, and so on; but what is the thing that is doing the causing and +combining? As Russell (1927) notes, this is a matter about which physical +theory is silent.28 +One might be attracted to the view of the world as pure causal flux, with +no further properties for the causation to relate, but this would lead to a +strangely insubstantial view of the physical world.29 It would contain only +causal and nomic relations between empty placeholders with no properties +of their own. Intuitively, it is more reasonable to suppose that the basic +entities that all this causation relates have some internal nature of their own, +some intrinsic properties, so that the world has some substance to it. But +physics can at best fix reference to those properties by virtue of their extrinsic +relations; it tells us nothing directly about what those properties might be. We +have some vague intuitions about these properties based on our experience of +their macroscopic analogs—intuitions about the very "massiveness" of mass, +for example—but it is hard to flesh these intuitions out, and it is not clear +on reflection that there is anything to them. +There is only one class of intrinsic, nonrelational property with which we +have any direct familiarity, and that is the class of phenomenal properties. + + 154 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +It is natural to speculate that there may be some relation or even overlap +between the uncharacterized intrinsic properties of physical entities, and the +familiar intrinsic properties of experience. Perhaps, as Russell suggested, at +least some of the intrinsic properties of the physical are themselves a variety +of phenomenal property?30 The idea sounds wild at first, but on reflection +it becomes less so. After all, we really have no idea about the intrinsic +properties of the physical. Their nature is up for grabs, and phenomenal +properties seem as likely a candidate as any other. +There is of course the threat of panpsychism. I am not sure that this is +such a bad prospect—if phenomenal properties are fundamental, it is natural +to suppose that they might be widespread—but it is not a necessary consequence. An alternative is that the relevant properties are protophenomenal +properties. In this case the mere instantiation of such a property does not +entail experience, but instantiation of numerous such properties could do +so jointly. It is hard to imagine how this would work (we know that it cannot +work for standard physical properties), but these intrinsic properties are +quite foreign to our conception. The possibility cannot be ruled out a priori. +Either way, this sort of intimate link suggests a kind of causal role for +the phenomenal. If there are intrinsic properties of the physical, it is instantiations of these properties that physical causation ultimately relates. If these +are phenomenal properties, then there is phenomenal causation; and if these +are protophenomenal properties, then phenomenal properties inherit causal +relevance by their supervenient status, just as billiard balls inherit causal +relevance from molecules. In either case, the phenomenology of experience +in human agents may inherit causal relevance from the causal role of the +intrinsic properties of the physical. +Of course, this would be a subtler kind of causal relevance than the usual +kind. It remains the case, for example, that one can imagine removing the +phenomenal properties, with the pattern of causal flux remaining the same. +But now the response is that in imagining such a scenario, one is effectively +altering the intrinsic properties of physical entities and replacing them by +something else (of course, the trouble is that we are not used to imagining +intrinsic properties of the physical at all). Thus one is simply moving to a +world where something else is doing the causation. If there could be a world +of pure causal flux, this argument would fail, but such a world is arguably +logically impossible, as there is nothing in such a world for causation to relate. +This position is rather akin to the second position described in section 2, +where electrons have a hidden essence to which physical descriptions merely +fix reference. I think that for the reasons given there, the intrinsic properties +should not be identified with physical properties such as mass. It seems +reasonable to say that there is still mass in the zombie world, despite differences in its intrinsic nature. If so, then mass is an extrinsic property that +can be "realized" by different intrinsic properties in different worlds. But + + Naturalistic Dualism + +155 + +whichever way we make this semantic decision, the position retains an essential duality between the properties that physics deals with directly and +the hidden intrinsic properties that constitute phenomenology. +There is a sense in which this view can be seen as a monism rather than +a dualism, but it is not a materialist monism. Unlike physicalism, this view +takes certain phenomenal or protophenomenal properties as fundamental. +What it finally delivers is a network of intrinsic properties, at least some of +which are phenomenal or protophenomenal, and which are related according +to certain causal/dynamic laws. These properties "realize" the extrinsic physical properties, and the laws connecting them realize the physical laws. In +the extreme case in which all the intrinsic properties are phenomenal, the +view might be best seen as a version of idealism. It is an idealism very +unlike Berkeley's, however. The world is not supervenient on the mind of +an observer, but rather consists in a vast causal network of phenomenal +properties underlying the physical laws that science postulates. A less extreme case in which intrinsic properties are protophenomenal, or in which +some are neither phenomenal nor protophenomenal, is perhaps best regarded as a version of Russell's neutral monism. The basic properties of +the world are neither physical nor phenomenal, but the physical and the +phenomenal are constructed out of them. From their intrinsic natures in +combination, the phenomenal is constructed; and from their extrinsic relations, the physical is constructed. +On this view, the most basic laws will be those that connect the basic +intrinsic properties. The familiar physical laws capture the relational shape +of these laws, while abstracting away from the intrinsic properties. Psychophysical laws can be reinterpreted as laws that connect intrinsic properties +(or properties constructed out of these) to their relational profiles (or to +complex relational structures). Thus these laws do not "dangle" ontologically +from physical laws. Rather, both are consequences of the truly basic laws. +But the epistemological order differs from the ontological order: we are +led first to the relational structure of the causal network, and only slowly +to the underlying intrinsic properties. For everyday explanatory purposes, +it is therefore most useful to continue to think of this view in terms of a network of physical laws, with further principles connecting the physical to +the phenomenal. +All this metaphysical speculation may need to be taken with a pinch of salt, +but it shows that the issue of epiphenomenalism is not cut and dried. There +are a number of subtle issues about causation and about the nature of +experience that will need to be understood better before we can say for +certain whether experience is epiphenomenal. In any case, I will now set +aside the metaphysical speculation and return to a less lofty plane (although +I will return to some of these issues in Chapter 8). + + 156 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +It remains the case that natural supervenience feels epiphenomenalistic. +We might say that the view is epiphenomenalistic to a first approximation: +if it allows some causal relevance for experience, it does so in a subtle way. +I think we can capture this first-approximation sense by noting that the +view makes experience explanatorily irrelevant. We can give explanations of +behavior in purely physical or computational terms, terms that neither involve nor imply phenomenology. If experience is tied in some intimate way +to causation, it is in a way that these explanations can abstract away from. +One might find even explanatory irrelevance troubling; I will say much more +about it in the next chapter. +Some have been tempted to avoid epiphenomenalism by leaping into the +"strong metaphysical necessity" position of section 2 of this chapter. If +experience does not supervene logically on the physical, it has seemed to +some that the only way to preserve its causal role is to declare it brutely +identical to or metaphysically supervenient on some physical property or +properties. Apart from the problems that I have already mentioned, however, +the view still has serious problems with explanatory irrelevance. The very +conceivability of a zombie shows that on this view, behavior can be explained +in terms that neither involve nor imply the existence of experience. Explanatory relations are conceptual relations, so that strong metaphysical necessity +is irrelevant here. The view still leaves behavior independent of experience +in a strong sense and has to face up to most of the same difficulties as a +property dualism. There is therefore not much to be gained by taking such +a position. +Interactionist dualism? +Some people, persuaded by the arguments for dualism but convinced that +phenomenal consciousness must play a significant causal role, may be +tempted by an interactionist variety of dualism, in which experience fills +causal gaps in physical processes. Giving in to this temptation raises more +problems than it solves, however. For a start, it requires a hefty bet on the +future of physics, one that does not currently seem at all promising; physical +events seem inexorably to be explained in terms of other physical events. It +also requires a large wager on the future of cognitive science, as it suggests +that the usual kinds of physical/functional models will be insufficient to explain behavior. But the deepest problem is that this view may be no better +at getting around the problems with epiphenomenalism than the view with +causal closure, for reasons I will discuss shortly. +The only form of interactionist dualism that has seemed even remotely +tenable in the contemporary picture is one that exploits certain properties +of quantum mechanics. There are two ways this might go. First, some have +appealed to the existence of quantum indeterminacy, and have suggested + + Naturalistic Dualism + +157 + +that a nonphysical consciousness might be responsible for filling the resultant causal gaps, determining which values some physical magnitudes might +take within an apparently "probabilistic" distribution (e.g., Eccles 1986). Although these decisions would have only a tiny proximate effect, perhaps +nonlinear dynamics could amplify these tiny fluctuations into significant macroscopic effects on behavior. +This is an audacious and interesting suggestion, but it has a number of +problems. First, the theory contradicts the quantum-mechanical postulate +that these microscopic "decisions" are entirely random, and in principle it +implies that there should be some detectable pattern to them—a testable +hypothesis. Second, in order that this theory allows that consciousness does +any interesting causal work, it needs to be the case that the behavior produced +by these microscopic decisions is somehow different in kind than that produced by most other sets of decisions that might have been made by a purely +random process. Presumably the behavior is more rational than it would +have been otherwise, and it leads to remarks such as "I am seeing red now" +that the random processes would not have produced. This again is testable +in principle, by running a simulation of a brain with real random processes +determining those decisions. Of course we do not know for certain which +way this test would come out, but to hold that the random version would +lead to unusually degraded behavior would be to make a bet at long odds. +A second way in which quantum mechanics bears on the issue of causal +closure lies with the fact that in some interpretations of the quantum formalism, consciousness itself plays a vital causal role, being required to bring +about the so-called "collapse of the wave-function." This collapse is supposed to occur upon any act of measurement; and in one interpretation, the +only way to distinguish a measurement from a nonmeasurement is via the +presence of consciousness. This theory is certainly not universally accepted +(for a start, it presupposes that consciousness is not itself physical, surely +contrary to the views of most physicists), and I do not accept it myself, but +in any case it seems that the kind of causal work consciousness performs +here is quite different from the kind required for consciousness to play a +role in directing behavior.31 It is unclear how a collapse in external perceived +objects allows consciousness to affect physical processing within the brain; +such theories are usually silent on what happens to the brain during collapse. +And even if consciousness somehow manages to collapse the brain state, +then all the above remarks about apparently random processes and their +connection with behavior still apply. +In any case, all versions of interactionist dualism have a conceptual problem that suggests that they are less successful in avoiding epiphenomenalism +than they might seem; or at least that they are no better off than the view +I have advocated. Even on these views, there is a sense in which the phenomenal is irrelevant. We can always subtract the phenomenal component from + + 158 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +any explanatory account, yielding a purely causal component. Imagine (with +Eccles) that "psychons" in the nonphysical mind push around physical processes in the brain, and that psychons are the seat of experience. We can +tell a story about the causal relations between psychons and physical processes, and a story about the causal dynamics among psychons, without ever +invoking the fact that psychons have phenomenal properties. Just as with +physical processes, we can imagine subtracting the phenomenal properties +of psychons, yielding a situation in which the causal dynamics are isomorphic. +It follows that the fact that psychons are the seat of experience plays no +essential role in a causal explanation, and that even in this picture experience is explanatorily irrelevant. +Some might object that psychons (or ectoplasm, or whatever) are entirely +constituted by their phenomenal properties. Even so, there is a sense in which +their phenomenal properties are irrelevant to the explanation of behavior; +it is only their relational properties that matter in the story about causal +dynamics. If one objects that still, they have further intrinsic properties that +are causally relevant, we have a situation like the one that arose above with +phenomenal properties intrinsic to physical entities. Either way, we have a +sort of causal relevance but explanatory irrelevance. Indeed, nothing especially is gained by moving away from the causal closure of the physical. +We still have a broader causal network that is closed, and it remains the case +that the phenomenal nature of entities in the network is explanatorily superfluous. +We can even imagine that if interactionism is true, then for reasons quite +independent of conscious experience we would be led eventually to postulate +psychons in order to explain behavior, to fill the observed causal gaps and +account for the data. If so, psychons would have the status of a kind of +theoretical entity like the theoretical entities of physics. Nothing in this +story would involve or imply experience, which would be as explanatorily +superfluous as in the usual case; we could still tell a zombie story involving psychons, and so on. The additional observation that these psychons +might have phenomenal properties works no better or worse as a response +to epiphenomenalism than the analogous observation that physical entities +(perhaps basic entities, perhaps quite complex ones) might have phenomenal +properties over and above their extrinsic features. The denial of the causal +closure of the physical therefore makes no significant difference in the avoidance of epiphenomenalism.32 +The problems of epiphenomenalism +Any view that takes consciousness seriously will at least have to face up to +a limited form of epiphenomenalism. The very fact that experience can be +coherently subtracted from any causal account implies that experience is + + Naturalistic Dualism + +159 + +superfluous in the explanation of behavior, whether or not it has some subtle +causal relevance. It is possible that it will turn out to be causally irrelevant +in a stronger sense; that question is open. We therefore need to pursue the +second prong of the strategy, and see just what are the problems with the +causal or explanatory irrelevance of experience, and whether they are ultimately fatal. I will do this at much greater length in Chapter 5, but here we +can briefly survey the field. +The most common objection to epiphenomenalism is simply that it is +counterintuitive or even "repugnant." Finding a conclusion counterintuitive +or repugnant is not sufficient reason to reject the conclusion, however, especially if it is the conclusion of a strong argument. Epiphenomenalism may +be counterintuitive, but it is not obviously false, so if a sound argument +forces it on us, we should accept it. Of course, a counterintuitive conclusion +may give us reason to go back and reexamine the argument, but we still +need to find something wrong with the argument on independent grounds. +If it turns out that the falsity of logical supervenience implies epiphenomenalism, then logical supervenience may be desirable, but we cannot simply +assert it as a brute fact. To hold logical supervenience, one needs some +account of how the physical facts might entail the facts about consciousness, +and this is precisely what I have argued cannot be given. +More detailed objections to epiphenomenalism fall into three classes: those +concerning the relationship of experience to ordinary behavior, those concerning the relationship of experience to judgments about experience, and +those concerning the overall picture of the world that it gives rise to. +Take the first class first. Many find it simply obvious that their feelings of +pain cause them to withdraw their hand from a flame, or that my experience +of a headache cannot be irrelevant to the explanation of why I take pills. +There is certainly a strong intuition to this effect. On the other hand, we +can easily explain away the source of this intuition, in terms of the systematic +regularities between these events. We are much more directly aware of experience and of behavior than we are of an underlying brain state; upon exposure to systematic regularities between experience and behavior, it is +natural that a strong causal connection should be inferred. Even if the connection were only an indirect nomic connection due to relations to the underlying +brain state, we would still expect the inference to be made. So this intuition +can be explained away. In any case, this sort of objection cannot be fatal to +the view, as it is an intuition that does not extend directly into an argument. +It is an instance of the merely counterintuitive. +The second class of objections is more worrying. It seems very strange +that our experiences should be irrelevant to the explanation of why we +talk about experiences, for instance, or perhaps even to our internal judgments about experiences; this seems much stranger than the mere irrelevance of my pain to the explanation of my hand's withdrawal. Some claim + + 160 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +that this sort of problem is not merely counterintuitive but fatal. For example, it might be claimed that this is incompatible with our knowledge of +experience, or with our ability to refer to experiences. I believe that when +these arguments are spelled out they do not ultimately gain their conclusion, +but these questions are certainly challenging. I devote Chapter 5 to these +issues. +Objections in the third class concern the overall structure of the view. +One objection is that the picture is ugly and implausible, with experience +hanging off the physical by "nomological danglers" that are not integrated +with the other laws of nature. I think this can be combated by developing +a theory that leads to a more integrated picture. The label "epiphenomenalism" tends to suggest a view on which experience is dangling "up there," +floating free of processing in some way; a better picture that is still compatible +with natural supervenience is a picture of experience sitting down among +the causal cracks. At the very least, we can try to make the psychophysical +laws as simple and elegant as possible. Also falling into this class is a worry +about how consciousness might evolve in an epiphenomenalist account, but +it is not hard to see that this poses no problem for the view I advocate; +I discuss this further at the end of this chapter. +On examination, there are not many arguments that do serious damage +to epiphenomenalism. The main class of worrying arguments are those concerning judgments about experience, which I will discuss in the next chapter. +Arguments aside, some have the intuition that epiphenomenalism must be +wrong, but the intuition does not suffice to reject the position in the face of +strong arguments in its favor. +I do not describe my view as epiphenomenalism. The question of the +causal relevance of experience remains open, and a more detailed theory of +both causation and of experience will be required before the issue can be +settled. But the view implies at least a weak form of epiphenomenalism, and +it may end up leading to a stronger sort. Even if it does, however, I think +the arguments for natural supervenience are sufficiently compelling that +one should accept them. Epiphenomenalism is counterintuitive, but the alternatives are more than counterintuitive. They are simply wrong, as we have +already seen and will see again. The overall moral is that if the arguments +suggest that natural supervenience is true, then we should learn to live with +natural supervenience. +Some will find that nevertheless the epiphenomenalist nature of this position is a fatal flaw. I have some sympathy with this position, which can be +seen as an expression of the paradox of consciousness: when it comes to +consciousness, it can seem that all the alternatives are bad. However, I think +the problems with all other views are fatal in a much stronger way than the +counterintuitiveness of this one. Given that some option in logical space has +to be correct, this view seems to be the only reasonable candidate. + + Naturalistic Dualism + +161 + +5. The Logical Geography of the Issues +The argument for my view is an inference from roughly four premises: +1. Conscious experience exists. +2. Conscious experience is not logically supervenient on the physical. +3. If there are phenomena that are not logically supervenient on the +physical facts, then materialism is false. +4. The physical domain is causally closed. +Premises (1), (2), and (3) clearly imply the falsity of materialism. This, +taken in conjunction with premise (4) and the plausible assumption that +physically identical beings will have identical conscious experiences, implies +the view that I have called natural supervenience: conscious experience arises +from the physical according to some laws of nature, but is not itself physical. +The various alternative positions can be catalogued according to whether +they deny premises (1), (2), (3), or (4). Of course, some of these premises +can be denied in more than one way. +Denying premise (1): +i. Eliminativism, On this view, there are no positive facts about conscious experience. Nobody is conscious in the phenomenal sense. +Denying premise (2): +Premise (2) can be denied in various ways, depending on how the entailment in question proceeds—that is, depending on what sort of physical +properties are centrally responsible for entailing consciousness. I call all of +these views "reductive materialist" views, as they all suppose an analysis +of the notion of consciousness that is compatible with reductive explanation. +ii. Reductive functionalism. This view takes consciousness to be conceptually entailed by the physical in virtue of functional or dispositional properties. On this view, what it means for a state to be +conscious is for it to play a certain causal role. In a world physically +identical to ours, all the relevant causal roles would be played, and +therefore the conscious states would all be the same. The zombie +world is therefore logically impossible. +iii. Nonfunctionalist reductive materialism. On this view, the facts about +consciousness are conceptually entailed by the physical facts in +virtue of some nonfunctional property. Possible candidates might +include biochemical and quantum properties, or properties yet to +be determined. +iv. New-physics materialism. According to this view, we have no current idea of how physical facts could explain consciousness, but + + 162 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +that is because our current conception of physical facts is too narrow. When one argues that a zombie world is logically possible, +one is really arguing that all the fields and particles interacting in +the space-time manifold, postulated by current physics, could exist +in the absence of consciousness. But with a new physics, things +might be different. The entities in a radically different theoretical +framework might be sufficient to entail and explain consciousness. +Denying premise (3): +v. Nonreductive materialism. This is the view that although there may +be no logical entailment from the physical facts to the facts about +consciousness, and therefore no reductive explanation of consciousness, consciousness just is physical. The physical facts "metaphysically necessitate" the facts about consciousness. Even though the +idea of a zombie world is quite coherent, such a world is metaphysically impossible. +Denying premise (4): +vi. Interactionist dualism. This view accepts that consciousness is nonphysical, but denies that the physical world is causally closed, so +that consciousness can play an autonomous causal role. +Then there is my view, which accepts premises (1), (2), (3), and (4): +vii. Naturalistic dualism. Consciousness supervenes naturally on the +physical, without supervening logically or "metaphysically." +There is also an eighth common view, which is generally underspecified: +viii. Don't-have-a-clue materialism. "I don't have a clue about consciousness. It seems utterly mysterious to me. But it must be physical, as +materialism must be true." Such a view is held widely, but rarely +in print (although see Fodor 1992). +To quickly summarize the situation as I see it, option (i) seems to be manifestly false; (ii) and (iii) rely on false analyses of the notion of consciousness +and therefore change the subject; (iv) and (vi) place large and implausible +bets on the way that physics will turn out, and also have fatal conceptual +problems; and (v) either makes an invalid appeal to Kripkean a posteriori +necessity or relies on a bizarre metaphysics. I have a certain amount of +sympathy with (viii), but it presumably must eventually reduce to some more +specific view, and none of these seem to work. This leaves (vii) as the only +tenable option. +More slowly, starting with options (iv) and (vi): Option (vi), interactionist +dualism, requires that physics will turn out to have gaps that can be filled + + Naturalistic Dualism + +163 + +by the action of a nonphysical mind. Current evidence suggests that this is +unlikely. Option (iv) requires that the shape of physics will be transformed +so radically that it could entail facts about conscious experience; but nobody +has an idea of how any physics could do this. Indeed, given that physics +ultimately deals in structural and dynamical properties, it seems that all +physics will ever entail is more structure and dynamics, which (unless one +of the other reductive options is embraced) will never entail the existence +of experience. +The deepest reason to reject options (iv) and (vi) is that they ultimately +suffer from the same problem as a more standard physics: the phenomenal +component can be coherently subtracted from the causal component. On +the interactionist view, we have seen that even if the nonphysical entities have +a phenomenal aspect, we can coherently imagine subtracting the phenomenal +component, leaving a purely causal/dynamic story characterizing the interaction and behavior of the relevant entities. On the new physics view, even if +it explicitly incorporates phenomenal properties, the fact that these properties are phenomenal can play no essential role in the causal/dynamic story; +we would be left with a coherent physics even if that aspect were subtracted. +Either way, the dynamics is all we need to explain causal interactions, and +no set of facts about dynamics adds up to a fact about phenomenology. A +zombie story can therefore still be told. +Various moves can be made in reply, but each of these moves can also +be made on the standard physical story. For example, perhaps the abstract +dynamics misses the fact that the nonphysical stuff in the interactionist story +is intrinsically phenomenal, so that phenomenal properties are deeply involved in the causal network. But equally, perhaps the abstract dynamics of +physics misses the fact that its basic entities are intrinsically phenomenal +(physics characterizes them only extrinsically, after all), and the upshot would +be the same. Either way, we have the same kind of explanatory irrelevance +of the intrinsic phenomenal properties to the causal/dynamic story. The move +to interactionism or new physics therefore does not solve any problems +inherent in the property dualism I advocate. At the end of the day, they can +be seen as more complicated versions of the same sort of view. +As for option (iii), the most tempting version is the one that gestures +toward unknown properties that we have so far overlooked as the key to +the entailment. But ultimately the problem is the same: physics only gives +us structure and dynamics, and structure and dynamics does not add up +to phenomenology. The only available properties would seem to be those +characterizing physical structure or function, or properties constructed out +of the two. But structural properties are obviously inappropriate analyses +of the concept of experience, and functional properties are not much better +(although I consider them below). Any view of this sort will ultimately +change the subject. + + 164 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +This leaves options (i), (ii), (v), and (vii), which correspond to the options +taken most seriously in the contemporary literature: eliminativism, reductive +functionalism, nonreductive materialism, and property dualism. Of these I +reject option (i) as being in conflict with the manifest facts. Perhaps an +extraordinary argument could establish that conscious experience does not +exist, but I have never seen an argument that comes remotely close to making +this case. In the absence of such an argument, to take option (i) is simply +to evade the problem by denying the phenomenon. +Option (v) is often attractive to those who want to take consciousness +seriously and also retain materialism. But I have argued that it simply does +not work. The nonreductive materialism advocated by Searle turns out to +have internal problems and collapses into one of the other views (most +likely property dualism). Other proponents of this view rely on an appeal +to Kripke's a posteriori necessity, but the sort of a posteriori necessity demonstrated by Kripke cannot save materialism. The only consistent way to take +option (v) is to appeal to a strong a posteriori necessity that goes well beyond +Kripke's, and to invoke brute constraints on the space of "metaphysically +possible" worlds. We have seen that there is no reason to believe in such +constraints, or to believe in such a third, intermediate grade of the possibility +of worlds. This metaphysics gains no support from any other phenomena, +and it is hard to see how it could be supported. +Even if this metaphysics of necessity is accepted, for most explanatory +purposes the view ends up looking like the view I advocate. It implies that +consciousness cannot be reductively explained. It implies that conscious +experience is explanatorily irrelevant to the physical domain. And it implies +that a theory of consciousness must invoke bridging principles to connect +the physical and phenomenal domains, principles that are not themselves +entailed by physical laws. This view calls these principles "metaphysically +necessary," but for all practical purposes the upshot is the same. This sort +of theory will have the same shape as the dualist theories I advocate, and +almost everything I say in developing a nonreductive theory in the next few +chapters will apply equally here. +Option (ii), reductive functionalism, is the most serious materialist option. +Leaving aside various wild options, if materialism is true, then consciousness +is logically supervenient, and the only remotely reasonable way for it to be +logically supervenient is via a functional analysis. On this view, then, all it +means for something to be a conscious experience is for it to play a certain +causal role in a system. Phenomenal properties are treated exactly the same +way as psychological properties, such as learning or categorization. +The problem with this view, of course, is that it misrepresents what it +means to be a conscious experience, or to be conscious. When I wonder +whether other beings are conscious, I am not wondering about their abilities +or their internal mechanisms, which I may know all about already; I am + + Naturalistic Dualism + +165 + +wondering whether there is something it is like to be them. This point can +be supported in various familiar ways. One way is to note that even once +we have explained various functional capacities, the problem of explaining +experience may still remain. Another rests on the observation that we can +imagine any functional role being played in the absence of conscious experience. A third derives from the fact that knowledge of functional roles does +not automatically yield knowledge of consciousness. There are also the objections, made earlier, that a functionalist analysis cannot account for the +semantic determinacy of attributions of consciousness and that it collapses +the conceptual distinction between consciousness and awareness. +At the end of the day, reductive functionalism does not differ much from +eliminativism. Both of these views hold that there is discrimination, categorization, accessibility, reportability, and the like; and both deny that there is +anything else that even needs to be explained. The main difference is that +the reductive line holds that some of these explananda deserve the name +"experience," whereas the eliminative line holds that none of them do. Apart +from this terminological issue, the substance of the views is largely the same. +It is often noted that the line between reductionism and eliminativism is +blurry, with reduction gradually sliding into elimination the more we are +forced to modify the relevant concepts in order to perform a reduction. In +allowing that consciousness exists only insofar as it is defined as some functional capacity, the reductive functionalist view does sufficient violence to +the concept of consciousness that it is probably best viewed as a version of +eliminativism. Neither is a view that takes consciousness seriously. +This leaves view (vii), the property dualism that I have advocated, as the +only tenable option. Certainly it seems to be a consequence of well-justified +premises. In some ways it is counterintuitive, but it is the only view without +a fatal flaw. Some will find its dualistic nature unpalatable; but I will argue +shortly that dualism of this variety is not as unreasonable as many have +thought, and that it is open to few serious objections. The biggest worry about +this view is that it implies a certain irrelevance of phenomenal properties in +the explanation of behavior, and may lead to epiphenomenalism, although +this is not automatic. I will argue in the next chapter, however, that this +explanatory irrelevance has no fatal consequences. Ultimately, this view +gives us a coherent, naturalistic, unmysterious view of consciousness and its +place in the natural order. +Type A, type B, and type C +Taking a broader view of the logical geography, we can say that there are +three main classes of views about conscious experience. Type-A views hold +that consciousness, insofar as it exists, supervenes logically on the physical, +for broadly functionalist or eliminativist reasons. Type-B views accept that + + 166 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +consciousness is not logically supervenient, holding that there is no a priori +implication from the physical to the phenomenal, but maintain materialism +all the same. Type-C views deny both logical supervenience and materialism. +Type-A views come in numerous varieties—eliminativism, behaviorism, +various versions of reductive functionalism—but they have certain things in +common. A type-A theorist will hold that (1) physical and functional duplicates that lack the sort of experience that we have are inconceivable; (2) +Mary learns nothing about the world when she first sees red (at best she +gains an ability); and (3) everything there is to be explained about consciousness can be explained by explaining the performance of various functions. +Archetypal type-A theorists include Armstrong (1968), Dennett (1991), +Lewis (1966), and Ryle (1949). Others may include Dretske (1995), Rey +(1982), Rosenthal (1996), Smart (1959), White (1986), and Wilkes (1984). +Type-B views, or nonreductive versions of materialism, usually fall prey +to internal difficulties. The only type-B view that seems to be even internally +coherent is the view that invokes strong metaphysical necessity in a crucial +role. Taking this view, a type-B theorist must hold that (1) zombies and +inverted spectra are conceivable but metaphysically impossible; (2) Mary +learns something when she sees red, but that this learning can be explained +away with a Loar-style analysis; and (3) consciousness cannot be reductively +explained, but is physical nevertheless. The central type-B view has never +received a definitive statement, but the closest thing to such a statement is +given by Levine (1983,1993) and Loar (1990). Others who appear to endorse +physicalism without logical supervenience include Byrne (1993), Flanagan +(1992), Hill (1991), Morgan (1984b), Lycan (1995), Papineau (1993), Tye +(1995), and van Gulick (1992). +Type-C positions include various kinds of property dualism, in which +materialism is taken to be false and some sort of phenomenal or protophenomenal properties are taken as irreducible. On such a view, (1) zombies and +inverted spectra are logically and metaphysically possible; (2) Mary learns +something new, and her knowledge is of nonphysical facts; and (3) consciousness cannot be reductively explained, but might be nonreductively explained +in terms of further laws of nature. Type-C positions are taken by Campbell +(1970), Honderich (1981), Jackson (1982), H. Robinson (1982), W. Robinson +(1988), Sprigge (1994), and in the present work. +It is perhaps worth mentioning separately the position discussed earlier +in which phenomenal properties are identified with the intrinsic properties +of physical entities. This sort of view is endorsed by Feigl (1958), Lockwood +(1989), Maxwell (1978), and Russell (1926), and I have some sympathy with +it myself. I include this as a version of type C, as it takes phenomenal or +protophenomenal properties as fundamental, but it has its own metaphysical +shape. In particular, it is more of a monism than the natural interpretation + + Naturalistic Dualism + +167 + +of type C. Perhaps we can call this position type C', but I will usually include +it under type C. +There are two main choice points between types A, B, and C. First, is +consciousness logically supervenient (type A versus the rest)? Second, is +physicalism true (type B versus type C)? Taking the second choice point +first, I have little difficulty in rejecting type B. While it has the virtue of taking +consciousness seriously, it relies on a metaphysics that is either incoherent or +obscure, and one that is largely unmotivated; the main motivation is simply +to avoid dualism at all costs. In the end, this view shares the same explanatory +shape as type C, but with an added dose of metaphysical mystery. Type C +is straightforward by comparison. +The central choice is the choice between type A and the rest. For myself, +reductive functionalism and eliminativism seem so clearly false that I find it +hard to fathom how anyone could accept a type-A view. To me, it seems +that one could only accept such a view if one believed that there was no +significant problem about consciousness in the first place. Nevertheless, experience indicates that almost one-third of the population are willing to accept +a type-A position and do not budge. This indicates the Great Divide mentioned in the preface: the divide between views that take consciousness seriously and those that do not. +In many ways, the divide between type A and the others is deeper than +that between type B and type C. The latter division involves relatively subtle +issues of metaphysics, but the former involves some very basic intuitions. +Even though type B and type A are both "materialist" views, type-B views +are much closer to type-C views in their spirit. Both these views acknowledge +the depth of the problem of consciousness where type-A views do not. +Ultimately, argument can take us only so far in settling this issue. If +someone insists that explaining access and reportability explains everything, +that Mary discovers nothing about the world when she first has a red experience, and that a functional isomorph differing in conscious experience is +inconceivable, then I can only conclude that when it comes to experience +we are on different planes. Perhaps our inner lives differ dramatically. Perhaps one of us is "cognitively closed" to the insights of the other. More +likely, one of us is confused or is in the grip of a dogma. In any case, once +the dialectic reaches this point, it is a bridge that argument cannot cross. +Rather, we have reached a brute clash of intuitions of a sort that is common in the discussion of deep philosophical questions. Explicit argument can +help us to isolate and characterize the clash, but not to resolve it. +At the beginning of this work, I said that my approach was premised on +taking consciousness seriously. We can now see just what this conies to. To +take consciousness seriously is to accept just this: that there is something +interesting that needs explaining, over and above the performance of various + + 168 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +functions.33 This has the status of aprimafacie premise that only an extremely +strong argument could overturn. No argument that I have ever seen comes +close to overturning the premise. Indeed, type-A theorists do not usually +argue against the premise, but simply deny it. Conversely, beyond a certain +point it is almost impossible to argue for the premise, any more than one +can argue that conscious experience exists. At best, one can try to clarify +the issues in the hope that enlightenment sets in. +With the issues clarified, readers can decide for themselves whether to +take consciousness seriously. All I claim is that if one takes consciousness +seriously, then property dualism is the only reasonable option. Once we +reject reductive functionalism and eliminativism, it follows inexorably that +consciousness is not logically supervenient on the physical. And once we +reject logical supervenience, the path to property dualism is unswerving. +Type-B views are popular, but do not appear to stand up to close philosophical scrutiny. The main metaphysical choice that remains open is whether to +accept a standard type-C view or a type-C' view. This is not a question +that we have to settle immediately—I do not have a settled opinion on it +myself—but in any case, it follows either way that if we want to take consciousness seriously, we must admit phenomenal or protophenomenal properties as fundamental. +Some other views found in the philosophical literature do not fall explicitly +into the framework I have outlined. With this framework in place, however, +it is not hard to locate them and to analyze their problems. I briefly discuss +nine such positions in the endnotes: biological materialism,34 physicalist-functionalism,35 psychofunctionalism,36 anomalous monism,37 representationalism,38 consciousness as higher-order thought,39 reductive teleofunctionalism,40 +emergent causation,40 and mysterianism.42 + +6. Reflections on Naturalistic Dualism +Many people, including a past self of mine, have thought that they could +simultaneously take consciousness seriously and remain a materialist. In this +chapter I have argued that this is not possible, and for straightforward reasons. The moral is that those who want to come to grips with the phenomenon +must embrace a form of dualism. One might say: You can't have your materialist cake and eat your consciousness too. +All the same, many will be searching for an alternative to the position I +have put forward, because they find its dualistic nature unacceptable. This +reaction is natural, given the various negative associations of dualism, but I +suspect that it is not grounded in anything more solid than contemporary +dogma. To see this, it is worthwhile to consider the various reasons that one + + Naturalistic Dualism + +169 + +might have for rejecting dualism in favor of materialism, and to measure +the force of these reasons as things stand. +The first reason to prefer materialism is simplicity. This is a good reason. +Other things being equal, one should prefer a simpler theory over one that +is ontologically profligate. Ockham's razor tells us that we should not multiply +entities without necessity. But other things are not equal, and in this case +there is necessity. We have seen that materialism cannot account for the +phenomena that need to be explained. Just as Maxwell sacrificed a simple +mechanistic worldview by postulating electromagnetic fields in order to explain certain natural phenomena, we need to sacrifice a simple physicalistic +worldview in order to explain consciousness. We have paid due respect to +Ockham by recognizing that for materialism to be overthrown, one will need +good arguments. But when the arguments against materialism are there, +Ockham's razor cannot save it. +The second and perhaps the most pervasive reason to believe in materialism is inductive: materialism has always worked elsewhere. With phenomena +such as life, cognition, and the weather, we either have materialist accounts +already or we have good reason to suppose that they are not far off. Why +should consciousness be any different? +But this reason is easy to defeat. As we have seen, there is a simple +explanation for the success of materialist accounts in various external domains. With phenomena such as learning, life, and the weather, all that needs +to be explained are structures and functions. Given the causal closure of the +physical, one should expect a physical account of this structure and function. +But with consciousness, uniquely, we need to explain more than structures +and functions, so there is little reason to expect an explanation to be similar +in kind. +Indeed, we saw in Chapter 2 that given the nature of our access to external +phenomena, we should expect a materialist account of any such phenomena +to succeed. Our knowledge of these phenomena is physically mediated, by +light, sound, and other perceptual media. Given the causal closure of the +physical, we should expect phenomena that we observe by these means to +be logically supervenient on the physical—otherwise we would never know +about them. But our epistemic access to conscious experience is of an entirely +different kind. Consciousness is at the very center of our epistemic universe, +and our access to it is not perceptually mediated. The reasons for expecting a materialist account of external phenomena therefore break down in +the case of consciousness, and any induction from those phenomena will be +shaky at best. +Third, many have preferred materialism in order to take science seriously. +It has been thought that a dualist view would challenge science on its own +grounds. According to Churchland (1988), "[D]ualism is inconsistent with + + 170 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +evolutionary biology and modern physics and chemistry." But this is quite +false. Nothing about the dualist view I advocate requires us to take the +physical sciences at anything other than their word. The causal closure of +the physical is preserved; physics, chemistry, neuroscience, and cognitive +science can proceed as usual In their own domains, the physical sciences +are entirely successful. They explain physical phenomena admirably; they +simply fail to explain conscious experience. +Churchland suggests a number of other reasons to reject dualism: (1) the +systematic dependence of mental phenomena on neurobiological phenomena; (2) modern computational results that suggest that complex results can +be achieved without a nonphysical homunculus; and (3) a lack of evidence, +explanation, or methodology for dualism. The first two reasons offer no +evidence against my view. As for the third, arguments for dualism have +already been presented, while dualist explanation and methodology will be +illustrated in the remainder of this work. +A fourth motivation to avoid dualism, for many, has arisen from various +spiritualistic, religious, supernatural, and other antiscientific overtones of +the view. But those are quite inessential. On the view I advocate, consciousness is governed by natural law, and there may eventually be a reasonable +scientific theory of it. There is no a priori principle that says that all natural +laws will be physical laws; to deny materialism is not to deny naturalism. A +naturalistic dualism expands our view of the world, but it does not invoke +the forces of darkness. +In a related concern, many have thought that to accept dualism would be +to give up on explanation. In the words of Dennett (1991), "[GJiven the way +that dualism wallows in mystery, accepting dualism is giving up" (p. 37). +Perhaps some dualist views have this feature, but it is far from an automatic +corollary, as I hope the remainder of this work will make clear. +One occasionally hears a fifth objection to dualism, which is that it cannot +explain how the physical and the nonphysical interact. But the answer to +this is simple on the natural supervenience framework: they interact by virtue +of psychophysical laws. There is a system of laws that ensures that a given +physical configuration will be accompanied by a given experience, just as +there are laws that dictate that a given physical object will gravitationally +affect others in a certain way. +It might be objected that this does not tell us what the connection is, or +how a physical configuration gives rise to experience. But the search for +such a connection is misguided. Even with fundamental physical laws, we +cannot find a "connection" that does the work. Things simply happen in +accordance with the law; beyond a certain point, there is no asking "how." +As Hume showed, the quest for such ultimate connections is fruitless. If +there are indeed such connections, they are entirely mysterious in both the +physical and psychophysical cases, so the latter poses no special problem here. + + Naturalistic Dualism + +171 + +It is notable that Newton's opponents made a similar objection to his +theory of gravitation: How does one body exert a force on another far away? +But the force of the question dissolved over time. We have learned to live +with taking certain things as fundamental. +There is also a worry, raised occasionally, about how consciousness might +have evolved on a dualist framework: did a new element suddenly pop into +nature, as if by magic? But this is not a problem. Like the fundamental +laws of physics, psychophysical laws are eternal, having existed since the +beginning of time. It may be that in the early stages of the universe there +was nothing that satisfied the physical antecedents of the laws, and so no +consciousness, although this depends on the nature of the laws. In any case, +as the universe developed, it came about that certain physical systems evolved +that satisfied the relevant conditions. When these systems came into existence, conscious experience automatically accompanied them by virtue of +the laws in question. Given that psychophysical laws exist and are timeless, +as naturalistic dualism holds, the evolution of consciousness poses no special problem. +In short, very few of the usual reasons for rejecting dualism have any force +against the view I am advocating. The main residual motivation to reject +dualism may simply lie in the term's negative connotations, and the fact that +it goes against what many of us have been brought up to believe. But once +we see past these associations, we see that there is no reason why dualism +cannot be a reasonable and palatable view. Indeed, I think that the position +I have outlined is one that those who think of themselves as materialists, +but who want to take conscious experience seriously, can learn to live with +and even to appreciate. +Indeed, mine is a view that many who think of themselves as "materialists" +may already implicitly share. All I have done is bring the ontological implications of a natural view—that consciousness "arises" from the physical, for +example—out into the open. Some dualists may even find my view all too +materialistic for their tastes, in which case so be it. Ideally, it is a view that +takes the best of both worlds and the worst of neither. +This dualism, then, requires us to give up little that is important about +our current scientific worldview. It merely requires us to give up a dogma. +Otherwise, the view is merely a supplement to the worldview; it is a necessary +broadening in order to bring consciousness within its scope. Our credo: If +this is dualism, then we should learn to love dualism. + + 5 +The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +1. Consciousness and Cognition +So far, the distinctions and divisions between consciousness and cognition +have been stressed above all else. Consciousness is mysterious; cognition is +not. Consciousness is ontologically novel; cognition is an ontological free +lunch. Cognition can be explained functionally; consciousness resists such +explanation. Cognition is governed entirely by the laws of physics; consciousness is governed in part by independent psychophysical laws. +While the focus on these distinctions has been necessary in order to come to +grips with the many subtle metaphysical and explanatory issues surrounding +conscious experience, it may encourage a misleading picture of the mind. In +this picture, consciousness and cognition are utterly detached from each +other, living independent lives. One might get the impression that a theory of +consciousness and a theory of cognition will have little to do with one another. +This picture is misleading. Our mental life is not alienated from itself in +the way that the picture suggests. There are deep and fundamental ties between consciousness and cognition. On one side, the contents of our conscious +experiences are closely related to the contents of our cognitive states. Whenever one has a green sensation, individuated phenomenally, one has a corresponding green perception, individuated psychologically. On the other side, +much cognitive activity can be centered on conscious experience. We know +about our experiences, and make judgments about them; as I write this, a +great deal of my thought is being devoted to consciousness. These relations +between consciousness and cognition are not arbitrary and capricious, but +systematic. + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +173 + +An analysis of this systematic relationship may provide much of the basic +material for a theory of consciousness. In this way, we can see that the nature +of cognition is not irrelevant to consciousness, but central to its explanation. +Of course a theory of cognition cannot do all the explanatory work on its +own, but it can nevertheless play a major role. After all, it is through cognition +that we get a handle on consciousness in the first place. A thorough investigation of the links between consciousness and cognition can provide the purchase we need to constrain a theory of consciousness in a significant way, +perhaps ultimately leading to an account of consciousness that neither mystifies nor trivializes the phenomenon. +In this chapter, I lay the groundwork for a study of the relationship between consciousness and cognition. The next section introduces some notions +that are at the center of this relationship. The remainder of the chapter is +largely defensive, addressing various problems that the relationship between +consciousness and cognition might seem to pose for a nonreductive view. In +the next chapter, I begin the task of building a positive theory that systematizes the relationship between consciousness and cognition, with the goal +of drawing them together into a unified picture of the mind. +Phenomenal judgments +The primary nexus of the relationship between consciousness and cognition +lies in phenomenal judgments. Our conscious experience does not reside in +an isolated phenomenal void. We are aware of our experience and its contents, we form judgments about it, and we are led to make claims about it. +When I have a red sensation, I sometimes form a belief that I am having a +red sensation, which can issue in a verbal report. At a more abstract level, +when one stops to reflect on the mysteries that consciousness poses, as I +have been doing throughout this book, one is making judgments about +consciousness. At a more concrete level, we frequently form judgments about +the objects of our conscious experience (in the environment, for example), +as when we think, "There is something red." The various judgments in the +vicinity of consciousness I call phenomenal judgments, not because they +are phenomenal states themselves, but because they are concerned with +phenomenology or with its objects. +Phenomenal judgments are often reflected in claims about consciousness: +verbal expressions of those judgments. At various times, people make claims +about consciousness ranging from "I have a throbbing pain now" through +"LSD gives me bizarre color sensations" to "The problem of consciousness +is utterly baffling." These claims and judgments are intimately related to +our phenomenology, but they are ultimately part of our psychology. Verbal +reports are behavioral acts, and are therefore susceptible to functional expla- + + 174 + +The Irredueibility of Consciousness + +nation. In a similar way phenomenal judgments are themselves cognitive +acts, and fall within the domain of psychology. +It is often taken that beliefs should be understood as functional states, +characterized by their causal ties to behavior, the environment, and other +beliefs, but this view is not universally accepted. Some hold that phenomenal +experience can be partly constitutive of belief or of belief contents. For +beliefs about consciousness, the functional view is likely to be particularly +controversial: if any beliefs are dependent on conscious experience, beliefs +about consciousness are the most likely candidates. I will therefore adopt +the less loaded label "judgment" for the functional states in question, and +will leave open the question of whether a judgment about consciousness is +all there is to a belief about consciousness. We can think of a judgment as +what is left of a belief after any associated phenomenal quality is subtracted. +That there are purely psychological states that qualify as these judgments +should not be a controversial matter. For a start, the disposition to make +verbal reports of a certain form is a psychological state; at the very least, +we can use the label "judgment" for this disposition. Moreover, whenever +I form a belief about my conscious experience, there are all sorts of accompanying functional processes, just as there are with any belief. These processes +underlie the disposition to make verbal reports, and all sorts of other dispositions. If one believes that LSD produces bizarre color sensations, the accompanying processes may underlie a tendency to indulge in or to avoid LSD +in future, and so on. We can use the term "judgment" as a coverall for the +states or processes that play the causal role in question. At a first approximation, a system judges that a proposition is true if it tends to respond affirmatively when queried about the proposition, to behave in an appropriate +manner given its other beliefs and desires, and so on. +Judgments can perhaps be understood as what I and my zombie twin have +in common. My zombie twin does not have any conscious experience, but +he claims that he does; at least, his detailed verbal reports sound the same +as my own. As I am using the term, I think it is natural to say that my zombie +twin judges that he has conscious experience, and that his judgments in this +vicinity correspond one-to-one with mine. +At the end of this chapter, I argue that the semantic content of my phenomenal beliefs is partly constituted in subtle ways by conscious experience itself +(for example, red sensations may play a role in constituting the content of +certain beliefs about red sensations). If this is so, then some of the zombie's +judgments will have contents that are not as rich as my corresponding belief +contents. Nevertheless, they will at least correspond one-to-one to mine, will +have the same form, and will function in the same way in directing behavior +as mine. So when I talk of a zombie's judgment that he is having a red +sensation, I am talking about something interesting in his psychology: at the + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +175 + +very least, my words can be taken to refer hi a deflationary way to the +judgment that he expresses using the words "I am having a red sensation" +(or words with that sound!). I will talk about "claims" in a similar way, +abstracting away from these subtle issues of content. +Strictly speaking, all descriptions of phenomenal claims and judgments in +terms of their content (e.g., references to the judgment that one is having a +red sensation) should be read in this deflationary way. The full content +attributed will certainly be possessed by a subject's phenomenal beliefs, but +the question of the content of a judgment is not so clear, precisely because +it is not clear what role consciousness plays in constituting the content of a +phenomenal belief. I will not make too much of this distinction for much of +this chapter, as I will be trying to raise some problems that phenomenal +judgments pose for my view in the most acute way possible. At the end of +the chapter, I will consider these questions about content in more detail. + +Three kinds of phenomenal judgment +Judgments related to conscious experience fall into at least three groups. +There are what I will call first-order, second-order, and third-order phenomenal judgments. I will usually drop the qualifier and speak of "first-order +judgments," and so on, where it is understood that these are always phenomenal judgments. +First-order judgments are the judgments that go along with conscious +experiences, concerning not the experience itself but the object of the experience. When I have a red sensation—upon looking at a red book, for instance—there is generally an explicit or implicit judgment, "There is something red." When I have the experience of hearing a musical note, there is +an accompanying psychological state concerning that musical note. It seems +fair to say that any object that is consciously experienced is also cognitively +represented, although there is more to say about this. Alongside every conscious experience there is a content-bearing cognitive state. This cognitive +state is what I am calling a first-order judgment. (One might argue that this +state is unlike a belief or judgment in certain ways, as for example it need +not be endorsed on reflection. I discuss this at more length in the next chapter, +but for now I will speak of "judgments" at least as a first approximation.) +We may think of the contents of these first-order judgments as making +up the contents of awareness, where awareness is the psychological counterpart of consciousness mentioned in Chapter 1: information of which we +are aware is roughly information that is accessible to the cognitive system, +available for verbal report, and so on. These judgments are not strictly about +consciousness. Rather, they are parallel to consciousness, and generally about +objects and properties in the environment, or even in the head. In fact, it is + + 176 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +reasonable to say that a first-order judgment is about what the corresponding +experience is about. Where I have an experience of a red book, there is a +corresponding first-order judgment about the red book. In a certain sense, we +can therefore say that experience and first-order judgments—and therefore +consciousness and awareness—share their contents. I will give a more refined +account of this relationship in the next chapter. +In this chapter, I will be most concerned with second-order judgments. +These are more straightforwardly judgments about conscious experiences. +When I have a red sensation, I sometimes notice that I am having a red +sensation. I judge that I have a pain, that I experience certain emotional +qualities, and so on. In general, it seems that for any conscious experience, +if one possesses the relevant conceptual resources, then one at least has the +capacity to judge that one is having that experience. +One can also make more detailed judgments about conscious experiences. +One can note that one is experiencing a particularly vivid shade of purple, +or that a pain has an all-consuming quality, or even that a green after-image +is the third such after-image one has had today. Apart from judgments +about specific conscious experiences, second-order judgments also include +judgments about particular kinds of conscious experiences, as when one +notes that some drug produces particularly intense sensations, or that the +tingle one gets before a sneeze is particularly pleasurable. +What I will call third-order judgments are judgments about conscious +experience as a type. These go beyond judgments about particular experiences. We make third-order judgments when we reflect on the fact that +we have conscious experiences in the first place, and when we reflect on +their nature. I have been making third-order judgments throughout this +work. A typical third-order judgment might be, "Consciousness is baffling; +I don't see how it could be reductively explained." Others include "Conscious experience is ineffable," and even "Conscious experience does not +exist." +Third-order judgments are particularly common among philosophers, and +among those with a tendency to speculate on the mysteries of existence. It +is possible that many people go through life without making any thirdorder judgments. Still, such judgments occur in a significant class of people. +The very fact that people make such judgments is something that needs +explanation. +To help keep the distinctions in mind, the various kinds of judgments +related to consciousness can be represented by the following: +• First-order judgment: That's red! +• Second-order judgment: I'm having a red sensation now. +• Third-order judgment: Sensations are mysterious. + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +177 + +2. The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment +The existence of phenomenal judgments reveals a central tension within a +nonreductive theory of consciousness. The problem is this. We have seen +that consciousness itself cannot be reductively explained. But phenomenal +judgments lie in the domain of psychology and in principle should be reductively explainable by the usual methods of cognitive science. There should +be a physical or functional explanation of why we are disposed to make the +claims about consciousness that we do, for instance, and of how we make +the judgments we do about conscious experience. It then follows that our +claims and judgments about consciousness can be explained in terms quite +independent of consciousness. More strongly, it seems that consciousness is +explanatorily irrelevant to our claims and judgments about consciousness. +This result I call the paradox of phenomenal judgment. +The paradox of phenomenal judgment does not seem to have received a +great deal of attention, but it is put forward vividly by physicist Avshalom +Elitzur (1989) as an argument against views that take consciousness to be +"passive"; he argues instead for an interactionist dualism.1 The paradox is +also expressed by psychologist Roger Shepard (1993), who suggests that it +is something we should become reconciled to: +In short, we still seem to be left with a dilemma: No analysis of the purely +physical processes in a brain (or in a computer) seems capable of capturing the +particular quality of the subjective experience corresponding to those processes. +Yet, some such analysis should surely be able to give a causal account of how +an individual comes to type a sentence such as the preceding. Perhaps we shall +have to reconcile ourselves to accepting that although both the existence of +conscious experiences and the similarity relations among their qualia have physical embodiments with physical causes and effects, the conscious experiences or +qualia themselves are neither characterizable as physical events nor communicable between physical systems, (p. 242) + +As we saw in the last chapter, the question of whether consciousness is +causally irrelevant in the production of behavior is a complex metaphysical +issue that is best left open. But the explanatory irrelevance of consciousness +is clearer, and raises many of the same difficulties that would be raised by +causal irrelevance. However the metaphysics of causation turns out, it seems +relatively straightforward that a physical explanation of behavior can be +given that neither appeals to nor implies the existence of consciousness. +When I say in conversation, "Consciousness is the most mysterious thing +there is," that is a behavioral act. When I wrote in an earlier chapter "Consciousness cannot be reductively explained," that was a behavioral act. When +I comment on some particularly intense purple qualia that I am experiencing, +that is a behavioral act. Like all behavioral acts, these are in principle ex- + + 178 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +plainable in terms of the internal causal organization of my cognitive system. +There is some story about firing patterns in neurons that will explain why +these acts occurred; at a higher level, there is probably a story about cognitive +representations and their high-level relations that will do the relevant explanatory work. We certainly do not know the details of the explanation now, +but if the physical domain is causally closed, then there will be some reductive +explanation in physical or functional terms. +In giving this explanation of my claims in physical or functional terms, +we will never have to invoke the existence of conscious experience itself. +The physical or functional explanation will be given independently, applying +equally well to a zombie as to an honest-to-goodness conscious experiencer. +It therefore seems that conscious experience is irrelevant to the explanations +of phenomenal claims and irrelevant in a similar way to the explanation of +phenomenal judgments, even though these claims and judgments are centrally concerned with conscious experience! +One way to resist this claim would be to argue that the full content of my +phenomenal claims and beliefs cannot be reductively explained, because +consciousness plays a role in constituting that content. One might argue that +a zombie's claims and beliefs are different claims and beliefs, for example +(although they look and sound just the same!), because a zombie would not +have the full concept of consciousness. But at the very least it is still puzzling +that consciousness should be irrelevant to the sounds we make when talking +about consciousness, to the finger movements I am making now, and so on; +so this response does not remove the full sense of bafflement. So I will set +aside this way of thinking about things for now, and will continue to think +about claims and judgments in the "deflationary" way that allows that they +can be reductively explained. +Another way to resist the point would be to argue that for any high-level +property that might be thought relevant in explanation, there will be a lowlevel explanation that does not invoke the existence of that property. One +could argue that a psychological property such as memory is explanatorily +irrelevant, as one can give neurophysiological explanations of actions that +never once mention memory; one could even argue that temperature is +explanatorily irrelevant in physics, as explanatory appeals to temperature +can in principle be replaced by a molecular account. (Kim [1989] calls this +the problem of explanatory exclusion.) This might suggest that consciousness +is no worse off than any other high-level property when it comes to explanatory irrelevance. If consciousness is on a par with memory or temperature, +this is not bad company to be in. +We have seen, however, that high-level properties such as temperature +and memory are all logically supervenient on the physical. It follows that +when one gives an explanation of some action in neurophysiological terms, +this does not make memory explanatorily irrelevant. Memory can inherit + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +179 + +explanatory relevance by virtue of its logically supervenient status. When +we explain a man's desire for female companionship in terms of the fact +that he is male and unmarried, this does not make the fact that he is a +bachelor explanatorily irrelevant! The general principle here is that when +two sets of properties are conceptually related, the existence of an explanation in terms of one set does not render the other set explanatorily irrelevant. +In a sense, one of the explanations can be a retelling of the other, due to +the conceptual relation between the terms involved. +When we tell a story about the interaction of memories, there is a sense +in which we are retelling the physical story at a higher level of abstraction. +This higher level will omit many details from the physical story, and will +therefore often make for a much more satisfying explanation (all those +details may have been irrelevant clutter), but it is nevertheless logically +related to the lower-level story. The same goes for temperature. These highlevel properties are no more rendered explanatorily irrelevant by the existence of a low-level explanation than the velocity of a billiard ball is rendered +explanatorily irrelevant by the existence of molecular processes within the +ball. In general, the high-level properties in question will constitute a more +parsimonious redescription of what a low-level explanation describes. One +might say that even a low-level description will often implicitly involve highlevel properties, by virtue of their logically supervenient status, even if it +does not invoke them explicitly. Where there is logical supervenience, there +is no problem of explanatory irrelevance. +The problems with consciousness are much more serious. Consciousness +is not logically supervenient on the physical, so we cannot claim that a +physical or functional explanation implicitly involves consciousness, or +that consciousness inherits explanatory relevance by logically supervening on the properties involved in such an explanation. A physical or functional explanation of behavior is independent of consciousness in a much +stronger sense. It can be given in terms that do not even imply the existence of conscious experience. Consciousness is conceptually independent +of what goes into the explanation of our claims and judgments about consciousness. +This is not to say that one can never appeal to conscious experience in +the explanation of behavior. It is perfectly reasonable to explain the fact of +someone's withdrawal from a flame by noting that they experienced pain. +After all, even on the nonreductive view there are lawful regularities between +experience and subsequent behavior. Such regularities ultimately depend on +regularities at the physical level, however. For any explanation of behavior +that appeals to a pain sensation, there is a more fundamental explanation +in purely physical/functional terms—perhaps in terms of psychological pain +or pain perception—that do not invoke or imply any properties of experience. Experience gains a sort of indirect explanatory relevance in virtue + + 180 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +of its nomic connection to these physical and functional processes, but it +nevertheless remains superfluous to the basic explanation. +To see the problem in a particularly vivid way, think of my zombie twin in +the universe next door. He talks about conscious experience all the time— +in fact, he seems obsessed by it. He spends ridiculous amounts of time +hunched over a computer, writing chapter after chapter on the mysteries of +consciousness. He often comments on the pleasure he gets from certain +sensory qualia, professing a particular love for deep greens and purples. He +frequently gets into arguments with zombie materialists, arguing that their +position cannot do justice to the realities of conscious experience. +And yet he has no conscious experience at all! In his universe, the materialists are right and he is wrong. Most of his claims about conscious experience are utterly false. But there is certainly a physical or functional explanation of why he makes the claims he makes. After all, his universe is fully +law-governed, and no events therein are miraculous, so there must be some +explanation of his claims. But such an explanation must ultimately be in +terms of physical processes and laws, for these are the only processes and +laws in his universe. +(As before, one might plausibly argue that a zombie does not refer to +consciousness in the full sense with his word "consciousness." For now, +talk of a zombie's claims and judgments about consciousness should be +read in the deflationary way discussed earlier. But even if he does not +have the full concept, there is no doubt that he judges that he has some +property over and above his structural and functional properties—a property that he calls "consciousness"—and the problem arises as strongly in +this form.) +Now my zombie twin is only a logical possibility, not an empirical one, +and we should not get too worried about odd things that happen in logically +possible worlds. Still, there is room to be perturbed by what is going on. +After all, any explanation of my twin's behavior will equally count as an +explanation of my behavior, as the processes inside his body are precisely +mirrored by those inside mine. The explanation of his claims obviously does +not depend on the existence of consciousness, as there is no consciousness +in his world. It follows that the explanation of my claims is also independent +of the existence of consciousness. +To strengthen the sense of paradox, note that my zombie twin is himself +engaging in reasoning just like this. He has been known to lament the fate +of his zombie twin, who spends all his time worrying about consciousness +despite the fact that he has none. He worries about what that must say about +the explanatory irrelevance of consciousness in his own universe. Still, he +remains utterly confident that consciousness exists and cannot be reductively +explained. But all this, for him, is a monumental delusion. There is no +consciousness in his universe—in his world, the eliminativists have been right + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +181 + +all along. Despite the fact that his cognitive mechanisms function in the same +way as mine, his judgments about consciousness are quite deluded. +This paradoxical situation is at once delightful and disturbing. It is not +obviously fatal to the nonreductive position, but it is at least something that +we need to come to grips with. It is certainly the greatest tension that a +nonreductive theory is faced with, and any such theory that does not at least +face up to the problem cannot be fully satisfactory. We have to carefully +examine the consequences of the situation and separate what is merely +counterintuitive from what threatens the viability of a nonreductive view +of consciousness. +Nietzsche said, "What does not kill us, makes us stronger." If we can cope +with this paradox, we may be led to valuable insights about the relationship +between consciousness and cognition. I devote the remainder of this chapter +to facing up to the paradox, and related issues about the connection between +consciousness and cognition will recur throughout the next few chapters. In +this way a theory of consciousness can be set onto much firmer ground. +(One might think one could evade the paradox by embracing what I have +called a type-B position, in which consciousness supervenes with metaphysical necessity but not with conceptual necessity, or a type-C' positions, in +which phenomenal properties constitute the intrinsic nature of the physical. +But the paradox arises almost as strongly for these views. Even if these +views salvage a sort of causal relevance for consciousness, they still lead to +explanatory irrelevance, as explanatory relevance must be supported by +conceptual connections. Even on these views, one can give a reductive explanation of phenomenal judgments but not of consciousness itself, making +consciousness explanatorily irrelevant to the judgments. There will be a +processing explanation of the judgments that does not invoke or imply the +existence of experience at any stage; the presence of any further "metaphysically necessary" connection or intrinsic phenomenal properties will be conceptually quite independent of anything that goes into the explanation of +behavior. +Another way to see this: on these views, zombies are still conceivable, +and there will be a perfectly good explanation of the zombie's behavior. +Because this explanation applies to a zombie, the existence of consciousness +will play no essential role in the explanation. But what is going on within +the zombies is also going on within us, so the same explanation will apply +equally to us. So even on these views there will be an explanation of our +phenomenal judgments to which consciousness is quite superfluous.) +Facing up to the paradox +When it comes to the explanation of most of our behavior, the fact that +consciousness is explanatorily irrelevant may be counterintuitive, but it is + + 182 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +not too paradoxical. To explain my reaching for the book in front of me, +we need not invoke my phenomenal sensation of the book; it is enough to +invoke my perception instead. When a concert-goer sighs at a particularly +exquisite movement, one might have thought that the experienced quality +of auditory sensations might be central to an explanation of this behavior, +but it turns out that an explanation can be given entirely in terms of auditory +perception and functional responses. Even in explaining why I withdraw my +hand from a flame, a functional explanation in terms of the psychological +notion of pain will suffice. +In general, it turns out that where one might think that one would need +to invoke phenomenal properties in the explanation of behavior, one can +usually invoke psychological properties instead. We saw in Chapter 1 that +there is a psychological state underlying every phenomenal state. Where one +might have invoked a sensation, one invokes a perceptual registration; where +one might have invoked the phenomenal quality of an emotion, one invokes +a corresponding functional state; where one might have invoked an occurrent +thought, one need only invoke the content of that thought. It is this correspondence between phenomenal and psychological properties that makes the +explanatory irrelevance of phenomenal properties not too serious a problem +in general. It is counterintuitive at first, but it is only counterintuitive. At +least for behavior that is not directly concerned with conscious experience, +there does not seem to be a pressing need to invoke phenomenal properties +in explanation. +It is with our claims and judgments about consciousness that the explanatory irrelevance of conscious experience becomes troubling. True, it may +not be especially worrying that consciousness is explanatorily irrelevant to +our first-order phenomenal judgments, such as "That is a red thing." It is +reasonable that these should be explained purely in terms of perception and +other psychological processes; after all, the judgments in question are not +directly concerned with conscious experience, but with the state of the world. +For second- and third-order phenomenal judgments, however, explanatory +irrelevance seems to raise real problems. It is these judgments that are about +conscious experience, and that are responsible for our talking about our +sensations and for philosophers' worries about the mysteries of consciousness. It is one thing to accept that consciousness is irrelevant to explaining +how I walk around the room; it is another to accept that it is irrelevant to +explaining why I talk about consciousness. One would surely be inclined to +think that the fact that I am conscious will be part of the explanation of why +I say that I am conscious, or why I judge that I am conscious; and yet it +seems that this is not so. +After all, part of the explanation of why we claim and judge that there is +water will involve the fact that there is indeed water. In a similar way, it +seems that the existence of stars and planets is almost certainly explanatorily + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +183 + +relevant to our judging that there are stars and planets. As a rule, when we +judge truly and reliably that P, the fact that P is true generally plays a central +role in the explanation of the judgment. There are some judgments for which +the objects of those judgments are explanatorily irrelevant to the judgments +themselves. Think of religious beliefs, for instance, or beliefs about UFOs, +which can arguably be explained without invoking any gods or UFOs. But +these are all quite possibly false beliefs, and not obviously instances of +knowledge. By contrast, we know that we are conscious. +Here we are faced with a difficult situation: how can knowledge of consciousness be reconciled with the fact that consciousness is explanatorily +irrelevant to phenomenal judgments? If phenomenal judgments arise for +reasons independent of consciousness itself, does this not mean that they +are unjustified? This, above all, is the central difficulty posed by the paradox +of phenomenal judgment, and I will address it at length later in this chapter. +The paradox is a consequence of the facts that (1) the physical domain is +causally closed; (2) judgments about consciousness are logically supervenient +on the physical; (3) consciousness is not logically supervenient on the physical; +and (4) we know we are conscious. From premises (1) and (2) it follows that +judgments about consciousness can be reductively explained. In combination +with premise (3), this implies that consciousness is explanatorily irrelevant +to our judgments, which lies in tension with premise (4). Thus we have the +paradox. One might try to escape the paradox by denying any one of these +premises. I will consider each of these escape routes briefly. +Some dualists will deny premise (1). Traditionally, a Cartesian interactionist dualism has been motivated by the thought that only this can give consciousness the relevance to action that it deserves. Indeed, Elitzur (1989) +argues directly from the existence of claims about consciousness to the +conclusion that the laws of physics cannot be complete, and that consciousness plays an active role in directing physical processes (he suggests that the +second law of thermodynamics might be false). But I have already argued +that interactionist dualism is of little help in avoiding the problem of explanatory irrelevance. +Some might be tempted to deny premise (2), but recall that we have +defined judgments so that they are functional states, logically supervenient +on the physical. Now, some might argue that there is no such functional +state that remotely resembles what we think of as a judgment; but even so, +we can simply retreat to claims about consciousness, which are behavioral +acts and so more straightforwardly logically supervenient, and which raise +the difficulties almost as strongly. Even if someone argued that behavioral +acts are not purely physical (they might argue that conscious experience is +required for something to qualify as a claim rather than a noise, or as a claim +about consciousness), it is still surprising that consciousness is explanatorily +irrelevant to the sounds we produce, and to the marks we write, all of + + 184 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +which can be systematically interpreted as concerning consciousness. So some +analogous problems will arise no matter how we define the relevant states. +Still, this sort of consideration can play at least a subsidiary role in dealing +with the paradox, as it is plausibly beliefs rather than claims that are most +closely connected to knowledge, and some sort of phenomenal belief content +may be constituted by experience itself. I return to this matter later in +the chapter. +Reductionists and eliminativists will of course deny premise (3) or (4). I +have argued exhaustively for (3) already, so I will not repeat the arguments +here. Similarly, the denial of premise (4) leads to eliminativism, an option +I have already rejected. Still, I will examine a way that a reductionist might +exploit the paradox of phenomenal judgment shortly. +It seems to me that the most reasonable attitude to take is to recognize +that all the premises are probably true; and to see how they can be reconciled +with one other. We know there is conscious experience; the physical domain +is almost certainly causally closed; and we have established earlier that +consciousness is not logically supervenient on the physical. The trick is to +learn to live with the combination. + +3. On Explaining Phenomenal Judgments +Given what has gone before, explaining why we say the things we do about +consciousness emerges as a reasonable and interesting project for cognitive +science. These claims are behavioral acts, and should be as susceptible to +explanation as any other behavioral act. Indeed, there should be rich pickings +for any cognitive scientist who takes this path. Explaining our claims and +judgments about consciousness may be difficult, but it will not be as difficult +as explaining consciousness itself. This explanation will not automatically +yield an explanation of consciousness, of course, but it may well point us in +the right direction. +We can do more than accept the possibility of such an explanation as an +intellectual conclusion, derived from the causal closure of physics and the +logical supervenience of behavior. There are independent reasons for thinking that phenomenal judgments will be natural concomitants of certain kinds +of cognitive processes, and that on reflection one should expect such judgments from an intelligent system with a certain design. If so, then the explanation of the claims and judgments may not be as difficult as one might think; +they might fall out of some basic principles about cognitive design. +Here, I will provide just a very brief sketch of why one might think this; +I go into this matter in more detail in Chapter 8. To get some feel for the situation, imagine that we have created computational intelligence in the form +of an autonomous agent that perceives its environment and has the capacity + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +185 + +to reflect rationally on what it perceives. What would such a system be like? +Would it have any concept of consciousness, or any related notions? +To see that it might, note that on the most natural design such a system +would surely have some concept of self—for instance, it would have the +ability to distinguish itself from the rest of the world, and from other entities +resembling it. It also seems reasonable that such a system would be able to +access its own cognitive contents much more directly than it could those of +others. If it had the capacity to reflect, it would presumably have a certain +direct awareness of its own thought contents, and could reason about that +fact. Furthermore, such a system would most naturally have direct access to +perceptual information, much as our own cognitive system does. +When we asked the system what perception was like, what would it say? +Would it say, "It's not like anything"? Might it say, "Well, I know there is +a red tricycle over there, but I have no idea how I know. The information +just appeared in my database"? Perhaps, but it seems unlikely. A system +designed this way would be quite inefficient and unnatural; its access to its +own perceptual contents would be curiously indirect. It seems much more +likely that it would say, "I know there is a red tricycle because I see it there." +When we ask it in turn how it knows that it is seeing the tricycle, the answer +would very likely be something along the lines of "I just see it." +It would be an odd system that replied, "I know I see it because sensors +78-84 are activated in such-and-such a way." As Hofstadter (1979) points +out, there is no need to give a system such detailed access to its low-level +parts. Even Winograd's program SHRDLU (1972) did not have knowledge +about the code it was written in, despite the fact that it could perceive a virtual +world, make inferences about that world, and even justify its knowledge to +a limited degree. Such extra knowledge would seem to be quite unnecessary, +and would only complicate the processes of awareness and inference. +Instead, it seems likely that such a system would have the same kind of +attitude toward its perceptual contents as we do toward ours, with its knowledge of them being direct and unmediated, at least as far as the system is +concerned. When we ask how it knows that it sees the red tricycle, an +efficiently designed system would say, "I just see it!" When we ask how it +knows that the tricycle is red, it would say the same sort of thing that we +do: "It just looks red." If such a system were reflective, it might start wondering about how it is that things look red, and about why it is that red just is +a particular way, and blue another. From the system's point of view it is just +a brute fact that red looks one way, and blue another. Of course from our +vantage point we know that this is just because red throws the system into +one state, and blue throws it into another; but from the machine's point of +view this does not help. +As it reflected, it might start to wonder about the very fact that it seems +to have some access to what it is thinking, and that it has a sense of self. A + + 186 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +reflective machine that was designed to have direct access to the contents +of its perception and thought might very soon start wondering about the +mysteries of consciousness (Hofstadter 1985a gives a rich discussion of this +idea): "Why is it that heat feels this way?"; "Why am I me, and not someone +else?"; "I know my processes are just electronic circuits, but how does this +explain my experience of thought and perception?" +Of course, the speculation I have engaged in here is not to be taken too +seriously, but it helps to bring out the naturalness of the fact that we judge +and claim that we are conscious, given a reasonable design. It would be a +strange kind of cognitive system that had no idea what we were talking about +when we asked what it was like to be it. The fact that we think and talk +about consciousness may be a consequence of very natural features of our +design, just as it is with these systems. And certainly, in the explanation of +why these systems think and talk as they do, we will never need to invoke +full-fledged consciousness. Perhaps these systems are really conscious and +perhaps they are not, but the explanation works independently of this fact. +Any explanation of how these systems function can be given solely in computational terms. In such a case it is obvious that there is no room for a ghost +in the machine to play an explanatory role. +All this is to say (expanding on a claim in Chapter 1) that consciousness +is surprising, but claims about consciousness are not. Although consciousness +is a feature of the world that we would not predict from the physical facts, +the things we say about consciousness are a garden-variety cognitive phenomenon. Somebody who knew enough about cognitive structure would immediately be able to predict the likelihood of utterances such as "I feel conscious, +in a way that no physical object could be," or even Descartes's "Cogito ergo +sum." In principle, some reductive explanation in terms of internal processes +should render claims about consciousness no more deeply surprising than +any other aspect of behavior. I have gestured toward such an explanation +above, and will consider the matter in more detail in a later chapter. +We will see later that the details of an appropriate explanation can be very +useful in getting a theory of consciousness off the ground. The relationship +between an explanation of phenomenal judgments and an explanation of +consciousness is a subtle one, however. Before proceeding, I will consider +a less subtle response to the situation we are placed in. +Is explaining the judgments enough? +At this point a natural thought has probably occurred to many readers, +especially those of a reductionist bent: If one has explained why we say we +are consciousness, and why we judge that we are conscious, haven't we +explained all that there is to be explained? Why not simply give up on the +quest for a theory of consciousness, declaring consciousness itself a chimera? + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +187 + +Even better, why not declare one's theory of why we judge that we are +conscious to be a theory of consciousness in its own right? It might well be +suggested that a theory of our judgments is all the theory of consciousness +that we need. +This position gets some support from considerations about judgments in +other domains. It might be thought that the widespread belief in gods, found +in all sorts of diverse cultures, provides an excellent reason to believe that +gods exist. But there is an alternative explanation of this belief, in terms of +social and psychological forces. Atheists might appeal to people's psychological insecurity in the face of the cosmos, to the need for a common outlet +for spiritual or emotional expression, and to the intrinsically self-propagating +nature of certain idea systems, to explain why it is all but inevitable that +religious beliefs should be widespread, given our nature and circumstances. +One can even point to the existence of certain highly plausible but faulty +arguments for the existence of a god, such as the argument from design and +the cosmological arguments. Although these arguments are faulty, they are +not obviously faulty (in particular, the argument from design could reasonably have been seen as compelling before the time of Darwin), and it is not +hard to see why they should generally contribute toward the naturalness of +religious belief. +The observation that widespread religious belief might be explained in +this way, without appeal to the existence of any gods, is generally taken to +provide further evidence that no gods in fact exist. On this interpretation, +the atheistic hypothesis can not only explain the complex structure of nature +as well as the theistic hypothesis; it can even explain why the theistic hypothesis is so popular. This is a powerful way to cut the support from underneath +an opposing view. In the case of religious belief, the argument seems very +strong. It makes a tempting argument in the case of consciousness, too. +This is surely the single most powerful argument for a reductive or eliminativist view of consciousness. But it is not enough. The analogy fails. Explaining +our judgments about consciousness does not come close to removing the +mysteries of consciousness. Why? Because consciousness is itself an explanandum. The existence of God was arguably hypothesized largely in order +to explain all sorts of evident facts about the world, such as its orderliness +and its apparent design. When it turns out that an alternate hypothesis can +explain the evidence just as well, then there is no need for the hypothesis +of God. There is no separate phenomenon God that we can point to and +say: that needs explaining. At best, there is indirect evidence.2 Similarly, the +existence of UFOs is often postulated to explain strange events in the sky, +markings in the ground, disappearances in the Bermuda Triangle, the claims +of UFO "survivors," and so on. If it turns out that this evidence can be +explained without postulating the existence of UFOs, then our reason for +believing in UFOs disappears. + + 188 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +But consciousness is not an explanatory construct, postulated to help +explain behavior or events in the world. Rather, it is a brute explanandum, +a phenomenon in its own right that is in need of explanation. It therefore +does not matter if it turns out that consciousness is not required to do any +work in explaining other phenomena. Our evidence for consciousness never +lay with these other phenomena in the first place. Even if our judgments +about consciousness are explained reductively, all this shows is that our +judgments can be explained reductively. The mind-body problem is not that +of explaining our judgments about consciousness. If it were, it would be a +relatively trivial problem. Rather, the mind-body problem is that of explaining consciousness itself. If the judgments can be explained without +explaining consciousness, then that is interesting and perhaps surprising, but +it does not remove the mind-body problem. +To take the line that explaining our judgments about consciousness is +enough (just as explaining our judgments about God is enough) is most +naturally understood as an eliminativist position about consciousness (as one +analogously takes an eliminativist position about God). As such it suffers +from all the problems that eliminativism naturally faces. In particular, it +denies the evidence of our own experience. This is the sort of thing that can +only be done by a philosopher—or by someone else tying themselves in +intellectual knots. Our experiences of red do not go away upon making such +a denial. It is still like something to be us, and that is still something that +needs explanation. To throw out consciousness itself as a result of the paradox of phenomenal judgment would be to throw out the baby with the +bathwater. +There is a certain intellectual appeal to the position that explaining phenomenal judgments is enough. It has the feel of a bold stroke that cleanly +dissolves all the problems, leaving our confusion lying on the ground in front +of us exposed for all to see. Yet it is the kind of "solution" that is satisfying +only for about half a minute. When we stop to reflect, we realize that all we +have done is to explain certain aspects of our behavior. We have explained +why we talk in certain ways, and why we are disposed to do so, but we have +not remotely come to grips with the central problem, namely conscious +experience itself. When thirty seconds are up, we find ourselves looking at +a red rose, inhaling its fragrance, and wondering: "Why do I experience it +like thisT' And we realize that this explanation has nothing to say about +the matter. +If this position is not taken as a kind of eliminativism, it can perhaps be +taken as a kind of functionalist position, in which the notion of consciousness +is construed as "the thing responsible for judgments about consciousness." +But this is as inadequate as any other functional definition of consciousness. +Whether or not consciousness is in fact responsible for judgments about +consciousness, this does not seem to be a conceptual truth. After all, it is at + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +189 + +least logically possible that one could explain the judgments without explaining consciousness, whether or not it is plausible; and that is enough to +show that this construal of consciousness is a false one. +There are other variations on this line of argument. For instance, one +could argue that there is a purely reductive explanation of why I think that +consciousness cannot be reductively explained, or of why I think consciousness is not logically supervenient, or of why I think it cannot be functionally +defined. We might even reductively explain why I think conscious experience +is an explanandum. This might be thought to undercut my arguments in +earlier sections entirely, opening the way for a reductive view of consciousness. But again this view can be satisfying only as a kind of intellectual cut +and thrust. At the end of the day, we still need to explain why it is like this +to be a conscious agent. An explanation of behavior or of some causal role +is simply explaining the wrong thing. This might seem to be mule-headed +stubbornness, but it is grounded in a simple principle: our theories must +explain what cries out for explanation. +This line of argument is perhaps the most interesting that a reductionist +or eliminativist can take—if I were a reductionist, I would be this sort of +reductionist—but at the end of the day it suffers from the problem that all +such positions face: it does not explain what needs to be explained. Tempting +as this position is, it ends up failing to take the problem seriously. The puzzle +of consciousness cannot be removed by such simple means.3 + +Dennett on phenomenal judgments +One advocate of the position that our judgments about consciousness are +all we need to explain is Daniel Dennett. In a 1979 paper he writes: +I am left defending the view that such judgments exhaust our immediate consciousness, that our individual stream of consciousness consists of nothing but +such prepositional episodes, or better: that such streams of consciousness, composed exclusively of such prepositional episodes, are the reality that inspires +the variety of misdescriptions that pass for theories of consciousness, both +homegrown and academic +My view, put bluntly, is that there is no phenomenological manifold in any such relation to our reports. There are the public +reports we issue, and then there are the episodes of our prepositional awareness, +our judgments, and then there is—so far as introspection is concerned—darkness. (1979, p. 95) + +To this, all I can say is that Dennett's introspection is very different from +mine. When I introspect, I find sensations, experiences of pain and emotion, +and all sorts of other accoutrements that, although accompanied by judgments, are not only judgments—unless one redefines the notion of judgment, +or of "episodes of our prepositional awareness," to include such experiences. +If we redefine the terms in this way, then Dennett's position is reasonable, + + 190 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +but there is no longer any reason to suppose that our judgments can be +reductively explained. If judgments are instead construed as functionally +individuated states such as dispositions to report, as I think Dennett intends, +then his thesis becomes implausible. It simply consists in a denial of the data +that a theory of consciousness must explain. +What might be going on when someone claims that introspection reveals +only judgments? Perhaps Dennett is a zombie.4 Perhaps he means something +unusual by "judgment." Most likely, however, he has taken something else +for introspection: what we might call extrospection, the process of observing +one's own cognitive mechanisms "from the outside," as it were, and reflecting +on what is going on. Observing one's mechanisms, it is easy to corne to the +conclusion that it is judgments that are doing all the work. All that is going +on in the relevant cognitive processes is a lot of categorization, distinction, +and reaction. The processes involved with my perception of a yellow object +can plausibly be fully explained in terms of certain retinal sensitivities, transformations into internal representations, and categorization and labeling of +these representations. But this does not explain the contents of introspection; +it explains only the processes involved. Extrospection is not introspection, +although it is easy to see how a philosopher inclined to speculate on his own +internal mechanisms could take one for the other. Conscious experience +remains untouched by this explanatory method. (Perhaps the descriptions +just given might provide an excellent account of the phenomenology of +blindsight (described in Chapter 6), if not of ordinary consciousness!) +A similar move is made by Dennett in what is perhaps the central argument +of Consciousness Explained (1991). Having presented his theory of reportability, Dennett needs to argue that it explains everything that needs to be +explained, and in particular that it explains experience insofar as experience +needs to be explained. After much preliminary skirmishing, he makes the +crucial argument (pp. 363-64) that a theory of experience needs to explain +why things seem the way they do to us. And he argues that his theory can +explain why things seem the way they do to us. Hence, he concludes, his +theory explains everything that needs to be explained. +This is an elegant argument, with a ring of plausibility that many reductionist arguments about consciousness lack. But its elegance derives from the +way it exploits a subtle ambiguity in the notion of "seeming," which balances +on the knife-edge between the phenomenal and psychological realms. There +is a phenomenal sense of "seem," in which for things to seem a certain way +is just for them to be experienced a certain way. And there is a psychological +sense of "seem," in which for things to seem a certain way is for us to be +disposed to judge that they are that way. It is in the first sense that a theory +of experience must explain the way things seem. But it is in the second sense +that Dennett's theory explains it.5 + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +191 + +Once this subtle equivocation is noted, the argument loses most of its +force. When Dennett says that his theory explains the way things seem to +us, what this ultimately comes to is that it explains why we say that things +are that way, and why we behave correspondingly in other fashions. (As +Dennett himself notes, his theory of consciousness is grounded in his quasibehaviorist theory of content.) But that sort of explanation falls far short of +what a theory of consciousness needs to explain. At the end of the day, calling a theory of this sort a theory of consciousness begs all the important +questions. +In general, when one starts from phenomenal judgments as the explananda +of one's theory of consciousness, one will inevitably be led to a reductive +view. But the ultimate explananda are not the judgments but experiences +themselves. No mere explanation of dispositions to behave will explain why +there is something it is like to be a conscious agent. + +4. Arguments Against Explanatory Irrelevance +We have seen that the paradox of phenomenal judgment leads to counterintuitive consequences. But so far this is all that we have seen. Some people will +think that the consequences are not just counterintuitive but fatal. To establish this, these objectors need an argument. Such an argument would show +us why the explanatory irrelevance of consciousness simply cannot be true. +Such arguments are surprisingly hard to come by, but they can be made. +The general idea is to argue that explanatory irrelevance is inconsistent with +some well-established fact about ourselves. I can see three ways this might +go. It might be argued that explanatory irrelevance is inconsistent with the +fact that we know about our conscious experiences; or that it is inconsistent +with the fact that we remember our conscious experiences; or that it is +inconsistent with the fact that we refer to our conscious experiences. I do +not think that any of these arguments are compelling, but they all raise +interesting issues and all need to be expressed. +Some of these arguments are most naturally framed in terms of causal +irrelevance rather than explanatory irrelevance. In order to give these arguments their full power, I will temporarily concede the causal irrelevance of +experience, in order to see whether the arguments succeed. It is possible +that similar arguments could be made wholly in terms of explanatory irrelevance, but they would be more complicated. In any case, I have at least +allowed that it might turn out that experience is causally irrelevant, and it +is interesting to see whether this would have fatal consequences. +In order to allow an opponent's objections their full force, I will also +occasionally speak of "beliefs" rather than "judgments" in what follows. As + + 192 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +I noted earlier, my main line of defense will not turn on the distinction +between beliefs and judgments, so I will not make too much of it here. That +issue might still have a supporting role to play, though. In what follows, it +should at least be kept in the back of one's mind that (1) when talking about +a zombie's beliefs and judgments, a deflationary notion is being stipulated, +and (2) my own phenomenal beliefs, in the full sense, may be partly constituted by conscious experience. + +5. The Argument from Self-Knowledge* +The most difficult problem posed by explanatory irrelevance is the one I +have already discussed: our knowledge of our own conscious experiences. +On the face of it, we do not just judge that we have conscious experiences; +we know that we have conscious experiences. But if a nonreductive view is +right, then experience is explanatorily irrelevant to the formation of the +judgment; the same judgment would have been formed even if experience +were absent. It may therefore seem hard to see how that judgment can +qualify as knowledge. +This might simply be phrased as a challenge: If experience is explanatorily +irrelevant, how can we know about experience? As such, it is an important +challenge, and one of the central questions about conscious experience. +There are already many such difficult questions, however, and we may not +be able to answer them before we develop a detailed theory of consciousness. It can also be phrased more strongly as an argument: If experience is explanatorily irrelevant, then we could not know that we have experiences. It +is arguments of this sort that I am concerned to answer here. I will also +make some suggestions in answer to the challenge, but that is a project that +will recur. +I can see two related ways that such an argument might go. First, it might +proceed directly from the possibility of my zombie twin. My zombie twin +makes the same phenomenal judgments that I do. Where I judge that I am +conscious, he judges that he is conscious. Further, his judgments are produced +by the same mechanisms as my judgments. If justification accrues to judgments solely in virtue of the mechanisms by which they are formed, as is +often supposed, then the zombie's judgments will be as justified as mine. +But surely his judgments are not justified at all. After all, they are utterly +and systematically false. It seems to follow that my judgments cannot be +justified, either. They are produced by the same mechanisms that are responsible for deluded judgments in a zombie, and so they surely cannot qualify +as knowledge. +//my phenomenal judgments are no more justified than a zombie's, then +the ground is cut out from under the nonreductive position. The very starting + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +193 + +point of the nonreductive position, our knowledge of the fact of experience, +would be destroyed. It follows that this point functions as both a challenge +and an argument. As a challenge: How can my judgments be any more +justified than a zombie's, given that they are formed by the same mechanisms? +As an argument: If my judgments are formed by the same mechanisms as +a zombie's, they cannot be any more justified. +The second argument appeals to a causal theory of knowledge. It is often +held that the crucial factor in justifying a belief about an entity is an appropriate causal connection between the belief and the entity it is about. My +beliefs about the table I am looking at, for example, are justified at least in +part by the fact that the table is causally responsible for the beliefs. Proponents of a causal theory hold that a judgment about some object or state of +affairs must bear a causal relation to that object or state of affairs if it is to +count as knowledge (perhaps with exceptions in a priori domains such as +conceptual or mathematical knowledge). Certainly, it seems that if my belief +that John is in the pool bears no causal relation to John or the pool, then I +do not know that John is in the pool. +But experience is causally irrelevant, or so I am conceding for now. A +conscious experience plays no causal role in the formation of a judgment +about that experience. If a causal theory of knowledge is correct, it follows +that we cannot know anything about our experiences. Again, there is a +challenge and an argument. The challenge: How can I know about experience, given that experience does not cause my judgments? The argument: +If experience plays no causal role in the formation of my judgments, then +they cannot count as knowledge. +Shoemaker (1975a) uses arguments like these to argue for materialism +about consciousness, and in fact to argue for reductive functionalism. Shoemaker explicitly assumes a causal theory of knowledge, arguing that if we +are to know about experience, then it must cause our introspective beliefs +about experience. He also uses a version of the zombie argument to support +reductive functionalism. If zombies or their functional equivalents are logically possible, then experience is inaccessible to introspection: zombies have +the same introspective mechanisms that we do, so those mechanisms do not +allow us to determine whether or not we are zombies. Shoemaker concludes +that zombies and their functional equivalents must be logically impossible. +The response to all of these arguments is fairly clear, I think. A property +dualist should argue that a causal theory of knowledge is not appropriate +for our knowledge of consciousness, and that the justification of our judgments about consciousness does not lie with the mechanisms by which those +judgments are formed. Knowledge of conscious experience is in many important respects quite different from knowledge in other domains. Our +knowledge of conscious experience does not consist in a causal relationship +to experience, but in another sort of relationship entirely. + + 194 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +This conclusion can be supported on independent grounds. One way to +come to this independent support is to first consider another way that a +property dualist might try to respond: through a reliabilist theory of knowledge. This might seem a promising response at first, but I think that one can +see that a reliabilist theory is inappropriate for dealing with our knowledge of +consciousness. It turns out that a causal theory is inappropriate for the +same reason. +On a reliabilist theory, beliefs about a subject matter are justified if they +are formed by a reliable process; that is, if they are formed by a process that +tends to produce true beliefs. Perceptual beliefs, for example, are justified +if they come about via optical stimulation from objects in the environment, +a process that generally produces true beliefs; they are not justified if they +are produced by hallucination, which is a very unreliable mechanism. It is +entirely compatible with a nonreductive theory of experience that in the +actual world, our phenomenal judgments are reliable: at least as a matter +of nomic correlation, it seems likely that when one judges that one is having +a visual experience, one is having a visual experience. The phenomenal +judgments of my zombie twin, by contrast, are entirely unreliable; his judgments are generally false. +It might therefore seem that a reliabilist theory is the answer to our +difficulties: it implies that our judgments about experience might be justified +even in the absence of a direct causal connection, and it has the resources +to explain the fact that my judgments are justified while my zombie twin's +are not. But many will find that the appeal to a reliabilist theory is unsatisfying +all the same; it has the feeling of a slippery maneuver that cannot meet the +burden it is being asked to carry. The knowledge that a reliabilist theory +grants us seems too weak to count as the kind of knowledge that we have +of our conscious experience. On reflection, it is not hard to see why. +The trouble is that if our beliefs about consciousness were justified only +by a reliable connection, then we could not be certain that we are conscious. +The mere existence of a reliable connection cannot deliver certainty, for we +have no way to rule out the possibility that the reliable connection is absent +and that there is no consciousness at the other end. The only way to be sure +here would be to have some further access to the other end of the connection; +but that would be to say that we have some further basis to our knowledge +of consciousness. This situation is often deemed acceptable for our knowledge of the external world: we do not need to be certain that chairs exist in +order to know (in an everyday sense) that chairs exist, so it is not a problem +that we are not certain that there is a reliable connection between chairs +and our judgments about chairs. But we are certain that we are conscious; +at least, this certainty is at the foundation of the position I have advocated. +Perhaps the knowledge that we are conscious can be doubted in various +"philosophical" ways, but not in the very direct way—analogous to doubting + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +195 + +our knowledge of the external world—that would be granted if our beliefs +were justified only by a reliable connection. +Beliefs justified only by a reliable connection are always compatible with +the existence of skeptical hypotheses. These concern scenarios where things +seem exactly the same to a subject but in which the beliefs are false, because +the reliable connection does not hold. In the case of perceptual knowledge, +for example, one can construct a case in which the reliable connection is +absent—a case where the subject is a brain in the vat, say—and everything +will still seem the same to the subject. Nothing about a subject's core epistemic situation rules this scenario out. But in the case of consciousness, one +cannot construct these skeptical hypotheses. Our core epistemic situation +already includes our conscious experience. There is no situation in which +everything seems just the same to us but in which we are not conscious, as our +conscious experience is (at least partly) constitutive of the way things seem. +It is notable that in constructing skeptical scenarios relevant to other sorts +of knowledge, such as our knowledge of the external world, philosophers +are always careful to stipulate that a skeptical scenario is experientially identical to the original scenario. As Descartes noted, skepticism goes only so far. +If a skeptical scenario involves a vastly different set of experiences at its +center—a host of bright flashing yellow and green experiences with a deafening noise, say—then it is ruled out automatically. We know (in a much +stronger sense than before) that such a situation is not our situation. +It follows that a reliabilist account of knowledge cannot deliver knowledge +that is strong enough to have the character of our knowledge of conscious +experience, and is therefore inappropriate in this case. But everything I have +said about a reliabilist account of knowledge also applies to a causal account +of knowledge. Where there is causation, there is contingency: a causal connection that holds might not have held. If the sole source of justification for +a belief about X is a causal connection to X, then a subject cannot know +for certain that the causal connection exists. The only way they might know +this for certain would be if they had some independent access to X or to the +causal chain, but this would imply knowledge grounded in something more +than the causal chain itself. There will always be a skeptical scenario in +which everything seems just the same to the subject, but in which the causal +connection is absent and in which X does not exist; so the subject cannot +know for certain about X. But we do know for certain that we are conscious; +so a causal account of this knowledge is inappropriate. +Of course, an opponent might simply deny that our knowledge of consciousness is certain, and assert that there are skeptical scenarios that we +cannot rule out—a zombie scenario, for example. But anyone who takes +this view will likely be an eliminativist (or a reductive functionalist) about +consciousness from the start. If one accepts that our immediate evidence +does not rule out the possibility that we are zombies, then one should embrace + + 196 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +the conclusion that we are zombies: it leads to a much simpler view of the +world, for a start. But the reason there is a problem about consciousness is +that our immediate evidence does rule out that possibility. To take consciousness seriously is to accept that we have immediate evidence that rules out +its nonexistence. Of course, all this is open to argument in the usual way; +but the point is that there is no special reason to start disputing this at +this point in the argument. Eliminativists and reductive functionalists have +departed long ago. // one takes consciousness seriously, then one has good +reason to believe that a causal or reliabilist account of our phenomenal +knowledge is inappropriate. + +What justifies phenomenal judgments? +The basic problem with the accounts above is that they make our access to +consciousness mediated, in the way that our access to objects in the environment is mediated, by some sort of causal chain or reliable mechanism. This +sort of mediation is appropriate when there is a gap between our core +epistemic situation and the phenomena in question, as in the case of the +external world: we are connected to objects in the environment from a +distance. But intuitively, our access to consciousness is not mediated at all. +Conscious experience lies at the center of our epistemic universe; we have +access to it directly. +This raises a question. What is it that justifies our beliefs about our experiences, if it is not a causal link to those experiences, and if it is not the +mechanisms by which the beliefs are formed? I think the answer to this is +clear: it is having the experiences that justifies the beliefs. For example, the +very fact that I have a red experience now provides justification for my belief +that I am having a red experience. Change the red experience to a different +sort of experience, or remove it altogether, and the chief source of justification for my belief is removed. When I believe that I am experiencing a loud +noise, my warrant for that belief stems chiefly from my experience of a loud +noise. Indeed, one might ask, from where else could it stem? +We can put the point by noting, as before, that experience is part of our +core epistemic situation. Replace my bright red experiences by dull green +experiences, and you change my evidence for some of my beliefs, including +my belief that I am having a bright red experience. This is mirrored in the +fact that there is no way to construct a skeptical scenario in which I am in +a qualitatively equivalent epistemic position, but in which my experiences +are radically different. My experiences are pan of my epistemic situation, +and simply having them gives me evidence for some of my beliefs. +All this is to say that there is something intrinsically epistemic about +experience. To have an experience is automatically to stand in some sort + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +197 + +of intimate epistemic relation to the experience—a relation that we might +call "acquaintance." There is not even a conceptual possibility that a subject could have a red experience like this one without having any epistemic contact with it: to have the experience is to be related to it in this +way. +Note that I do not say that to have an experience is automatically to know +about it, in the sense in which knowledge requires belief. I think that thesis +would be false: we have many experiences that we do not have beliefs about, +and so do not know about. Further, one might have an experience without +conceptualizing the experience in any way. To have an experience, and +consequently to be acquainted with the experience, is to stand in a relationship to it more primitive than belief: it provides evidence for our beliefs, but +it does not in itself constitute belief. +Indeed, nothing I have said implies that all beliefs about experiences are +incorrigible, in that every such belief is automatically fully justified. Because +beliefs about experiences lie at a distance from experiences, they can be +formed for all sorts of reasons, and sometimes unjustified beliefs will be +formed. If one is distracted, for example, one may make judgments about +one's experiences that are quite false. The claim is not that having an experience is the only factor that may be relevant to the justification or lack of +justification of a belief about experience. The claim is simply that it is a +factor—perhaps the primary factor—and provides a potential source of justification that is not present when the experience is absent. +Some might find all this an ad hoc construction to save a troubled theory, +but I do not think it is ad hoc. We have very good reason, quite independent +of any considerations about explanatory irrelevance, to believe that the +epistemology of experience is special, and very different in kind from epistemology in other domains. Many have spoken of our "direct knowledge" of +or "acquaintance" with experience, without being forced into the position +as a defensive maneuver. Many have even claimed that knowledge of experience is the foundation of all knowledge, precisely because we stand in such +a direct epistemic relationship to it. The claim that all knowledge derives +from knowledge of experience may have been overblown, but the general +point that there is something special about our knowledge of experience has +never been overturned.6 +Similarly, the claim that experiences themselves justify our beliefs about +experience is easy to motivate on independent grounds. For example, in his +careful discussion of our knowledge of our own minds, Siewert (1994)—who +takes consciousness seriously, but who shows no signs of sympathy with the +view that consciousness is explanatorily irrelevant—gives an in-depth defense +of the view that we have a "first-person warrant" for our beliefs about our +experiences, a warrant that is grounded at least partly in our having the + + 198 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +experiences. So it is not going out on a limb to see experience as providing +a direct source of justification. + +Answering the arguments +Given all this, the answer to the arguments against explanatory irrelevance +is straightforward. In response to the argument from the causal theory of +knowledge, we note that there is independent reason to believe that the +causal theory is inappropriate to explicate our knowledge of experience: our +knowledge of experience is grounded in a more immediate relation. And in +response to the argument from my zombie twin, we note that the justification +of my beliefs about experience involves more than the mechanisms by which +the beliefs are formed: it crucially involves experiences themselves. Because +my zombie twin lacks experiences, he is in a very different epistemic situation +from me, and his judgments lack the corresponding justification. +It may be tempting to object that if my belief lies in the physical realm, +its justification must lie in the physical realm; but this is a nonsequitur. From +the fact that there is no justification in the physical realm, one might conclude +that the physical portion of me (my brain, say) is not justified in its belief. +But the question is whether / am justified in the belief, not whether my brain +is justified in the belief, and if property dualism is correct then there is more +to me than my brain. I am constituted by both physical and nonphysical +properties, and the full story about me cannot be told by focusing on only +one half. In particular, the justification of my belief accrues not just in +virtue of my physical features but in virtue of some of my nonphysical +features—namely the experiences themselves. +It might still be objected, "But the belief would still have been formed +even if the experience had been absent!" To this, the answer is, "So what?" +In this case, I have evidence for my belief, namely my immediate acquaintance with experience. In a different case, that evidence is absent. To note +that in a different case the belief might have been formed in the absence of +the evidence is not to say that the evidence does not justify the belief in this +case.7 I know I am conscious, and the knowledge is based solely on my +immediate experience. To say that the experience makes no difference to +my psychological functioning is not to say that the experience makes no +difference to me. +Finally, there is a persistent refrain that comes up in these situations: "But +your zombie twin would say the same thing!" If I say I know I am conscious, +it is noted that my zombie twin says the same. If I say my belief is justified +by my immediate acquaintance with experience, it is noted that my zombie +twin says the same. To this, the answer is again, "So what?" At most this +shows that from the third-person point of view, my zombie twin and I are + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +199 + +identical, so that you cannot be certain that I am conscious; but we knew +this all along. But it does nothing to imply that from the first-person view, +I cannot know I am conscious. From the first-person point of view, my +zombie twin and I are very different: I have experiences, and he does not. +Because of this, I have evidence for my belief where he does not. Despite +the fact that he says the same things I do, I know that I am not him (though +you might not be sure) because of my direct first-person acquaintance with +my experiences. This may sound somewhat paradoxical at first, but really it +is simply saying the obvious: our experience of consciousness enables us to +know that we are conscious. +Even when it is objected that my zombie twin would believe the same +things that I would, this does nothing to make plausible the first-person +skeptical hypothesis that I might be a zombie. Underlying this sort of objection may be the implicit assumption that the beliefs themselves are the +primary determinants of my epistemic situation; so if there is a situation in +which I believe exactly the same things that I do now, it is a situation that +is evidentially equivalent to my current one. But of course this is false. The +evidence for my beliefs about experiences is much more primitive than the +beliefs themselves. It is experience itself that is primary; the beliefs are +largely a secondary phenomenon. +It should also be remembered that we are stipulating a deflationary (i.e., +functional) notion of belief, so to say that my zombie twin believes the same +things as me is still only to make a claim about our commonalities from the +third-person point of view: he is disposed to make the same sorts of claims, +the same sort of inferences, and so on. This says nothing about how things +are from the inside. The feeling that "a zombie would have the same beliefs" +provides an objection here may stem from assuming an inflationary notion +of belief, in which belief is at least in part an experiential phenomenon. Only +in that sense might it be the case that identity in beliefs would make the +situations indistinguishable from the first-person point of view; but of course +in that sense there is no reason to accept that a zombie has the same beliefs +in the first place. +The upshot of all this is that arguments about self-knowledge provide no +reason to reject the view I advocate. If one takes consciousness seriously, +one will already have good reason to embrace an epistemology of consciousness that renders these arguments toothless. Although there are many tempting arguments that can be made, none of them appear to stand up to scrutiny. +Very much remains to be done in clarifying the first-person epistemology +of consciousness, of course. At best I have sketched the bare outline of a +framework for thinking about these things; many issues remain to be dealt +with. In particular, one would like an analysis of just how an experience +justifies a belief; of what other factors are relevant in justifying beliefs about + + 200 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +experiences; of under just what circumstances a belief about experience is +fully justified; and so on. All of these are important questions that deserve +to be taken up at length in a study of the epistemology of consciousness. +But all of these are part of the challenge, and on the face of it there is no +reason to believe that the challenge cannot be met. What is important is +that the arguments that self-knowledge might appear to provide against a +nonreductive view of experience do not succeed. + +6. The Argument from Memory* +The second objection to the causal or explanatory irrelevance of experience +is that it is incompatible with the fact that we remember our experiences. It +certainly seems that I often remember my old experiences, as when I recall +the tangy odor of mothballs in a closet when I was a child, or when I recollect +a particularly vivid experience of orange while I was watching the sun set +last night. But to remember something, it is often held, is to stand in an +appropriate causal relation to it; this is sometimes known as the causal +theory of memory. If experiences are causally irrelevant to my psychological +functioning, however, it seems that my old experiences are not causally +related to any of my current states. If so, then we could not remember our +experiences at all. +The causal theory of memory is not written in stone, however. It comes +from an analysis of what seems the appropriate thing to say about various +cases. As with the case of knowledge, it may be that a causal theory is +appropriate in many domains without being appropriate across the board. In +particular, it is not obvious that it is appropriate in the domain of experience. +Causal theories might not be as inappropriate in the case of memory as they +are in the case of knowledge, as there is no doubt that our relation to a +remembered experience is mediated, and it is plausible that much of that +mediation involves a causal chain. But this is not to say that the causal chain +tells the whole story. +In the case of remembered experiences, there will certainly be a causal +connection at the level of psychology: the underlying cognitive state at the +time of the original experience will be causally connected to the cognitive +state at the time of the memory. And it seems plausible that an appropriate +causal connection of this sort is all that is required for memory of experience. +For example, there may be a causal connection between a phenomenal belief +at the earlier time and beliefs at the later time; and if what I have said in +the previous section is correct, this original belief may count as knowledge, +being justified by an acquaintance with the experience itself. This sort of +causal connection between a belief justified by acquaintance and a later + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +201 + +belief seems quite sufficient for the later belief to count as an instance of +memory. So there seems to be good reason to believe that a causal connection +to an experience is not required to remember that experience. +Of course the question of just what counts as a "memory" and what counts +as merely a justified true belief about the past is largely a semantic decision +in these cases. What is important is that a nonreductive theory can save the +appearances by giving a mechanism by which true beliefs about one's past +experiences are formed. As long as a nonreductive theory can do this, then +any argument that memory provides against such a theory is defanged. If +someone insists that a causal connection to an object is required for memory, +then we can simply say that we "pseudo-remember" experiences instead, or +some such, and nothing important will be lost. But in any case it seems to +me that a causal connection to a relevant original psychological state is quite +enough for these beliefs to qualify as memories. + +7. The Argument from Reference* +The third argument against the causal or explanatory irrelevance of consciousness is that it is incompatible with our ability to refer to our conscious +experiences. Certainly, it seems that we can think about our conscious experiences, and talk about them—I have been doing that throughout this book. But +it is sometimes held that reference to an entity requires a causal connection to +that entity; this is known as the causal theory of reference. If so, then it +would be impossible to refer to causally irrelevant experiences. +There seems to be no principled reason why reference to an entity requires +a causal connection to that entity, however. Reference frequently involves +a causal connection, but it is not clear that things have to be that way. In +referring to an entity, all that is required is that our concepts have intensions +(in particular, primary intensions) that the entity might satisfy. For example, +my concept "the largest star in the universe" has a primary intension, picking +out a referent in any given centered world. In the actual world, this intension +picks out a certain star 5—whether or not I am causally connected to S—so +S qualifies as the referent of the concept. Given that there is a primary +intension that an entity in the actual world might satisfy, we have the basic +ingredients needed for reference. +It happens that for many of our concepts, primary intensions are characterized causally: at a given centered world, they pick out an appropriate entity +that is causally connected to the center. This is the insight of the so-called +causal theory of reference. But there is no reason why a primary intension +has to work this way. There are many other functions that pick out, in a +hypothetical centered world, an entity that has no causal connection to the + + 202 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +center. Such functions might make perfectly good primary intensions, with +a perfectly good referent. +Further, the existence of a primary intension—even in cases where a primary intension is characterized causally—does not depend in any way on a +causal connection to the referent. The primary intension is independent of +those actual-world goings on. A causal connection may often play a role in +evaluating the primary intension at a world, but this is very different from +playing a role in determining the primary intension itself. Indeed, some of +our concepts (e.g., "Santa Claus") have no referent at all, but they still have +a primary intension—an intension that could have picked out a referent if +the world had turned out the right way. +It will often be the case that causal connection to a referent plays a role +in acquiring a concept, and thus in forming a primary intension. One might +argue that even in the case of "the largest star in the universe," causal +connections to the world play a role in acquiring the basic concepts from +which this compositional concept is formed. But again, there seems to be +no principled reason why the existence of a primary intension requires a +causal connection to relevant subject matter. Even a brain in a vat might +have concepts with primary intensions, despite its causal isolation (though +most of them would be intensions that nothing in its world satisfies). Again, +the constitution of a primary intension is independent of such causal connections. +There is a natural reason why causation is central to so many of our +concepts: it is because we generally refer to what we know about, and the +things we know about are generally things we are causally connected to. But +we have already seen that there is good reason to reject the causal model +of knowledge at least in the case of consciousness: in that case we have +knowledge of a more immediate variety. So to refer to consciousness, we +do not need to refer via an intension that picks out something that the center +is causally connected to; instead, we can refer via an intension that picks +out something that the center is immediately acquainted with. +In any case, what is important is that (1) my concept of "consciousness" +can have a primary intension, whether or not there is a causal connection +to the referent (for the existence of a primary intension never depends on +such a causal connection); and (2) the primary intension can pick out +a referent whether or not there is a causal connection to the referent +(for there is no reason why a primary intension must pick out its referent in +virtue of a causal connection). The intension specifies a perfectly good function from centered worlds to features of those worlds; in this world, there +is something that satisfies the intension, so my concept has a referent. As +we have seen, consciousness is something of a primitive concept (like space +and time, perhaps), so there is no hope of characterizing the intension in + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +203 + +detail in the way one might for some concepts; but there is no reason to believe that it should not be perfectly capable of picking out a referent in a world. + +8. The Content of Phenomenal Beliefs* +Even if it is accepted that property dualism is compatible with referring to +consciousness, there remain many interesting puzzles about the content of +our phenomenal concepts and beliefs. First, there are questions about the +nature of our concepts' intensions, both for general concepts such as "consciousness" and for more specific concepts such as "red experience": Just +what do they pick out in a given world? And second, there are questions +about what constitutes the content of our concepts: Is the content constituted +by our psychological nature alone, or by our psychological and phenomenal +nature, and what role do each of these play? I do not have settled opinions +on these matters, but I will at least scratch the surface here. +An interesting way to get at some of these questions is to ask whether +there is a difference between the content of my phenomenal beliefs and +those of a zombie; and if so, what is it? I return to speaking of "beliefs" +here rather than "judgments," as the question is precisely whether there is +an element to the content of a phenomenal belief over and above the content +of a phenomenal judgment, which was stipulated to be a purely psychological +entity. I will allow, at least for the purposes of discussion, that a zombie +has beliefs (although his beliefs are certainly nothing over and above his +judgments). The question is whether there is any difference between the +content of his beliefs and mine. In particular, what is the difference, if any, +between the truth conditions of our respective beliefs, and between the +intensions of our respective concepts? +One line that could be taken is that the content of our beliefs and concepts +is exactly the same. On this view, the zombie has concepts of "consciousness" +and of "red experience" with the same primary intensions as my corresponding concepts, and beliefs with the same (primary) truth conditions. His concept "conscious being," for example, still picks out the conscious beings in +a given centered world. It is just that in his world, there are no such beings; +or at least, he is not such a being. So his belief "I am conscious" has the +same (primary) truth conditions as my belief; the only difference is that his +belief is false where mine is true. +To evaluate this line, one needs to consider some specific questions. First, +when a zombie says, "I am conscious," does he speak falsely? Some might +say no: we should interpret the zombie's remark charitably, so that his +concept refers to some functional property that he instantiates, and the +remark comes out true.8 But the zombie (at least if he is my zombie twin) + + 204 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +will certainly insist that his is not a functional concept: he means to refer to +a property of his over and above his ability to discriminate, categorize, report, +and so on. It seems reasonable to take his word on this. Of course we can +also allow a "deflationary" interpretation of his words, so that claims such +as "I have regained consciousness" might come out true in everyday contexts; +but at least in philosophical contexts, it seems reasonable to hold his concepts to the higher standard that he intends, so that his beliefs come out +false. It is not as if he is suffering under a conceptual confusion that could +be cleared up by more careful conceptual analysis. (If he could do that, I +could do it too; but this discussion is premised on the idea that I am not +suffering from such a conceptual confusion.) So there seems to be a reasonable sense in which his claims of consciousness are false.9 +This is not enough to show that the zombie's concept has the same intension +as mine, however. Perhaps this only shows that he has a concept something +like "property over and above any physical and functional property," without +possessing the full-blown concept of consciousness. The real test is whether +there are any centered worlds in which everything relevant is identical, but +in which a zombie's belief has a different truth-value from mine. For example, +what if we are both talking to a conscious being? I say, "You are conscious," +and speak truly. If he says, "You are conscious," does he speak truly? Some +might say no, because he lacks the immediate acquaintance with consciousness to give him the full concept. But there is also an intuition that "yes" +may be reasonable. +Perhaps the most relevant examples involve a hypothetical being with +some nonstructural, nonfunctional intrinsic property that is not a phenomenal +property—if there could be such a property—where the property stands in +the usual sort of relations that phenomenal properties stand in. When I say, +"You are conscious," to such a being, I speak falsely; but perhaps when my +zombie twin says this, then if he spoke truly in the previous case, he also +speaks truly here? In the absence of any acquaintance with consciousness, +it is hard to see how the zombie's concept could be specific enough to +distinguish the two cases. If so, then the zombie's concept of consciousness +falls short of the full-blown concept. +If our acquaintance with consciousness plays a role in constituting the +primary intension of our concept, this would mean that the concept of "consciousness" is interestingly different from other concepts, such as "water." +In these cases the primary intension is independent of the actual referent; +a cognitive system with a different referent, or with no referent at all, might +have the same primary intension. But consciousness is not an ordinary referent: our relation to it is unmediated, and it is at the center of our mental +lives, so it might play an unusually strong role in constituting a primary +intension. In any case, I leave the question open. + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +205 + +What about specific phenomenal concepts, such as the concept of "red +experience"? These are somewhat more complicated, as there may be more +than one concept in the vicinity of such a term. One way to get at these +concepts is to consider how to describe individuals with inverted spectra: +for example, someone who, when looking at red things, has the sort of +experience I have when looking at green things. When I say that such a +person (on looking at a red rose) is having a red experience, there may be +a loose sense in which the remark can be taken to be true: in this sense, +"red experience" comes to something like "experience of the sort typically +caused (in the individual having the experience) by red things." Perhaps +there is a public-language concept of "red experience" that works something +like this, but in any case I set this one aside. +More natural, perhaps, is a sense in which such a remark is false: the +person is not having a red experience but a green experience. In one way +of explicating such a sense, the primary intension of my concept "red experience" might come to something like "experience of the sort typically caused +(in me) by red things." This sense has some interesting properties: for example, if you and I have spectra inverted relative to each other, then your +concept "green experience" will pick out (what I call) red experiences. +It follows that your remark "Grass gives me green experiences" might be +true, even though my remark "Grass gives you green experiences" is false. +This is occasionally found distasteful,10 but it is a natural consequence +of the indexicality of the concept (a similar phenomenon arises with +"I"-remarks, and with the "water"-remarks of me and my Twin Earth twin). +If one wants to avoid this sort of thing, the more "public" concept characterized above is always available.11 +The primary intension of this concept "red experience" should be quite +straightforward, if the general concept of experience is already granted. Your +concept "red experience" may have the same primary intension as mine, +even if our spectra are inverted: both pick out the same entities at a given +centered world (experiences of the sort typically caused at the center by red +things), although of course our concepts will have different referents, as we +inhabit different centered worlds (mine is centered on me, and yours on +you). Because of this, our concepts may also have different secondary intensions: mine picks out red experiences in a counterfactual world, whereas +yours picks out green experiences. Even a zombie might have the same +primary intension as the two of us, at least insofar as it has the concept of +experience at all, although of course its intension will not pick out anything +at its centered world, and its concept "red experience" will fail to refer. +There is more to the story than this, however. This relational construal +of the concept "red experience" is still relatively peripheral. One has a +concept in the vicinity—perhaps the most important concept in these discus- + + 206 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +sions—that is not exhausted by the relational characterization. In particular, +one has a concept of the quality of red experiences. Nothing in the relational +characterization above captures the concept of this quality, as witnessed +by the fact that the primary intension characterized above is compatible +with many different qualities. Someone with an inverted spectrum would +share that intension, but I have a concept of this quality—call it "R?"—that +is distinct from the corresponding concept—call it "G"—in my inverted +counterpart. +At first glance, one might think it enough that this quality is captured by +the secondary intension of my concept "red experience" as characterized +above. As we have seen, my inverted counterpart and I have different secondary intensions corresponding to the different qualities picked out by our +"red experience" concepts. But capturing it in a secondary intension is not +enough. To see this, note that it is informative to learn that red experiences +(that is, experiences caused by red objects) have their specific quality. That +is, it is far from a priori that red experiences should be R. In learning this, +one narrows down one's model of the way the actual world is: the sort of +experience that is caused by red things might have been this way or this way, +but instead it is this way. And this sort of informativeness requires a difference +in primary intension: when two concepts have the same primary intension, +it is a priori that they are coextensive.12 +Another way to see this is to note that when Mary has a red experience +for the first time, she learns something different from what is learned by +her inverted twin, who has green experiences where Mary has red. Mary +learns that red things cause experiences like this, whereas her counterpart +learns that they cause experiences like that. Their models of the world are +narrowed down in different ways: Mary now endorses one set of centered +worlds, where her twin endorses another. It follows that their concepts of +the qualities in question must have different primary intensions. Mary's +primary intension picks out experiences of one sort (this sort) in any given +centered world, whereas her counterpart's picks out experiences of a different sort. +My qualitative concept "R?" plays little direct role in communicative practices. In that way, it resembles Wittgenstein's "beetle in a box."13 My inverted +counterpart has a different concept "G" in the vicinity, but others understand +him to be saying the same things that they understand me to be saying, +assuming that their own situations remain constant across the two scenarios. +This reflects the "ineffability" that I noted in Chapter 1: despite the rich +intrinsic nature of red sensations, there is little I can say to communicate +this difference apart from pinning it down via various relational properties, +and assuming that others have the same associated experiences. That is, it +appears to be the relational concept of "red experience" that carries the + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +207 + +communicative burden. This ineffability can be seen as providing indirect +support for the explanatory irrelevance of experience: the fact that there is +little one can say that captures the intrinsic quality of the experience meshes +well with the fact that the quality plays no direct role in governing cognitive processes.14 +(Of course, one can still talk about these qualities, as I have done on +occasion throughout this book. I can express my phenomenal beliefs in +language; it is just that my language will communicate the full content of +my beliefs to others only if they have the relevant qualities for themselves, +standing in the same sort of relevant relations.) +This clearly provides a case where the content of our concepts and beliefs +is constituted by something over and above our physical and functional +structure, so that no reductive account of the belief contents will succeed.15 +My inverted twin and I might be physically identical, but our corresponding +qualitative concepts are distinct, not just in reference but in primary intension. +Here, even more clearly than in the case of "consciousness," is a case where +the content of a phenomenal belief is constituted by phenomenology itself. +Something undeniably interesting is going on here: somehow a sort of experience, which one might think of as the referent of a qualitative concept, is +getting inside the concept and constituting its sense (where sense is equated +with primary intension). This is quite unlike standard cases where the object +of a concept might play a role in constituting a secondary intension but not +a primary intension.16 It is made possible only by the fact that experience is +at the heart of the mind. +We see then that there is in fact something more to a phenomenal belief +than to a phenomenal judgment, at least in these cases. It is possible that +this might help in understanding the epistemology of consciousness. For +example, the most specific case of this sort of constitution relation will arise +when only a single 5 experience is involved in constituting a phenomenal +concept S ("this sort of experience"17). The direct constitution relation—the +way the experience gets inside the concept, so to speak—might help us in +understanding how the experience itself could justify a belief to the effect +that the experience is S. Certainly, this gives a tight relation between the +experience and the belief of a sort that might be thought appropriate. And +given this sort of specific justified phenomenal belief, one can see how more +general justified phenomenal beliefs (such as the belief that one is conscious) +might follow. I leave this issue here, as we are entering deep water, but this +relation between experiences and phenomenal concepts provides much food +for thought. +(Perhaps one might put forward a thesis to the effect that a belief that an +experience is S, where the concept S is constituted by the experience itself +in the above fashion, is always justified. There would still be unjustified + + 208 + +The Irreducibility of Consciousness + +phenomenal beliefs, but these would arise in cases where there is a different +relation between the concept and the experience, such as when a concept +constituted by one experience—or one set of experiences, or an extrinsic +description—is applied to another experience. Perhaps this relatively weak +thesis might capture an element of what is plausible in standard "incorrigibility" theses, while at the same time leaving room for all the usual counterexamples; it might even serve as the central plank in a detailed account of +the epistemology of experience. But I am unsure about this.) +The fact that there is an element in my belief that is not present in +my zombie twin's corresponding belief may also help deflate any intuitions +supporting the epistemological arguments mentioned previously. It is only +our judgments (functionally construed) that are the same: it is not true that +the same beliefs would have been present even if the experience had been +absent.18 And it is beliefs, after all, that are most central here. We have +seen that this sort of distinctness in beliefs is not required to defeat the +epistemological arguments (I did not assume it in the earlier discussion), but +it may nevertheless help remove any lingering doubts in the vicinity. +It is natural to wonder how far this sort of constitution of content by +experience might extend. The fact that this holds for specific phenomenal +concepts lends further support to the idea that it does so for the more +general concept of "consciousness," although the question of the relationship +between my concept and that of a zombie remains unclear. One might then +wonder whether experience could play a role in constituting the content +of nonphenomenal concepts, such as concepts of external kinds, as some +philosophers have suggested. It is not obvious how the extension would be +made, but perhaps the fact that experience plays this role in one case lends +some support to the idea that it might in others. +In any case, nothing here requires a causal theory of reference. Indeed, +a causal connection to experience would probably be inappropriate in +allowing the sort of direct relationship that we find between experiences and +the primary intensions of phenomenal concepts: in all the usual cases in +which there is a causal connection ("water," for example), there is no such +relationship. Instead, it appears to be our immediate acquaintance with +experience that makes this sort of constitution possible. So a causal connection to experience is not required to constitute possession of the relevant +primary intensions; and certainly no causal connections are required for +the primary intensions to pick out a referent in these cases; so there is +no principled difficulty with referring to experience, even on a property +dualist view. +It appears, then, that while the explanatory irrelevance of experience to +physical behavior may be counterintuitive at first, there are no strong arguments against it. What might appear to be strong arguments, from epistemol- + + The Paradox of Phenomenal Judgment + +209 + +ogy and reference, turn out merely to be challenges. Consideration of these +points raises a large number of interesting issues, but at the end of the day +we have seen that there is good reason to believe that the epistemology and +semantics of experience cannot be essentially causal, and should instead be +understood in other terms. I have said a little here about how one might +go about understanding those things on a property dualist view. A full +understanding of these issues would require a lengthy separate investigation; +but I hope I have said enough to make clear that the nonreductive view +provides a natural framework for making sense of these issues. + + This page intentionally left blank + + PART III + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + + This page intentionally left blank + + 6 +The Coherence Between Consciousness +and Cognition + +1. Toward a Nonreductive Theory +Even if consciousness cannot be reductively explained, there can still be a +theory of consciousness. We simply need to move to a nonreductive theory +instead. We can give up on the project of trying to explain the existence of +consciousness wholly in terms of something more basic, and instead admit +it as fundamental, giving an account of how it relates to everything else in +the world. +Such a theory will be similar in kind to the theories that physics gives us +of matter, of motion, or of space and time. Physical theories do not derive +the existence of these features from anything more basic, but they still give +substantial, detailed accounts of these features and of how they interrelate, +with the result that we have satisfying explanations of many specific phenomena involving mass, space, and time. They do this by giving a simple, powerful set of laws involving the various features, from which all sorts of specific +phenomena follow as a consequence. +By analogy, the cornerstone of a theory of consciousness will be a set of +psychophysical laws governing the relationship between consciousness and +physical systems. We have already granted that consciousness supervenes +naturally (although not logically) on the physical. This supervenience must +be underwritten by psychophysical laws; an account of these laws will tell +us just how consciousness depends on physical processes. Given the physical +facts about a system, such laws will enable us to infer what sort of conscious +experience will be associated with the system, if any. These laws will be on +a par with the laws of physics as part of the basic furniture of the universe. + + 214 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +It follows that while this theory will not explain the existence of consciousness in the sense of telling us "why consciousness exists," it will be able to +explain specific instances of consciousness, in terms of the underlying physical structure and the psychophysical laws. Again, this is analogous to explanation in physics, which accounts for why specific instances of matter or motion +have the character they do by invoking general underlying principles in +combination with certain local properties. All sorts of macroscopic physical +phenomena can be explained in terms of underlying physical laws; similarly, +we might expect that all sorts of "macroscopic" experiential phenomena +might be explained by the psychophysical laws in a theory of consciousness. +There need be nothing especially supernatural about these laws. They are +part of the basic furniture of nature, just as the laws of physics are. There +will be something "brute" about them, it is true. At some level, the laws +will have to be taken as true and not further explained. But the same holds +in physics: the ultimate laws of nature will always at some point seem arbitrary. It is this that makes them laws of nature rather than laws of logic. +In science, we never get something for nothing: something, somewhere +must always be taken for granted. It is a remarkable fact that in most areas +of science, all we ultimately need to take for granted are the laws of physics +and perhaps some boundary conditions. But there is no reason why the +laws of physics should be absolutely privileged in this way. If it turns out +that in the study of consciousness one needs to take some aspect of the +relationship between physical processes and consciousness for granted, then +so be it. That is the price of constructing a theory. +Still, we certainly want to take as little for granted as we possibly can. An +ultimate theory will not leave the connection at the level of "Brain state X +produces conscious state Y" for a vast collection of complex physical states +and associated experiences. Instead, it will systematize this connection via +an underlying explanatory framework, specifying simple underlying laws in +virtue of which the connection holds. Physics does not content itself with +being a mere mass of observations about the positions, velocities, and charges +of various objects at various times; it systematizes these observations and +shows how they are consequences of underlying laws, where the underlying +laws are as simple and as powerful as possible. The same should hold of a +theory of consciousness. We should seek to explain the supervenience of +consciousness upon the physical in terms of the simplest possible set of laws. +Ultimately, we will wish for a set of fundamental laws. Physicists seek a +set of basic laws simple enough that one might write them on the front of +a T-shirt; in a theory of consciousness, we should expect the same thing. In +both cases, we are questing for the basic structure of the universe, and we +have good reason to believe that the basic structure has a remarkable simplicity. The discovery of fundamental laws may be a distant goal, however. In +physics, we first had laws characterizing macroscopic regularities, and only + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +215 + +later proceeded to the underlying fundamental laws. In a theory of consciousness, we might similarly expect to start with nonbasic laws, characterizing +the relationship between physical processes and conscious experience at a +fairly high level. Even this sort of high-level principle might give us significant +explanatory purchase in the meantime, just as the principles of thermodynamics were useful well before we had the underlying principles of statistical +mechanics. And these high-level laws, once discovered, will put strong constraints on any underlying fundamental laws, thus guiding us in the search +for an ultimate theory. +When we finally have fundamental theories of physics and of consciousness +in hand, we may have what truly counts as a theory of everything. The +fundamental physical laws will explain the character of physical processes; +the psychophysical laws will explain the conscious experiences that are associated; and everything else will be a consequence. +Of course, it may be that in the quest for such theories, there will be +developments that change our conception of an ultimate theory. It may be, +for example, that we will find overarching laws that subsume the phenomena +of both physics and consciousness into a grander theory, just as we found a +theory that subsumed electricity and magnetism, and as physicists are now +searching for a theory that unifies all the basic physical forces. Perhaps there +will be developments that are more surprising still. But the current framework +at least provides a start in the search for a theory that might serve as a +first approximation, providing a springboard for any more radical successor +theories that might be in the distance. +How might we build a theory of consciousness? +All this metaphysical grandeur is well and good, one might reply, but how +does it cash out in practice? In particular, how can we discover the psychophysical laws that will constitute a theory of consciousness? After all, there +is an enormous problem for a theory of consciousness that does not confront +a theory of physics: the lack of data. Because consciousness is not directly +observable in experimental contexts, we cannot simply run experiments measuring the experiences that are associated with various physical processes, +thereby confirming and disconfirming various psychophysical hypotheses. +Perhaps these laws, even if they exist, might remain in an unknowable limbo? +Indeed, it might seem that the untestabiiity of any theory of consciousness +that we might put forward would relegate such theories to the status of +pseudoscience. +There is certainly something to this worry: it is this that makes a theory +of consciousness more difficult to get a grip on than a theory in physics. But +it does not disbar us from the search for a theory of consciousness altogether. +For a start, we each have access to a rich source of data in our own case. + + 216 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +We know about our own detailed and specific conscious experiences, and +we also know about the underlying physical processes, so there is a significant +set of regularities right there. Given these regularities, we can invoke some +sort of inference to the best explanation to find the simplest possible underlying laws that might generate the regularities. Right now, we do not have +even a single set of laws that might do this, so this is far from a trivial +constraint on a theory. It might well turn out that there is only one reasonably +simple set of laws that gives the right results, in which case we would have +good reason to believe that those laws are part of a correct theory. +It might still be objected that all sorts of theories remain compatible with +the first-person data: from solipsistic theories (in which only I am conscious) +to panpsychist theories (in which everything is conscious); from biochemicalist theories (in which consciousness arises only from certain biochemical +organizations) to computationalist theories (in which consciousness arises +from anything with the right sort of computational organization); including +along the way such bizarre theories as the theory that people are only +conscious in odd-numbered years (right now, it is 1995). How can we rule +out any of these theories, given that we cannot poke inside others' minds +to measure their conscious experience? +All such theories are logically compatible with the data, but this is not +enough to make them plausible. Solipsistic theories, for example, are extremely implausible due to their great arbitrariness (why should only this +person be conscious?) and their great heterogeneity in space and time (my +conscious experience is systematically tied to my physical structure, but a +physical duplicate of me located elsewhere will not be conscious at all). All +sorts of plausibility considerations play a role in shaping our theories, over +and above the role played by empirical evidence, in all sorts of domains. +Consider, for example, our acceptance of the theory of evolution, as opposed +to the theory that the world was created fifty years ago with memories and +fossil record intact. Or consider the acceptance of certain simple theories of +quantum mechanics instead of other empirically equivalent but highly juryrigged theories. Empirical evidence is not all that we have to go on in theory +formation; there are also principles of plausibility, simplicity, and aesthetics, +among other considerations. +The role played by simplicity, in particular, cannot be overstated. Without +this constraint, scientific theorizing in general would be woefully underconstrained. For any scientific theory one can easily construct an ad hoc hypothesis that is empirically equivalent. No one will accept such a hypothesis, +however, precisely because of its unnecessary complexity. So if we can find +a simple set of underlying laws that are compatible with the data we have, +we have good reason to reject more complex alternatives. +Other plausibility constraints can take us a long way in generating a theory +of consciousness. The most obvious is the principle we rely on whenever we + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +217 + +take someone's verbal report as an indicator of their conscious experience: +that people's reports concerning their experiences by and large accurately +reflect the contents of their experiences. This is not a principle that we +can prove to be true, but it is antecedently much more plausible than the +alternative. This plausibility is based to some extent on an inference from +our own case, but it also has the character of a methodological constraint +in developing a theory of consciousness. If the principle turned out to be +entirely false, all bets would be off: in that case, the world would simply be +an unreasonable place, and a theory of consciousness would be beyond us. +In developing any sort of theory, we assume that the world is a reasonable +place, where planets do not suddenly pop into existence with fossil records +fully formed, and where complex laws are not jury-rigged to reproduce the +predictions of simpler ones. Otherwise, anything goes. +With a plausibility assumption such as this one in hand, we have a very +useful constraint on a theory of consciousness, and indeed a rich source of +data even from the third-person case: to find out whether someone is consciously experiencing a stimulus, just ask them! This principle allows us to +draw much stronger conclusions about the association between conscious +experiences and their physical bases. Of course, the assumption is so plausible +that researchers rely on it all the time, and few would think of questioning +it. Related assumptions can also play a useful role, as with the principle that +people's memories of their experiences are not radically incorrect, by and +large. Of course, there may be occasional exceptions to these principles; but +there is at least a presumption that reports and memories are likely to be +accurate reflections of experience in the absence of good reasons to believe otherwise. +Some other plausibility assumptions might include the following: that fundamental laws are homogeneous in space and time; that conscious experience +depends only on the internal physical state of an organism; that arbitrary +factors such as the distribution of molecules within a neuron are unlikely to +be reflected in conscious experience, unless perhaps they affect the neuron's +functioning; and so on. Of course it is logically possible that any of these +assumptions be false, but in the absence of reasons to believe otherwise, there +is a reasonable presumption that each is true. Together, these plausibility +assumptions place strong constraints on a theory of consciousness, and can +help us considerably in generating such a theory. +What of the worry that a theory of consciousness is untestable, then? This +worry will only come into play in a strong way if it turns out that there are +two equally simple theories, both of which fit the data perfectly, and both +of which meet the relevant plausibility constraints. This may well not happen: +a single theory may emerge that is clearly superior to all competitors. If two +equally good theories do come along, we may be hard pressed to choose +between them, but even so we will have gained significant insight into con- + + 218 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +sciousness by narrowing things down so far. In any case, it is clearly premature +to worry about untestability before we have even a single theory that can +handle the phenomena in a remotely satisfactory way. +Of course this reliance on first-person data and on plausibility constraints +means that a theory of consciousness will have a speculative character not +shared by theories in most scientific domains. Because rigorous intersubjective testing is impossible, we will never be quite as certain that our theories +are on the right track. For this reason, the science of consciousness will +probably always lack the strong empirical credentials of other sciences, and +the most hard-headed researchers will always keep their distance. But consciousness is such a central phenomenon that it is better to have some +understanding of it than no understanding at all: if a reasonable theory of +consciousness can be devised and found superior to all competitors, this will +be an achievement of some importance even if the theory can never be given +absolutely conclusive support. This is simply the boat in which we find ourselves, in trying to understand the universe: we take the materials that we +have, and we work with them. +In this chapter and the next two, I take some initial steps toward a theory +of consciousness. The first two of these chapters discuss possible nonbasic +psychophysical laws, arguing for certain principles that express high-level +regularities in the dependence of consciousness on physical processes. The +third chapter speculates on the character of the underlying fundamental +laws. All this has the character of a preliminary investigation, but we have +to start somewhere. + +2. Principles of Coherence +The most promising way to get started in developing a theory of consciousness +is to focus on the remarkable coherence between conscious experience and +cognitive structure. The phenomenology and the psychology of the mind do +not float free of each other; they are systematically related. The many lawful +relations between consciousness and cognition can provide much of what +we need to get a theory of consciousness off the ground. The best way to +get a handle on this relationship is to focus on phenomenal judgments. +These judgments are part of psychology, but they are closely bound up with +phenomenology, and as such they provide a bridge between the domains. +By thinking about these judgments and the way they function in our own +case, we can come up with a number of principles connecting the phenomenal +to the psychological. +The most obvious principle of this sort is the one I mentioned in section +1: our second-order judgments about consciousness are by and large correct. +We can call this the reliability principle. When I judge that I am having an + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +219 + +auditory sensation, I am usually having an auditory sensation. When I think +I have just experienced a pain, I have usually just experienced a pain. There +is also a converse principle, which we might call the detectability principle: +where there is an experience, we generally have the capacity to form a +second-order judgment about it. Of course many experiences slip by without +our paying any attention to them, but we usually have the ability to notice +them: it would be an odd sort of experience that was unnoticeable by us +in principle.1 +The principles I have outlined are not absolute. Our second-order judgments can sometimes go wrong, providing exceptions to the reliability principle. This might happen due to inattention (when distracted, I might believe +I have just experienced pain when I only experienced loud noise), failure to +grasp relevant categories (as when I mislabel a crimson experience maroon), +mental illness or neurophysiological pathology (as with cases such as blindness denial, when subjects make false claims about their experiences), and +for various other reasons. In the reverse direction, it is arguable that experiences can be unnoticeable if they occur while one is asleep, for example, or +if they flicker by too fast for one to attend to them. But all the same, these +principles at least encapsulate significant regularities. In a typical case, a +second-order judgment will usually be correct, and an experience will usually +be noticeable. These regularities are not exceptionless laws, but they hold +far too often to be a mere coincidence. Something systematic is going on. +I will not try to justify these claims in detail, as they will not be the central +coherence principles on which I will be focusing. But consideration of the +first-person case makes it clear that the principles are plausible at least +there, and they can naturally be extended to other cases by principles of +homogeneity and simplicity. The principles are also endorsed by common +sense, which carries some weight; of course common sense can be overridden +if we have have compelling grounds to do so, but other things being equal, +one should come down on the side of common sense rather than against +it. Finally, as I noted above, these principles have the status of a sort of +methodological constraint in developing a theory of consciousness. If second-order judgments were unreliable across the board, or if most of our +experiences were entirely unnoticeable, then our judgments about experience +would bear so little relation to the reality that a theory of consciousness +could not even get off the ground. +The coherence between consciousness and awareness +The most fundamental coherence principle between consciousness and cognition does not involve second-order phenomenal judgments. Rather, it concerns the relationship between consciousness and first-order judgments. The +principles with which we will deal here concern the coherence between + + 220 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +consciousness and awareness. Recall that awareness is the psychological correlate of consciousness, roughly explicable as a state wherein some information is directly accessible and available for the deliberate control of behavior +and for verbal report. The contents of awareness correspond to the contents +of first-order phenomenal judgments (with a caveat to be mentioned), the +contentful states—such as "That object is red"—that are not about consciousness, but parallel to it. +Where there is consciousness, there is awareness. My visual experience +of a red book upon my table is accompanied by a functional perception of the +book. Optical stimulation is processed and transformed, and my perceptual +systems register that there is an object of such-and-such shape and color on +the table, with this information available in the control of behavior. The +same goes for the specific details in what is experienced. Each detail is +cognitively represented in awareness. To see that each detail must be so +represented, simply observe that I am able to comment on those details and +to direct my behavior in ways that depend on them; for instance, I can point +to appropriate parts of the book. Such systematic availability of information +implies the existence of an internal state carrying that content. +This internal state is a first-order phenomenal judgment—at least to a +first approximation. I include the qualification because one might question +whether this state should strictly be called a "judgment" at all. The content +of this state need not be something that the subject would endorse on +reflection, and indeed it might not be conceptualized by the subject at all. +Such a state might qualify as a judgment only in a weak sense; it may be +better to speak of it as a sort of informational registration, or as an implicit +or subpersonal judgment at best. I will discuss this issue in more depth later +in this chapter, but for now, when I speak of these states as judgments, this +talk should be understood broadly as picking out a class of representational +states that need not be reflectively endorsed by the subject, and which need +not have conceptualized content. +What goes for visual experience here goes equally for any sensory experience. What is experienced in audition is represented in our auditory system, +in such a way that later processes have access to it in the control of behavior; +in particular, the contents are available for verbal report. In principle, somebody who knew nothing about consciousness might examine our cognitive +processes and ascertain these contents of awareness by observing the role +that information plays in directing later processes. In the same sort of way +we can handle hallucinations and other cases of sensations without a real +object being sensed. Although there is no real object for the contents of +perception to concern, there is still representation in our perceptual system. +Macbeth had a first-order cognitive state with the content "dagger there" +to accompany his experience of a dagger, despite the fact that there was no +dagger to be perceived or experienced. + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +221 + +Even nonperceptual experience falls under this umbrella. Although there +may be no object of a pain experience, contents along the line of "something hurts"—or perhaps better, "something bad"—are still cognitively represented. The very fact that we can comment on the pain and direct our +behavior appropriately brings out this fact. There is awareness here just as +there is awareness in visual perception, even though the object of the awareness is not so clear-cut. A similar story goes for our experience of emotion, +and other "internal" experiences. In all these cases, there are cognitive states +corresponding to the experiences; if there were not, then the content of the +experience could not be reflected in behavior at all. +Note that the principle is not that whenever we have a conscious experience +we are aware of the experience. It is first-order judgments that are central +here, not second-order judgments. The principle is that when we have an +experience, we are aware of the contents of the experience. When we experience a book, we are aware of the book; when we experience a pain, we are +aware of something hurtful; when we experience a thought, we are aware +of whatever it is that the thought is about. It is not a matter of an experience +followed by a separate judgment, as might be the case for second-order +judgments; these first-order judgments are concomitants of experiences, existing alongside them. +The tie between experiences and second-order judgments is much more +indirect: although we have the ability to notice our experiences, most of the +time we notice only the contents of the experience, not the experience itself. +Only occasionally do we sit back and take notice of our experience of the +red book; usually we just think about the book. Where second-order judgments are infrequent, first-order judgments are ubiquitous. The most direct +link is therefore the link between consciousness and first-order judgments. +So far I have argued that where there is consciousness there is awareness. +But the arrow goes both ways. Where there is awareness, there is generally +consciousness. When we are aware of something in our environment, with +some reportable content directing our behavior, there is generally a corresponding conscious experience. When my cognitive system represents a dog +barking, I have an experience of a dog barking. When I am aware of heat +around me, I feel hot. And so on. +Things get a little tricky here. It may seem that there are various kinds of +awareness that do not have corresponding experiences. Awareness involving +information in memory provides an example. I am aware that Clinton is +president, in the sense that I have access to this information, can verbally +report it, and can use it in the deliberate direction of my behavior. If I am +not having an occurrent thought to this effect, however, there does not seem +to be a corresponding conscious experience; or if there is, it is an extremely +weak one. Similarly, I may be (nonoccurrently) aware that there is a bicycle +downstairs, without there being an associated bicycle experience. This sort + + 222 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +of awareness without experience is most pronounced with propositional +awareness—I am aware that my bicycle is downstairs—although it also applies to a kind of objectual awareness, in that it seems reasonable to say +that I am aware of my bicycle. +We could leave this matter as it stands, but it is more satisfying to put +restrictions on the notion of awareness so that it is more truly parallel to +consciousness. It seems plausible that there is some kind of functional difference between the processes involved in one sort of case and in the other—the +very fact that I can report on the difference between them bears witness to +that. It is this functional difference that needs to be isolated. +Perhaps the most salient difference is that in cases of awareness with +consciousness, there is a kind of direct access that cases of awareness without +consciousness lack. The information that Clinton is president, for example, +needs to be "called up" in order for it to make a difference in the deliberate +control of behavior, at least if it is not the content of an occurrent thought. +It is not as immediately poised to make a difference in control as are the +cognitive states associated with experiences and occurrent thoughts. That is, +the cognitive access to the information in this case is somewhat more indirect. It is this that provides the functional distinction between occurrent and +nonoccurrent thoughts. +We can therefore build this directness of access into a revised notion of +awareness. According to the revised notion, nonoccurrent thoughts do not +qualify as part of the contents of awareness, but occurrent thoughts do. +Correspondingly, we should expect that occurrent thoughts will be associated +with experiences, even if nonoccurrent thoughts are not. This is just what +we find. My nonoccurrent thought that Clinton is president has no impact +on my phenomenology, but an occurrent thought to that effect will be associated with an experience. To see this, note that there is something it is like +to think to oneself that Clinton is president; if I had not been thinking that +thought just now, it would have been like something subtly different to +be me.2 +Thus it is plausible that with awareness appropriately defined, consciousness is always accompanied by awareness, and vice versa. There is more to +be said in characterizing the relevant sort of awareness; I will refine the +characterization further in what follows, partly by considering various interesting cases. Even at the coarse level, however, we can see that this relationship provides a useful focal point in understanding the coherence between +consciousness and cognition. +The principle of structural coherence +So far we have a hypothesis: where there is consciousness, there is awareness, +and where there is (the right kind of) awareness, there is consciousness. The + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +223 + +correlation between these can be made more detailed than this. In particular, +various structural features of consciousness correspond directly to structural +features that are represented in awareness. +An individual's conscious experience is not in general a homogeneous +blob; it has a detailed internal structure. My visual field, for example, has a +definite geometry to it. There is a large red patch here, with a small yellow +patch in close proximity, with some white in between; there are patterns of +stripes, squares, and triangles; and so on. In three dimensions, I have experiences of shapes such as cubes, experiences of one thing as being behind +another thing, and other manifestations of the geometry of depth. My visual +field consists in a vast mass of details, which fit together into an encompassing structure. +Crucially, all of these details are cognitively represented, within what we +can think of as the structure of awareness. The size and shape of various +patches is represented in my visual system, for example: perhaps in a fairly +direct topographic map, but even if not, we know that it is represented +somehow. It must be, as witnessed by the fact that the relevant information +is available to guide the control of behavior. The same goes for perceptual +representation of the stripes, and of cubical shapes, and so on. Each of these +structural details is accessible to the cognitive system, and available for use +in the control of behavior, so each is represented in the contents of awareness. +In principle, someone with complete knowledge of my cognitive processes +would be able to recover all of these structural details. The geometry of the +visual field can be recovered by an analysis of the information that the visual +system makes available for later control processes; the very fact that each +of these details can be reflected in the behavioral capacities of the subject—a +subject might trace the various structural details with arm movements, for +example, or comment on them in verbal reports—implies that the information must be present somewhere. Of course the details of the analysis would +be very tricky, and far beyond present-day methods, but we know that the +information is there. In this way we can see that the structure of consciousness is mirrored in the structure of awareness. +The same goes for implicit structure in the phenomenal field, such as +relations between colors. Even if I am only seeing one color at a given time, +there are a host of colors I could have been seeing, colors to which this color +bears a structural relation. One color is very similar to another color, and +quite different from another. Two colors can seem complementary, or one +color group can seem "warm" and another "cold." On a close analysis, our +phenomenal colors turn out to fall into a three-dimensional structure, ordered +along a red-green dimension, a yellow-blue dimension, and a white-black +dimension (the choice of axes is somewhat arbitrary, but there will always +be three of them). It turns out that this three-dimensional phenomenal +structure is mirrored by a three-dimensional structure in the color informa- + + 224 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +tion processed within our perceptual systems. Of course it is predictable that +it would be, as we know the relevant information is available in the control +of behavior, but it is interesting to see that the structure is currently being +worked out in detail in studies of the visual system (see Hardin 1988 for +discussion). We might say that in this case there is a difference structure in +our conscious experience (a space of differences between possible experiences) that is mirrored by a difference structure in awareness: to the manifold +of color experiences and relations among them, there corresponds a manifold +of color representations and corresponding relations among them. +We can find similar sorts of implicit structure in other phenomenal domains, and a similar correspondence to implicit structures at the processing +level. The phenomenological structure in a musical chord must be mirrored +by structure in what is represented, for example, in order that it can be +reported and reflected in other processes of control. The same holds for the +implicit structure of tastes. Such correspondences are found in empirical +studies of the relevant processes with considerable frequency; but even without such studies, one can see that there must be some sort of correspondence, +by reflecting on the fact that these structural details are available to play a +control role. In general, this sort of reasoning leads us to the conclusion that +any detailed structure that one might find in a phenomenal field will be +mirrored in the structures represented in awareness. +There are various more specific features of experience that are also mirrored within awareness. The most obvious of these is intensity of experience. +It is clear that intensity makes a difference to later processes, so it must +somehow be represented in the structure of awareness. Indeed, it is plausible +that the intensity of an experience corresponds directly to the extent to +which an underlying representation tends to play a control role, occupying +the resources of later processes (think of the difference between an intense +pain and a faint one, or between an all-consuming emotion and a background +emotion). Another such feature is the resolution of experiences, as found +for example in the difference between the high resolution at the center of +a visual field and the low resolution at the fringes. This resolution is something +that we would expect to be mirrored in the resolution of underlying representations, and indeed that is what we find. +In general, even if experiences are in some sense "ineffable," relations +between experiences are not; we have no trouble discussing these relations, +whether they be relations of similarity and difference, geometric relations, +relations of intensity, and so on. As Schlick (1938) pointed out, the form of +experience seems to be straightforwardly communicable, even if the content +(intrinsic quality) is not: I can characterize the relationship between a red +and a green experience, if not the redness and greenness themselves.3 So we +should expect that these relations will be cognitively represented, and this +is indeed what we find. Similarities and differences between experiences + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +225 + +correspond to similarities and differences represented in awareness; the geometry of experience corresponds to the geometry of awareness; and so on. +If we refine the notion of awareness as suggested above, so that states of +awareness are always accompanied by states of experience, then a structural +correspondence in the other direction will also be plausible: the structure +represented in awareness is mirrored in the structure of experience. +So alongside the general principle that where there is consciousness, there +is awareness, and vice versa, we have a more specific principle: the structure +of consciousness is mirrored by the structure of awareness, and the structure +of awareness is mirrored by the structure of consciousness. I will call this +the principle of structural coherence.4 This is a central and systematic relation +between phenomenology and psychology, and ultimately can be cashed out +into a relation between phenomenology and underlying physical processes. +As we will see, it is useful in a number of ways. + +3. More on the Notion of Awareness +One of the most interesting philosophical projects in the study of consciousness is that of refining the notion of awareness so that it becomes a more +perfect psychological correlate of consciousness. On an initial definition, +awareness corresponds only imperfectly to consciousness, but the notion can +be refined to handle problem cases. Ultimately we would like to characterize +a psychological state that plausibly correlates with conscious experience +across the board, at least in a range of cases with which we are familiar. +I defined awareness initially as the state wherein some information is +accessible for verbal report and the deliberate control of behavior. Considerations about prepositional awareness in the absence of experience suggested +modifying this to require direct access. Other modifications are possible. The +most obvious is that availability for verbal report is not strictly required +for conscious experience, as considerations about experience in mammals +suggest, although it is a good heuristic in cases where language is present. +A natural suggestion is to modify the definition of awareness to something +like direct availability for global control. That is, a subject is aware of some +information when that information is directly available to bring to bear in +the direction of a wide range of behavioral processes. This allows for the +possibility of experience in nonhuman animals, and also squares nicely with +the reportability criterion. In cases where information is reportable, it is +generally available for global control (for example, in the deliberate direction +of a wide range of behaviors). The reverse implication does not always hold +(as witnessed by the animal case), but at least in subjects that have the +capacity to report, availability of information for global control generally +implies its availability for report. + + 226 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +Of course this project of refinement can only go so far, as we lack an +experience meter with which to confirm and refine these hypotheses empirically. Still, we have a good idea from the first-person case about states in +which we have experiences and states in which we do not, and an analysis of what is going on in these cases usually allows us to characterize those +states in functional terms. So reflection on the relationship between experience and function in familiar cases gives us considerable leverage. We might +also try to empirically refine these hypotheses via first-person experimentation. For example, we can place ourselves into a given functional state, and +see what sort of experience we have. With a little help from principles of +homogeneity and reliability, we can draw conclusions from the investigation +of corresponding situations in others. +There is also a role for the empirical consideration of cases farther from +home, for example by considering what sorts of experiences are plausibly +had by subjects suffering from certain pathologies, or by nonhuman animals. +Of course, we can never be completely certain about what experiences are +present in these cases, but some conclusions are much more plausible than +others. In effect, these cases act as a focus for our reasoning and an aid to +the imagination in distilling plausible principles on the connection between +experience and function. The principles may be ultimately grounded in nonempirical analysis, but focus on empirical cases at least ties this sort of +reasoning to the real world. +For example, reflection on the attribution of experience to mammals +squares with the refined criterion I have suggested above. We are generally +prepared to attribute perceptual experience of a stimulus to mammals in +cases where the direction of behavior can be made to depend on that stimulus, +especially if this is exhibited in a number of different kinds of behavior. If +we found that information about a stimulus could only be exhibited in +a single, relatively minor behavioral reaction, we might suppose that the +information is entirely unconscious. As its availability for use becomes more +widespread, it becomes more plausible to suppose that it is experienced. +So the coherence between consciousness and this notion of awareness is +compatible both with the first-person data and with the natural reasoning +concerning nonhuman cases. +There are a number of other interesting problem cases for analysis. One +example is blindsight (described in Weiskrantz 1986). This is a deficit arising +from damage to the visual cortex, in which the usual route for visual information processing is damaged, but in which visual information nevertheless +seems to be processed in a limited way. Subjects with blindsight can see +nothing in certain areas of their visual field, or so they say. If one puts a red +or green light in their "blind area" they claim to see nothing. But when one +forces them to make a choice about what is in that area—on whether a red +or green light is present, for example—it turns out that they are right far + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +227 + +more often than they are wrong. Somehow they are "seeing" what is in the +area without really seeing it. +Blindsight is sometimes put forward as a case in which consciousness and +the associated functional role come apart. After all, in blindsight there is +discrimination, categorization, and even verbal report of a sort, but it seems +that there is no conscious experience. If this were truly a case in which +functional role and experience where dissociated, it would clearly raise problems for the coherence principle. Fortunately, the conclusion that this is an +example of awareness without consciousness is ungrounded. For a start, it +is not obvious that there is no experience in these cases; perhaps there is a +faint experience that bears an unusual relation to verbal report. More to the +point, however, this is far from a standard case of awareness. There is a large +difference between the functional roles played here and those played in the +usual case—it is precisely because of this difference in functional roles that +we notice something amiss in the first place.5 +In particular, subjects with blindsight seem to lack the usual sort of access +to the information at hand. Their access is curiously indirect, as witnessed +by the fact that it is not straightforwardly available for verbal report, and +in the deliberate control of behavior. The information is available to many +fewer control processes than is standard perceptual information; it can be +made available to other processes, but only by unusual methods such as +prompting and forced choice. So this information does not qualify as directly +available for global control, and the subjects are not truly aware of the information in the relevant sense. The lack of experience corresponds directly +to a lack of awareness. It is also possible, perhaps, that blindsight subjects +have a weak sort of experience, in which case one might also want to say +that they have a weak sort of awareness, by drawing the standards of directness and globality appropriately. The description of the situation is somewhat +underdetermined, given our lack of access to the facts of the matter, but +either way it is compatible with the coherence between consciousness and +awareness. +In general, this sort of case cannot provide evidence against a link between +functional organization and conscious experience, as our conclusions about +the presence or absence of consciousness in these cases are drawn precisely +on functional grounds. In particular, the evidence for unusual states of consciousness in these pathological cases usually relies entirely on evidence for +unusual states of awareness. Such cases therefore cannot damage the principle of coherence; they can only bolster and refine it. +A tricky problem case is provided by experiences during sleep. It is plausible that we have experiences when we dream (although see Dennett 1978b), +but reportability and any role in the control of action are missing, as action +is missing entirely. Still, these cases might plausibly be analyzed in terms of +availability for global control; it is just that the relevant control processes + + 228 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +themselves are mostly shut down. Perhaps the information makes it into the +sort of position from which it can usually be used for control purposes; this +suggestion is supported by the accessibility of current dream content in a +half-waking state. We could then still run the counterfactual: if reportability +and control had been enabled (e.g., if the motor cortex had been functioning +normally), then the information could have played a role. But this deserves +a more careful analysis, along with empirical investigation of what is really +going on during sleep. +Some interesting cases are presented by Block (1995) in his extended +discussion of the distinction between phenomenal consciousness and "access +consciousness." In Block's account, a state is "access-conscious" if its content is poised to be used as a premise in reasoning, poised for rational control +of action, and poised for rational control of speech. So access consciousness +corresponds roughly to my initial definition of awareness, although my definition gives less of a role to rationality. Block presents some cases where +the two varieties of consciousness might come apart. It is instructive to see +how a coherence principle might handle them. +On the possibility of access consciousness without phenomenal consciousness, Block appeals only to cases that are conceptually possible, such as +zombies; these nonactual cases clearly cannot threaten the coherence principle. He mentions blindsight, but notes that blindsight only yields access +consciousness in a weak sense. He also discusses cases such as "superblindsight," which is like blindsight except that a subject is trained to have much +better access to the information in the blind field. There are clearly conceivable cases of awareness without consciousness in the vicinity, but Block +himself notes that there is no reason to believe such cases are actual. Interestingly, he notes that in the closest thing to empirical examples of such a case +(a monkey described in Humphrey 1992 and a human patient described in +Weiskrantz 1992; see also Cowey and Stoerig 1992), there is reason to believe +that phenomenal consciousness is actually present. +On phenomenal consciousness without access consciousness, Block mentions some actual cases. One is a situation in which a subject suddenly +becomes aware of the fact that there has been a loud drill in the background +for some time. Block suggests that before realizing this, the subject was +phenomenally conscious but not access-conscious of the drilling noise. Using +the account of awareness I have given, however, it seems reasonable to say +that the subject was aware of the drill all along. It is plausible that relevant +information about the drill was available the whole time; it simply was not +accessed. So if access consciousness or awareness is defined dispositionally, +this case is no problem for a coherence principle. Block also mentions a case +in which a three-by-three array of letters is flashed briefly at a subject (Sperling 1960). If asked to name the letters in the top row, subjects can name +those but then cannot name the others; the same for the other rows. Block + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +229 + +argues that a subject is phenomenally conscious of all nine of the letters, +but is access-conscious of only three at a time. But once again it is plausible +that information about all nine letters was initially available; it is just +that information about only three letters was accessed, and the very process +of access destroyed the accessibility of the other information. So this case +is also compatible with the coherence principle, on a dispositional account +of awareness. +There are many other cases that might be considered. All I have done +here is to present some cases and some brief analysis as illustration, to give +some idea of the shape of an interesting philosophical project. In a more +careful analysis, one might seek to put stronger constraints on just what kind +of accessibility goes along with conscious experience, and just what kind of +global control role is relevant. The account of awareness in terms of direct +availability for global control is just a start. This is a fertile area for further analysis. + +Relationship to functionalist theories of consciousness* +The project I have outlined can be seen as a search for a sort of functionalist +account of consciousness. It is not a reductive functionalist account—it does +not say that the playing of some functional role is all there is to consciousness, +or all there is to be explained. Rather, it is a nonreductive account, one that +gives functional criteria for when consciousness arises. All the same, there +is a sense in which it is playing in the same ballpark as reductive functionalist +accounts; these also give functional criteria for when consciousness arises, +alongside their more ambitious metaphysical claims. It is interesting to leave +the metaphysical differences aside and compare various accounts in terms +of their functional criteria alone. +For example, the proposal that consciousness goes along with direct availability for global control is reminiscent of Dennett's (1993b) proposal that +consciousness is cerebral celebrity: "Consciousness is cerebral celebrity— +nothing more and nothing less. Those contents are conscious that persevere, +that monopolize resources long enough to achieve certain typical and 'symptomatic' effects—on memory, on the control of behavior and so forth" +(p. 929). +Leaving aside the fact that Dennett takes this to be a conceptual truth, it +is quite close to the present account. The main difference is that my account +takes consciousness to go along with potential cerebral celebrity. It is not +required that a content actually play a global control role to be conscious, +but it must be available to do so. This seems to square better with the +properties of experience. For example, we experience the fringes of our +visual field, but most of the time these do not play much of a role in global +control; they are merely available to do so if required. Many of the noises + + 230 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +Figure 6.1. Zippy the Pinhead on higher-order theories of consciousness. +(Reprinted with special permission of King Features Syndicate) + +we experience may pass without leaving significant effects on memory, behavior, and the like, but the information could have done so. Of course, Dennett +may simply be using the term"consciousness" in a stronger sense, a sense +in which we are not conscious of those fringes and noises (Dennett is dubious +about the very idea of experience, after all), but the comparison is interesting +all the same. +Another functionalist account is Rosenthal's (1996) proposal that for a +state to be conscious is for it to be the object of a higher-order thought. In +the language I have been using, this means that a first-order state is a content +of consciousness precisely when there is a second-order judgment about it. +This is considerably stronger than my proposal, in the same sort of way that +Dennett's proposal is stronger. On the face of it, there is little reason to +believe that we form second-order judgments about all of our experiences, +including experiences of every detail of the visual field, of background noises, +and so on. Rosenthal holds that the second-order judgments are usually +themselves unconscious, which is why we do not notice they are present, +but even third-person considerations seem to militate against them. All these +second-order judgments seem quite unnecessary in the design of a cognitive +system. One might expect a system to have the ability to form such judgments +when necessary, as we do about our more salient experiences, but a system +with a second-order judgment for every detail of the visual field would seem +quite redundant (Figure 6.1). +In Rosenthal's account, conscious states are states that we are conscious +of. This may have a ring of plausibility, but I think it is only in the weak +sense (of the last chapter) in which we are acquainted with all of our experiences.6 It is not at all clear that most of our experiences are objects of our +thoughts. To suppose that there are two separate cognitive states for every + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +231 + +detail of experience, a first-order and a second-order judgment, leads to a +cluttered picture of the mind. It is hard to see why evolution would bother +to build in these second-order judgments across the board, when a simple +availability for global control would serve its purposes just as well. Rosenthal's account is better taken as an account of introspective consciousness, +although he puts it forward as an account of consciousness in the "what it +is like" sense. +It is useful to divide functional accounts of consciousness into first-order +and second-order varieties. On the second-order varieties (which include +Rosenthal's higher-order thought account, as well as the higher-order perception account of Lycan [1995] and others), what is central to consciousness +is the presence of some second-order cognitive state. In first-order theories, +only a first-order cognitive state is required, with some restrictions on the +role that it plays. Second-order theories may give a good account of introspection or of reflective consciousness, but first-order theories seem more closely +linked to conscious experience.7 +Of course not all first-order cognitive states correspond to conscious experiences; there can be first-order judgments about the world that correspond +to no experience at all. One therefore needs an additional component in +such a theory to distinguish those relevant class of first-order states. The +obvious way to do this is to constrain the role of those states. This is what +I have done, suggesting that the relevant first-order judgments are precisely +those that are directly available for global control. Other first-order accounts +suggest related constraints, as we will see. One might argue that the causation +of a higher-order thought is just another constraint of this kind; the trouble +is that the constraint seems to be much too strong. +An interesting intermediate proposal is that a conscious state corresponds +to a first-order judgment that has the capacity to cause a second-order +judgment about it.8 This avoids the clutter of the previous proposal, and +has an element of plausibility. Indeed, it is not all that different from the +notion that a conscious state corresponds to a first-order judgment that is +available for global control: presumably the availability for global control +and the availability for second-order judgment will go together much of +the time. Such a proposal may falter when it comes to systems such as +babies and animals that arguably have experiences but lack the capacity for +second-order judgments, however; it seems to require more conceptual sophistication than may be required for the possession of experiences. +If so, the characterization in terms of availability for global control is superior. +It is likely that any first-order functionalist account will invoke a constraint +involving some sort of availability. An examination of existing reductive +accounts bears this out. For example, Kirk (1992) suggests that perceptual + + 232 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +consciousness requires that incoming information is "present" to a system's +main decision-making processes, and Kirk (1994) suggests that "directly +active" information is required. The suggestion by Dretske (1995) that experience is information that is represented to a system also has this flavor, as +does the suggestion by Tye (1995) that information must be "poised" for +cognitive processing in an appropriate way. One could probably reconcile +these suggestions with each other without too many difficulties. All of them +seem intended to express a similar idea. +In any case, it is interesting that a nonreductionist about consciousness +need not regard the issues between the various first-order and second-order +functionalist accounts as internecine warfare among doomed theories. Although these accounts cannot explain consciousness, they are still quite +relevant as candidate theories of consciousness's cognitive basis, and some +of them succeed here better than others. Even a property dualist can acknowledge an element of truth in them, and can attach some significance to the +differences between them. +First-order judgments and first-order registrations* +I have argued that states of experience correspond directly to underlying +cognitive states, which I have called first-order judgments. But as I noted +before, and as Dretske (1995) has stressed, it may be misleading to call these +states judgments. Judgments, recall, were originally defined to come to much +the same thing as beliefs (with the stipulation that any phenomenal element +is excluded). But while it is reasonable to suppose that there is a representational state corresponding to every detail in an experienced visual field, it +is not clear that the subject has beliefs about all those details. The contents +of the fringes of my visual field, for example, might seem to be something +about which I do not have beliefs one way or another, at least until I pay +attention to them. Nevertheless, even in the absence of beliefs, there is some +sort of cognitive state carrying the relevant information, as the information +is at least available. +We might simply stipulate that we are using the term "judgment" in a +broader way to cover this sort of cognitive state in addition to explicit beliefs. +After all, it is plausible that representations of the fringes of the visual field +can be seen as "microjudgments," or as implicit judgments made by processes +within the cognitive systems, even if they are not judgments of the whole +person. But it is probably best to avoid confusion on this matter and introduce a broader term for representational states that are not necessarily +judgments. I will use the term "registrations" for this purpose. The cognitive +contents of perceptual states, for example, will be carried by first-order +registrations rather than by first-order judgments. A first-order registration +need not be a state that is endorsed by the subject, but it is nevertheless a + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +233 + +contentful state that is available to the subject and that plays a role in the +cognitive system. +First-order registrations may even on occasion be contradicted by firstorder judgments. Optical illusions provide a clear example: a subject might +know that two objects have the same size, but perception can represent them +as having different sizes anyway. Dretske gives another example: You hold +up seven fingers, and I see all seven. But I do not have time to count them, +and I mistakenly take there to be eight fingers before me. So I judge that +there are eight fingers before me, but my phenomenal experience is of seven +fingers. The judgment therefore does not directly parallel the phenomenology. But somewhere within the perceptual system, the visual information of +seven fingers is represented and made available to later systems. It is this +earlier representation that I am calling a first-order registration. We can +think of first-order registrations as the immediate product of perceptual and +introspective processes, before they are rationally integrated into a coherent whole.9 +The contents of awareness, then, will strictly speaking be constituted by +first-order registrations rather than by first-order judgments. In particular, +the contents of awareness will consist approximately of those first-order +registrations that are directly available for use in global control. So defined, +the contents of awareness correspond directly to the contents of consciousness. Of course, there will be some first-order registrations that fall outside +the contents of awareness, as with states of subliminal perception, for example. As with judgments, we can speak of first-order phenomenal registrations to distinguish those registrations that correspond to experiences from +those that do not. It is always those in the first class that I will be concerned +with, however, so I will usually speak simply of "first-order registrations" +and leave the qualifier implicit. +(The representational content of a first-order registration is probably best +taken to be nonconceptual content, as is the parallel content of experience. +I discuss this and some other issues about the contents of awareness and +experience in an endnote.)10 + +4. The Explanatory Role of Coherence Principles +The principles of coherence that I have outlined are not just metaphysical +set pieces. They can play a central role in empirical work on conscious +experience. Any empirical study of consciousness requires some preexperimental reasoning to even get off the ground, in order to draw conclusions +about conscious experience on the basis of physical data. The coherence +principles provide the necessary purchase. With them in place, there is a +methodological foundation for empirical research on conscious experience + + 234 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +in a number of areas. A lot of work along these lines is already taking place; +the coherence principles simply bring the assumptions that lie behind the +work into the open. +There are at least three main projects in which these principles might play +an explanatory role. First, the principle of structural coherence can help us +in the project of using facts about physical processing to help explain the +structure of specific sorts of experience. Second, the coherence between +consciousness and awareness acts as a kind of epistemic lever in allowing +researchers to infer conclusions about experience from third-person data. +And third, the coherence between consciousness and awareness can serve +as a background principle in the search for the physical correlates of consciousness. I will discuss each of these in turn. +The first of these provides the clearest example in contemporary practice. +It is common to see empirical work on neurobiological and cognitive processes used to shed light on structural features of experience. As I have +already discussed, for example, a study of the processes underlying color +vision is very useful in helping to explain the structure of phenomenal color +space. Similarly, the study of topographic maps in the visual cortex helps +shed light on the structure of the phenomenal visual field, and the study of +processing in the auditory cortex helps us understand many structural aspects of auditory experiences (pitch relationships and directional aspects, +for example). Something similar applies in many other phenomenal domains. +One might wonder how any story about physical processes could be used +to shed light on features of experience, given what I have said about the +impossibility of reductive explanation. The principle of structural coherence +allows us to understand what is going on. In essence, this principle is being +used as a background assumption, to provide a bridge from features of +physical processes to features of experience. If we take for granted the +coherence between the structure of consciousness and the structure of awareness, then in order to explain some specific aspect of the former, we need +only explain the corresponding aspect of the latter. The bridging principle +does the rest of the work. +In the case of color, for example, what happens is that a story about +physical processes gives us a reductive account of the structure of awareness, +by explaining the relevant similarities and differences between the visual +stimuli that the color system processes and makes available to later systems. +Once we have this account of the relevant structure of color awareness in +hand, then the coherence principle tells us that this structure will be mirrored +in the structure of color experience. So if the coherence principle is taken +for granted, a functional account of visual processing serves as an indirect +account of the structure of phenomenal color space. The same method can +be exploited to explain many other features of experience. + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +235 + +Some have been sufficiently impressed by the coherence between the +structure in consciousness and in cognition to suggest that this is all we need +for a physical explanation of consciousness. Van Gulick (1993), for instance, +notes the fact that the structure of our color space corresponds directly to +a structure that is represented in visual processing, and suggests that this +closes the "explanatory gap" by providing a functional explanation of color +sensation. Clark (1993) devotes an entire book to this strategy, arguing that +sensory qualities can be completely explained by accounting for the relations +of similarity and difference within quality spaces. +If what I have said before is correct, these claims are a little too strong. +First, this method does not explain the intrinsic nature of a color experience, +as the possibility of a structure-preserving spectrum inversion shows. At best, +it explains the relational structure between such experiences or between +parts of a complex experience; so more is required for a full account of +consciousness. Second and more important, no account of the structure of +awareness explains why there is any accompanying experience at all, precisely because it cannot explain why the principle of structural coherence +holds in the first place. By taking the principle as a background assumption +we have already moved beyond reductive explanation: the principle simply +assumes the existence of consciousness, and does nothing to explain it. This +counts as a kind of nonreductive explanation, taking the existence of consciousness for granted and trying to explain some of its properties. +Within these limits, the principle of structural coherence provides an enormously useful explanatory relation between the physical and the phenomenal. +If we want to explain some apparent structure in a phenomenal domain— +say, the relations we find between our experiences of musical chords—then +we can investigate the functional organization of the corresponding psychological domain, taking advantage of insights from cognitive science and neuroscience to reductively explain the structure of awareness in that domain. +In doing so we have explained the structure of the phenomenal domain, +modulo the contribution of the principle of structural coherence. Because +of our appeal to this principle we will not have explained consciousness itself +by doing so, but we will still have explained much of what is special about +a particular phenomenal domain. +This way, the principle of structural coherence can serve as the backbone +of a project that Crick and Koch11 call "the natural history of qualia." Even +if neuroscience cannot explain the existence of experience, it can explain a +vast number of facts about experience. Neuroscience can indirectly explain +the similarity and difference relations between experiences; the geometry of +experiential spaces such as taste space and color space; the detailed structure +of experiential fields, such as the visual field; the perceived location associated +with experiences within such a field; the intensity of experiences; the duration + + 236 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +of experiences; associations between experiences; and much more. As Crick +and Koch put it, neuroscience can give an account of all those features of +experiences that are objectively communicable. The very communicability +of those features implies that they are mirrored in physical features of the +system, and indeed in features of awareness. The structural coherence between consciousness and awareness is the implicit or explicit foundation on +which this sort of explanation rests. (Such a foundation is particularly crucial +in the field of psychophysics, as I discuss in an endnote.)12 +Using these methods, we might even get some insight into what it is like +to be a bat! Functional organization can tell us much about the kind of +information that a bat has access to—the kinds of discriminations it can +make, the ways it categorizes things, the most salient properties in its perceptual field, and so on—and about the way in which it uses it. Eventually +we should be able to build up a detailed picture about the structure of +awareness in a bat's cognitive system. By the principle of structural coherence, we will then have a good idea about the structure of the bat's experiences. We will not know everything about what it is like to be a bat—we +will not have a clear conception of the intrinsic nature of the experiences, +for instance—but we will know quite a bit. An interesting paper by Akins +(1993) about the mental lives of bats can be read as contributing to this +project. +In a similar way, Cheney and Seyfarth's (1990) book How Monkeys See +the World is put forward as an answer to a question like the one about bats, +taking us inside the mind of another species. In effect the work uses the +principle of structural coherence as a background assumption throughout, +giving an account of certain functional processes and the structure of awareness that they entail, and inviting us to infer a corresponding structure of +experience. Of course this does not answer Nagel's real worry, for the usual +reasons, but it is nevertheless a striking achievement. We do not need to +engage the ultimate mystery of consciousness every time we want to account +for a specific phenomenal domain. +Coherence principles as epistemic levers +Empirical researchers in neuroscience, psychology, ethology, and related +fields sometimes want to make claims about the presence of conscious experience in a system. Although consciousness is most often set to one side in +these fields, there is a nonnegligible body of work in which conclusions about +conscious experience are drawn from empirical results. How is this possible, +given the difficulties in observing experience directly? If all that can be +observed are physical processes, what justifies any conclusion at all? +The answer must be that whenever conclusions about experience are drawn +from empirical results, a bridging principle linking physical processes to ex- + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +237 + +perience is doing the work. A bridging principle will give a criterion for the +presence of consciousness in a system, a criterion that applies at the physical +level. Such a principle will act as an epistemic lever leading from knowledge +about physical processes to knowledge about experience. The epistemic lever +is not itself experimentally testable, at least from the third-person viewpoint; +instead, it acts as a kind of prior background assumption. These assumptions +are not always made explicit, but they are the only way that this sort of work +gets any purchase on conscious experience. +Bridging principles are so crucial here that it makes sense to be explicit +about them. There is a sense in which anyone who appeals to a bridging +principle—which means anyone who draws conclusions about experience +from external observations—is doing "philosophy," as bridging principles +are not themselves experimental conclusions. Such principles must be based +on considerations from the first-person case, and on general principles of +plausibility. These principles effectively precede any experimental results, +as it is the principles themselves that tell us how to interpret those results. +Of course there are a priori assumptions involved in any experimental enterprise, but here they play an unusually significant role. It is therefore important to justify those assumptions as well as we can, by a careful analysis. +That is one way to interpret the project in which I have been engaged in +this chapter. +The bridging principle that I have recommended is that of the coherence +between consciousness and awareness: when a system is aware of some information, in the sense that the information is directly available for global +control, then the information is conscious. I suspect that if one undertook +a careful study of the bridging principles used by empirical researchers and +by those who interpret empirical research, almost all such principles would +be compatible with this one and indeed derivable from it. The most common +bridging principle, of course, is the use of reportability as a criterion for experience: at least in a language-using system, it is generally held that information is conscious if it is reportable. Reportability is a version of awareness—when information is reportable, it is always available for control—so +this criterion clearly squares with the coherence principle, although it is more +limited in its scope. +Other criteria are also occasionally used; sometimes researchers want to +make claims about experience in animals without language, or in humans +whose report mechanisms are not functioning normally. In these cases, the +best sign of experience is usually taken to be a strong effect of some information in the control of behavior. For example, Logothetis and Schall +(1989) present their work as isolating the "neuronal correlates of subjective +visual perception" in monkeys. Here, a monkey is taken to be having perceptual experience of a moving object in its environment when it can reliably +make an eye movement or press a bar in response to that movement. This + + 238 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +again squares perfectly with the criterion provided by awareness, or direct +availability for global control. +Some may find an appeal to preexperimental bridging principles disturbing +in an experimental science; indeed, the need for such epistemic levers may be +the reason that such sciences have so often stayed away from consciousness. +Nevertheless, this is the boat we find ourselves in, and conclusions drawn +on the basis of these principles are better than no conclusions at all. It makes +sense for the relevant principles to be made explicit, though, and justified +by careful analysis, rather than being swept under the rug. In this way the +underlying reasoning that leads to empirical conclusions about conscious +experience will be clarified. +The physical correlates of consciousness +What are the neural and information-processing correlates of consciousness? +This is one of the central questions about consciousness that empirical research is often taken to address. Various empirical hypotheses have been +put forward. For example, Crick and Koch (1990) put forward the hypothesis that certain 40-hertz oscillations in the cortex are the neural correlates +of experience. Baars (1988) can be interpreted as suggesting that a global +workspace is the information-processing basis for experience, with the contents of experience corresponding directly to the contents of the workspace. +Farah (1994) argues that consciousness is associated with "high-quality" +representations in the brain. Libet (1993) puts forward a neural "time-on" +theory, in which consciousness is associated with neuronal activities that persist for a long enough time, with a minimal duration of around 500 milliseconds. There have been numerous other proposals in a similar vein. +The coherence between consciousness and awareness provides a natural +way to make sense of much of this work. It is striking that each of these +candidates is itself a plausible candidate to play a role in facilitating awareness—direct availability for global control. Crick and Koch's oscillations are +put forward because of the role they may play in binding information and +placing that information in working memory; and of course working memory +is just a system whereby contents are made available for control. Libet's +temporally extended neural activity may be relevant precisely because that +sort of activity has the widespread robust effects on the cognitive system +required for awareness. The same goes for Farah's "high-quality" representations; it is arguable that "low-quality" representations might not be able to +permeate cognitive functioning in the appropriate way. For Baars's global +workspace, the link is clearest of all: the workspace is put forward precisely +in virtue of its role in mediating global access and control. +A deflationary interpretation of what is going on here would be that these +researchers simply mean awareness when they say "consciousness," so that + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +239 + +this commonality is unremarkable. But I think it is clear from context that +most of them—at least Crick and Koch and Farah, and probably Libet—are +talking about consciousness in the full phenomenal sense, and are trying to +isolate physical correlates for it. All of them make remarks that suggest they +would accept a conceptual distinction between consciousness and awareness +as I am defining it. +A more interesting interpretation is to take these researchers to be talking +about consciousness in the phenomenal sense, and to note that all their +proposals are compatible with the overarching bridging principle of coherence between consciousness and awareness. Indeed, these hypotheses may +be derivable from the coherence principle, together with relevant empirical +results. Say we accept the coherence principle as a background assumption, +so we take it that experience is directly associated with direct availability +for global control. If empirical results suggest that in a particular species +(such as Homo sapiens), 40-hertz oscillations subserve global availability, +then we have reason to believe that the oscillations are a correlate of experience in that species. If results suggest that temporally extended activity +subserves global availability, then we have reason to believe that that sort +of activity is a correlate of experience. And so on. +Of course, more than one of these hypotheses might be correct. Perhaps +both oscillations and temporally extended activity subserve global availability in different instances, or perhaps they simultaneously play a role at +different stages of the access/control process. Perhaps the oscillations subserve high-quality representations in the global workspace. Those are empirical issues. But the hypotheses could also turn out to be false. Perhaps it will +turn out that the oscillations play no special role in global control, and instead +are involved only with peripheral operations. Perhaps they have only very +limited effects on later processes and on behavior. +What is notable is that if We had reason to believe that oscillations were +dissociated from awareness in this way, we would also have reason to believe +that they were dissociated from experience. If it turned out that oscillations +had no special relationship with reportability and awareness, for example, +the ground would be cut from under the correlation hypothesis. After all, +we do not have independent evidence for the hypothesis: all our evidence +comes from the link with reportability and awareness. Because we lack an +"experience meter," we must always rely on such indirect criteria, and the +criteria of reportability and awareness seem to be the best we can do. It +follows that we can only have empirical evidence for a link between a process +N and consciousness if we already have evidence for a link between N +and awareness. +This suggests a clear methodology for finding physical correlates of experience. Preexperimental considerations suggest that the basic processing +correlate of consciousness is awareness, or global availability. Empirical + + 240 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +results suggest that the physical states that play a role in awareness in a +given species are of a certain type N. The prior bridging principle and the +empirical results combine to suggest that in this species, N is a physical +correlate of consciousness. +(Interestingly, Dennett [1993b] suggests almost the same methodology. +He suggests that specific proposals about the basis of consciousness, such as +the oscillation proposal, are plausible precisely insofar as the relevant processes play a role in securing "cerebral celebrity". I can agree with almost +all of this, except that I require only potential cerebral celebrity, and I think +the link between consciousness and celebrity is a nomic principle rather than +a conceptual truth. Indeed, anyone empirically investigating consciousness +will need a nonempirical bridging principle to interpret physical results in +terms of conscious experience. For the reductionist this will be a conceptual +truth, and for the property dualist it will be a nomic principle based on firstperson considerations and plausible analysis. But many of the points I make +here apply either way.) +It seems natural to say that the central correlation between physical processing and experience is the coherence between consciousness and awareness. What gives rise directly to experience is not oscillations or temporally +extended activity or high-quality representations, but the process of direct +availability for global control. Any more specific physical state will qualify +as a correlate only insofar as it plays a role in global availability; so the more +specific correlations are derivative on the overarching correlation. +There may be many such correlates. Different types of physical process +may subserve availability in different modalities, for example. There may +also be different correlates at different stages of the processing path; even +taking visual experience alone, there may be one sort of correlate in the +visual cortex and another in areas further downstream. Of course, there is +no guarantee that even within a particular modality, there will be a neural +correlate of any simple type. Perhaps there will be no straightforward characterization of the processes in the visual cortex that subserve experience; it +might happen that they could be grouped together only by their functional +role (that is, by the fact that they subserve awareness). But we can at least +hope that there might be a more straightforward characterization to be +found: if not in the perceptual cortices, then perhaps at some later point on +the processing path. +We might also find correlates at levels higher than the neural. On constructing an appropriate cognitive or computational model, we might be able +to find some way of characterizing in information-processing terms those +entities that are responsible for awareness and that therefore underlie experience. Of course the simplest such characterization is tautologous—the +processes subserving awareness are those responsible for global access, control, and verbal report. But a substantial cognitive model might give us less + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +241 + +tautologous characterizations. Perhaps we might be able to characterize in +relatively local terms the type of information that turns out to play a significant global role, for example, given the overall design of the system. An +example is the suggestion of Shallice (1972) that the contents of consciousness +correspond to the contents of "selector inputs" to certain action systems. +According to the design of the model, the selector inputs determine which +action systems become "dominant," or play a role in global control. If so, +selector inputs facilitate awareness and are a plausible correlate of conscious experience. +Other information-processing correlates fall somewhere between the tautologous and the nontautologous. An example is Baars's global workspace. +We might define the global workspace as a kind of "virtual" area, corresponding precisely to those contents that are widely disseminated; if so the contents +of the workspace are the contents of awareness almost by definition. Baars's +model has more empirical bite than this: he proposes that the workspace is +a single unified system (one that we can localize at least in informationprocessing terms) in which information is integrated and disseminated. This +could turn out to be false, so the proposal has empirical substance that +experimental work might support or deny. But the characterization of the +workspace is still sufficiently close to the characterization of awareness to +explain the slight flavor of the a priori that the proposal retains; it sometimes +seems that almost any empirical results could be made compatible with such +a framework. (Of course Baars makes many more specific claims about the +operations of the workspace, and these claims carry significant empirical +substance.) Farah's "high-quality representation" proposal also has a slight +whiff of tautology, though it depends on how a high-quality representation +is defined: if to be a "high-quality" representation is just to be able to play +a significant global role, then the a priori flavor is strong, but if it is defined +in terms of the way that such a representation is formed, the flavor is +much weaker. +Even at the cognitive level, there is no special reason to believe that there +will be a single isolable mechanism that underlies experience. Schacter (1989) +suggests that there may be a single mechanism, such as a module, but this +is only one way things might go. It might turn out that a role in global control +is always facilitated by some central mechanism (such as Baars's global +workspace), but on the face of it, it is equally likely that processes of many +different kinds are responsible at different times for securing the appropriate +availability, even within a single species or a single subject. +Sometimes people want to draw stronger conclusions about physical correlates than I have suggested. For example, if we find that 40-hertz oscillations are the basis for experience in familiar cases, might we not hypothesize +that 40-hertz oscillations are the ultimate basis of experience? Perhaps those +oscillations give rise to experience even when they are not associated with + + 242 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +awareness, and perhaps well-functioning systems without the oscillations +might lack experience? Such a conclusion would be unjustified, however. +The 40-hertz oscillations were taken to be relevant because of their association with awareness; we have no reason to believe that when they do not +play that role, there is anything special about them. Certainly there is no +reason to believe that 40-hertz oscillations in a test-tube should give rise to +experiences like mine! And even in intermediate cases, such as those of +animals or anesthetized systems, it would be dangerous to infer anything +about experience from the presence of the oscillations, except insofar as the +presence of the oscillations gives us reason to believe that some sort of +awareness is present. +In general, we cannot expect these empirical methods to yield universal +psychophysical principles incompatible with those we started with. They can +yield more specific principles, applying within a given species, but these will +be derived by a direct application of preexisting bridging principles. Given +that the preexisting principles bear the entire burden in drawing conclusions +about experience from physical data, it is impossible for the data to support +a conclusion that contradicts the principles. +We should therefore not expect the search for a neural correlate of consciousness to lead to the holy grail of a universal theory. We might expect +it to be valuable in helping us to understand consciousness in specific cases, +such as the human case: learning more about the processes underlying awareness will certainly help us understand the structure and dynamics of consciousness, for example. But in holding up the bridge from physical processes +to conscious experience, preexperimental coherence principles will always +play a central role. + +5. Coherence as a Psychophysical Law +So far I have mostly considered coherence within a range of relatively familiar +cases, involving humans and other biological systems. But it is natural to +suppose that these principles of coherence may have the status of universal +laws. If consciousness is always accompanied by awareness, and vice versa, +in my own case and in the case of all humans, one is led to suspect that +something systematic is going on. There is certainly a lawlike correlation in +the familiar cases. We can therefore put forward the hypothesis that this +coherence is a law of nature: in any system, consciousness will be accompanied by awareness, and vice versa. The same goes for the full-blown principle +of structural coherence. The remarkable correlation between the structure +of consciousness and the structure of awareness seems too specific to be an +accident. It is natural to infer an underlying law: for any system, anywhere + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +243 + +in space-time, the structure of consciousness will mirror and be mirrored by +the structure of awareness. +Laws such as these would make a significant contribution to a theory of +consciousness. So far, all we know is that consciousness arises from the +physical somehow, but we do not know in virtue of what physical properties +it so arises; that is, we do not know what properties enter into the physical +side of the connection. Given the laws of coherence, we have a partial answer: +consciousness arises in virtue of the functional organization associated with +awareness. We can even arrive at a fairly specific understanding of parts of +the supervenience relation by virtue of the principle of structural coherence: +not only does consciousness arise from awareness, but the structure of consciousness is determined by the structure of awareness. +Of course this law will probably not be a fundamental psychophysical law. +Fundamental laws connect properties more basic or at least more cleanly +defined than a high-level construct such as "awareness." But not all laws +are fundamental laws. It may even be that the coherence principles are not +strict laws; there may be some exceptions around the edges, especially given +the underdetermined nature of the concept of awareness. But even if these +laws are neither fundamental nor strict, they nevertheless provide a strong +constraint that any fundamental psychophysical laws must satisfy. A proposed theory of consciousness that does not have the coherence principles +as a consequence will be in trouble. Conversely, if a proposed fundamental +psychophysical law is simple, well motivated, and has the coherence principles +as a consequence, then that may provide good reason to accept it. +What, then, are the grounds for accepting the coherence principles as +laws? The basic evidence comes from the correlations in familiar cases: +ultimately, for me, from my own case. The apparent correlations between +awareness and consciousness in my own case are so detailed and remarkable +that there must be something more than a mere chance regularity. There +must be some underlying law. The only question is what law? This law +must entail that in my own case, awareness will always be accompanied by +consciousness, and vice versa, and further that the structures of the two will +correspond. The principles of coherence I have put forward will do the job. +Might some different principle also suffice? +It is very plausible that some kind of awareness is necessary for consciousness. Certainly all the instances of consciousness that I know about are +accompanied by awareness. There seems to be little reason to believe in +any instances of consciousness without the accompanying functional processes. If there are any, we have no evidence for them, not even indirect +evidence, and we could not in principle. It therefore is reasonable to suppose +on the grounds of parsimony that wherever there is consciousness, there +is awareness. If we are wrong about this—if for example a static electron + + 244 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +has the rich conscious life of a Proust—then we will certainly never know +about it. +The question of the sufficiency of awareness is more difficult. Given the +necessity of awareness, any candidates for an underlying law will have the +form "Awareness plus something gives rise to consciousness." At least, any +underlying laws must entail a principle of this form, in order to explain the +regularities in my own case. The remaining question then, is: What is the +extra something, or is nothing extra required? +Call the hypothetical extra ingredient the X-factor. Either I am conscious +in virtue of awareness alone, or I am conscious in virtue of awareness and +the X-factor. The X-factor might consistently be any property, as long as it +is possessed by me now, and preferably throughout my life. Perhaps the Xfactor is a matter of nationality, and awareness gives rise to consciousness +only in Australians. Perhaps it is a matter of location, and awareness gives +rise to consciousness only within a hundred million miles of a star. Perhaps +it is a matter of identity, and awareness gives rise to consciousness only in +David Chalmers. +All of these laws would be compatible with my evidence, and would explain the correlation, so why do they all seem so unreasonable? It is because in each of these cases, the X-factor seems quite arbitrary. There is +no reason to believe that consciousness should depend on these things; they +seem to be irrelevant frills. It is not as if the X-factor plays a role in explaining +any of the phenomena associated with consciousness. At least awareness +might help explain our phenomenal judgments, which have a close tie to +consciousness, so there is some reason to believe in a connection there. By +contrast, each of these X-factors seems to appear out of nowhere. Why +would the universe be such that awareness gives rise to consciousness in one +person, and one person only? It would be a strange, arbitrary way for a +world to be. +The same goes for more "plausible" X-factors that someone might put +forward seriously. A natural candidate for such an X-factor is cell-based +biology, or even human neurophysiology. Certainly some people have supposed that consciousness is limited to beings with the right kind of biological +make-up. In a similar way, some have suggested that consciousness arises +from functional organization only when that organization is not implemented +in a "homunculi-headed" manner, as in the example of the Chinese nation. +But X-factors like these are equally arbitrary. They only complicate the laws +without any added compensation. Why should the world be set up so that +awareness gives rise to consciousness only in beings with a particular biology, or such that internal homunculi are ruled out? The hypotheses seem +baroque, with extraneous distractions built in. +Why might someone believe in an X-factor? I think such beliefs arise for +a natural but misleading reason. There is a basic intuition that consciousness + + The Coherence Between Consciousness and Cognition + +245 + +is something over and above functional organization. This is an intuition +that of course I share—consciousness is a further fact, for which no functional +organization is logically sufficient. There is also a natural tendency to believe +that everything is physical, and that consciousness must be physically explainable one way or another. Faced with these two pressures, there is a natural +reaction: we have to add something extra, and the extra something must be +physical. Human biology is a natural candidate for that extra ingredient. In +this way, it might be thought that we have bridged the gap from functional +organization to human biology. +But this is quite misguided. The addition of biology into the picture has +not helped the original problem at all. The gap is as large as ever: consciousness seems to be something over and above biology, too. As argued earlier, +no physical facts suffice to explain consciousness. The X-factor can do no +work for us; we are looking in the wrong place for a solution to our problem. +The problem was the assumption of materialism in the first place. Once we +accept that materialism is false, it becomes clear that the search for a physical +X-factor is irrelevant; instead, we have to look for a "Y-factor," something +additional to the physical facts that will help explain consciousness. We find +such a Y-factor in the postulation of irreducible psychophysical laws. Once +we have imported these into our framework, the intuition that consciousness +is a further fact is preserved, and the problem is removed. +The desire for a physical X-factor is a holdover from the attempt to have +one's materialist cake and eat one's consciousness too. Once we recognize +that consciousness is a further nonphysical fact and that there are independent psychophysical laws, the X-factor becomes quite redundant. To ask for +an independent psychophysical connection and an X-factor is to ask for two +gifts when we only need one. +The X-factor therefore has no explanatory role to play in a theory of +consciousness, and only complicates the story. Any such factor only makes +the fundamental laws more complex than they need to be. Given the simplicity of the picture in which awareness gives rise to consciousness, a universe +in which consciousness depends on a separate X-factor begins to look like +an unreasonable place. One might as well have a clause in Newton's laws +saying every action has an equal and opposite reaction unless the objects +involved are made of gold. Principles of simplicity dictate that the best +hypothesis is that no X-factor is required, and that awareness gives rise to +consciousness without qualifications. +Some people will still be unsure about the functionalist conclusion that I +have reached, even if it is a dualist version of functionalism. It is true that +the argument from X-factors is somewhat tentative and relies strongly on +simplicity assumptions. I will give more concrete arguments for the same +conclusion in the next chapter, using thought experiments to make the case +that a functional replica of a conscious being will have precisely the same + + 246 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +kind of conscious experience. But for now I note that these considerations +at least provide a strong prima facie case for this sort of functionalism. +It is worthwhile taking a moment to grasp the overall epistemological +framework. What we have here is essentially an inference to the best explanation. We note remarkable regularities between consciousness and awareness +in our own case, and postulate the simplest possible underlying law. This is +the same sort of reasoning that goes on in formulating physical theories, +and even in combating skeptical hypotheses about causation and about the +external world. In all these cases, the underlying assumption is that the world +is a simple and reasonable place. Failing such an assumption, anything goes. +With such an assumption, things fall into place. +It also seems that this is as good a solution to the problem of other minds +as we are going to get. We note regularities between experience and physical +or functional states in our own case, postulate simple and homogeneous +underlying laws to explain them, and use those laws to infer the existence +of consciousness in others. This may or may not be the reasoning that we +implicitly use in believing that others are conscious, but in any case it seems +to provide a reasonable justification for our beliefs. +It is interesting to speculate on just what our principles of coherence imply +for the existence of consciousness outside the human race, and in particular +in much simpler organisms.The matter is unclear, as our notion of awareness +is only clearly defined for cases approximating human complexity. It seems +reasonable to say that a dog is aware, and even that a mouse is aware +(perhaps they are not self-aware, but that is a different matter). For example, +it seems reasonable to say that a dog is aware of a fire hydrant in the basic +sense of the term "aware." The dog's control systems certainly have access +to information about the hydrant, and can use it to control behavior appropriately. By the coherence principle, it seems likely that the dog experiences +the hydrant, in a way not unlike our visual experience of the world. This +squares with common sense; all I am doing here is making the commonsense reasoning a little more explicit. +The same is arguably true for mice and even for flies. Flies have some +limited perceptual access to environmental information, and their perceptual contents presumably permeate their cognitive systems and are available +to direct behavior. It seems reasonable to suppose that this qualifies as +awareness, and that by the coherence principle there is some kind of accompanying experience. Around here the matter gets tricky. It is tempting to extend +the coherence further down the information-processing scale; but sooner or +later, the notion of "awareness" gives out on us and can do no explanatory +work, due to its indeterminacy. I will not speculate further on this matter +for now, but I return to it later. + + 7 + +Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, +Dancing Qualia + +1. The Principle of Organizational Invariance +If consciousness arises from the physical, in virtue of what sort of physical +properties does it arise? Presumably these will be properties that brains can +instantiate, but it is not obvious just which properties are the right ones. +Some have suggested biochemical properties; some have suggested quantum +properties; many have professed uncertainty. A natural suggestion is that +consciousness arises in virtue of the functional organization of the brain. On +this view, the chemical and indeed the quantum substrate of the brain is +irrelevant to the production of consciousness. What counts is the brain's +abstract causal organization, an organization that might be realized in many +different physical substrates. +Functional organization is best understood as the abstract pattern of causal +interaction between various parts of a system, and perhaps between these +parts and external inputs and outputs. A functional organization is determined by specifying (1) a number of abstract components, (2) for each +component, a number of different possible states, and (3) a system of dependency relations, specifying how the state of each component depends on +previous states of all components and on inputs to the system, and how +outputs from the system depend on previous component states. Beyond +specifying their number and their dependency relations, the nature of the +components and the states is left unspecified. +A physical system realizes a given functional organization when the system +can be divided into an appropriate number of physical components each +with the appropriate number of states, such that the causal dependency +relations among the components of the system, inputs, and outputs precisely + + 248 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +reflect the dependency relations given in the specification of the functional +organization. (A more formal account along these lines is given in Chalmers +[1994a, 1994b] and is summarized in Chapter 9, but the informal understanding will suffice for now.) +A given functional organization can be realized by diverse physical systems. For example, the organization realized by the brain at the neural level +might in principle be realized by a silicon system. A description of the +brain's functional organization abstracts away from the physical nature of +the parts involved, and from the way that the causal connections are implemented. All that counts is the existence of the parts, and the dependency +relations between their states. +A physical system has functional organization at many different levels, +depending on how finely we individuate its parts and on how finely we divide +the states of those parts. At a coarse level, for instance, it is likely that the +two hemispheres of the brain can be seen as realizing a simple two-component organization, if we choose appropriate interdependent states of the +hemispheres. It is generally more useful to view cognitive systems at a finer +level, however. If we are interested in cognition, we will usually focus on a +level fine enough to determine the behavioral capacities associated with the +brain, where behavior is individuated to some appropriate level of precision. +Organization at too coarse a level (e.g., the two-component organization +above) will fall far short of determining behavioral capacities, as the mechanisms that drive behavior will fall between the cracks of this description; a +simple system might share the organization without sharing the behavior. +At a fine enough level, though—perhaps the neural level—functional organization will determine behavioral capacities. Even if our neurons were replaced with silicon chips, then as long as these chips had states with the same +pattern of causal interactions as we find in the neurons, the system would +produce the same behavior. +In what follows, the relevant sort of functional organization of a system +will always be at a level fine enough to determine behavioral capacities. Call +such an organization a fine-grained functional organization. For the purposes +of illustration, I will usually focus on the neural level of organization in the +brain, although a higher level might suffice, and it is not impossible that a +lower level could be required. In any case, the arguments generalize. For +the purposes of what follows, we need also stipulate that for two systems to +share their functional organization, they must be in corresponding states at +the relevant times; although my sleeping twin might count as sharing my +organization in a broad sense, he will not count in the strict sense required +below. When two systems share their functional organization in this strict +sense, I will say that they are functional isomorphs. +I claim that conscious experience arises from fine-grained functional organization. More specifically, I will argue for a principle of organizational + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +249 + +invariance, holding that given any system that has conscious experiences, +then any system that has the same fine-grained functional organization will +have qualitatively identical experiences. According to this principle, consciousness is an organizational invariant: a property that remains constant +over all functional isomorphs of a given system. Whether the organization +is realized in silicon chips, in the population of China, or in beer cans and +ping-pong balls does not matter. As long as the functional organization is +right, conscious experience will be determined. +This thesis has often been associated with a reductive functionalist view +about consciousness, such as the view that all it is to be conscious is to be +in the appropriate functional state. From such a view the invariance principle +would naturally follow, but the invariance principle can be held independently. Just as one can believe that consciousness arises from a physical +system but is not a physical state, one can believe that consciousness arises +from functional organization but is not a functional state. The view that I +advocate has this form—we might call it nonreductive functionalism. It might +be seen as a way of combining functionalism and property dualism. +I will not be especially concerned with the nonreductive aspects of my +view below, being mostly concerned to argue for the invariance principle. +My arguments might even be embraced by reductive functionalists. While +the arguments do not establish the full reductive conclusion, they nevertheless can be seen as supporting that position against other reductive views, +such as a view on which consciousness is equated with a biochemical property. +Of course I think that all reductive views ultimately fail, but the following +discussion will be largely independent of that issue. +I have already argued for a version of the invariance principle, in effect, +with the "X-factor" argument of Chapter 6. In this chapter, however, I will +use thought experiments to argue for the principle in a much more direct way. +Absent qualia and inverted qualm +The invariance principle is far from universally accepted. Many people of +both dualist and materialist persuasions have argued against it. Many have +held that for a system to be conscious, it must have the right sort of biochemical makeup; if so, a metallic robot or a silicon-based computer could never +have experiences, no matter what their causal organization. Others have +conceded that a robot or a computer might be conscious if it were organized +appropriately, but have held that it might nevertheless have experiences +quite different from ours. +Corresponding to these two views, there have generally been two kinds +of argument against the invariance principle. The first kind comprises arguments from absent qualia. In these arguments, a particularly bizarre realization of a given functional organization is described, in a system so outlandish + + 250 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +that it is natural to suppose that the qualities (qualia) of conscious experience must be absent. A popular example from Block (1978) is a case in +which our organization is realized in the population of a country (as in +Chapter 3). Surely, it is argued, that could not give rise to conscious experience. If not, then consciousness cannot arise from functional organization. +The second class of arguments includes those from inverted qualia, or the +inverted spectrum. According to these arguments, if our functional organization were realized in a different physical substrate, a system might still have +experience, but it would have a different kind of experience. Where we have +red experiences, it might have blue experiences, and so on. Often these +arguments are made via complex scenarios that appeal to brain surgery, in +which we wake up one morning seeing blue instead of red even though our +functional organization is unchanged. +Many of those arguing for the possibility of absent and inverted qualia +have been arguing only for logical possibility; this is all that is required to +refute a reductive form of functionalism. Indeed, I have used such arguments +myself, in Chapter 3. These proponents are not subject to the counterarguments in this chapter. What is at issue here is a weaker form of functionalism, +one which does not turn on questions of logical possibility. +The key question in this chapter is whether absent or inverted qualia are +naturally (or empirically) possible. It is logically possible that a plate may +fly upward when one lets go of it in a vacuum on a planetary surface, but +it is nevertheless naturally impossible. The laws of nature forbid it. In a +similar way, establishing the logical possibility of absent qualia and inverted +qualia falls far short of establishing their natural possibility. The invariance +principle holds that functional organization determines conscious experience +by some lawful link in the actual world; here, matters of logical possibility +are irrelevant. In this chapter, whenever "possibility" is used alone, it is +natural possibility that is intended. +In what follows, I will discuss arguments that have been put forward in +favor of the natural possibility of absent and inverted qualia, and will then +offer detailed arguments against those possibilities. These arguments will +crucially involve thought experiments. Against the possibility of absent qualia, I will offer a thought experiment concerning fading qualia. Against the +possibility of inverted qualia, I will offer a thought experiment concerning +dancing qualia. +These arguments from thought experiments are only plausibility arguments, as always, but I think they have considerable force. To maintain the +natural possibility of absent and inverted qualia in the face of these +thought experiments requires accepting some implausible theses about the +nature of conscious experience, and in particular about the relationship +between consciousness and cognition. Given certain natural assumptions + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +251 + +about this relationship, the invariance principle is established as by far the +most plausible hypothesis. +Perhaps it is useful to see these thought experiments as playing a role +analogous to that played by the "Schrodinger's cat" thought experiment in +the interpretation of quantum mechanics. Schrodinger's thought experiment +does not deliver a decisive verdict in favor of one interpretation or another, +but it brings out various plausibilities and implausibilities in the interpretations, and it is something that every interpretation must ultimately come to +grips with. In a similar way, any theory of consciousness must ultimately +come to grips with the fading and dancing qualia scenarios, and some will +handle them better than others. In this way, the virtues and drawbacks of +various theories are clarified. + +2. Absent Qualia +Positive arguments for the natural possibility of absent qualia have not been +as prevalent as arguments for inverted qualia, but they have been made. +The most detailed presentation of these arguments is given by Block (1978). +These arguments almost always have the same form. They consist in the +exhibition of a realization of our functional organization in some unusual +medium, combined with an appeal to intuition. It is pointed out, for example, +that the organization of our brain might be simulated by the people of China +or even mirrored in the economy of Bolivia. If we got every person in China +to simulate a neuron (we would need to multiply the population by ten or +one hundred, but no matter), and equipped them with radio links to simulate +synaptic connections, then the functional organization would be there. But +surely, says the argument, this baroque system would not be conscious +There is a certain intuitive force to this argument. Many people have a +strong feeling that a system like this is simply the wrong sort of thing to +have a conscious experience. Such a "group mind" would seem to be the +stuff of a science-fiction tale, rather than the kind of thing that could really +exist. But there is only an intuitive force. This certainly falls far short of a +knockdown argument. Many have pointed out1 that while it may be intuitively +implausible that such a system should give rise to experience, it is equally +intuitively implausible that a brain should give rise to experience! Whoever +would have thought that this hunk of gray matter would be the sort of thing +that could produce vivid subjective experiences? And yet it does. Of course +this does not show that a nation's population could produce a mind, but it +is a strong counter to the intuitive argument that it would not. +Of course, we would not see any conscious experience in such a system. +But this is nothing new; we do not see conscious experience in anyone. It +might seem that there is no "room" for conscious experience in such a + + 252 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +system, but again the same appears to be true of the brain. Thirdly, we might +explain the functioning of the system without invoking conscious experience, +but again this is familiar in the standard case. Once we absorb the true force +of the failure of logical supervenience, it begins to seem no more surprising +that the population of a country could give rise to conscious experience than +that a brain could do so.2 +Some have objected to the invariance principle on the grounds that the +functional organization might arise by chance, in the Bolivian economy or +even in a pail (Hinckfuss, quoted in Lycan 1987, p.32). But this could only +happen by the most outrageous coincidence.3 The system would need to +have over a billion parts each with a number of states of its own (say, ten +each). Between these states there would have to be a vast, intricate system +of just the right causal connections, so that given this state pattern, then this +state pattern will result, given that state pattern, then that state pattern will +result, and so on. To realize the functional organization in question, these +conditionals cannot be mere regularities (where this state pattern happens +to be followed by that state pattern on this occasion); they have to be reliable, +counterfactual-supporting connections, such that this state pattern will be +followed by that state pattern whenever it comes up.4 +It is not hard to see that about 10109 such conditionals will be required of +a system in order that it realize the appropriate functional organization, if +we suppose a division into a billion parts. The chance that these conditionals +could be satisfied by an arbitrary system under a given division into parts +and states will be on the order of 1 in (10109)10109 (actually much less, as the +requirement that each conditional be reliable further reduces the chance +that it will be satisfied).5 Even given the freedom we have in dividing a +system into parts, it is extraordinarily unlikely that such organization would +be realized by an arbitrary system, or indeed by any system that was not +shaped by the highly nonarbitrary mechanisms of natural selection. +Once we realize how tightly a specification of functional organization +constrains the structure of a system, it becomes less implausible that even +the population of China could support conscious experience if organized +appropriately. If we take our image of the population, speed it up by a factor +of a million or so, and shrink it into an area the size of a head, we are left +with something that looks a lot like a brain, except that it has homunculi—tiny +people—where a brain would have neurons. On the face of it, there is not +much reason to suppose that neurons should do any better a job than homunculi in supporting experience. +Of course, as Block points out, we know that neurons can do the job, +whereas we do not know about homunculi. The issue therefore remains +open. The important point is that this sort of argument provides only very +weak evidence that absent qualia are naturally impossible. A more compelling argument is required to settle the matter one way or the other. Perhaps + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +253 + +it is correct to say, as Block does, that our intuitions throw the burden of +proof onto one who holds that qualia are organizationally invariant, although +this is not clear to me. In any case, I will take up that burden in what follows. +A separate argument that is sometimes put forward for the natural possibility of absent qualia stems from the phenomenon of blindsight. It is argued +that blindsight patients are functionally similar to us in relevant ways—they +can discriminate, report contents, and so on—but that they lack visual experience. Therefore the functional organization of visual processing does not +determine the presence or absence of experience. +We have seen in Chapter 6 that there is a significant difference between +processing in normal subjects and those with blindsight, however. These +subjects lack the usual kind of direct access to visual information. If the +information is accessible at all, the access is indirect, and the information is +certainly not available for the control of behavior in the usual way. Indeed, +it is precisely because of the difference in the organization of their processing, as manifested in their behavior, that we notice anything unusual in the +first place and are led to postulate the absence of experience. These cases +therefore provide no evidence against the invariance principle. + +3. Fading Qualia +My positive argument against the possibility of absent qualia will be based +on a thought experiment involving the gradual replacement of parts of a +brain, perhaps by silicon chips. Such thought experiments have been a popular response to absent qualia arguments in the folk tradition of artificial +intelligence and sometimes in print. The gradual-replacement scenario is +canvased by Pylyshyn (1980), although without a systematic accompanying +argument. Arguments not unlike the one I am about to give have been +put forward by Savitt (1982) and Cuda (1985), although they develop the +arguments in different ways and draw slightly different morals from the +scenario.6 +This "fading qualia" argument will not be my strongest and most central +argument against the possibility of absent qualia; that role is played by the +"dancing qualia" argument, to be outlined in section 5, which also provides +an argument against the possibility of inverted qualia. However, the fading +qualia argument is strong in itself, and provides good motivation and background for the more powerful second argument. +The argument takes the form of a reductio ad absurdum. Assume that +absent qualia are naturally possible. Then there could be a system with +the same functional organization as a conscious system (say, me), but which +lacks conscious experience entirely. Without loss of generality, assume that +this is because the system is made of silicon chips instead of neurons. I will + + 254 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +show how the argument can be extended to other kinds of isomorphs later. +Call this functional isomorph Robot. The causal patterns in Robot's cognitive system are the same as they are in mine, but he has the consciousness +of a zombie. +Given this situation, we can construct a series of cases intermediate between me and Robot such that there is only a very small change at each +step and such that functional organization is preserved throughout. We can +imagine, for instance, replacing a certain number of my neurons by silicon +chips. In the first such case, only a single neuron is replaced. Its replacement +is a silicon chip that performs precisely the same local function as the neuron. +Where the neuron is connected to other neurons, the chip is connected to +the same neurons. Where the state of the neuron is sensitive to electrical +inputs and chemical signals, the silicon chip is sensitive to the same. We +might imagine that it comes equipped with tiny transducers that take in +electrical signals and chemical ions, relaying a digital signal to the rest of +the chip. Where the neuron produces electrical and chemical outputs, the +chip does the same (we can imagine it equipped with tiny effectors that +produce electrical and chemical outputs depending on the internal state of +the chip). Importantly, the internal states of the chip are such that the input/ +output function of the chip is precisely the same as that of the neuron. It +does not matter how the chip does this—perhaps it uses a look-up table that +associates each input with the appropriate output, perhaps it performs a +computation that simulates the processes inside a neuron—as long as it gets +the input-output dependencies right. If local interactions are correct, then +the replacement will make no difference to the overall function of the +system. +In the second case, we replace two neurons with silicon chips. It will be +easiest to suppose that they are neighboring neurons. In this way, once both +are replaced we can dispense with the awkward transducers and effectors +that mediate the connection between the two chips. We can replace these +by any kind of connection we like, as long as it is sensitive to the internal +state of the first chip and affects the internal state of the second chip appropriately (there may be a connection in each direction, of course). Here we +ensure that the connection is a copy of the corresponding connection in +Robot; perhaps this will be an electronic signal of some kind. +Later cases proceed in the obvious fashion. In each succeeding case a +larger group of neighboring neurons has been replaced by silicon chips. +Within this group of chips, the biochemical substrate has been dispensed +with entirely. Biochemical mechanisms are present only in the rest of the +system, and in the connection between chips at the border of the group and +neighboring neurons. In the final case, every neuron in the system has +been replaced by a chip, and there are no biochemical mechanisms playing an essential role. (I abstract away here from detailed issues concerning + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +255 + +whether, for instance, glial cells play a nontrivial role; if they do, they will +be components of the appropriate functional organization, and will be replaced also.) +We can imagine that throughout, the internal system is connected to a +body, is sensitive to bodily inputs, and produces motor movements in an +appropriate way, via transducers and effectors. Each system in the sequence +will be functionally isomorphic to me at a fine enough grain to share my +behavioral dispositions. But while the system at one end of the spectrum is +me, the system at the other end is essentially a copy of Robot. +To fix imagery, imagine that as the first system I am having rich conscious +experiences. Perhaps I am at a basketball game, surrounded by shouting +fans, with all sorts of brightly colored clothes in my environment, smelling +the delicious aroma of junk food, perhaps suffering from a throbbing headache, and so on. Let us focus in particular on the bright red and yellow +experiences I am having from watching the players' uniforms. The final +system, Robot, is in the same situation, processing the same inputs and +producing similar behavior, but by hypothesis is experiencing nothing at all. +Between me and Robot, there will be many intermediate cases. Question: +What is it like to be them? What, if anything, are they experiencing? As we +move along the spectrum, how does conscious experience vary? Presumably +the very early cases have experiences much like mine, and the very late cases +have little or no experience, but what of the intermediate cases? +Given that the system at the other end of the spectrum (Robot) is not +conscious, it seems that one of two things must happen along the way. Either +(1) consciousness gradually fades over the series of cases, before eventually +disappearing, or (2) somewhere along the way consciousness suddenly blinks +out, although the preceding case had rich conscious experiences. Call the +first possibility fading qualia and the second suddenly disappearing qualia. +It is not difficult to rule out suddenly disappearing qualia. On this hypothesis, the replacement of a single neuron (leaving everything else constant) +could be responsible for the vanishing of an entire field of conscious experience. This seems extremely implausible, if not entirely bizarre. If this were +possible, there would be brute discontinuities in the laws of nature unlike +those we find anywhere else. Any specific point for qualia to suddenly disappear (50 percent neural? 25 percent?) would be entirely arbitrary. We can +even imagine running the thought experiment at a finer grain within the +neuron, so that ultimately the replacement of a few molecules causes a whole +field of experience to vanish (if not, we revert to the fading qualia scenario). +As always in these matters, the hypothesis cannot be disproved, but its antecedent plausibility is low. +(One might argue that there are situations in nonlinear dynamics in which +one magnitude depends sensitively on another, with large changes in the first +arising from small changes in the second. But in these cases the dependence + + 256 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +is nevertheless continuous, so there will be intermediate cases in which the +dependent magnitude takes on intermediate values; the analogy therefore +leads to fading qualia. And in any case, the sensitive dependence in these +cases generally arises from the compound effects of a number of more basic +gradual dependencies. In all fundamental laws known to date, the dependence of one magnitude on another continuous magnitude is continuous in +this fashion, and there is no way to compound continuity into discontinuity. +Suddenly disappearing qualia, in contrast to nonlinear dynamics, would require brute discontinuities in fundamental laws.) +If suddenly disappearing qualia are ruled out, we are left with fading +qualia. To get a fix on this scenario, consider a system halfway along the +spectrum between me and Robot, after consciousness has degraded considerably but before it has gone altogether. Call this system Joe. What is it like +to be Joe? Joe, of course, is functionally isomorphic to me. He says all the +same things about his experiences as I do about mine. At the basketball +game, he exclaims about the glaring bright red-and-yellow uniforms of the +basketball players. +By hypothesis, though, Joe is not having bright red and yellow experiences +at all. Instead, perhaps he is experiencing tepid pink and murky brown. +Perhaps he is having the faintest of red and yellow experiences. Perhaps his +experiences have darkened almost to black. There are various conceivable +ways in which red experiences might gradually transmute to no experience +at all, and probably even more ways that we cannot conceive. But presumably in each of these the experiences must stop being bright before they +vanish (otherwise we are left with the problem of the suddenly disappearing +qualia). Similarly, there is presumably a point at which subtle distinctions +in my experience are no longer present in an intermediate system's experience; if we are to suppose that all the distinctions in my experience are +present right up until a moment when they simultaneously vanish, we are +left with another version of suddenly disappearing qualia. +For specificity, then, imagine that Joe sees a faded pink where I see bright +red, with many distinctions between shades of my experience no longer +present in shades of his experience. Where I am having loud noise experiences, perhaps Joe is experiencing only a distant rumble. Not everything is +so bad for Joe: where I have a throbbing headache, he only has the mildest twinge. +The crucial feature here is that Joe is systematically wrong about everything +that he is experiencing. He certainly says that he is having bright red and +yellow experiences, but he is merely experiencing tepid pink.7 If you ask +him, he will claim to be experiencing all sorts of subtly different shades of +red, but in fact many of these are quite homogeneous in his experience. He +may even complain about the noise, when his auditory experience is really +very mild. Worse, on a functional construal of belief, Joe will even believe + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +257 + +that he has all these complex experiences that he in fact lacks. In short, Joe +is utterly out of touch with his conscious experience, and is incapable of +getting in touch. +This seems to be quite implausible. Here we have a being whose rational +processes are functioning and who is in fact conscious, but who is utterly +wrong about his own conscious experiences. Perhaps in the extreme case, +when all is dark inside, it might be reasonable to suppose that a system could +be so misguided in its claims and judgments—after all, in a sense there is +nobody in there to be wrong. But in the intermediate case, this is much less +plausible. In every case with which we are familiar, conscious beings are +generally capable of forming accurate judgments about their experience, in +the absence of distraction and irrationality. For a sentient, rational being that is suffering from no functional pathology to be so systematically +out of touch with its experiences would imply a strong dissociation between consciousness and cognition. We have little reason to believe that +consciousness is such an ill-behaved phenomenon, and good reason to believe +otherwise. +To be sure, fading qualia are logically possible. There is no contradiction +in the description of a system that is so wrong about its experiences.8 But +logical possibility and natural possibility are different things. We have no +reason to believe that this sort of case could happen in practice, and every +reason to believe otherwise. One of the most salient empirical facts about +consciousness seems to be that when a conscious being with the appropriate +conceptual sophistication has experiences, it is capable of forming judgments about those experiences. Perhaps there are unusual cases where the +rational processes in a system are strongly impaired, leading to a malfunction in the mechanisms of judgment, but this is not such a case. Joe's processes are functioning as well as mine—by hypothesis, he is functionally isomorphic. It is just that he happens to be completely misguided about his +experience. +There are various cases of fading qualia in everyday life, of course. Think +of what happens when one is dropping off to sleep; or think of moving back +along the evolutionary chain from people to trilobites. In each case, as we +move along a spectrum of cases, conscious experience gradually fades away. +But in each of these cases, the fading is accompanied by a corresponding +change in functioning. When I become drowsy, I do not believe that I am +wide awake and having intense experiences (unless perhaps I start to dream, +in which case I very likely am having intense experiences). The lack of +richness in a dog's experience of color accompanies a corresponding lack of +discriminatory power in a dog's visual mechanisms. These cases are quite +unlike the case under consideration, in which experience fades while functioning stays constant. Joe's mechanisms can still discriminate subtly different wavelengths of light, and he certainly judges that such discriminations + + 258 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +are reflected in his experience, but we are to believe that his experience +does not reflect these discriminations at all. +Searle (1992) discusses a thought experiment like this one, and suggests +the following possibility: +[A]s the silicon is progressively implanted into your dwindling brain, you find +that the area of your conscious experience is shrinking, but that this shows no +effect on your external behavior. You find, to your total amazement, that you +are indeed losing control of your external behavior. You find, for example, that +when the doctors test your vision, you hear them say, "We are holding up a +red object in front of you; please tell us what you see." You want to cry out, +"I can't see anything. I'm going totally blind." But you hear your voice saying +in a way that is completely out of your control, "I see a red object in front of +me." If we carry the thought-experiment out to the limit, we get a much more +depressing result than last time. We imagine that your conscious experience +slowly shrinks to nothing, while your externally observable behavior remains +the same. (pp. 66-67) + +Here, Searle embraces the possibility of fading qualia, but suggests that +such a system need not be mistaken in its beliefs about its experience. The +system might have true beliefs about its experience; it is just that these beliefs +are impotent to affect its behavior. +It seems that this possibility can be ruled out, however. There is simply +no room in the system for any new beliefs to be formed. Unless one is a +dualist of a very strong variety, this sort of difference in belief must be +reflected in the functioning of a system—perhaps not in behavior, but at +least in some process. But this system is identical to the original system (me) +at a fine grain. There is simply no room for new beliefs such as "I can't see +anything," new desires such as the desire to cry out, and other new cognitive +states such as amazement. Nothing in the physical system can correspond to +that amazement. There is no room for it in the neurons, which after all are +identical to a subset of the neurons supporting the usual beliefs; and Searle +is surely not suggesting that the silicon replacement is itself supporting the +new beliefs! Failing a remarkable, magical interaction effect between neurons and silicon—and one that does not manifest itself anywhere in processing, as organization is preserved throughout—such new beliefs will not arise. +An organization-preserving change from neurons to silicon simply does +not change enough to effect such a remarkable change in the content and +structure of one's cognitive states. A twist in experience from red to blue is +one thing, but a change in beliefs from "Nice basketball game" to "Oh no! +I seem to be stuck in a bad horror movie!" is of a different order of magnitude. If such a major change in cognitive contents were not mirrored in a +change in functional organization, cognition would float free of internal +functioning like a disembodied Cartesian mind. If the contents of cognitive +states supervened on physical states at all, they could do so only by the most + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +259 + +arbitrary and capricious of rules (if this organization in neurons, then "Pretty +colors!"; if this organization in silicon, then "Alas!"). +It follows that the possibility of fading qualia requires either a bizarre +relationship between belief contents and physical states, or the possibility +of beings that are massively mistaken about their own conscious experiences +despite being fully rational. Both of these hypotheses are significantly less +plausible than the hypothesis that rational conscious beings are generally +correct in their judgments about their experiences. A much more reasonable +hypothesis is therefore that when neurons are replaced, qualia do not fade +at all. A system like Joe, in practice, will have conscious experiences just as +rich as mine. If so, then our original assumption was wrong, and the original +isomorph, Robot, has conscious experiences. +The argument can be straightforwardly extended to other functional isomorphs. To deal with the case where the population of a country implements +my organization, we can construct a similar spectrum of cases between my +silicon isomorph and the population. Perhaps we first gradually expand the +silicon system until it is many square miles across. We also slow it down so +that the chips are receiving inputs at a manageable rate. After doing this, +we get people to step in one at a time for the chips, making sure that they +set off outputs appropriately in response to inputs. Eventually, we will be +left with a case where the entire population is organized as my neurons +were, perhaps even controlling a body by radio links. At every stage, the +system will be functionally isomorphic to me, and precisely the same arguments apply. Either conscious experience will be preserved, or it will fade, +or it will suddenly disappear. The latter two possibilities are just as implausible as before. We can conclude that the population system will support +conscious experiences, just as a brain does. +We can do the same thing for any functionally isomorphic system, including +those that differ in shape, size, speed, physical makeup, and so on. In all +cases, the conclusion is the same. If such a system is not conscious, then +there exists an intermediate isomorphic system that is conscious, has faded +experiences, and is completely wrong about its experiences. Unless we are +prepared to accept this massive dissociation between consciousness and cognition, the original system must have been conscious after all. +If absent qualia are possible, then fading qualia are possible. But I have +argued above that fading qualia are almost certainly impossible. It follows +that absent qualia are almost certainly impossible. +I will now deal with various objections to the argument. +Objection 1: Neural replacement would be impossible in practice +Those of a practical bent might not be impressed by this thought-experimental methodology. They might object that replacing neurons by silicon chips + + 260 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +is the stuff of science fiction, not the stuff of reality. In particular, they might +object that this sort of replacement would be impossible in practice, so that +any conclusions that can be drawn do not reflect the realities of the situation. +If this is just supposed to be a technological impossibility, it is not much +of a problem.What is at issue here is what kind of experience such systems +would have //they existed, whether or not we can actually construct such a +system. Natural impossibility might be relevant, though. Perhaps silicon simply lacks the capacity to perform the functions in the brain that a neuron +performs, so that no silicon chip could be up to the task. It is not clear that +there is a principled basis for this objection; we already have prosthetic arms +and legs, and prosthetic eyes are on the way, so why not prosthetic neurons? +In any case, even if a silicon functional isomorph were impossible (perhaps +because neural function is uncomputable?), the argument for the invariance +principle would not be affected. The invariance principle says only that if +there is a functional isomorph of a conscious system, then it will have the +same sort of conscious experiences. If silicon isomorphs are impossible, the +assessment of silicon systems is simply irrelevant here. +An opponent might try to focus on problems with the silicon/neuron +interface, in which case the pure neural system and the pure silicon system +might both be quite possible, but intermediate systems would be challenged. +Perhaps there just would not be enough room for the transducers and effectors in the tiny space a chip has available? After all, the effectors may +have to store a reservoir of chemicals in order that they can be emitted when +necessary. But we only need a small reservoir; the argument only requires +isomorphism for a few seconds! And we could always run the thought experiment by supposing an expansion of the system. In any case, it is hard to +see how this sort of point could support a deep, principled objection to +the invariance principle. There will presumably be some systems between +which gradual replacement is possible; will an objector argue that the invariance principle holds for those systems, but no other? If so, the situation +seems quite arbitrary; if not, then there must be a deeper objection available. +Objection 2: Some systems are massively mistaken +about their experience +This objection notes that there are actual cases in which subjects are seriously +mistaken about their experiences. In cases of blindness denial, for example, +subjects believe that they are having visual experiences when they likely +have none. In these cases, however, we are no longer dealing with fully +rational systems. In systems whose belief formation mechanisms are im- + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +261 + +paired, anything goes. Such systems might believe that they are Napoleon, +or that the moon is pink. My "faded" isomorph Joe, by contrast, is a fully +rational system, whose cognitive mechanisms are functioning just as well as +mine. In conversation, he seems perfectly sensible. We cannot point to any +unusually poor inferential connections between his beliefs, or any systematic +psychiatric disorder that is leading his thought processes to be biased toward +faulty reasoning. Joe is an eminently thoughtful, reasonable person, who +exhibits none of the confabulatory symptoms of those with blindness denial. +The cases are therefore disanalogous. The plausible claim is not that no system can be massively mistaken about its experiences, but that no rational +system whose cognitive mechanisms are unimpaired can be so mistaken. Joe +is certainly a rational system whose mechanisms are working as well as mine, +so the argument is unaffected. +Objection 3: Sorites arguments are suspect +Some object that this argument has the form of a Sorites or "slippery-slope" +argument, and observe that such arguments are usually suspect. Using a +Sorites argument, we can "show" that even a grain of sand is a heap; after +all, a million grains of sand form a heap, and if we take a single grain away +from a heap we still have a heap. This reaction is based on a superficial +reading of the argument, however. Sorites arguments generally gain their +leverage by ignoring the fact that some apparent dichotomy is in fact a +continuum: there are all sorts of vague cases between heaps and nonheaps, +for example. My argument, by contrast, explicitly accepts the possibility of +a continuum, but argues that the intermediate cases are impossible for independent reasons. +The argument would be a Sorites if it had the form: I am conscious; if +you replace one neuron in a conscious system by a silicon chip it will still +be conscious; therefore an all-silicon system will be conscious. But this is +not its form. It is true that the argument against suddenly disappearing qualia +relies on the impossibility of a sudden transition, but importantly it argues +against sudden large transitions, from rich conscious experiences to none at +all. This is implausible for reasons quite independent of Sorites considerations.9 +Objection 4: Similar arguments could +establish behavioral invariance +A fourth objection suggests that the argument proves too much. If it establishes the principle of organizational invariance, a similar argument would + + 262 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +establish a principle of behavioral invariance. To do this, we would construct +a continuum of cases from me to any behaviorally equivalent system. It +would follow by similar reasoning that such a system must be conscious. But +it is plausible that some systems, such as Block's (1981) giant look-up table +that stores outputs for every pattern of inputs, are not conscious. Therefore +there must be a flaw in the argument. +This objection fails in two ways. First, my argument relied partly on the fact +that a functionally isomorphic system will have the same cognitive structure as +me, and in particular the same judgments. This is what led us to the conclusion +that the faded system Joe must be massively wrong in its judgments. The +corresponding point does not hold for behaviorally equivalent systems. A +perfect actor need not have the same judgments as me. Nor will the lookup table; nor will intermediate systems. These will work by quite different +mechanisms. +Second, it is not at all obvious how one could get from me to an arbitrary +behavioral isomorph by taking small steps and preserving behavioral equivalence throughout. How would one do this for the look-up table, for instance? +Perhaps there are ways of doing it by taking large steps at once, but this will +not be enough for the argument: if there are large steps between neighboring +systems, then suddenly disappearing qualia are no longer so implausible. +With functional isomorphs, there was a natural way to take very small steps, +but there is no such natural method for behavioral isomorphs. It therefore +seems unlikely that such an argument could get off the ground. +Ultimately, I think the only tenable way for an opponent of organizational +invariance to respond to this argument is to bite the bullet and accept the +possibility of fading qualia with the consequent possibility that a rational +conscious system might be massively mistaken about its experience, or perhaps to bite another bullet and accept suddenly disappearing qualia and the +associated brute discontinuities. This position is unattractive in its implication +of a dissociation between consciousness and cognition, and the alternative +seems much more plausible; but unlike the other objections it is not obviously +wrong. The dancing qualia argument in section 5 will provide even more +evidence against the possibility of absent qualia, however, so opponents of +the invariance principle cannot rest easily. +I note briefly that a similar argument might establish that systems whose +functional organization is similar (as opposed to identical) to that of a conscious system will have conscious experiences. The invariance principle taken +alone is compatible with the solipsistic thesis that my organization and only +my organization gives rise to experience. But one can imagine a gradual +change to my organization, just as we imagined a gradual change to my +physical makeup, under which my beliefs about my experience would be + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +263 + +mostly preserved throughout, I would remain a rational system, and so on. +For similar reasons to the above, it seems very likely that conscious experience would be preserved in such a transition. + +4. Inverted Qualia +The fading qualia argument suggests that my functional isomorphs will have +conscious experience, but it does not establish that isomorphs will have the +same sort of conscious experience. That is, functional organization determines the existence or absence of conscious experience, but it might not +determine the nature of that experience. To establish that functional organization determines the nature of experience, we will have to establish that +functional isomorphs with inverted qualia are impossible. +The idea of inverted qualia is familiar to most of us. Few people have not +wondered at some point whether what looks red to one person looks blue +to another, and vice versa. It is one of those philosophical puzzles where +one is at first uncertain whether the idea even makes sense, and that can be +baffling even on reflection. +The possibility of inverted qualia was apparently first put forward by John +Locke, in his Essay Concerning Human Understanding: +Though one Man's Idea of Blue should be different from another's. Neither +would it carry any imputation of falsehood to our simple ideas, if by the different +structure of our organs it were so ordered that the same object should produce +in several men's minds different ideas at the same time; v.g. if the idea that a +violet produced in one man's mind by his eyes were the same that a marigold +produced in another man's, and vice versa. For, since this could never be known, +because one man's mind could not pass into another man's body, to perceive +what appearances were produced by those organs, neither the idea hereby, nor +the names, would be at all confounded, or any falsehood be in either. For all +things that had the texture of a violet producing constantly the idea which he +called blue, and those which had the texture of a marigold producing constantly +the idea which he called yellow, whatever those appearances were in his mind, +he would be able as regularly to distinguish things for his use by those appearances, and understand and signify those distinctions marked by the names "blue" +and "yellow," as if the appearances or idea in his mind received from those +two flowers were exactly the same with the ideas in other men's minds, (bk. 2, +chap. 32, sec. 15) + +Here, Locke is concerned with inverted qualia between systems with similar behavior, rather than between precise functional isomorphs. It certainly +seems that a conceptual possibility is being expressed. The question for us +is whether an empirical possibility is being expressed. + + 264 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +Even those who consider themselves materialists have often supposed +that functional isomorphs might have different conscious experiences. For +example, it is often thought naturally possible that a functional isomorph +of me with different physical makeup might have blue experiences where +I have red experiences, or something similar. This is the hypothesis of +inverted qualia. If it is true, then while the presence of conscious experience might depend only on functional organization, the nature of experiences would depend on physiological makeup, or some other nonfunctional +factor.10 +We have seen earlier that it is difficult to hold this position consistently +with materialism. If it is naturally possible that a functional isomorph could +have inverted qualia, then it is logically possible. It is therefore equally +logically possible that a physical isomorph would have inverted qualia, as +there is no more of a conceptual connection from neurons to a specific kind +of qualia than from silicon. It follows that the nature of specific experiences +is a further fact over and above the physical facts, and that materialism must +be false (unless one embraces the "strong metaphysical necessity" line). I +will leave this point aside in what follows, however. The discussion will be +independent of the truth of materialism or dualism. +The possibility of inverted qualia, or of the "inverted spectrum" as it is +sometimes known, is sometimes objected to on the verificationist grounds +that we could never know that anything different was going on, so that there +could be no could be no real difference (e.g., Schlick 1932). Obviously I do +not accept these arguments: the mere fact that we cannot tell what qualia a +system is experiencing is not sufficient to conclude that there is no fact of +the matter, as the nature of qualia is not conceptually tied to behavior; so +I will leave this sort of objection aside here. As I discussed in Chapter 3, +the hypothesis is also sometimes objected to on the grounds that our color +space is asymmetrical, so that no inversion could map things appropriately +(e.g., Hardin 1987; Harrison 1967, 1973). Some of the responses I made +earlier are still appropriate here, even though the question is now one of +natural possibility; in particular, we can still appeal to the possibility of a +creature with asymmetrical color space and ask whether it could have an +inverted functional isomorph. In any case I will ignore this worry, granting +for the sake of argument that we have a symmetrical color space, and arguing +that inverted qualia are impossible all the same. +Discussion of inverted qualia can be confusing. When I say "blue experience," do I mean (1) what a subject calls a "blue" experience, (2) an experience caused by a blue object, or (3) what I call a "blue" experience? I choose +the latter usage. Throughout my discussion, by "blue experience" I will mean +the kind of experience that I call "blue," that I usually have when I see blue +things like the sky and the sea, and so on. In this usage, it is conceivable + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +265 + +that others (or even a future version of me) might have blue experiences +caused by yellow objects, or by objects they call "red," and so on. +Arguments for inverted qualia often consist simply in a conceivability claim, +as with absent qualia, but such claims clearly leave the issue of natural possibility open. A couple of arguments have been given for the natural possibility of versions of inverted qualia, but neither threatens the principle of organizational invariance. +The first such argument establishes the possibility of qualia that are inverted while behavior is held constant (see Gert 1965; Lycan 1973; and +Wittgenstein 1968). We first note that qualia could be inverted within a +subject, perhaps by rewiring the connection from retina to central areas in +my brain while I am asleep. Upon waking, I will assert that the sky suddenly +seems red, grass seems yellow, and so on, and there will be every reason to +believe that my qualia have been inverted. Next, we raise the possibility of +someone whose brain had been rewired this way since birth. Such a person +might have qualia that are systematically inverted with respect to the norm, +but of course they will have learned to call the sky blue, to call grass green, +and so on, so this inversion might never show up in their behavior.11 +This does not, however, establish the possibility of inverted qualia with +fixed functional organization. To see this, we need only note that in crossing +my wires, the demon has changed my functional organization in a significant +way. Similarly, the functional organization of the subject who is rewired +from birth has been changed, so he will not be a functional duplicate of me. +He may share some of my functional properties at a coarse grain, but he +certainly will not share my fine-grained functional organization. The principle +of organizational invariance is therefore unthreatened by such cases.12 +A related argument, put forward by Block (1990), concerns "Inverted +Earth," where the sky is yellow, grass is red, and so on.13 We are to suppose +that I am kidnapped and taken to Inverted Earth, but at the same time I +am given color-inverting contact lenses so that everything looks normal to +me. Block uses this scenario to argue against a representationalist view of +qualia, where for example a blue experience is equated with a perceptual +state that is about blue things (after some time on Inverted Earth, one's +blue experiences will be about yellow things). He also uses it against a functionalist view of the sort on which blue experiences are equated with states +caused by blue objects. +Again, this case does nothing to refute the organizational invariance principle. After all, when I see the yellow sky through my inverting lenses on +Inverted Earth, my internal functional organization will be just as it is when +I see blue sky on earth, and my experience will be the same too, just as the +principle predicts. At most, the thought experiment dissociates experiences + + 266 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +from properties of one's environment, and from "wide" functional properties +that involve one's environment; but the functional organization I am concerned with is entirely internal. The thought experiment provides no cases +where two internally isomorphic systems have different experiences, so the +invariance principle is unaffected.14 + +5. Dancing Qualia +One might think that the fading qualia argument could be directly adapted +to provide an argument against the possibility of inverted qualia. Unfortunately this will not work. Imagine how an analogous argument would go. +We start with me, having a red experience, and an inverted system having +a blue experience. By gradual replacement, we construct a series of cases, +each having some intermediate color. But there is nothing wrong with this! +The intermediate systems are simply cases of mild qualia inversion and are +no more problematic than the extreme case. +To be sure, it may not be obvious just what the intermediate systems are +experiencing. Perhaps no color from our usual color space can do the job, +consistently with the systems' patterns of categorization and differences. +But perhaps they are experiencing entirely new colors, ones that I cannot +experience but that nevertheless form a continuum from red to blue. This +would be odd, but it is not vastly implausible. Importantly, the problem with +the fading qualia case will be entirely absent. These systems will not be +systematically wrong about the features of their experience. Where they +claim to experience distinctions, they may still experience distinctions; where +they claim intense experiences, they have intense experiences; and so on. +To be sure, the colors they call "red" will be different from what I call red, +but this is nothing problematic; it happens already in the usual inversion +case. What counts is that unlike the fading qualia case, the structural features +of these systems' experiences are preserved throughout. +Nevertheless, a good argument against the possibility of inverted qualia +can be found in the vicinity.15 Once again, for the purposes of reductio, +assume that inverted qualia are empirically possible. Then there can be two +functionally isomorphic systems, in the same functional state but having +different experiences. Suppose for the sake of illustration that these systems +are me, having a red experience, and my silicon isomorph, having a blue +experience (there is a small caveat about generality, which I discuss later). +As before, we construct a series of cases intermediate between me and +my isomorph. Here, the argument takes a different turn. We need not worry +about the way in which experiences change as we move along the series. +Perhaps they change suddenly, perhaps they jump all over the map, although + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +267 + +surely it is most plausible that they change gradually. All that matters is that +there must be two points A and B in this series, such that (1) no more than +one-tenth of the brain is replaced between A and B, and (2) A and B have +significantly different experiences. To see that this must be the case, we need +only consider the points at which 10 percent, 20 percent, and so on up to +90 percent of the brain have been replaced. Red and blue are sufficiently +different experiences that some neighboring pairs here must be significantly +different (that is, different enough that the difference would be noticeable +if they were experienced by the same person); there is no way to get from +red to blue by ten unnoticeable jumps. +It is true that there can be unnoticeable differences between different +experiences. If one changes a shade of red little enough, I will not be able +to tell the difference. One might suppose that this is because there is no +difference in experience, only a difference in the world; but if this were all +that was going on one could iterate such a change a thousand times, eventually showing that red and blue produce the same experiences, which is ridiculous. So there can be some difference in experience that is not noticeable. +One can observe this phenomenon by looking at a wide expanse of paint of +subtly varying shade; sometimes it is extremely difficult to tell whether one's +experiences of different parts is the same or different. But importantly, +unnoticeable differences are very small. At best, ten such jumps could take +us from a shade of red to a subtly different shade of the same color. (This +opens up a small loophole in the generality of the argument; I return to this +point later.) +Between the red and blue systems, there must therefore be two systems +that differ in at most 10 percent of their internal makeup, but that have +significantly different experiences. For the purposes of illustration, let these +systems be me and Bill. Where I have a red experience, Bill has a slightly +different experience. We may as well suppose that Bill sees blue; perhaps +his experience will be more similar to mine than that, but it makes no +difference to the argument. The two systems also differ in that where there +are neurons in some small region of my brain, there are silicon chips in Bill's +brain. This substitution of a silicon circuit for a neural circuit is the only +physical difference between Bill and me. +The crucial step in the thought experiment is to take a silicon circuit just +like Bill's and install it in my own head as a backup circuit. This circuit will +be functionally isomorphic to a circuit already present in my head. We equip +the circuit with transducers and effectors so that it can interact with the rest +of my brain, but we do not hook it up directly. Instead, we install a switch +that can switch directly between the neural and silicon circuits. Upon flipping +the switch, the neural circuit becomes irrelevant and the silicon circuit takes +over. We can imagine that the switch controls the points of interface where + + 268 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +the relevant circuits affect the rest of the brain. When it is switched, the +connections from the neural circuit are pushed out of the way, and the silicon +circuit's effectors are attached. (We can imagine that the transducers for +both circuits are attached the entire time, so that the state of both circuits +evolves appropriately, but so that only one circuit at a time is involved in +processing. We could also run a similar experiment where both transducers +and effectors are disconnected, to ensure that the backup circuit is entirely +isolated from the rest of the system. This would change a few details, but +the moral would be the same.) +Immediately after flipping the switch, processing that was once performed +by the neural circuit is now performed by the silicon circuit. The flow of +control within the system has been redirected. However, my functional organization is exactly the same as it would have been if we had not flipped the +switch. The only relevant difference between the two cases is the physical +makeup of one circuit within the system. There is also a difference in the +physical makeup of another "dangling" circuit, but this is irrelevant to functional organization, as it plays no role in affecting other components of the +system and directing behavior. +What happens to my experience when we flip the switch? Before installing +the circuit, I was experiencing red. After we install it but before we flip the +switch, I will presumably still be experiencing red, as the only difference is +the addition of a circuit that is not involved in processing in any way; for +all the relevance it has to my processing, I might as well have eaten it. After +flipping the switch, however, I am more or less the same system as Bill. The +only difference between Bill and me now is that I have a causally irrelevant +neural circuit dangling from the system (we might even imagine that the +circuit is destroyed when the switch is flipped). Bill, by hypothesis, was +enjoying a blue experience. After the switch, then, I will have a blue experience too. +What will happen, then, is that my experience will change "before my +eyes." Where I was once experiencing red, I will now experience blue. All +of a sudden, I will have a blue experience of the apple on my desk. We can +even imagine flipping the switch back and forth a number of times, so that +the red and blue experiences "dance" before my eyes. +This might seem reasonable at first—it is a strangely appealing image— +but something very odd is going on here. My experiences are switching from +red to blue, but / do not notice any change. Even as we flip the switch a +number of times and my qualia dance back and forth, I will simply go +about my business, noticing nothing unusual. By hypothesis, my functional +organization remains normal throughout. In particular, my functional organization after flipping the switch evolves just as it would have if the switch +had not been flipped. There is no special difference in my behavioral disposi- + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +269 + +tions. I am not suddenly disposed to say "Hmm! Something strange is going +on!" There is no room for a sudden start, for an exclamation, or even for a +distraction of attention. Any unusual reaction would imply a functional +difference between the two circuits, contrary to their stipulated isomorphism. +By design, my cognitive organization is just as it usually is, and in particular +is precisely as it would have been had the switch not been flipped. +Certainly, on any functional construal of belief, it is clear that I cannot +acquire any new beliefs as the flip takes place. Even if one disputes a functional account, it is extremely implausible that a simple replacement of a +neural circuit by a silicon circuit while overall organization is preserved could +be responsible for the addition of significant new beliefs such as "My qualia +just flipped." As in the case of fading qualia, there is simply no room for +such a change to take place, unless it is in an accompanying Cartesian disembodied mind. +We are therefore led once more into a reductio ad absurdum. It seems +entirely implausible to suppose that my experiences could change in such a +significant way, with my paying full attention to them, without my being +able to notice the change. It would suggest once again a radical dissociation +between consciousness and cognition. If this kind of thing could happen, +then psychology and phenomenology would be radically out of step; much +further out of step than even the fading qualia scenario would imply. +This "dancing qualia" scenario may be logically possible (although the +case is so extreme that it seems only just logically possible), but that does +not mean that it is plausible as an empirical possibility, any more than it +is plausible that the world was created five minutes ago. As an empirical +hypothesis, it seems far more plausible that when one's experiences change +significantly, then as long as one is rational and paying attention, one should +be able to notice the change. If not, then consciousness and cognition are +tied together only by the most slender of threads. +Indeed, if we are to suppose that dancing qualia are naturally possible, +we are led to a worrying thought: they might be actual and happening to us +all the time. The physiological properties of our functional mechanisms +are constantly changing. The functional properties of the mechanisms are +reasonably robust; one would expect that this robustness would be ensured +by evolution. But there is no adaptive reason for the nonfunctional properties to stay constant. From moment to moment there will certainly be +changes in low-level molecular properties. Properties such as position, atomic +makeup, and so on can change while functional role is preserved, and such +change is almost certainly going on constantly. +If we allow that qualia are dependent not just on functional organization +but on implementational details, it may well be that our qualia are in fact +dancing before our eyes all the time. There seems to be no principled reason + + 270 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +why a change from neurons to silicon should make a difference while a +change in neural realization should not;16 the only place to draw a principled +line is at the functional level.17 The reason why we doubt that such dancing +is taking place in our own cases is that we accept the following principle: +When one's experiences change significantly, one can notice the change. If +we were to accept the possibility of dancing qualia in the original case, we +would be discarding this principle, and it would no longer be available as a +defense against skepticism even in the more usual cases. +It is not out of the question that we could actually perform such an +experiment. Of course the practical difficulties would be immense, but at +least in principle, one could install such a circuit in me and I could see +what happened, and report it to the world. But of course there is no point +performing the experiment: we know what the result will be. I will report +that my experience stayed the same throughout, a constant shade of red, +and that I noticed nothing untoward. I will become even more convinced +than I was before that qualia are determined by functional organization. Of +course this will not be a proof, but the evidence will be hard to seriously +dispute. +I conclude that by far the most plausible hypothesis is that replacement +of neurons while preserving functional organization will preserve qualia. The +problems with the dancing qualia scenario can be blamed on the initial +assumption that a functionally isomorphic silicon system might experience +blue where I experience red. The most reasonable reaction is to withdraw +this assumption, thus concluding that experience is wholly determined by +functional organization. +It should be noted that this thought experiment works just as well against +the possibility of absent qualia as against that of inverted qualia. We simply +take two points on the way to absent qualia between which experience differs significantly and install a backup circuit in the same way. As before, if +absent qualia are possible, then switching will cause my qualia to oscillate +before my eyes, from vivid to tepid and back, without my ever noticing. +Again, it is far more plausible that such dancing without noticing is impossible, so that absent qualia are impossible. +Personally, I find this an even more convincing argument against absent +qualia than the argument in section 3, although both have a role to play. +An opponent might just bite the bullet and accept the possibility of fading +qualia, but dancing qualia seem an order of magnitude more difficult to +accept. The very immediacy of the switch seems to make a significant difference, as does the fact that the phenomenon the subject cannot notice is so +dynamic and striking. Fading qualia would mean that some systems are out +of touch with their conscious experience, but dancing qualia would establish +an even stranger gap. + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +271 + +Because of the structure of the dancing qualia argument, it leaves open +a few more loopholes than the fading qualia argument. It does not seem +that any of these loopholes can be exploited to lead to an attractive position +for an opponent, however. I will discuss these loopholes in what follows, +alongside another objection to the argument. The objections to the fading +qualia case can all be made again, and the replies are more or less the same; +I will not bother to repeat them. +Objection 1: Loopholes concerning speed and history +The argument I have given here can naturally be extended from the neural/ +silicon case to many other examples of functional isomorphs, but there are +a couple of exceptions involving speed and history. If an isomorph is much +faster or slower than the original system, we cannot simply substitute a circuit +from one system into the other and expect everything to function normally. +So the argument as I have given it does not rule out the possibility that +a change in speed that leaves functional organization constant might be +responsible for an inversion in qualia. A similar loophole is left open for +physical isomorphs that differ merely in their history: perhaps if I was born +in the Southern Hemisphere I will experience green, whereas a physical twin +born in the North will experience red. History cannot be varied in a dancing +qualia scenario (although it can be varied in a fading qualia scenario), so +the argument does not bear on the hypothesis that qualia supervene on +the past. +But neither of these hypotheses were very plausible in the first place. It +is reasonable that history should affect our qualia by affecting our physical structure, but the history dependence required above would be much +stronger: there would in effect be a "nonlocal" effect of distal history on +present qualia, unmediated by anything in physical structure or nearby in +space and time. As for speed, it would seem quite arbitrary that a change +in speed would invert qualia when nothing else could. The hypotheses here +are coherent, so an opponent could embrace them, but there is little reason +to. Once we have established that all other organization-preserving changes +preserve qualia, there is little attraction in the idea that speed or history +might be the only things that make a difference. +Objection 2: What about mild inversions? +Another small loophole is that the argument does not refute the possibility +of very mild spectrum inversions. Between dark red and a slightly darker +red, for instance, there may be nine intermediate shades such that no two +neighboring shades are distinguishable. In such a case the dancing qualia + + 272 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +scenario is not a problem; if the system notices no difference on flipping the +switch, that is just what we would expect. +Of course, there is nothing special about the figure of one-tenth as the +amount of difference between two neighboring systems. But we cannot make +the figure too high. If we made it as high as one half, we would run into +problems with personal identity: it might reasonably be suggested that upon +flipping the switch, we are creating a new person, and it would not be a +problem that the new person noticed no change. Perhaps we might go as +high as 20 percent or 25 percent without such problems; but that would still +allow the possibility of very mild inversions, the kind that could be composed +of four or five unnoticeable changes. We can reduce the impact of this worry, +however, by noting that it is very unlikely that experience depends equally +on all areas of the brain. If color experience depends largely on a small area +of the visual cortex, say, then we could perform any qualia inversion in one +fell swoop while only replacing a small portion of the system, and the argument would succeed against even the mildest noticeable qualia inversion. +In any case, any loophole here is an unthreatening one. At best, we +have left open the possibility that an extremely mild underdetermination of +experience by organization is possible. This sort of underdetermination might +seem so slight as to be uninteresting, but in any case, we can note that it +leads to an unattractive position. It would seem reasonable that experiences +should be invertible across the board, or not invertible at all, but why should +the world be such that a small inversion is possible but nothing more? This +would seem quite arbitrary. We cannot rule it out, but it is not a hypothesis +with much antecedent plausibility. +Objection 3: Unattended qualia +In a similar way, the argument leaves open the loophole that unattended +qualia might be invertible. If we are not attending to the fringes of our visual +field, for example, a qualia inversion might take place there without our +noticing. Indeed, recent experiments (Rensink, O'Regan, and Clark 1995) +show that one can change quite significant features of an image that a subject +is looking at without the subject noticing, if they are not concentrating on +those features (these experiments typically involve a short time interval +between the display of two images, so it is not quite like the dancing qualia +scenario, but it is close). So these arguments leave open the possibility that +unattended qualia might be invertible. +Nothing in this sort of consideration suggests that attended qualia could +be invertible, however. So to exploit this loophole would leave one in the +unattractive position that qualia are organizationally invariant when they +are central enough in one's attention, but dependent on other features when + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +273 + +they are not. (Presumably an inverted green experience on the fringe will +flip back to red when one attends to it?) It seems most unlikely that such a +position could be made theoretically satisfying. As with the other loopholes, +this loophole opens the way only to positions that lack any significant antecedent plausibility. +Objection 4: Double switching +Another objection is the following.18 We can imagine a related experiment +in which we rewire the connections from red and blue inputs to central areas +of the brain so that blue inputs play the role that red inputs once played, +and in which we also systematically rewire connections downstream from +the central area to compensate. When a blue input causes the central area +to go into a state previously associated with red, connections from the central +area to the rest of the brain are rewired so that the rest of the brain functions +just as it would function had there been no rewiring at all. This way, my +experience will almost certainly switch from red to blue, but my behavioral +dispositions will stay constant throughout. In this case, a repeated switch +would surely lead to dancing qualia. So aren't dancing qualia reasonable +after all? +First, I should note that this rewiring would be a much vaster task than +any other cases I have described. The central area will affect the rest of the +brain at all sorts of different places. Each of these connections will have to +be rewired, and crucially, no simple rewiring could do the job at any of them. +We cannot simply switch "red outputs" to "blue outputs," as we could with +inputs; the outputs from the central system may represent such diverse +things as retrieved memories, motor instructions, and so on, with no simple +difference in "polarity" between an output for red and an output for blue. +To determine an appropriate "blue output," one would probably need to +simulate the entire processing of the central area, given its initial state and +input, to see what it produces. If so, it will be this simulation that is doing +the causal work, not the central area itself, and the force of the scenario will +be lost. +Second, even if there somehow turned out to be a simple way in which +outputs could be rewired, note that only behavioral dispositions are preserved, and not functional organization. What might this feel like? In this +case, I imagine that I would notice the switch and try to act accordingly, but +would feel as if some jarring puppeteer was interfering with my actions. +Unlike the previous case, there will be room for these extra beliefs and other +cognitive states; they will be supported by the different states of the central +area. And we can imagine that once feedback takes place, and input to the +central areas indicates that its motor movements have been entirely different + + 274 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +from what was planned, we can imagine that the central area state will be +severely shaken up. In fact, this leads us back to the first objection, as it +would seem almost impossible to systematically compensate for these feedback effects. In any case, the significant difference in functional organization +means that the cases are not analogous. + +6. Nonreductive Functionalism +To summarize: We have established that if absent qualia are possible, then +fading qualia are possible; if inverted qualia are possible, then dancing qualia +are possible; and if absent qualia are possible, then dancing qualia are possible. But it is implausible that fading qualia are possible, and it is extremely +implausible that dancing qualia are possible. It is therefore extremely implausible that absent qualia and inverted qualia are possible. It follows that we +have good reason to believe that the principle of organizational invariance is +true, and that functional organization fully determines conscious experience. +It should be noted these arguments do not establish functionalism in the +strongest sense, as they establish at best that absent and inverted qualia +are empirically (or naturally) impossible. There are two reasons why the +arguments cannot be extended into arguments for the logical impossibility +of absent and inverted qualia, as some functionalists might like. First, both +fading qualia and dancing qualia seem to be coherent hypotheses, even if +they are not plausible. Some might dispute the logical possibility of these +hypotheses, perhaps holding that it is constitutive of qualia that we can notice +differences in them. This conceptual intuition is disputable, but in any case +there is a second reason why these arguments fail to establish the logical +determination of experience by functional organization. +To see this second reason, note that the arguments take as an empirical +premise certain facts about the distribution of functional organization in +physical systems: that I have conscious experiences of a certain kind, or that +some biological systems do. If we established the logical impossibility of +fading and dancing qualia, this might establish the logical necessity of the +conditional: if one system with fine-grained functional organization F has a +certain sort of conscious experience, then any system with organization F +has those experiences. But we cannot establish the logical necessity of the +conclusion of this conditional without establishing the logical necessity of +the premise, and the premise is itself empirical. To establish the logical +determination of experience by functional organization, we would first have +to establish the logical supervenience of experience on the physical, which +I have argued cannot be done. Even if we could establish logical supervenience on the physical, it would probably be through a functional definition, + + Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia + +275 + +but with such a definition the logical impossibility of absent and inverted +qualia would follow without any need for any fancy arguments. So either +way, the fading and dancing qualia arguments are of little use in arguing for +the logical or metaphysical impossibility of absent or inverted qualia. +The arguments therefore fail to establish a strong form of functionalism +upon which functional organization is constitutive of conscious experience; +but they succeed in establishing the weaker form that I have called nonreductive functionalism, on which functional organization suffices for conscious +experience with natural necessity. On this view, conscious experience is determined by functional organization, but it need not be reducible to functional organization. +In any case, the conclusion is still a strong one. The invariance principle +tells us that in principle, cognitive systems realized in all sorts of media +can be conscious. In particular, the conclusion gives strong support to the +ambitions of researchers in artificial intelligence, as I discuss further in Chapter 9. If nonreductive functionalism is correct, the irreducibility of consciousness poses no barrier to the eventual construction of a conscious computational device. +Most importantly, we have advanced in our quest to constrain the principles in virtue of which consciousness naturally supervenes on the physical. +We have narrowed down the relevant properties in the supervenience base +to organizational properties. In a certain sense, we can say that not only +does consciousness supervene on the physical, but it supervenes on the +organizational. This needs to be spelled out carefully, due to the fact that +every system realizes numerous kinds of functional organization, but we can +say the following: for every physical system that gives rise to conscious +experience, there is some functional organization F realized by the system, +such that it is naturally necessary that any system that realizes F will have +identical conscious experiences. To pick out the relevant F, we need to go +to a fine enough grain to fix cognitive states such as judgments. This in +turn can be achieved by requiring that F is fine-grained enough to fix the +mechanisms responsible for the production of behavior, and to fix behavioral dispositions. This is all that the fading and dancing qualia arguments +required, so it is all we need for organizational invariance. +It is therefore a law, for certain functional organizations F, that realization +of F will be accompanied by a specific kind of conscious experience. This is +not to say that it will be a fundamental law. It would be odd if the universe +had fundamental laws connecting complex functional organizations to conscious experiences. Rather, one would expect it to be a consequence of +simpler, more fundamental psychophysical laws. In the meantime, the principle of organizational invariance acts as a strong constraint on an ultimate +theory. + + 8 + +Consciousness and Information +Some Speculation + +1. Toward a Fundamental Theory +So far, we have isolated a few connections between consciousness and physical processes that deserve to be called psychophysical laws. One of these is +the coherence principle connecting consciousness to awareness, or global +availability. Another is the more specific principle of structural coherence, +connecting the structure of consciousness to the structure of awareness. The +principle of organizational invariance is a third. These principles may be +components of a final theory of consciousness. They enable us to use physical +facts to predict and even to explain certain facts about conscious experience. +And they certainly constrain the form of a final theory of consciousness: if +such a theory is not compatible with these laws, it is unlikely to be correct. +But there must be more to the story than this. These principles do not themselves add up to a final theory, or anything close to it. +The trouble is that none of these principles are plausible candidates to be +fundamental laws in a theory of consciousness. All of them express regularities at a fairly high level. The concept of awareness (or global availability) +is a high-level concept, for example, and its boundaries are somewhat vague; +it is very unlikely that this concept would be involved in a fundamental law. +The principle of organizational invariance may be less vague, but it still expresses a regularity at a level that is far from fundamental. Another problem: +these principles grossly underdetermine the nature of the psychophysical +connection. All sorts of questions about the connection remain unanswered. +For example, just what kind of organization gives rise to conscious experience? How simple can an organization be before experience vanishes? And +how can we predict the specific character of an experience (not just its struc- + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +277 + +ture) from its physical basis? We would like a complete theory of consciousness to answer these questions, but the principles covered so far do not help. +For a final theory, we need a set of psychophysical laws analogous to +fundamental laws in physics. These fundamental (or basic) laws will be cast +at a level connecting basic properties of experience with simple features of +the physical world. The laws should be precise, and should together leave +no room for underdetermination. When combined with the physical facts +about a system, they should enable us to perfectly predict the phenomenal +facts about the system. Further, just as the basic laws of physics entail all +higher-level physical laws and regularities (at least when combined with +boundary conditions), the basic laws about consciousness should entail and +explain the various nonbasic laws, such as the coherence principles and the +principle of organizational invariance. Once we have a set of fundamental +physical and psychophysical laws, we may in a certain sense understand the +basic structure of the universe. +This is a tall order, and we will not achieve it anytime soon. But we can +at least move in this direction. The principles of organizational invariance +and structural coherence already put a strong constraint on the form of a +fundamental theory, and there are not a vast number of candidates for the +basic constructs that might be the theory's fundamental ingredients. In this +chapter, I present some ideas toward a fundamental theory. I do not present +a full-fledged theory with a comprehensive set of basic laws, but I put forward +suggestions about the constructs involved in these laws, and about what the +broad shape of the laws might be. This could be considered a prototheory: +a skeleton around which a theory might be built. +The ideas in this chapter are much sketchier and more speculative than +those elsewhere in the book, and they raise as many questions as they answer. +They are also the most likely to be entirely wrong. In putting forward these +loose ideas, the goal is not to set out a framework that will withstand close +philosophical scrutiny; instead, they are put forward in the spirit of getting +ideas onto the table. We have to start thinking about fundamental theories +of consciousness, and perhaps there will be something useful here that might +be carried forward. + +2. Aspects of Information +The basic notion I will deal with in this chapter is that of information. +There are many different concepts of information afloat in the space of +contemporary ideas, so the first thing one has to do when talking about +information is to clarify what one is talking about. The concept of information I am concerned with has much in common with that discussed by +Shannon (1948). Here, I present an adaptation and development of this idea. + + 278 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +I leave the development relatively informal, providing just enough formalism to capture the most central aspects of the concept that will be relevant. +There are a few technicalities in this section, but later sections are more +straightforward. +Shannon was not concerned with a semantic notion of information, on +which information is always information about something. Rather, he focused on a formal or syntactic notion of information, where the key is the +concept of a state selected from an ensemble of possibilities. The most +basic sort of information is the bit, which represents a choice between two +possibilities: a single bit (0 or 1) selected from a two-state space is said +to carry information. In a more complex case, a "message" such as +"0110010101" chosen from a space of possible binary messages carries information in a similar way. What is important, on Shannon's account, is not +any interpretation of these states; what matters is the specificity of a state +within a space of different possibilities. +We can formalize this idea by appealing to the concept of an information +space. An information space is an abstract space consisting of a number of +states, which I will call information states, and a basic structure of difference +relations between those states. The simplest nontrivial information space is +the space consisting of two states with a primitive difference between them. +We can think of these states as the two "bits," 0 and 1. The fact that these +two states are different from each other exhausts their nature. That is, this +information space is fully characterized by its difference structure. +Other information spaces are more complex. This can happen in two +ways: by allowing a more complex difference structure between states, or +by allowing the states themselves to have internal structure. To illustrate +the first way, we might move to a four-state space involving states 0, 1, 2, +and 3. To illustrate the second way, we might move to a structured space +involving states such as "110010101." Of course the two ways might be +combined, yielding doubly complex states as in the space of messages such +as "233102032." I discuss these two sorts of complexity in more detail in +what follows. +Starting with the first sort of complexity: most obviously, there is a threestate space, a four-state space, and so on, whose difference structure is a +natural extension of that of the two-state space. For example, an element +A, B, C, or D chosen from a four-element space carries information in the +same sort of way that a bit carries information. Of course, the nature of the +labels "A," "B," and so on is irrelevant here; once again, all that is essential +to the space is its structure. +More importantly, there are continuous information spaces, whose states +lie on a continuum analogous to the continuum of real numbers between 0 +and 1. Such a space has an infinite number of states. This space has a much +more complex difference structure than the previous cases: the structure + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +279 + +corresponds directly to the topology of the continuum, with certain states +lying between other states, some states closer to each other than other +states, and so on. But as before, we can see a single point chosen from the +continuum as carrying information. +One can also have an information space whose structure is that of a twodimensional continuum, or a multidimensional continuum, analogous to the +structure of a region of n-dimensional space. A single point selected from +a region of three-dimensional space will carry information, for example. In +the most general case, the structure can be given by that of an arbitrary +topological space, which in effect supplies a set with "proximity" or "neighborhood" relations. The details of this will not matter too much in what +follows, however, where I will deal with intuitively familiar structures such +as that of the continuum. +The second sort of complexity involves states with internal structure. These +states are made up from a number of more basic states that I will call +elements. An example is the space of ten-bit states, analogous to "messages" +such as "1001101000." Each state here consists of ten elements, and each +element can be seen to fall into its own two-state subspace corresponding +to the original two-state space. We can see this information space as a kind +of product of ten subspaces, each of which is an information space in its +own right. +There can also be more interesting internal structures. For example, an +information state might have continuous internal structure, so that it is a +sort of continuous analog of the ten-element structure discussed earlier. Such +a state would have an infinite number of elements, each of which falls into +a subspace of its own. We might think of the corresponding information +space here as akin to the space of functions over a continuum (with each +value falling into a subspace), or over a more complex continuous space. +It can also happen that the subspaces are complex in the first way mentioned above: for example, the elements in each subspace might fall along +a continuum. So there is room for two simultaneous levels of complexity +here. For example, each state might consist in a continuous structure of +elements, each of which can take on values within a continuous subspace. +An information state in this space might be seen as a waveform, or some +other function with continuous domain and range: it is a continuous analog +of the discrete "messages" described previously. +In the most general case, an information space will have two sorts of +structure: each complex state might have an internal structure, and each +element in this state will belong to a subspace with a topological difference +structure of its own. We might call the first of these the combinatorial structure of the space, and the second of these the relational structure of the +subspaces. Much of the time, each subspace will have the same relational +structure, so we can just speak of the relational structure of the space itself. + + 280 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +The overall structure of the space is given by these combinatorial and relational structures together. I will often restrict attention to information spaces +with only relational structure and not combinatorial structure—the case in +which there is only one element in an information state—as the discussion +is much simpler in that case. +This framework does not incorporate anything like a notion of semantic +content, so the sort of information discussed here is at best indirectly related +to the semantic variety of information discussed by philosophers such as +Dretske (1981) and Barwise and Perry (1983). It might be possible to extend +the current framework so it has a semantic element, by associating some +sort of semantic content with each information state, but as it stands the +framework is independent of semantic considerations. +This formalization captures Shannon's idea that information essentially +involves a state selected from a number of possibilities (in the relational +structure of a space), and also captures the idea that complex information +can be built up from simple information (in the combinatorial structure of +a space). A single bit can constitute information for Shannon, as can a +long "message" such as "10011010." Shannon also considers the case where +information falls into a continuous space, or into a space of functions over +a continuous domain. In each case, it is the selection of a single element +from a space of contrasting possibilities that is crucial. +Shannon's own account is often concerned with the amount of information +in an information state, which measures how specific a state is within an +information space. A state within a two-state information space carries one +bit of information; a state within a four-state space carries two bits; a state +within an n-element space carries Iog2n bits. When a space is a combination +of subspaces, a state carries an amount of information equal to the sum of +the amounts carried by its elements: so a ten-digit binary "message" carries +ten bits of information. This treatment applies to discrete spaces; within +continuous spaces, amount of information must be defined more subtly. +Here, I will not be very concerned with amounts of information. Rather, I +will be concerned with information states themselves, which we might think +of as standing to amount of information as matter stands to mass. +Physically realized information +As I have defined them, information spaces are abstract spaces, and information states are abstract states. They are not part of the concrete physical or +phenomenal world. But we can find information in both the physical and +the phenomenal world, if we look at things the right way. To do this, we +need to discuss the various ways in which information spaces and states can +be realized in the world. I will discuss physical realization and phenomenal +realization in turn. + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +281 + +It seems intuitively clear that information spaces and states are realized +throughout the physical world. We can see my light switch as realizing a +two-state information space, for example, with its states "up" and "down" +realizing the two states. Or we can see a compact disk as realizing a combinatorial information state, consisting in a complex structure of bits. One can +see information realized in a thermostat, a book, or a telephone line in +similar ways. How can we make sense of these intuitions? +The natural way to make the connection between physical systems and +information states is to see physically realized information in terms of a +slogan due to Bateson (1972): information is a difference that makes a difference. While my light switch can take on an infinite number of positions in +a continuous range, most of this variation makes no difference at all to my +light. Whether the switch is all the way up, or one-quarter of the way down, +the light will be on. When it is in positions more than about one-third of +the way down, on the other hand, the light will be off. As far as the light is +concerned, there are only two relevant states of the switch, which we can +call "up" and "down." The difference between these two states is the only +difference that makes a difference to the light. So we can see the switch as +realizing a two-state information space, with some physical states of the +switch corresponding to one information state and with some corresponding +to the other. +In general, an information space associated with a physical object will +always be defined with respect to a causal pathway (in this case, the pathway +from the light switch to the light) and a space of possible effects at the end +of the pathway (in this case, the on/off state of the light). Physical states will +correspond to information states according to their effects on the causal +pathway. When two physical states have the same effect on the pathway—as +with two positions of the light switch both of which lead to the light being +on—they will correspond to the same information state. If we carve up +physical states in this way, we will arrive at a basic set of physical differences +that make a difference, making up the physical realization of an information +space. +The structure of the information space will correspond directly to the +structure of the space of effects, which will itself be either a discrete or +continuous space. In the case of the light, for example, there are two relevant +effects on the causal pathway: the light can be on or off. So the switch can +be seen to realize a two-state information space. +We can treat continuous information spaces in a similar way. If my light +has a dimmer switch, then rotating the knob to different positions produces +different intensities of light in a continuous range. (In practice the range may +be discrete, but I idealize.) The effects on light intensity define a continuous +information space realized in my light switch. Physical states of the switch +that produce the same light intensity (states in areas where the knob is in- + + 282 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +sensitive, perhaps, or states that vary in irrelevant parameters such as color +of the switch) will be associated with the same information state. The space +of information states has the topological structure of a continuum, with the +structure of differences between the states corresponding to the structure +of differences in the effect on light intensity. +The information realized in a compact disk can also be analyzed this way. +A disk has an infinite number of possible physical states, but when its effects +on a compact-disk player are considered, it realizes only a finite number +of possible information states. Many changes in the disk—a microscopic +alteration below the level of resolution of the optical reading device, or a +small scratch on the disk, or a large mark on the reverse side—make no +difference to the functioning of the system. The only differences relevant to +the disk's information state are those that are reflected in the output of the +optical reading device. These are the differences in the presence of pits and +lands on the disk, which correspond to what we think of as "bits." Any given +state of the disk will have an associated information state within a large +information space. The physical states of different pressings of the same +recording will be associated with the same information state, if all goes well. +Pressings of different recordings, or indeed imperfect pressings of the same +recording, will be associated with different information states, due to their +different effects. +This is a case in which a physically realized information space has combinatorial structure. Each "bit" on the compact disk has an independent effect +on the compact disk player, so that each location on the disk can be seen +to realize a two-state subspace of its own. Putting all these independent +effects together, we find a combinatorial structure in the space of total effects of a compact disk, and so we can find the same combinatorial structure +in the information space that the compact disk realizes. This information +space can be seen to be the product of a large collection of two-state subspaces, one for every pit or land on the disk. +Note that on this account, physically realized information is only information insofar as it can be processed. As Mackay (1969) puts it, "[I]nformation +is as information does." This squares with Shannon's own treatment of information. Shannon's "amount of information" measures how specific a state +is within the space of states that can be transmitted—that is, that can play +distinct roles on a different causal pathway (what Shannon calls a communication channel). For Shannon, information is always a transmittable state, and +indeed the extent of an information space is implicitly defined by the function +of a transmitter. Information is a difference that can make a difference +in transmission. +This is made clear by Shannon's standard diagram (Figure 8.1) and his +associated discussion. An information source is a set of "messages" (information states), where it is assumed that distinct messages are coded into distinct + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +283 + +Figure 8.1. Shannon's diagram of an information channel. (Diagram 1, from Claude +E. Shannon and Warren Weaver, The Mathematical Theory of Communication, 1963. +Copyright 1949 by the Board of Trustees of the University of Illinois Press. Used +with permission of the University of Illinois Press.) + +signals by a transmitter, and that distinct transmitted signals correspond to distinct messages. Indeed, this property defines what it is for states to count as +distinct messages. If two different physical states of the system are converted +into the same signal, then they realize the same message. Corruption and +loss of information may be introduced later in the process, as the right-hand +side of the diagram indicates, but it is constitutive of an information channel +that distinct information states produce different effects through a transmitter. All this is implicit rather than explicit in Shannon's account, where +there is no direct treatment of the relationship between physical states and +information states. But on a close look it is clear that when information +states are individuated, the transmittability principle is doing the work. +I will not try to give precise criteria for the realization of an information +space in a physical system. Instead, I will leave things at the informal level +of the "difference that makes a difference" principle. There are a number +of different ways in which this informal idea might be fleshed out into a +formal account, some of which put stronger constraints on realization than +others. It would be premature to settle on one of these in particular at this +point. By leaving things informal, we allow some room for maneuver in the +details, which can be clarified as we get a better idea of what is appropriate for a specific application. For the purpose of a theory of consciousness, +fleshing out these details in the right way will be part of the process of +fleshing out the theory. +Phenomenally realized information +Physical realization is the most common way to think about information +embedded in the world, but it is not the only way information can be found. + + 284 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +We can also find information realized in OUT phenomenology. States of experience fall directly into information spaces in a natural way. There are natural +patterns of similarity and difference between phenomenal states, and these +patterns yield the difference structure of an information space. Thus we can +see phenomenal states as realizing information states within those spaces. +For example, the space of simple color experiences has a three-dimensional relational structure that we have already discussed. Abstracting the +patterns of similarity and difference among these experiences, we obtain an +abstract information space with a three-dimensional relational structure +which the phenomenal space realizes. Any given simple color experience corresponds to a specific location within this space. A specific red experience is +one phenomenally realized information state; a specific green experience is +another. +More complex experiences, such as experiences of an entire visual field, +fall into information spaces with a complex combinatorial structure. When +I look at a picture, for example, my experience falls into a space with (at +least) the combinatorial structure of a two-dimensional continuum, with +each element in that continuum having (at least) the three-dimensional +relational structure of simple color space. The structure of color patches in +a visual field is not so different in kind from the structure of binary digits +in a ten-digit message, although both the combinatorial and the relational +structure are much more complex. +To find information spaces realized phenomenally, we do not rely on the +causal "difference that makes a difference" principle that we used to find +information spaces realized physically. Rather, we rely on the intrinsic qualities of experiences and the structure among them—the similarity and difference relations that they bear to each other, and their intrinsic combinatorial +structure. Any experience will bear natural relations of similarity and difference with other experiences, so we will always be able to find information +spaces into which experiences fall. +The double-aspect principle +This treatment of information brings out a crucial link between the physical +and the phenomenal: whenever we find an information space realized phenomenally, we find the same information space realized physically. And +when an experience realizes an information state, the same information state +is realized in the experience's physical substrate. +Take a simple color experience, realizing an information state within a +three-dimensional information space. We can find the same space realized +in the brain processes underlying the experience: this is the three-dimensional +space of neurally coded representations in the visual cortex. Elements of this + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +285 + +three-dimensional space correspond directly to elements of the phenomenal +information space. +We do not know exactly how these states are coded, and thus we do not +know exactly how the information space is physically realized. But we know +that it must be realized, as later processes show all the systematic effects of +informational realization. Our reports can vary systematically with the location in color space, for example, as when we assess colors as relatively +"darker" and "lighter"; and we can match objects with other objects according to their similarities and differences in color. So we know that there +must be relevant differences in the visual cortex that are transmittable to +other areas of the brain yielding a three-dimensional space of possible effects. +The states underlying any two indistinguishable experiences will have the +same relevant effects, even if there are slightly different physical details +associated—think of the analogy with small differences in the state of the +light switch—and states underlying any two similar experiences will have +similar effects. So we can see the visual cortex as realizing information states +in a three-dimensional space. +The same goes for more complex experiences, such as experiences of a +whole visual field. These are realized in a combinatorial information space, +and the same space must be physically realized in the underlying brain +processes. We know that for each location in the field, different simple experiences correspond to differences in various later effects, where these later +differences are separable according to the location in the field. For example, +we can respond separately to specific queries about the color at a given +location; this separate space of effects for each location yields a separate subspace for each location. So somewhere in the visual cortex, there +must be an encoding of a combinatorial information state, in order that all +the relevant differences can be transmitted to later processes. The space of +relevant possible states here is isomorphic to the space of possible experiences; so we can see the same information state realized both physically +and phenomenally. +It need not be the case that information is encoded locally, in a small +structure of neighboring neurons, for example. It is quite possible for information to be physically realized in a holistic fashion, as one finds for example +with certain holographic forms of information storage. The relevant differences in states of the visual cortex might correspond to differences spread +across the cortex. But as long as these are the differences that are transmitted +and that have the relevant effects, the information will be realized all the +same. +It is natural to suppose that this double life of information spaces corresponds to a duality at a deep level. We might even suggest that this double +realization is the key to the fundamental connection between physical pro- + + 286 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +cesses and conscious experience. We need some sort of construct to make +the link, and information seems as good a construct as any. It may be that +principles concerning the double realization of information could be fleshed +out into a system of basic laws connecting the physical and phenomenal +domains. +We might put this by suggesting as a basic principle that information (in +the actual world) has two aspects, a physical and a phenomenal aspect. +Wherever there is a phenomenal state, it realizes an information state, an +information state that is also realized in the cognitive system of the brain. +Conversely, for at least some physically realized information spaces, whenever an information state in that space is realized physically, it is also realized phenomenally.1 +This principle does not on its own come close to constituting a full psychophysical theory. Rather, it forms a sort of template for a psychophysical +theory by providing a basic framework in which detailed laws can be cast. +In fleshing out the principle into a theory, all sorts of questions need to be +answered. For example, to just which physically realized information spaces +does the basic principle apply? I will discuss this question further in section +4, but in the meantime I leave it open. Another sort of underspecificity stems +from the looseness of the definition of physically realized information: for +a fully specific psychophysical theory, we will need to know precisely what +it is for an information space to be physically realized. But all this is part of +the process of developing a theory. +Some other important questions concern the ontology of the view. How +seriously should we take the "double aspect" talk? To what extent will this +framework reify information, or treat it as real? Does it claim that the +physical, the phenomenal, or both, are ontologically dependent on the informational? I will leave all these questions open for now. Later in the chapter +I will consider various possible interpretations of the ontology. Some of +these interpretations take information simply as a useful construct in characterizing the psychophysical laws; others give it a more fundamental role in +the ontology. Similarly, some interpretations take the idea of a "double +aspect" more seriously than others. +In the meantime, I abstract away from these metaphysical issues. The +principle should simply be considered as a law connecting the physical and +phenomenal domains, with ontological implications that are not especially +different from those of the laws already considered. We already know that +experience arises from the physical in virtue of certain laws, which apply to +certain physical features of the world. The key suggestion here is that the +basic level at which the laws apply to the physical world is that of physically +realized information. +Of course, information may not be a primitive feature of the physical +world in the way that mass and charge are primitive, but it need not be + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +287 + +primitive to play a role in fundamental psychophysical laws. We already have +all the fundamental properties we need, in basic physical and phenomenal +properties. What we need now is a construct to connect the domains. Information seems to be a simple and straightforward construct that is well +suited for this sort of connection, and which may hold the promise of yielding a set of laws that are simple and comprehensive. If such a set of laws +could be achieved, then we might truly have a fundamental theory of consciousness. +It may just be, however, that there is a way of seeing information itself +as fundamental. The idea that physics ultimately deals in information has +already been canvased by some physicists, for example. If this idea could be +made to pan out, it could be that in some way the physical is derivative on +the informational, and the ontology of this view could be worked out very +neatly. I discuss some ideas along these lines later in the chapter. + +3. Some Supporting Arguments +I do not have any knockdown arguments to prove that information is the +key to the link between physical processes and conscious experience, but +there are some indirect ways of giving support to the idea. I have already +discussed the first sort of supporting consideration: the observation that the +same information spaces are realized physically and phenomenally. I will +mention another major source of support and two minor sources in what +follows. +The two minor sources of support lie with the fact that the double-aspect +view of information is compatible with the psychophysical principles developed earlier: in particular, the principle of structural coherence and the +principle of organizational invariance. These principles are strong constraints, +and it is not obvious how a fundamental theory could meet them, so it is a +mark in favor of the informational view that it is compatible with both. +The compatibility with structural coherence is particularly easy to see: in +some ways the informational view is tailor-made to satisfy this constraint. +The structure of experience is just the structure of a phenomenally realized +information space, and the structure of awareness is just the structure of a +physically realized information space. To see the first point, note that what +I have called the implicit structure of an experience corresponds to the relational structure of an information space, and what I have called the explicit structure of an experience corresponds to the combinatorial structure +of the space. To see the second, note that the various details in the structure +of awareness are by definition differences that make a difference in later +processing, as they are directly available for global control, and so are the +physical realization of an information space. Given that these two are in + + 288 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +fact realizations of the same information space, the principle of structural +coherence follows. +I should note that the double-aspect principle does not on its own ensure +that the structure of awareness will be projected into experience. To make +sure of that, we must show that the physical information space here is one +of those to which the double-aspect principle applies. For this, we would +need a more detailed version of the principle that narrows down the information spaces involved in an appropriate way, so that it at least includes information that is made available for global control in familiar cases. As it stands, +the double-aspect principle does not yet predict the full principle of structural +coherence, but at least it is compatible with it. +It is also not hard to see that the double-aspect principle is compatible +with the principle of organizational invariance. To see this, note that when +a system realizes an information space, it does so in virtue of its functional +organization. Any other system that is functionally isomorphic at a fine +enough grain will have the same pattern of differences that make a difference, +and therefore will realize the same information space. So if my experiences +arise in virtue of information spaces realized in my brain, then the same +information spaces will be realized in a functional isomorph, and the same +experiences will arise, as the invariance principle predicts. +A fundamental theory of consciousness will have to invoke physical features that are both organizationally invariant and simple enough to play a +role in fundamental laws. Most organizationally invariant features are not +very simple, and most simple features are not organizationally invariant. +Physically realized information may be the most natural feature that meets +both criteria. The fact that it meets both is a mark in favor of an informational +approach to psychophysical laws. +Explaining phenomenal judgments +Earlier, we saw that although consciousness cannot be reductively explained, +phenomenal judgments—judgments of the form "I am conscious," "Isn't +consciousness strange," and so on—can be so explained, at least in principle. +This put some strain on a nonreductive theory of consciousness, although it +did not appear to be fatal. It is counterintuitive that these judgments might +be explained without invoking consciousness itself, but it is something that +we can learn to live with. We can still hope, though, that the explanation of +phenomenal judgments will be tied in some deep way to the explanation of +consciousness itself. It would seem unreasonable and coincidental for these +two explanations to be entirely independent. +We can put this as a kind of explanatory coherence requirement on a +theory of consciousness. A completed theory of mind must provide both a +(nonreductive) account of consciousness and a (reductive) account of why + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +289 + +we judge that we are conscious, and it is reasonable to expect that these two +accounts will cohere with each other. In particular, we might expect that +those features of processing that are centrally responsible for bringing about +phenomenal judgments will also be those that are centrally responsible for +consciousness itself. In this way, even if consciousness itself is not part of +the explanation of phenomenal judgments, the roots of consciousness will be. +Of course one cannot prove that a theory of consciousness must satisfy +this requirement, but any theory of consciousness that satisfies it will have +an element of force to it that other theories will lack. If a theory shows how +the explanation of phenomenal judgments centrally involves the explanatory +basis of consciousness, then we will have woven the two together into a +more unified picture of the mind, and some of the feeling of outrageous +coincidence will be removed. +I have often thought that this might be the key to finding a theory of +consciousness.2 First, we need to do our best to understand why judgments +about consciousness are produced. This might be a difficult question, but it +should not involve deep metaphysical mysteries; in principle, it is a question +in the domain of cognitive science. Then, we need to abstract out the key +features in that explanation, and consider how they might play a role in a +theory of consciousness itself. There is no guarantee that this will lead to a +satisfying theory of consciousness, but it is a promising strategy. +The search for a reductive explanation of our judgments about consciousness is likely to be enlightening in any event, and among the most worthwhile +uses for reductive methods in working toward a theory of consciousness. +We might focus on why a processing system should produce judgments that +consciousness is present, and in particular, on why it should judge that +consciousness is such a strange phenomenon. I have already said a few +words in this direction in Chapter 5; here, I will go into more detail. The +"explanation" that I will give is merely a plausible-sounding just-so story, +but one can hope that it might be fleshed out, with the aid of empirical +research, into a detailed theory. There are likely to be rich rewards for cognitive science and neuroscience in coming to grips with these phenomena. +So, let us leave consciousness itself aside for the moment, and concentrate +on the cognitive processing system from a third-person point of view. Think +of this explanation as applying to a zombie, if you like. Why might we expect +that a processing system should produce this sort of judgment? What sort +of process might subserve the judgment that a color sensation is present, for +example? To think about this, consider what might be going on when we +perceive colors. +Without going into low-level details, the story is roughly as follows. A +particular spectral envelope of light impinges on our eyes, activating different +sorts of retinal cells. Three varieties of cones abstract out information according to the amount of light present in various overlapping wavelength + + 290 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +ranges. Immediately, many distinctions present in the original light wave are +lost. This information is transmitted down the optic nerve to the visual cortex, where it is further transformed by neural processing into information +corresponding to values on three axes: perhaps the red-green, yellow-blue, +and achromatic axes. What happens after this is poorly understood, but it +seems that information corresponding to a given color's position in this threedimensional space is preserved, before eventually being categorized into the +familiar category of "red," "green," "brown," and so on. Verbal categories +are attached to these labels, and eventually a report such as "I see red now" +is issued. +Now, let us take the system's "point of view" toward what is going on. +What sort of judgments will it form? Certainly it will form a judgment such +as "red object there," but if it is a rational, reflective system, we might also +expect it to be able to reflect on the process of perception itself. How does +perception "strike" the system, we might ask? +The crucial feature here is that when the system perceives a red object, +central processes do not have direct access to the object itself, and they do +not have direct access to the physical processes underlying perception. All +that these processes have access to is the color information itself, which is +merely a location in a three-dimensional information space. When it comes +to linguistically reporting on the situation, the system cannot report, "This +patch is saturated with 500- to 600-nanometer reflections," as all access to +the original wavelengths is gone. Similarly, it cannot report about the neural +structure, "There's a 50-hertz spiking frequency now," as it has no direct +access to neural structures. The system has access only to the location in +information space. +Indeed, as far as central processing is concerned, it simply finds itself in a +location in this space. The system is able to make distinctions, and it knows +it is able to make distinctions, but it has no idea how it does it. We would +expect after a while that it could come to label the various locations it is +thrown into—"red," "green," and the like—and that it would be able to +know just which state it is in at a given time. But when asked just how it +knows, there is nothing it can say, over and above "I just know, directly." +If one asks it, "What is the difference between these states?" it has no answer +to give beyond "They're just different," or "This is one of those," or "This +one is red, and that one is green." When pressed as to what that means, the +system has nothing left to say but "They're just different, qualitatively." +What else could it say? +It is natural to suppose that a system that can know directly the location +it occupies in an information space, without having access to any further +knowledge, will simply label the states as brutely and primitively different, +differing in their "quality." Certainly, we should expect these differences to + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +291 + +strike the system in an "immediate" way: it is thrown into these states which +in turn are immediately available for the direction of later processing; there +is nothing inferential, for example, about its knowledge of which state it is +in. And we should expect these states to be quite "ineffable": the system +lacks access to any further relevant information, so there is nothing it can +say about the states beyond pointing to their similarities and differences +with each other, and to the various associations they might have. Certainly, +one would not expect the "quality" to be something it could explicate in +more basic terms. +It might be objected that the system could be set up so that it accesses +the information as "hunches," in much the same way as a subject with +blindsight might. Perhaps it might say, "The judgment 'red' just popped into +my head," without any claims about "quality." But this would likely be an +inefficient setup, with the system required to wait on a hunch. And what of +the times—when one is playing tennis, say—when one needs to react to +visual information without forming judgments? Presumably the system +would say, "I just found myself knowing where the ball was and doing the +right thing, without experiencing it"? Perhaps this is a coherent scenario, +but it does not seem to be a natural design for a cognitive system. If one +were designing such a system, it would be much more natural to design it +so that it just "sees" the difference between red and green for itself, bases +its behavior immediately on the perceived difference, and responds confidently and directly when queried. In any case, the latter is at least one reasonable way that one might design a system, which is all that is needed here. +Given this kind of direct access to information states, then, it is natural +to expect the system to use the language of "experience" and "quality" to +describe its own cognitive point of view on perception. And it is unsurprising +that all this will seem quite strange to the system: these immediately known, +ineffable states, which seem so central to its access to the world but which +are so hard to pin down. Indeed, it is natural to suppose that this would +seem odd to the system in the same sort of way in which consciousness seems +odd to us. +So this is the beginning of a potential reductive explanation of our judgments about consciousness: these judgments arise because our processing +system is thrust into locations in information space, with direct access to +those locations but to nothing else. This direct knowledge will strike the system as a brute "quality": it knows that the states are different, but cannot articulate this beyond saying, in effect, "one of those." This immediate access +to brute differences leads to judgments about the mysterious primitive nature +of these qualities, about the impossibility of explicating them in more basic +terms, and to many of the other judgments that we often make about conscious experience. + + 292 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +In all this, it is information that plays the key role. It is because the system +has access only to information states that the various judgments of brute +"qualities" are formed. The system is simply thrust into different states, and +later processes have access only to the difference structure of these earlier +states, and not to anything concrete. What is doing the work here is a system +of differences that make a difference. It is information, and our access to it, +that reductively explains the judgments that we make about consciousness. +Some might end things here, declaring that the mystery of consciousness +has been removed and that an explanation has been given. Of course, I do +not think this is correct: we have only explained certain judgments, which +is a much more straightforward matter. But we can now use the principle +of explanatory coherence to gain some leverage in a theory of consciousness. +If the information states that are realized in this processing carry the main +responsibility for our judgments about consciousness, perhaps these information states carry responsibility for consciousness itself. +In fact, this is how I was led to the informational view of consciousness +in the first place. If the explanatory basis for our phenomenal judgments lies +in a structure of differences that make a difference, it is natural to suppose +that the explanatory basis for consciousness might lie in the same place. This +would explain why our judgments are so well tuned to actual states of consciousness. A conscious experience is a realization of an information state; +a phenomenal judgment is explained by another realization of the same +information state. And in a sense, postulating a phenomenal aspect of information is all we need to do to make sure those judgments are truly correct: +there really is a qualitative aspect to this information, showing up directly +in phenomenology and not just in a system of judgments. So this allows +consciousness to cohere very nicely with cognitive structure, leading to a +more tightly knit view of the mind. +We can also note that there is a nice fit between the cognitive role of +information states and the epistemology of experience. Corresponding to +experiences with which we are directly acquainted are physically realized information states to which the system has direct (cognitive) access. +The system forms its phenomenal judgments based on its direct access to +the information states; this causal connection maps nicely onto the claim +that the experience—the phenomenal realization of the same information +state—is what justifies the phenomenal beliefs that are formed. On both +sides, it is the same information state that is playing the crucial role; it is +just the physical realization in one case, and the phenomenal realization in +the other. +None of this is a knockdown proof that the information-based approach +to consciousness must be correct. But it does provide the approach with +further support. + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +293 + +4. Is Experience Ubiquitous? +By now, readers are probably lining up to object that information is ubiquitous. We find information everywhere, not just in systems that we standardly +take to be conscious. My compact-disk player realizes information; my car's +engine realizes information; even a thermostat realizes information. In fact, +as I have spelled out the notion, we find information everywhere we find +causation. We find causation everywhere, so we find information everywhere. +But surely we do not find experience everywhere? +There are two ways that a supporter of the information-based approach +might react to this situation. The first and most obvious is to look for further +constraints on the kind of information that is relevant to experience. Not +just any physically realized information space is associated with experience, +but only those with certain properties. This would require careful consideration of what the further constraints might be, and of how they might fit +into fundamental laws. I will consider strategies along these lines later, but +for now I wish to consider the alternative. This is to bite the bullet and +accept that all information is associated with experience. If so, then it is not +just information that is ubiquitous. Experience is ubiquitous too. +If this is correct, then experience is associated even with very simple +systems. This idea is often regarded as outrageous, or even crazy. But I think +it deserves a close examination. It is not obvious to me that the idea is +misguided, and in some ways it has a certain appeal. So here, I will examine the reasons one might reject the view, to see if they are compelling, +while simultaneously considering various positive reasons to take the view +seriously. + +What is it like to be a thermostat? +To focus the picture, let us consider an information-processing system that +is almost maximally simple: a thermostat. Considered as an informationprocessing device, a thermostat has just three information states (one state +leads to cooling, another to heating, and another to no action). So the claim +is that to each of these information states, there corresponds a phenomenal +state. These three phenomenal states will all be different, and changing the +information state will change the phenomenal state. We might ask: What is +the character of these phenomenal states? That is, what is it like to be a +thermostat? +Certainly it will not be very interesting to be a thermostat. The information +processing is so simple that we should expect the corresponding phenomenal +states to be equally simple. There will be three primitively different phenome- + + 294 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +nal states, with no further structure. Perhaps we can think of these states by +analogy to our experiences of black, white, and gray: a thermostat can have +an all-black phenomenal field, an all-white field, or an all-gray field. But +even this is to impute far too much structure to the thermostat's experiences, +by suggesting the dimensionality of a visual field, and the relatively rich +natures of black, white, and gray. We should really expect something much +simpler, for which there is no analog in our experience. We will likely be +unable to sympathetically imagine these experiences any better than a blind +person can imagine sight, or than a human can imagine what it is like to +be a bat; but we can at least intellectually know something about their +basic structure. +To make the view seem less crazy, we can think about what might happen to experience as we move down the scale of complexity. We start with +the familiar cases of humans, in which very complex information-processing +gives rise to our familiar complex experiences. Moving to less complex systems, there does not seem much reason to doubt that dogs are conscious, +or even that mice are. Some people have questioned this, but I think this is +often due to a conflation of phenomenal consciousness and self-consciousness. Mice may not have much of a sense of self, and may not be given to +introspection, but it seems entirely plausible that there is something it is like +to be a mouse. Mice perceive their environment via patterns of information +flow not unlike those in our own brains, though considerably less complex. +The natural hypothesis is that corresponding to the mouse's "perceptual +manifold," which we know they have, there is a "phenomenal manifold." +The mouse's perceptual manifold is quite rich—a mouse can make many +perceptual distinctions—so its phenomenal manifold might also be quite +rich. For example, it is plausible that for each distinction that the mouse's +visual system can make and use in perceiving the environment, there corresponds a phenomenal distinction. One cannot prove that this is the case, but +it seems to be the most natural way to think about the phenomenology of +a mouse. +Moving down the scale through lizards and fish to slugs, similar considerations apply. There does not seem to be much reason to suppose that phenomenology should wink out while a reasonably complex perceptual psychology persists. If it does, then either there is a radical discontinuity from +complex experiences to none at all, or somewhere along the line phenomenology begins to fall out of synchrony with perception, so that for a while, +there is a relatively rich perceptual manifold accompanied by a much more +impoverished phenomenal manifold. The first hypothesis seems unlikely, +and the second suggests that the intermediate systems would have inner lives +strangely dissociated from their cognitive capacities. The alternative is surely +at least as plausible. Presumably it is much less interesting to be a fish than + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +295 + +to be a human, with a simpler phenomenology corresponding to its simpler +psychology, but it seems reasonable enough that there is something there. +As we move along the scale from fish and slugs through simple neural +networks all the way to thermostats, where should consciousness wink out? +The phenomenology of fish and slugs will likely not be primitive but relatively +complex, reflecting the various distinctions they can make. Before phenomenology winks out altogether, we presumably will get to some sort of maximally simple phenomenology. It seems to me that the most natural place +for this to occur is in a system with a corresponding simple "perceptual +psychology," such as a thermostat. The thermostat seems to realize the sort +of information processing in a fish or a slug stripped down to its simplest +form, so perhaps it might also have the corresponding sort of phenomenology +in its most stripped-down form. It makes one or two relevant distinctions +on which action depends; to me, at least, it does not seem unreasonable that +there might be associated distinctions in experience. +Of course, there are other ways that things might go as we move down +the scale of complexity, and this is not any sort of demonstration that thermostats must have experiences. But this seems one reasonable way for things +to go, and on reflection perhaps as natural a way as any. It is arguable that +the reasoning involved here is just an extension of the reasoning whereby +we attribute experience to dogs or mice. At least, once we start to think +about what might be going on in the experience of a mouse, and the grounding +in its perceptual psychology, the extension to simpler systems begins to seem +much more natural than it might have at first. +Someone who finds it "crazy" to suppose that a thermostat might have +experiences at least owes us an account of just why it is crazy. Presumably +this is because there is a property that the thermostat lacks that is obviously +required for experience; but for my part no such property reveals itself as +obvious. Perhaps there is a crucial ingredient in processing that the thermostat lacks and a mouse possesses, or that a mouse lacks and a human possesses, +but I can see no such ingredient that is obviously required for experience, +and indeed it is not obvious that such an ingredient must exist. +Of course, to say that thermostats have experience is not to say that they +have much in the way of a mental life. A thermostat will not be self-conscious; +it will not be in the least intelligent; and I would not claim that a thermostat +can think.3 Some of the resistance to the idea of a conscious thermostat may +arise from running together experience with these other mental features, all +of which almost certainly require much more complexity. These features all +have a large psychological component, and it is likely that a complex system +would be needed to support the relevant causal roles. But once we have +distinguished phenomenal properties from psychological properties, the +idea of a conscious thermostat seems less threatening. We need imagine only + + 296 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +something like an unarticulated "flash" of experience, without any concepts, +any thought, or any complex processing in the vicinity. +Another reason why some may reject the idea of a conscious thermostat +is that one cannot find any room for consciousness in the system. It seems +too simple, and there seems no role for consciousness to play. But to have +this reaction is to fail to learn the lesson of the nonreductive view: one will +never find consciousness within a system on a close examination, and we +will always be able to understand processing without invoking consciousness. +If consciousness is not logically supervenient, we should not expect to have +to find "room" for consciousness in a system's organization; consciousness +is quite distinct from the processing properties of the system. +It may be that some are unwilling to accept the possibility of conscious +thermostats simply because we understand thermostats too well. We know +everything about their processing, and there seems no reason to invoke +consciousness. But thermostats are really no different from brains here. Even +once we understand brain processing perfectly, there will still seem to be no +reason to invoke consciousness. The only difference is that right now, what +is going on inside a brain is enough of a mystery that one may be tempted +to suppose that consciousness is somehow "located" in those brain processes +that we do not yet understand. But as I have argued, even coming to understand those processes will not alone bring consciousness into the picture; so +here, once again, brains and thermostats are on a par. +One might be bothered by the fact that one could build a thermostat +oneself, without putting any consciousness in. But of course the same applies +to a brain, at least in principle. When we build a brain (in reproduction and +development, say), consciousness conies along for free; the same will go for +a thermostat. We should not expect to locate consciousness as a physical +component of the system! Some may worry about the fact that a thermostat +is not alive; but it is hard to see why that should make a principled difference. A disembodied silicon brain of the sort discussed in the last chapter +would arguably fail to qualify as alive, but we have seen that it might be +conscious. And if the arguments in the last chapter are right, then the fact that +a thermostat is not made up of biological components makes no difference, in +principle. +Some intuitive resistance may come from the fact that there does not seem +to be room in a thermostat for someone or something to have the experiences: +where in the thermostat can a subject fit? But we should not be looking for +a homunculus in physical systems to serve as a subject. The subject is the +whole system, or better, is associated with the system in the way that a +subject is associated with a brain. The right way to speak about this is tricky. +We would not say that my brain has experiences, strictly speaking, but that +/ have experiences. However we make sense of this relation, the same will +apply to thermostats: strictly speaking it is probably best not to say that the + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +297 + +thermostat has the experiences (although I will continue to say this when +talking loosely), but that the experiences are associated with the thermostat. +We will not find a subject "inside" the thermostat any more than we will +find a subject inside a brain. +To return to positive points in favor of simple systems having experiences: +this way, we avoid the need for consciousness to "wink in" at a certain level +of complexity. There is something odd about the idea that a system with n +elements could not be conscious but a system with n + 1 elements could be. +And we cannot avoid making a decision in the way that we might avoid +making a decision about just when someone becomes "bald": in the latter +case, there is plausibly a degree of semantic indeterminacy, but it is much +less plausible that it can be indeterminate whether a system is conscious. +(This holds especially if we take a nonreductive view, on which we cannot +explicate facts about experience in terms of more basic facts, as we explicate +indeterminate issues about baldness in terms of determinate facts about the +number of hairs on a head.) While it could be the case that experience winks +in at a particular point, any specific point seems arbitrary, so a theory that +avoids having to make this decision gains a certain simplicity. +A final consideration in favor of simple systems having experience: if +experience is truly a fundamental property, it seems natural for it to be +widespread. Certainly all the other fundamental properties that we know +about occur even in simple systems, and throughout the universe. It would +be odd for a fundamental property to be instantiated for the first time only +relatively late in the history of the universe, and even then only in occasional +complex systems. There is no contradiction in the idea that a fundamental +property should be instantiated only occasionally; but the alternative seems +more plausible, if other things are equal. +Whither panpsychism? +If there is experience associated with thermostats, there is probably experience everywhere: wherever there is a causal interaction, there is information, +and wherever there is information, there is experience. One can find information states in a rock—when it expands and contracts, for example—or even +in the different states of an electron. So if the unrestricted double-aspect +principle is correct, there will be experience associated with a rock or an +electron. +(I would not quite say that a rock has experiences, or that a rock is +conscious, in the way that I might loosely say that a thermostat has experiences or is conscious. A rock, unlike a thermostat, is not picked out as an +information-processing system. It is simply picked out as an object, so the +connection to experience is less direct. It may be better to say that a rock +contains systems that are conscious: presumably there are many such subsys- + + 298 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +terns, none of whose experiences count canonically as the rock's (any more +than my experiences count as my office's). For the thermostat, by contrast, +there is a canonical associated information space, so it seems more reasonable to talk of the thermostat's canonical experiences. Of course even this +usage is somewhat loose, as noted above.) +The view that there is experience wherever there is causal interaction is +counterintuitive. But it is a view that can grow surprisingly satisfying with +reflection, making consciousness better integrated into the natural order. If +the view is correct, consciousness does not come in sudden jagged spikes, with +isolated complex systems arbitrarily producing rich conscious experiences. +Rather, it is a more uniform property of the universe, with very simple +systems having very simple phenomenology, and complex systems having +complex phenomenology. This makes consciousness less "special" in some +ways, and so more reasonable. +An interesting question is whether active causation is required for experience. Could a thermostat have experience when it is sitting in a constant +state (in a sense "causing" an output, but without really doing anything)? +Or does it have experience only when in a state of flux? Most of the causation underlying experience in the brain seems to be active, in that relevant +information is being processed constantly, neurons are firing, and so on. On +the other hand, it may be that the distinction between active and passive +causation cannot be drawn at a fundamental level, in which case the two +might be treated equally. I do not know the answer to this question, but +there is an intuition that some sort of activity is required for experience. +One possibility that I have not considered so far but that cannot be ruled +out is that simple systems do not have phenomenal properties, but have +protophenomenal properties. I mentioned in Chapter 4 the possibility that +there might be properties more fundamental than phenomenal properties +from which the latter are constituted. If there are indeed such properties +then it would seem natural for them to be instantiated in simple systems. If +so, then thermostats might not have experiences as we usually think of +them, but instead instantiate a related sort of property that we do not fully +understand (a sort of protoexperience, perhaps). This would retain the unified view of the natural order mentioned above, and might also help with +the "winking out" problem (if protophenomenal properties are fundamental, +then experiences constituted out of these properties might gradually "wink +in" after all). By not claiming that thermostats have full-fledged experiences, +this view may also seem a little less "crazy" than the alternative. Of course, +the cost is the postulation of a class of unfamiliar properties that we do not +understand; but the possibility has to be left open. +Either way, this view has a lot in common with what is often known as +panpsychism—the view that everything has a mind. There are a few reasons +I do not generally use the term myself: (1) because I think that having + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +299 + +experiences may fall well short of what we usually think of as having a +mind, although it may qualify as mind in its simplest form; (2) because +protophenomenal properties may be even further away from the usual concept of "mind"; (3) because I do not think it is strictly accurate to say that +rocks (for example) have experiences, for the reasons mentioned above, +although rocks may have experiences associated with them. Perhaps the +central reason why the term is misleading, though, is that it suggests a view +in which the experiences in simple systems such as atoms are fundamental, +and in which complex experiences are somehow the sum of such simpler +experiences. While this is one way things could go, there is no reason that +things have to go this way: complex experiences may be more autonomous +than this suggests. In particular, the informational view suggests a picture +on which complex experiences are determined more holistically than this. +With these caveats noted, it is probably fair to say that the view is a variety of panpsychism. I should note, however, that panpsychism is not at the +metaphysical foundation of my view: what is rather at the foundation is +naturalistic dualism with psychophysical laws. Panpsychism is simply one +way that the natural supervenience of experience on the physical might +work. In a sense, natural supervenience provides the framework; panpsychism is just one way of working out the details. +Personally, I am much more confident of naturalistic dualism than I am +of panpsychism.The latter issue seems to be very much open. But I hope to +have said enough to show that we ought to take the possibility of some +sort of panpsychism seriously: there seem to be no knockdown arguments +against the view, and there are various positive reasons why one might embrace it. +Constraining the double-aspect principle +Even if one is prepared to accept that very simple systems have experiences, +the idea that all information is associated with experience might still make +one uncomfortable. For example: only a small amount of the information +in human cognitive processing seems to correspond to the information in +conscious experience. Is it not simply a fact that most of our information +processing is unconscious? +If the unrestricted double-aspect principle is correct, then presumably the +answer is that all that "unconscious" information is realized in experience— +it is just not realized in my experience. For example, if there is experience +associated with one of my neurons in the way that there is experience +associated with a thermostat, we would not expect it to be part of my experience, any more than we would expect my experience to be radically +transformed if the neuron were replaced by a small conscious homunculus. +Similarly, there might be experience associated with various "unconscious" + + 300 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +information-processing subsystems in the brain—it is just that those experiences belong to a different subject. There are many different informationprocessing systems in the brain, and the one that corresponds to me—perhaps the system that makes some information available for a certain sort of +global control and report—is just one of them. I would not expect myself +to have direct access to the experiences of the other systems, any more +than I would expect myself to have direct access to the experiences of +other humans. +One might also worry about all the relatively complex information-processing systems in the world, found anywhere from my compact-disk player +to my stomach. Do all these qualify as conscious individuals with complex +experiences? In reply, it is worth noting that these systems do not have anything like the coherent cognitive structure of our own system, so that any +associated experiences are likely to be nothing like our own. If a compactdisk player has associated experiences, for example, it is likely to be nothing +more than a "flat" structure of bits; and if the information in my stomach +is associated with experience, then there is no reason to think this experience +would correspond to the sort of thing we think of as a mind. The sorts of +experience that we have will only arise when information-processing systems +have been shaped by evolution to have complex, coherent cognitive structures reflecting a rich representation of the outside world. It is likely that +only a very restricted group of subjects of experience would have the psychological structure required to truly qualify as agents or as persons. +Still, this great proliferation of experiences, especially the proliferation +within a single brain, might be cause for discomfort. This is exacerbated by +noting that when given an information space, it is usually easy to find many +slightly different information spaces simply by individuating a relevant causal +pathway differently, or by carving up the relevant effects (the "differences" +that the information makes) in a slightly different way. Are we to suppose +that there are different sets of experiences floating around for all these +information spaces? If so, then I might have a number of very close but +slightly different phenomenal relatives arising from the processes in my +own head! +The alternative is to constrain the double-aspect principle so that it narrows +down the class of physically realized information spaces that have phenomenal counterparts. The most natural strategy may be to constrain the way that +the information is processed. After all, I have already said that the information in my system that corresponds most directly to my experience is the +information that is directly available for global control. As it stands, this +"criterion" is most unlikely to play a role in a fundamental law, as it is too +vague and high-level a notion; indeed, we can use the principle only if we +have already individuated a high-level system such as a person or a brain. +But perhaps there is a more precise, simpler criterion that could do the work. + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +301 + +One possibility is that amplification of information is crucial. Physically +realized information is also realized in experience only if the information is +amplified in certain ways, becoming available to make a large difference +along certain causal pathways. Perhaps one could even say that the intensity +of an experience corresponds to the degree of amplification, or some such. +This could fit nicely with the global availability criterion, although it might +have other problems: there is plenty of amplified information that is not +intuitively conscious, for example; and it is not obvious just how the notion +of amplification is to be made precise. +Another possibility is that we could restrict the kind of causation involved +in a system. We have seen that wherever there is causation, there is information; but perhaps only a certain sort of causation counts in individuating +the information spaces underlying experience. Perhaps only certain sorts of +"active" causal relations are relevant, for example, or perhaps certain sorts +of "natural" causal relations are required. There is an intuition that many +of the information spaces that can be found according to the criteria given +so far are in a sense unnatural; perhaps there is a way to clarify the relevant +restriction. This would probably still let in a very wide class of information +states, but it might prevent an astronomical proliferation. +I am not certain of what the relevant constraining criterion should be, but +this is not to say that there might not be one. It might even be that a constraining criterion could restrict the relevant information spaces so that +information in simple systems such as thermostats does not qualify. My own +intuition is that there may well be a constraint on the double-aspect principle +but information in simple systems such as thermostats might qualify all the +same. For my part, the proliferation of many related experiences in the brain +seems more counterintuitive than the presence of experiences in simple systems, though neither matter is cut and dried. In any case, there are many different ways things might go, as the prototheory is elaborated into a theory. + +5. The Metaphysics of Information +The issue remains: How do we understand the ontology of the double-aspect +view of information? How seriously do we take this talk of information +spaces and information states: are these just useful constructs, or are they +in some way ontologically fundamental? Is information primary, or is it really +the physical and the phenomenal that are primary, with information merely +providing a useful link? +There are various ways all this might be understood. The most straightforward, and the least adventurous, is to take the physical and phenomenal +realizations of information to be wholly separate features, with no ontological link over and above a lawful connection and a sort of structural isomor- + + 302 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +phism. On this view, the ontology remains the straightforward ontology of +property dualism, with physical properties, separate phenomenal properties, +and a lawful connection between the two. Here, talk of a "double aspect" +must be taken in a deflationary way: it is merely a colorful way of talking +about two different sorts of correlated properties with a similar structure. +And information is simply a useful tool in characterizing this common structure; it does not correspond to anything ontologically "deep." +This may be a perfectly adequate way to look at things, but there are +some more interesting possibilities. Most of these involve taking the role of +information more seriously. I will consider one way of doing this in what +follows. The reader is warned that the discussion falls well into the realm +of speculative metaphysics, but speculative metaphysics is probably unavoidable in coming to terms with the ontology of consciousness. + +It from bit +It is sometimes suggested within physics that information is fundamental to +the physics of the universe, and even that physical properties and laws may +be derivative from informational properties and laws. This "it from bit" view +is put forward by Wheeler (1989, 1990) and Fredkin (1990), and is also +investigated by papers in Zurek (1990) and Matzke (1992, 1994). If this is +so, we may be able to give information a more serious role in our ontology. +To get a better grip on this, I will consider one key way in which information +can be seen as fundamental to physics. This is not the only way in which +the "it from bit" ideas have been put forward (in particular it differs somewhat from Wheeler's view),4 but it strikes me as perhaps the most natural +way of making sense of the notion. This interpretation is closely related to +the "Russellian" ideas discussed in Chapter 4 (pp. 153-55), as we will see. +This approach stems from the observation that in physical theories, fundamental physical states are effectively individuated as information states. When +we look at a feature such as mass or charge, we find simply a brute space +of differences that make a difference. Physics tells us nothing about what +mass is, or what charge is: it simply tells us the range of different values that +these features can take on, and it tells us their effects on other features. As +far as physical theories are concerned, specific states of mass or charge might +as well be pure information states: all that matters is their location within +an information space. +This is reflected in the fact that physics makes no commitment about the +way these states are realized. Any realization of these information states will +serve as well for the purposes of a physical theory, as long as it maintains +the correct structure of causal or dynamic relations between states. After +all, as long as the shape of these relations is the same, physics will look the +same to our perceptual systems: we do not have access to any further proper- + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +303 + +ties of the realization in the external world, over and above the shape of the +causal network. (Except, perhaps, insofar as our phenomenal properties are +tied directly to realizing properties.) +Sometimes it has even been suggested that the universe could be a giant +computer. Fredkin (1990) has suggested that the universe could be a huge +cellular automaton, realized at bottom in a vast structure of bits.5 Leckey +(1993) has suggested that all of space-time could be grounded in a computational process, with separate registers for each instantiated fundamental +feature of the world. As long as these registers have the appropriate causal +relations among them, none of the creatures in that world would be any the +wiser. The computer example illustrates the great range of possible ways +that the physical entities that we "know" can be realized, just as long as +there are entities that play the appropriate causal roles. This qualifies as part +of the "metaphysics of physics": speculation about the ontology underlying +the causal structure of space-time itself. +This sort of metaphysics is clearly not something that physics itself deals +in. Physics can remain quite neutral on these questions of how its features +are realized, and indeed about whether the features are "realized" in some +such way at all. As far as physics is concerned, the state of the world might +as well be exhausted by an informational characterization. If there are any +further underlying "realizing" properties, they play no direct role in physical theories. So one might be tempted to dispense with them altogether. +This would lead to a picture of the world as a world of pure information. +To each fundamental feature of the world there corresponds an information +space, and wherever physics takes those features to be instantiated, an information state from the relevant space is instantiated. As long as these information states have the right relations among them, then everything will be as +it needs to be. On this picture of the world, there is nothing more to say. +Information is all there is. +This is how I understand the "it from bit" conception of the world. It is +a strangely beautiful conception: a picture of the world as pure informational +flux, without any further substance to it. (Some versions of the view may +also allow space-time as a primitive framework within which the information +spaces are embedded; other versions see space-time itself as constituted by +the relations among information spaces.) The world is simply a world +of primitive differences, and of causal and dynamic relations among those +differences. On this view, to try to say anything further about the world is +a mistake. +Grounding information in phenomenology +There seem to be two main problems with this picture of the world. The +first is posed by consciousness itself. It seems that here, we have something + + 304 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +over and above a pure information space. Phenomenal properties have an +intrinsic nature, one that is not exhausted by their location in an information +space, and it seems that a purely informational view of the world leaves no +room for these intrinsic qualities. +The second problem is that it is not obvious that the notion of pure +informational flux is coherent. One may feel that on this view the world is +too lacking in substance to be a world. Could there be differences that are +primitive differences, not grounded in differences in any underlying quality? +One might find it plausible that every concrete difference in the world must +be grounded: that is, that it must be a difference in something. +This problem is closely related to the problems of the "pure causal flux" +view discussed in Chapter 4 (p. 153), of which this view is a variant. That +view subtracted the world of all intrinsic qualities, leaving a world of causal +relations, with nothing, it seemed, to do the causing. The current view may +do slightly better by allowing information states as what the causal relations +relate, but these states are remarkably insubstantial, being merely different +from each other and having no nature of their own. One might find this +picture of a world without intrinsic nature not to be a picture of a world at all. +Indeed, one might argue that information spaces must have something of +a further nature. It may be that two fundamental properties will have the +same sort of informational structure, both involving real quantities on a +continuum, for example. If physics is pure information, there will be nothing +to distinguish instantiations of the two information spaces. But there must +be some difference between them, as the two properties enter into quite +different laws, and have different effects on other features of the world. So +there must be something further to distinguish these instantiations; something that goes beyond pure information. It would seem that some sort of +intrinsic quality is needed to make the distinction. +There are a number of ways one might try to deal with these problems. +One could decide that the second problem is not in the end a fatal problem +and be happy with a physics of pure information; and then one could try to +incorporate phenomenal properties as lawfully tied to that information in +some fashion. Alternatively, one might answer the second problem by postulating intrinsic properties in which physical information spaces are grounded, +and deal with the first problem by introducing phenomenal properties +separately. +The most intriguing strategy, however, is to try to answer both problems +together. The first problem suggests that we have direct knowledge of some +intrinsic nature in the world, over and above pure information, in phenomenal properties; and the second suggests that we may need some intrinsic +nature in the world, to ground information states. Perhaps, then, the intrinsic +nature required to ground the information states is closely related to the +intrinsic nature present in phenomenology. Perhaps one is even constitutive + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +305 + +of the other. That way, we get away with a cheap and elegant ontology, and +solve two problems in a single blow. +Once again, this is closely related to the Russellian suggestion described +in Chapter 4, on which the unknown intrinsic properties of the world are +themselves taken to be phenomenal (or protophenomenal) properties. Russell needed these properties to underlie the causal relations given by physics, +and we need them here to ground the information states (the differences +that make a difference) postulated by physics. These are essentially the same +problem. In both cases, we have the feeling of two solutions for the price +of one. We need some intrinsic properties to make sense of the physical +world, and we need to find a place for the intrinsic properties revealed in +phenomenology. The two problems seem to be well-matched. +So the suggestion is that the information spaces required by physics are +themselves grounded in phenomenal or protophenomenal properties. Each +instantiation of such an information space is in fact a phenomenal (or protophenomenal) realization. Every time a feature such as mass and charge is +realized, there is an intrinsic property behind it: a phenomenal or protophenomenal property, or a microphenomenal property for short. We will have +a set of basic microphenomenal spaces, one for each fundamental physical property, and it is these spaces that will ground the information spaces +that physics requires. The ultimate differences are these microphenomenal +differences. +Of course, this view again requires a variety of "outrageous" panpsychism, but I have already argued that such a panpsychism is not as unreasonable +as commonly supposed. Given that I have already suggested that there may +be phenomenal properties wherever there is information, we might as well +press these properties into service in a useful role. +The ontology that this leads us to might truly be called a double-aspect +ontology. Physics requires information states but cares only about their +relations, not their intrinsic nature; phenomenology requires information +states, but cares only about the intrinsic nature. This view postulates a single +basic set of information states unifying the two. We might say that internal +aspects of these states are phenomenal, and the external aspects are physical. Or as a slogan: Experience is information from the inside; physics is +information from the outside. +What about macroscopic phenomenology? +All this works very nicely as ontology, although it is certainly on the wild +side. But before we get too carried away, an enormous question remains: +How can this ontology be made compatible with the details of a psychophysical theory? In particular, how can it be made compatible with psychophysical regularities at the macroscopic level? The trouble is that the double-aspect + + 306 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +principle here applies at the fundamental physical level, with microscopic, +physically realized information having a phenomenal realization. But for the +purposes of a theory of consciousness, we need macroscopic, physically +realized information to have a phenomenal realization also. And it is not at +all obvious that this sort of "macroscopic phenomenology" can be derived +from the microscopic phenomenology. +On the face of it, our conscious experience does not seem to be any sort +of sum of microphenomenal properties corresponding to the fundamental +physical features in our brain, for example. Our experience seems much +more holistic than that, and much more homogeneous than any simple sum +would be. This is a version of the "grain problem," raised by Sellars (1965) +as a problem for materialism: How could an experience be identical to a +vast collection of physiological events, given the homogeneity of the former +and the fine-grainedness of the latter? The analogous problem is particularly +pressing for Russellian views of the sort I am discussing.6 If the roots of +phenomenology are exhausted by microphenomenology, then it is hard to +see how smooth, structured macroscopic phenomenology could be derived: +we might expect some sort of "jagged," unstructured phenomenal collection instead. +There are various ways one might try to handle this. First, one might try +to set things up so that the double-aspect ontology holds at all levels, not +just at the microscopic level. That is, even physical information spaces at +the macroscopic level are grounded in a phenomenal realization. It can be +argued that there is nothing privileged about the microscopic level: things +are simpler there, but it need not be ontologically special. The arguments +we have given for seeing the physical world in informational terms also apply at the macroscopic level. One could argue that even at this level, there +is just a space of macroscopic differences that make a difference, each of +which could be realized in corresponding phenomenology. +The trouble is that there may not be room for all these separate phenomenal realizations. Once we have fundamental physical features realized in +phenomenal information spaces, then macroscopic information seems to +be grounded already: the differences that make a difference here are now +grounded in configurations of microscopic physical features, which are themselves grounded in microphenomenology. One could try to introduce a separate phenomenal grounding all the same, but this would seem to be redundant, and less theoretically elegant than the corresponding move in the +microscopic case. One could try to remove the redundancy by making macroscopic grounding primary, but it would then be hard to deal with cases of +isolated microscopic systems and the like. So it is not clear that the "grounding" approach to the double-aspect ontology can work directly at the +macroscopic level. + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +307 + +Second, one could try to understand a way in which macroscopic phenomenology might be constituted by these microphenomenal properties. On the +face of it, it does not seem to be any simple sum or collection of these +properties; that would lead directly to "jaggedness" problems. But perhaps +the problem is just that we do not understand the mental part-whole relation, +as Nagel (1986) has put it. That is, we lack an accurate conception of the +way in which low-level microphenomenal properties "add up" to yield highlevel phenomenology. We tend to think about this in terms of a physical +analogy, based on the way in which microphysics adds up to macrophysics, +but this may be the wrong way to think about it. Perhaps phenomenology +is constituted in a different way entirely. +For example, it might be that microphenomenal properties add up to +macrophenomenology in a way that reflects their joint informational structure, rather than their joint spatiotemporal structure. If a collection of these +properties jointly realize a complex information state by virtue of the causal +relations between them, perhaps we could expect any derived macrophenomenology to have the shape of that information state. After all, the central +role of the microphenomenal properties is to realize information states, so +it would not be entirely surprising for informational structure to play a role +in the constitutional relations between the properties. If this were so, then any +derived macrophenomenal states would have the "smooth" informational +structure that the original double-aspect principle predicts. This is not easy +to understand, but after all we cannot expect our everyday understanding +of the physical domain to apply to the phenomenal domain. So it may just +be that a better understanding of the nature of phenomenology itself would +be compatible with this view of its constitution. +If it turned out that no constitution relation could work this way, we might +try the third option, which is to link macrophenomenology to microphenomenology by laws.7 For example, it could simply be a law that when microphenomenal states realize an information state of a certain sort by virtue of the +causal relations between them (by the "difference that makes a difference" +principle), then a direct phenomenal realization of the same state will arise. +This would solve the theoretical problems, at the cost of complicating the +ontology. No longer would we have the simple ontology with phenomenology +being the intrinsic aspect of physically realized information: some phenomenology would be "dangling" from this information by laws in the fashion of +a more standard property dualism. So some of the attraction of a Russellian +view would be lost, although the view would still be quite coherent. +In any case, I will leave this question open. It is certainly the hardest +problem for any sort of Russellian view; but it is not obvious that it cannot +be solved. If it could be made to work, the second strategy seems a particularly promising way to go; or it might be that some entirely new idea + + 308 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +is needed to solve this problem. Looking at things optimistically, we can +see the problem—how to make a psychophysical theory compatible with +both the macro-level facts about our phenomenology and its physical basis +and the micro-level ontology of the Russellian view—as one of the crucial +constraints that might eventually lead us to a detailed theory of consciousness. +One of the difficulties in constructing such a theory is that there are not +many constraints around. It might just be that this problem could provide +some much-needed focus. +If none of these strategies turns out to be satisfactory, we will have to +retreat from the Russellian view to some other view of the metaphysics. One +might try to work with the metaphysics of pure information, for example, +as a way of understanding the physical world; and then somehow hook +phenomenology up, perhaps by way of a lawful connection to pure information. Or one could simply retreat to the "tame" ontology with separate +physical and phenomenal realms, each with their own intrinsic nature, tied +together by lawful connections along the lines of the information principle. +This would mean that talk of a "double aspect" would have to be taken less +seriously, and the ontology would be somewhat less elegant, but it could +still lead to a perfectly satisfactory theory. + +6. Open Questions +The sketch I have given of the informational framework for psychophysical +laws leaves an enormous number of questions open. For the picture to be +turned into a final theory, all of these questions would have to be answered. +I have mentioned a few problems about the ontology of the view in the +previous section. But there are also numerous questions about the shape of +the laws, and about just how our phenomenology is to be explained. Some +of these questions include: +1. When an information space is phenomenally realized, why is it realized one way rather than another? For example, given that our phenomenal color space might have been inverted, it seems somewhat +arbitrary that it is the way it is. Do we need to add further laws, or +postulate contingent "constants," to settle this matter? +2. Is the character of a phenomenal information space settled by the +structure of the space (or at least settled up to the possibility of inversions)? It might seem, for example, that color space and taste +space are both simple three- or four-dimensional spaces, but they have +very different characters despite their similar shape. It is arguable that +the similarity in the structures is an illusion, and that when we embed +both of these in a wider structure—seeing color experiences as part + + Consciousness and Information: Some Speculation + +309 + +of the full, deep structure of visual experiences, for example—the +similarity will disappear. But the question remains: Is something with +the approximate character of our color experiences the only way that +visual color information might have been projected into phenomenology, or is there a different way entirely? I suspect that the answer +may be closer to the former than to the latter, but it is not at all +obvious how one would go about arguing for this. +3. I have used this framework mostly to discuss simple perceptual experiences, such as color experiences. It is not obvious how one would +extend it to deal with more subtle experiences, such as complex +emotional experiences, for example, and the experience of occurrent +thought. Can this extension be made? +4. What sort of formal structure is best suited for capturing the structure of phenomenal information? What sort of topological spaces +are needed to capture the relational structure of experience? Should +we move to a more specific sort of structure, such as a metric space +or a differential manifold? The combinatorial structure of an experience is even more interesting: a simple multidimensional continuum is probably a great simplification of the structure of a visual +field, for example. How can we best capture the full structure? Should +the definition of an information space be modified for this purpose? +5. How, within this framework, can one account for the unity of consciousness? That is, what makes my visual experiences, auditory experiences, and so on, all experiences of the same subject? I suspect +that the answer involves the way that the relevant information is +processed, so that the unity of consciousness corresponds to the fact +that the relevant information is available to be integrated in a certain +way. But just how to cash this out is unclear. +6. What, exactly, are the criteria that determine which information in +the brain corresponds to my experiences? Is there a particular causal +pathway, or a particular sort of causal flux, that is relevant? Presumably something like direct availability for global control plays a +central role here, in individuating the information and the relevant +pathways. +The existence of all these questions shows just how far these sketchy ideas +are from being a true theory. Another way of seeing this is to note how far +these ideas are from allowing us to predict exactly what the phenomenal +properties associated with a physical system will be from the physical properties of the system. As it stands, the idea lacks a strong explanatory and +predictive power, it needs to be beefed up considerably in order to be +truly useful. + + 310 + +Toward a Theory of Consciousness + +A number of new insights would be required to turn this idea into a +satisfying theory. Perhaps a breakthrough could come from considering the +problem of the previous section: how to square phenomenal information +on the macroscopic scale with the "intrinsic property" view of information +at the microscopic scale. Another might come from trying to find a constraint +that yields the class of physically realized information spaces that are realized +in experience. Others may come from sources I have not considered at all. +The idea may prove to be entirely misguided. That would not surprise +me; in fact, I think it is more likely than not that the key to a fundamental +theory will lie elsewhere. But I have put these ideas forward because we +need to start thinking about these matters, and because seeing even an +inadequate example in the genre may be instructive. I also hope that some +of the ideas raised along the way—about how to explain phenomenal judgments, about the ubiquity of experience, and about the connection between +experience, information, and intrinsic properties of the physical—may turn +out to be useful even when translated into a different framework. Perhaps +a more adequate theory of consciousness could share something of the feel +of the ideas put forward here, even if its details are very different. +It is often said that the problem with theories of consciousness of this sort +is that they are too speculative and untestable. But I think the real problem +with the "theory" I have put forward is different: it is too unspecific in its +predictions, If we had a theory of a comparable level of simplicity that could +predict all the specific facts about our experiences—even only those facts +familiar from the first-person case—when given the physical facts about our +processing system, that would be a remarkable achievement, and would give +us very good reason to accept the theory as true. Right now we have no +such theory, but there is no reason to believe that such a theory is impossible. + + PART IV + +Applications + + This page intentionally left blank + + 9 + +Strong Artificial Intelligence + +1. Machine Consciousness +Could a machine be conscious? Could an appropriately programmed computer truly possess a mind? These questions have been the subject of an +enormous amount of debate over the last few decades. The field of artificial +intelligence (or AI) is devoted in large part to the goal of reproducing mentality in computational machines.So far progress has been limited, but supporters argue that we have every reason to believe that eventually computers +will truly have minds. At the same time, opponents argue that computers +are limited in a way that human beings are not, so that it is out of the +question for a conscious mind to arise merely in virtue of computation. +Objections to artificial intelligence typically take one of two forms. First, +there are external objections, which try to establish that computational systems could never even behave like cognitive systems. According to these +objections, there are certain functional capacities that humans have that no +computer could ever have. For example, sometimes it is argued that because +these systems follow rules, they could not exhibit the creative or flexible +behavior that humans exhibit (e.g., Dreyfus 1972). Others have argued that +computers could never duplicate human mathematical insight, as computational systems are limited by Godel's theorem in a way that humans are not +(Lucas 1961; Penrose 1989). +External objections have been difficult to carry through, given the success +of computational simulation of physical processes in general. In particular, +it seems that we have good reason to believe that the laws of physics are +computable, so that we at least ought to be able to simulate human behavior +computationally. Sometimes this is disputed, by arguing for a noncomputable + + 314 + +Applications + +element in physical laws (as Penrose does), or by arguing for nonphysical +causation (as Lucas does), but it is clear that those putting forward these +objections are fighting an uphill battle. +More prevalent have been what I call internal objections. These objections +concede at least for the sake of argument that computers might simulate +human behavior, but argue that they would lack minds all the same. In +particular, it is suggested that they would have no inner life: no conscious +experience, no true understanding. At best, a computer might provide a +simulation of mentality, not a replication. The best known objection in this +class is John Searle's "Chinese room" argument (Searle 1980). According +to these objections, computational systems would at best have the hollow +shell of a mind: they would be silicon versions of a zombie. +Those who take a nonreductive view of conscious experience have often +been attracted to internal objections to artificial intelligence, with many +arguing that no mere computer could be conscious. Indeed, those who have +been impressed by the problem of consciousness have sometimes characterized the problem by pointing to consciousness as the feature that we have +but that any computer would lack! Many have found it hard to believe that +an artificial, nonbiological system could be the sort of thing that could give +rise to conscious experience. +A nonreductive view of consciousness does not automatically lead to a +pessimistic view of AI, however. The two issues are quite separate. The +first concerns the strength of the connection between physical systems and +consciousness: Is consciousness constituted by physical processes, or does it +merely arise from physical processes? The second concerns the shape of the +connection: Just which physical systems give rise to consciousness? Certainly +it is not obvious that executing the right sort of computation should give +rise to consciousness; but it is not obvious that neural processes in a brain +should give rise to consciousness, either. On the face of it, there is no clear +reason why computers should be any worse off than brains in this regard. +Given that we have accepted the surprising fact that brains give rise to +consciousness, it would not be a further sort of surprise to find that computation might give rise to consciousness. So the mere embrace of a nonreductive +view of consciousness ought to leave the matter open. +In this chapter, I will take things further and argue that the ambitions of +artificial intelligence are reasonable (Figure 9.1). In particular, I will argue +for the view that Searle calls strong artificial intelligence: that there is a +nonempty class of computations such that the implementation of any computation in that class is sufficient for a mind, and in particular, is sufficient for +the existence of conscious experience. This sufficiency holds only with natural +necessity, of course: it is logically possible that any computation might take +place in the absence of consciousness. But the same goes for brains, as we + + Strong Artificial Intelligence + +315 + +Figure 9.1. Bloom County on strong AI. (© 1985, Washington Post Writers Group. +Reprinted with permission) + +have seen. In evaluating the prospects of machine consciousness in the actual +world, it is natural possibility and necessity we are concerned with. +(Lest this conclusion be thought a triviality, given the panpsychist suggestions in the last chapter, I note that nothing in this chapter rests on those +considerations. Indeed, I will argue not just that implementing the right +computation suffices for consciousness, but that implementing the right computation suffices for rich conscious experience like our own.) +I have already done most of the work required for this defense of strong +AI, in arguing for the principle of organizational invariance in Chapter 7. If +that argument is correct, it establishes that any system with the right sort of +functional organization is conscious, no matter what it is made out of. So +we already know that being made of silicon, say, is no bar to the possession +of consciousness. What remains to be done is to clarify the link between +computation and functional organization, in order to establish that implementing an appropriate computation is sufficient to ensure the presence of +the relevant functional organization. Once this is done, strong AI falls out +as a consequence. I will also answer a number of objections that have been +put forward against the strong AI enterprise. + +2. On Implementing a Computation +In its standard form, the theory of computation deals wholly with abstract +objects: Turing machines, Pascal programs, finite-state automata, and so +on. These are mathematical entities inhabiting mathematical space. Cognitive systems in the real world, on the other hand, are concrete objects, +physically embodied and interacting causally with other objects in the physical world. But often we want to use the theory of computation to draw +conclusions about concrete objects hi the real world. To do this, we need a +bridge between the abstract and concrete domains.1 + + 316 + +Applications + +This bridge is the notion of implementation: the relation between abstract +computational objects—"computations" for short—and physical systems +that holds when a physical system "realizes" a computation, or when a +computation "describes" a physical system. Computations are often implemented on synthetic, silicon-based computers, but they can be implemented +in other ways. Natural systems such as the human brain are often said to +implement computations, for example. Computational descriptions are +used to make sense of physical systems in all sorts of domains. Whenever +this happens, a notion of implementation is implicitly or explicitly doing the +work. +The notion of implementation is rarely analyzed in detail; it is usually +simply taken for granted. But to defend strong AI, we need a detailed account +of it. The strong AI thesis is cast in terms of computation, telling us that +implementation of the appropriate computation suffices for consciousness. +To evaluate this claim, we need to know just what it is for a physical system +to implement a computation. Once we know this, we can combine it with +our earlier analysis of psychophysical laws to determine whether the conclusion might follow. +Some have argued that no useful account of implementation can be given. +In particular, Searle (1990b) has argued that implementation is not an objective matter, but instead is "observer-relative": any system can be seen to +implement any computation if interpreted appropriately. Searle holds, for +example, that his wall can be seen to implement the Wordstar word processing program. If this were so, it would be hard to see how computational +notions could play any foundational role in a theory that ultimately deals +with concrete systems. As for strong AI, it would either be emptied of +content or would imply a strong form of panpsychism. But I think this sort +of pessimism is misplaced: an objective account of implementation can +straightforwardly be given. In this section I will outline such an account. +(The account is a little technical, but the rest of the chapter should make +sense even if the details here are skimmed.) +Any account of what it is for a computation to be implemented will +depend on the class of computations in question. There are many different +computational formalisms, with correspondingly different classes of computations: Turing machines, finite-state automata, Pascal programs, connectionist networks, cellular automata, and so on. In principle, we need an +account of implementation for each of these formalisms. I will give an account +of implementation for a single formalism, that of combinatorial-state automata. This class of computations is sufficiently general that the associated +account of implementation can be easily extended to apply to other classes. +A combinatorial-state automaton is a more sophisticated cousin of a finitestate automaton. A finite-state automaton (FS A) is specified by giving a finite +set of inputs, a finite set of internal states, and a finite set of outputs, and + + Strong Artificial Intelligence + +317 + +by giving an associated set of state transition relations. An internal state of +an FSA is a simple element Si without any internal structure; the same +goes for inputs and outputs. The state transition relations specify, for every +possible pair of inputs and internal states, a new internal state and an output. +If the initial state of an FSA is given, these state transition relations specify +how it will evolve over time and what outputs it will produce, depending on +what inputs are received. The computational structure of an FSA consists +in this relatively simple set of state transition relations among a set of unstructured states. +Finite-state automata are inadequate to represent the structure of most +computations that are relevant in practice, as the states and state transition +relations in these computations generally have complex internal structure. +No FSA description can capture all the structure present in a Pascal program, for example, or a Turing machine, or a cellular automaton. It is +therefore more useful to concentrate on a class of automata that have structured internal states. +Combinatorial-state automata (CSAs) are just like FSAs, except that their +internal states are structured. A state of a CSA is a vector [S1, S 2 ,..., Sn]. +This vector can be either finite or infinite, but I will focus on the finite case. +The elements of this vector can be thought of as the components of the +internal state; they correspond to the cells in a cellular automaton or the +tape-squares and head-state in a Turing machine. Each element S', can take +on a finite number of values Sj, where Sj is the jth possible value of the ith +element. These values can be thought of as "substates" of the overall state. +Inputs and outputs have a similar sort of complex structure: an input is a +vector [I1, ...,I k ], and an output is a vector [O 1 ,..., Om]. +A CSA is determined by specifying the set of internal state vectors and +input and output vectors, and by specifying a set of state transition rules that +determine how the state of the CSA evolves with time. For each element +of the internal-state vector, a state transition rule determines how its new +value depends on old values of the input and internal state vectors. For each +element of the output vector, a state transition rule determines how its new +value depends on old values of the internal state vector. Every finite CSA +can be represented as an FSA with equal computational power, but the FSA +description will sacrifice most of the structure that is crucial to a CSA. That +structure is central in using CSAs to capture the organization that underlies +a mind. +We are now in a position to give an account of implementation. Computations such as CSAs are abstract objects, with a formal structure determined +by their states and state transition relations. Physical systems are concrete +objects, with a causal structure determined by their internal states and the +causal relations between the states. Informally, we say that a physical system +implements a computation when the causal structure of the system mirrors + + 318 + +Applications + +the formal structure of the computation. That is, the system implements the +computation if there is a way of mapping states of the system onto states of +the computation so that physical states that are causally related map onto +formal states that are correspondingly formally related. +This intuitive idea can be straightforwardly applied to yield an account of +implementation for CSAs. A physical system implements a CSA if there is +a decomposition of internal states of the system into substates, a decomposition of the system's inputs and outputs into input and output substates, and +a mapping from substates of the system onto substates of the CSA, such +that the causal state transition relations between physical states, inputs, and +outputs reflect the formal state transition relations between the corresponding formal states, inputs, and outputs. +The formal criterion for implementing a CSA is as follows: +A physical system P implements a CSA M if there is a decomposition of +internal states of P into components [s 1 ,... ,s"], and a mapping /from +the substates s' into corresponding substates Sj of M, along with similar +decompositions and mappings for inputs and outputs, such that for every +state transition rule ([I 1 ,... ,Ik], [S 1 ,... ,Sn]) ---> ([S' 1 ,..., Sn], +[O 1 ,..., O1]) of M: if P is in internal state [s1,..., s"] and receives input +[i1,..., in], which map to formal state and input [S 1 ,..., Sn] and [I 1 ,..., Ik] +respectively, this reliably causes it to enter an internal state and produce +an output that map to [S' 1 ,..., S'n] and [O 1 ,..., O1] respectively. +We may stipulate that in a decomposition of the state of a physical system +into a vector of substates, the value of each element of the vector must +supervene on a separate region of the physical system, to ensure that the +causal organization relates distinct components of the system. Otherwise, it +is not clear that the detailed causal structure is really present within the +physical system. There is room to tinker with this and with other details in +the definition above. The notion of implementation is not written in stone, +and it might be tightened or loosened for various purposes. But this gives +the basic shape that will be shared by any account of implementation. +It may seem that CSAs are not much of an advance on FSAs. After +all, for any finite CSA, we can find a corresponding FSA with the same +input-output behavior. But there are some crucial differences. First and +foremost, the implementation conditions on a CSA are much more constrained than those of the corresponding FSA. An implementation of a CSA +is required to consist in a complex causal interaction among a number of +separate parts; a CSA description can therefore capture the causal organization of a system to a much finer grain. Second, CSAs provide a unified account +of the implementation conditions for both finite and infinite machines. And +third, a CSA can directly reflect the complex formal organization of computa- + + Strong Artificial Intelligence + +319 + +tional objects such as Turing machines and cellular automata. In the corresponding FSA, much of this structure would be lost. +Indeed, we can use this definition of implementation to straightforwardly +provide implementation criteria for other sorts of computations. To specify +what it takes to implement a Turing machine, for example, we need merely +redescribe a Turing machine as a CSA and apply the definition above. To +do this, we describe the state of the Turing machine as a giant vector. One +element of the vector represents the state of the machine head, and there +is an element for each square of the tape, representing the symbol in the +square and also indicating whether or not the machine head occupies that +square. The state transition rules between the vectors are those derived +naturally from the mechanisms specifying the behavior of the machine head +and the tape. Of course, the vectors here are infinite, but the implementation +conditions in the infinite case are a straightforward extension of those in the +finite case. Given this translation from the Turing machine formalism to the +CSA formalism, we can say that a Turing machine is implemented whenever +the corresponding CSA is implemented. We can give similar translations +of computations in other formalisms, such as cellular automata or Pascal +programs, yielding implementation conditions for computations in each of +these classes. +This yields a perfectly objective criterion for implementing a computation. +Implementation of a computation does not collapse into vacuity in the way +that Searle suggests. It is true that some computations will be implemented +by every system. For example, the single-element, single-state CSA will be +implemented by every system, and a two-state CSA will be implemented +almost as widely. It is also true that most systems will implement more than +one computation, depending on how we carve up that system's states. There +is nothing surprising about this: it is only to be expected that my workstation +implements a number of computations, as does my brain. +What is crucial is that there is no reason to believe that every CSA will +be implemented by every system. For any given complex CSA, very few +physical systems will have the causal organization required to implement it. +If we take a CSA whose state vectors have one thousand elements, with +ten possibilities for each element, then arguments along the lines of those +presented in Chapter 7 suggest that the chance of an arbitrary set of physical +states having the requisite causal relations is something less than one in +(101000)101000 (actually much less than this, because of the requirement that the +transition relations be reliable).2 +What of Searle's claim that computational descriptions are "observerrelative," then? It is true that there is a limited degree of observer relativity: +any given physical system will implement a number of computations, and +which one of these an observer chooses to focus on will depend on her +purposes. But this is not threatening to AI or computational cognitive sci- + + 320 + +Applications + +ence. It remains the case that for any given computation, there is a fact of +the matter about whether or not a given system implements it, and there +will be only a limited class of systems that qualify as implementations. For +computational accounts to have metaphysical and explanatory bite, this is +all that the fields require. +To say that a physical system implements a given complex computation +P is to say something very substantial about the causal structure of that +system, something that may be quite useful in providing cognitive explanations and perhaps in understanding the basis of consciousness. Only systems +with a very specific sort of causal organization will have a hope of satisfying +the strong constraints of implementation. So there is no danger of vacuity, +and there is room to hope that the notion of computation can provide a substantial foundation for the analysis of cognitive systems. + +3. In Defense of Strong AI +What it takes to implement a CSA is strikingly similar to what it takes to +realize a functional organization. Recall that a functional organization is determined by specifying a number of abstract components, a number of states +for each component, and a system of dependency relations indicating how +the states of each component depend on previous states and on inputs, and +how outputs depend on previous states. The notion of a CSA is effectively +a direct formalization of this notion. +Indeed, given any functional organization of the sort described in Chapter +7, it can be straightforwardly abstracted into a CSA. We need only stipulate that the CSA's state vectors have an element for each component of +the organization, and that the formal state transitions between the CSA +states correspond to the causal dependency relations between components. +To realize the functional organization comes to almost exactly the same +thing as implementing the corresponding CSA. There are a few small differences, such as different treatments of inputs and outputs, but these are +not significant. +The account of implementation that I have given thus makes clear the +link between causal and computational organization. This way, we can see +that when computational descriptions are applied to physical systems, they +effectively provide a formal description of the systems' causal organization. +The language of computation provides a perfect language in which this +sort of abstract causal organization can be specified. Indeed, it can be argued +that this is precisely why computational notions have had such wide application throughout cognitive science. What is most relevant to the explanation of the behavior of a complex cognitive system is the abstract causal +organization of the system, and computational formalisms provide an ideal + + Strong Artificial Intelligence + +321 + +framework within which this sort of organization can be described and +analyzed.3 +This link makes the defense of strong artificial intelligence straightforward. +I have already argued for the principle of organizational invariance, which +tells us that for any system with conscious experiences, a system with the +same fine-grained functional organization will have qualitatively identical +conscious experiences. But we know that any given functional organization +can be abstracted into a CS A that is implemented whenever the organization +is realized. It follows that for a given conscious system M, its fine-grained +functional organization can be abstracted into a CSA M, such that any system that implements M will realize the same functional organization, and +will therefore have conscious experiences qualitatively indistinguishable +from those of the original system. This establishes the thesis of strong artificial +intelligence. +For example, we might abstract a neural description of the brain into a +CSA, with an element of the state vector for each neuron and with substates +for each element reflecting the relevant range of each neuron's states. The +state transition rules of the CSA reflect the way in which the state of each +neuron depends on the state of other neurons, and the way in which neural +states are related to inputs and output. If nonneural components of the +brain are relevant, we can include components for those, too. Any physical +system that implements this CSA will have a fine-grained functional organization that duplicates the neuron-level functional organization of the brain. +By the invariance principle, this system will have experiences indistinguishable from those associated with the brain. +It is easy to think of a computer as simply an input-output device, with +nothing in between except for some formal mathematical manipulations. +This way of looking at things, however, leaves out the key fact that there +are rich causal dynamics inside a computer, just as there are in the brain. +Indeed, in an ordinary computer that implements a neuron-by-neuron simulation of my brain, there will be real causation going on between voltages +in various circuits, precisely mirroring patterns of causation between the +neurons. For each neuron, there will be a memory location that represents +the neuron, and each of these locations will be physically realized in a voltage +at some physical location. It is the causal patterns among these circuits, just +as it is the causal patterns among the neurons in the brain, that are responsible +for any conscious experience that arises. +We can also defend the strong AI thesis directly, using the fading qualia +and dancing qualia arguments. Given any two implementations of a CSA, +there will be a spectrum of cases between them, in which physical components of the implementations are replaced one at a time while the pattern +of their causal interaction with the rest of the system is preserved. If one of +the systems is conscious, and if the CSA abstracts its fine-grained functional + + 322 + +Applications + +organization, then the arguments in question imply that the other system +must be conscious and that it must have indistinguishable conscious experiences. If the other system were not conscious, there would be an intermediate +system with fading qualia. If the other system were not conscious or had +different conscious experiences, then we could construct an intermediate +system with dancing qualia. These consequences are implausible, for the +reasons outlined in Chapter 7. Given that qualia cannot fade or dance in +this way, it follows that the second of the original systems has experiences +indistinguishable from the first, and that the strong AI thesis holds. +There is a small caveat. The argument assumes that the brain's organization +can be abstracted into a CSA description. This requires only that the relevant +organization can be described in terms of a finite number of parts each +having a finite number of relevant states. Nevertheless, some might dispute +this. For example, perhaps an infinite number of states are needed for each +neuron, to capture the vital role of continuous processing. And some might +claim that the transitions between these infinite states might be uncomputable. I will discuss this sort of objection later; for now, I am happy to embrace the conclusion that if cognitive dynamics are computable, then the +right sort of computational organization will give rise to consciousness. That +is, I am more concerned with internal than external objections here. All the +same, I will address some external objections later in the chapter. + +4. The Chinese Room and Other Objections +Of course, opponents of strong AI have sometimes put forward concrete +arguments against the position. The best known of these are due to John +Searle, in his 1980 paper, "Minds, Brains, and Programs," and elsewhere. +Here I will use the framework I have outlined to answer these arguments. +The Chinese room +In a celebrated argument against strong AI, Searle (1980) argues that any +program can be implemented without giving rise to a mind. He does this by +exhibiting what he takes to be a counterexample to the strong AI claim: +the Chinese room, inside which a person manipulating symbols simulates +someone who understands Chinese. The Chinese room is intended to provide +an example, for any given program, of a system that implements that program but that lacks the relevant conscious experience. +In the original version, Searle directs the argument against machine intentionality rather than machine consciousness, arguing that it is "understanding" that the Chinese room lacks. All the same, it is fairly clear that consciousness is at the root of the matter. What the core of the argument +establishes directly, if it succeeds, is that the Chinese room system lacks + + Strong Artificial Intelligence + +323 + +conscious states, such as the conscious experience of understanding Chinese. +On Searle's view, intentionality requires consciousness, so this is enough to +see that the room lacks intentionality also. Others deny this, however. In +any case we can factor out the issue about the connection between consciousness and intentionality, and cast the issue solely in terms of consciousness. +The issues may be somewhat clearer this way. +(That is, we can separate Searle's conclusions into two parts: (1) no program suffices for consciousness; and (2) no program suffices for intentionality. +Searle believes that (1) implies (2), but others deny this. Things are clearest +if the argument about strong AI is taken to focus on (1): all parties will +accept that if (1) is true, then the most interesting form of strong AI is +doomed, and even Searle would accept that refuting (1) would show that +the Chinese room argument fails. The link between consciousness and intentionality can then be set aside as a separate issue, not crucial to the argument +against AI. +This way one avoids the situation in which opponents argue against (2) +without bothering to argue against (1). For example, replies that focus on +the connection between the Chinese room and its environment [Fodor 1980; +Rey 1986] and replies that give procedural or functional accounts of intentionality [Boden 1988; Thagard 1986] may or may not shed light on the issue +of intentionality, but they do nothing to make it more plausible that the +Chinese room is conscious. Consequently, they leave one with the feeling +that the problem the scenario poses for AI has not been addressed. At +best, what has been disputed is the auxiliary premise that intentionality +requires consciousness.)4 +The Chinese room argument runs as follows. Take any program that is +supposed to capture some aspect of consciousness, such as understanding +Chinese or having a sensation of red. Then this program can be implemented +by a monolingual English speaker—who we will call the demon—in a blackand-white room. The demon follows all the rules specified by the program +manually, keeping a record of all the relevant internal states and variables +on slips of paper, erasing and updating them as necessary. We can imagine +that the demon is also connected to a robotic body, receiving digital inputs +from perceptual transducers, manipulating them according to the program's +specifications, and sending digital outputs to motor effectors. In this way, +the program is implemented perfectly. Nevertheless, it seems clear that the +demon does not consciously understand Chinese, and that the demon is not +having a sensation of red. Therefore implementing a program is not sufficient +for these conscious experiences. Consciousness must require something more +than the implementation of a relevant program. +Proponents of strong AI have typically replied by conceding that the +demon does not understand Chinese, and arguing that understanding and +consciousness should instead be attributed to the system consisting of the +demon and the pieces of paper. Searle has declared this reply manifestly + + 324 + +Applications + +implausible. Certainly, there is something counterintuitive about the claim +that a system of an agent and associated pieces of paper has a collective +consciousness. At this point, the argument reaches an impasse. Proponents +of AI argue that the system is conscious, opponents find the conclusion +ridiculous, and it seems difficult to proceed any further. I think that the +arguments already given provide grounds for breaking the impasse in favor +of strong AI, however. +Let us assume that the relevant program is in fact a combinatorial-state +automaton that reflects the neuron-level organization of a Chinese speaker +who is looking at a juicy red apple. The demon in the room is implementing +the CSA by maintaining a slip of paper for each element of the state vector, and updating the slips of paper at every time-step according to the state +transition rules. We may run the fading and dancing qualia arguments by +constructing a spectrum of cases between the original Chinese speaker and +the Chinese room.5 This is not difficult to do. First, we can imagine that the +neurons in the Chinese speaker's head are replaced one at a time by tiny +demons, each of whom duplicates the input-output function of a neuron.6 +Upon receiving stimulation from neighboring neurons, a demon makes the +appropriate calculations and stimulates neighboring neurons in turn. As +more and more neurons are replaced, demons take over, until the skull is +filled with billions of demons reacting to each others' signals and to sensory +inputs, making calculations, and signaling other demons and stimulating +motor outputs in turn. (If someone objects that all those demons could never +fit in a skull, we can imagine a scenario with radio transmission equipment +outside the skull instead.) +Next, we gradually cut down on the number of demons by allowing them +to double up on their work. At first, we replace two neighboring demons +with a single demon doing the job of both of them. The new demon will +keep a record of the internal state of both neurons he is simulating—we can +imagine that this record is kept on a piece of paper at each location. Each +piece of paper will be updated depending on signals from neighboring demons and also on the state of the other piece of paper. The demons are +consolidated further, until eventually there is just a single demon, and billions +of tiny slips of paper. We may imagine that each of these slips is at the +original location of its corresponding neuron, and that the demon dashes +around the brain, updating each slip of paper as a function of the states of +neighboring slips, and of sensory inputs where necessary. +Despite all these changes, the resulting system shares the functional organization of the original brain. The causal relations between neurons in the +original case are mirrored by the causal relations between demons in the intermediate case, and by the causal relations between slips of paper in the +final case. In the final case, the causal relations are mediated by the actions +of a demon—a piece of paper affects the state of the demon, which affects +a neighboring piece of paper—but they are causal relations nevertheless. If + + Strong Artificial Intelligence + +325 + +we watch the system function at a speeded-up rate, we will see a whir of +causal interaction that corresponds precisely to the whir among the neurons. +We can therefore apply the fading and dancing qualia arguments. If the +final system lacks conscious experience, then there must be an intermediate +system with faded conscious experiences. This is implausible for just the +same reasons as before. We can also imagine switching between a neural +circuit and a corresponding backup circuit implemented with demons, or +with a single demon and pieces of paper. As before, this would lead to +dancing qualia with constant functional organization, so that the system +could never notice the difference. Once again, it is much more plausible to +suppose that qualia stay constant throughout. +It is therefore reasonable to conclude that the final system has precisely +the conscious experiences of the original system. If the neural system gave +rise to experiences of bright red, so will the system of demons, and so will +the network of pieces of paper mediated by a demon. But of course, this +final case is just a copy of the system in the Chinese room. We have therefore +given a positive reason to believe that that system really has conscious +experiences, such as that of understanding Chinese or of experiencing red. +This way of looking at things makes clear two things that may be obscured +by Searle's description of the Chinese room. First, the "slips of paper" +in the room are not a mere pile of formal symbols. They constitute a concrete +dynamical system with a causal organization that corresponds directly to the +organization of the original brain. The slow pace that we associate with +symbol manipulation obscures this, as does the presence of the demon manipulating the symbols, but nevertheless it is the concrete dynamics among +the pieces of paper that gives rise to conscious experience. Second, the role +of the demon is entirely secondary. The interesting causal dynamics are those +that take place among the pieces of paper, which correspond to the neurons +in the original case. The demon simply acts as a kind of causal facilitator. +The image of a demon scurrying around in the skull makes it clear that to +attribute the experiences of the system to the demon would be a serious +confusion of levels. The fact that the demon is a conscious agent may tempt +one to suppose that if the system's experiences are anywhere, they are in +the demon; but in fact the consciousness of the demon is entirely irrelevant +to the functioning of the system. The demon's job could be performed by a +simple look-up table. The crucial aspect of the system is the dynamics among +the symbols. +Searle's argument gains its purchase on our intuitions by implementing +the program in a bizarre way that obscures the realization of the relevant +causal dynamics. Once we look past the images brought to mind by the +presence of the irrelevant demon and by the slow speed of symbol shuffling, +however, we see that the causal dynamics in the room precisely reflect the +causal dynamics in the skull. This way, it no longer seems so implausible to +suppose that the system gives rise to experience. + + 326 + +Applications + +Searle also gives a version of the argument in which the demon memorizes +the rules of the computation, and implements the program internally. Of +course, in practice people cannot memorize even one hundred rules and +symbols, let alone many billions, but we can imagine that a demon with a +supermemory module might be able to memorize all the rules and the states +of all the symbols. In this case, we can again expect the system to give rise +to conscious experiences that are not the demon's experiences. Searle argues +that the demon must have the experiences if anyone does, as all the processing +is internal to the demon, but this should instead be regarded as an example +of two mental systems realized within the same physical space. The organization that gives rise to the Chinese experiences is quite distinct from the +organization that gives rise to the demon's experiences. The Chinese-understanding organization lies in the causal relations between billions of locations +in the supermemory module; once again, the demon only acts as a kind of +causal facilitator. This is made clear if we consider a spectrum of cases in +which the demon scurrying around the skull gradually memorizes the rules +and symbols, until everything is internalized. The relevant structure is gradually moved from the skull to the demon's supermemory, but experience +remains constant throughout, and entirely separate from the experiences of +the demon. +Some may suppose that because my argument relies on duplicating the +neuron-level organization of the brain, it establishes only a weak form of +strong AI, one that is closely tied to biology. (In discussing what he calls +the "Brain Simulator" reply, Searle expresses surprise that a supporter of +AI would give a reply that depends on the detailed simulation of human +biology.) This would be to miss the force of the argument, however. The +brain simulation program merely serves as the thin end of the wedge. Once +we know that one program can give rise to a mind even when implemented +Chinese-room style, the force of Searle's in-principle argument is entirely +removed: we know that the demon and the paper in a Chinese room can +indeed support an independent mind. The floodgates are then opened to a +whole range of programs that might be candidates to generate conscious +experience. The extent of this range is an open question, but the Chinese +room is not an obstacle. +Syntax and semantics +A second argument, put forward by Searle (1984), runs as follows: +1. A computer program is syntactic. +2. Syntax is not sufficient for semantics. +3. Minds have semantics. +4. Therefore, implementing a program is insufficient for a mind. + + Strong Artificial Intelligence + +327 + +Once again, this is put forward as an argument about intentionality, but +it can also be taken as an argument about consciousness. For Searle, the +central sort of intentionality is phenomenological intentionality, the kind +that is inherent in consciousness. +There are various ways in which this argument can be interpreted and +criticized, but the main problem is that the argument does not respect the +crucial role of implementation. Programs are abstract computational objects +and are purely syntactic. Certainly, no mere program is a candidate for +possession of a mind. Implementations of programs, on the other hand, are +concrete systems with causal dynamics, and are not purely syntactic. An +implementation has causal heft in the real world, and it is in virtue of this +causal heft that consciousness and intentionality arise. It is the program that +is syntactic; it is the implementation that has semantic content. +Searle might argue that there is a sense in which even implementations +are syntactic, perhaps because the dynamics of implementations are determined by formal properties. Any sense of "syntax" in which implementations +are syntactic, however, loses touch with the sense in which it is plausible +that syntax is not sufficient for semantics. While it may be plausible that +static sets of abstract symbols do not have intrinsic semantic properties, it +is much less clear that formally specified causal processes cannot support +a mind. +We can parody the argument as follows: +1. Recipes are syntactic. +2. Syntax is not sufficient for crumbliness. +3. Cakes are crumbly. +4. Therefore, implementing a recipe is insufficient for a cake. +In this form the flaw is immediately apparent. The argument does not +distinguish between recipes, which are syntactic objects, and implementations of recipes, which are full-bodied physical systems in the real world. +Again, all the work is done by the implementation relation, which relates +the abstract and concrete domains. A recipe implicitly specifies a class of +physical systems that qualify as implementations of the recipe, and it is these +systems that have such features as crumbliness. Similarly, a program implicitly +specifies a class of physical systems that qualify as implementations of the +program, and it is these systems that give rise to such features as minds. + +A simulation is just a simulation +A popular objection to artificial intelligence (e.g., Searle 1980, Hamad 1989) +is that a simulation of a phenomenon is not the same as a replication. For +example, when we simulate digestion computationally, no food is actually +digested. A simulated hurricane is not a real hurricane; when a hurricane is + + 328 + +Applications + +simulated on a computer, no one gets wet. When heat is simulated, no real +heat is generated. So when a mind is simulated, why should we expect a real +mind to result? Why should we expect that in this case but not others, a +computational process is not just a simulation but the real thing? +It is certainly true that for many properties, simulation is not replication. +Simulated heat is not real heat. On the other hand, for some properties, +simulation is replication. For example, a simulation of a system with a causal +loop is a system with a causal loop. So the real question here is, how do we +distinguish those types X such that a simulation of an X really is an X from +those such that it is not? +I suggest that the answer is as follows: A simulation of X is an X precisely +when the property of being an X is an organizational invariant. The definition +of an organizational invariant is as before: a property is an organizational +invariant when it depends only on the functional organization of the underlying system, and not on any other details. A computational simulation of +a physical system can capture its abstract causal organization, and ensure +that that causal organization is replicated in any implementation, no matter +what the implementation is made out of. Such an implementation will then +replicate any organizational invariants of the original system, but other properties will be lost. +The property of being a hurricane is not an organizational invariant, as it +depends partly on nonorganizational properties such as the velocity, shape, +and physical composition of the underlying system (a system with the same +causal interactions implemented very slowly among a large set of billiard +balls would not be a hurricane). Similarly, digestion and heat depend on +aspects of underlying physical makeup that are not wholly organizational. +We could gradually replace the biological components in a digestive system +so that acid-base reactions are replaced by causally isomorphic interactions +among pieces of metal, and it would no longer count as an instance of +digestion. So we should not expect a simulation of systems with these properties to itself have these properties. +But phenomenal properties are different. As I have argued in Chapter 7, +these properties are organizational invariants. If so, it follows that the right +sort of simulation of a system with phenomenal properties will itself have +phenomenal properties, by virtue of replicating the original system's finegrained functional organization. Organizational invariance makes consciousness different in principle from the other properties mentioned, and opens +the way to strong AI. + +5. External Objections +I have been most concerned with internal objections to strong artificial +intelligence, as these are most relevant to the topic of this book, but I will + + Strong Artificial Intelligence + +329 + +also at least mention some external objections. As I said earlier, the prima +facie case against external objections to artificial intelligence is strong: there +is every reason to believe that the laws of physics, at least as currently +understood, are computable, and that human behavior is a consequence of +physical laws. If so, then it follows that a computational system can simulate +human behavior. Objections are occasionally mounted all the same, however, +so I will discuss these briefly. +Objections from rule following +Perhaps the oldest external objection to AI is that computational systems +always follow rules, so they will always lack certain human capacities, such +as creativity or flexibility. This is in many ways the weakest of the external +objections, partly as it is so vague and underspecified. Indeed, it can easily +be replied in turn that at the neural level, the human brain may be quite +mechanical and reflexive, but this is no bar to creativity and flexibility at the +macroscopic level. Of course, an opponent could always choose to deny the +thesis about mechanism at the neural level, but in any case there seems to +be no good argument for the thesis that computational dynamics at a basic +causal level is incompatible with creativity and flexibility at the macroscopic level. +This sort of objection may gain some leverage from the implicit identification of computational systems with symbolic computational systems: systems +that perform symbolic manipulations of high-level conceptual representations—in the extreme case, systems that inflexibly draw conclusions from +premises in first-order logic. Perhaps the objection has some force in these +cases, although even that is disputable. But in any case, the class of computational systems is much broader than this. A low-level simulation of the brain +is a computation, for example, but is not a symbolic computation of this +sort. At an intermediate level, connectionist models in cognitive science +have appealed to a sort of computation that does not consist in symbolic +manipulation. In these cases, there may be a level at which the system +follows rules, but this is not directly reflected at the level of behavior; indeed, +connectionists often claim that theirs is a method of yielding high-level +flexibility from low-level mechanicality. As Hofstadter (1979) has put it, the +level at which I think is not necessarily the level at which I sum.7 +Objections from Gddel's theorem +It is sometimes held that Godel's theorem shows that computational systems +are limited in a way that humans are not. Godel's theorem tells us that for +any consistent formal system powerful enough to do a certain sort of arithmetic, there will be a true sentence—the system's Godel sentence—that +the system cannot prove. But we can see that the Godel sentence is true, + + 330 + +Applications + +it is argued, so we have a capacity that the formal system lacks. It follows +that no formal system can precisely capture human capacities. (Arguments +of this sort are made by Lucas [1961] and Penrose [1989, 1994], among +others.) +The short answer to these arguments is that there is no reason to believe +that humans can see the truth of the relevant Godel sentences, either. At +best, we can see that if a system is consistent, then its Godel sentence is +true, but there is no reason to believe that we can determine the consistency +of arbitrary formal systems.8 This holds particularly in the case of complex +formal systems, such as a system that simulates the output of a human brain: +the task of determining whether such a system is consistent might well be +beyond us. So it may well be that each of us can be simulated by a complex +formal system F, such that we cannot determine whether F is consistent. If +so, we will not be able to see the truth of our own Godel sentences. +There are many variants on the Godelian argument, with replies that an +opponent might make to this suggestion and further byways that come up +in turn. I will not discuss these here (although I discuss them at length in +Chalmers 1995c). These issues lead to many stimulating points of interest, +but I think it is fair to say that the case that Godelian limitations do not +apply to humans has never been convincingly made. +Objections from uncomputability and continuity +The objections above are "high-level" arguments that cognitive functioning +is uncomputable. One might also try to attack the AI position at the low +level, by arguing that physical functioning is not computable. Penrose (1994) +argues that there may be a noncomputable element in a correct theory of +quantum gravity, for example. His only evidence for this conclusion, however, lies in the Godelian argument above. There is nothing in physical +theory itself to support the conclusion; so if the Godelian argument is overturned, any reason for believing in uncomputable physical laws disappears. +Indeed, one might argue that given that every element of the brain, such as +a neuron, has only a finite number of relevant states, and given that there +are only a finite number of relevant elements, then the relevant causal +structure of the brain must be capturable in a computational description. +This leads to the final objection, which is that brain processes may be +essentially continuous where computational processes are discrete, and that +this continuity may be essential to our cognitive competence, so that no +discrete simulation could duplicate that competence. Perhaps in approximating a neuron by an element with only a finite number of states, one loses +something vital to its functioning. An opponent might appeal, for example, +to the presence of "sensitive dependence on initial conditions" in certain +nonlinear systems, which implies that even a small round-off error at one + + Strong Artificial Intelligence + +331 + +stage of processing can lead to major macroscopic differences at a later stage. +If brain processing is like this, then any discrete simulation of the brain will +yield results that differ from the continuous reality. +There is good reason to believe that absolute continuity cannot be essential +to our cognitive competence, however. The presence of background noise +in biological systems implies that no process can depend on requiring more +than a certain amount of precision. Beyond a certain point (say, the 10~10 +level on an appropriate scale), uncontrollable fluctuations in background +noise will wash out any further precision. This means that if we approximate +the state of the system to this level of precision (perhaps a little further to +be on the safe side—to the 10-20 level, for example), then we will be doing +as well as the system itself can reliably do. It is true that due to nonlinear +effects, this approximation may lead to behavior different from the behavior +produced by the system on a given occasion—but it will lead to behavior +that the system might have produced, had biological noise been a little +different. We can even approximate the noise process itself, if we want +to.9 The result will be that the simulating system will have the same behavioral capacities as the original system, even if it produces different specific +behavior on specific occasions. The moral is that when it comes to duplicating +our cognitive capacities, a close approximation is as good as the real +thing. +It is true that a system with unlimited precision might have cognitive +capacities that no discrete system could ever have. For example, one might +encode an analog quantity corresponding to the real number whose nth +binary digit is 1 if and only if the nth Turing machine halts on all inputs. +Using this quantity, a perfect continuous system could solve the halting +problem, something no discrete system can do. But the presence of noise +implies that no biological process could reliably implement this system. Biological systems can rely on only a finite amount of precision, so human and +animal brains must be limited to capacities that discrete systems can share. + +6. Conclusion +The conclusion is that there do not appear to be any in-principle barriers +to the ambitions of artificial intelligence. The external objections do not +appear to carry much force. The internal objections may be more worrying, +but none of the arguments for these objections seem to be compelling on +analysis; and indeed if the arguments I have given in previous chapters are +correct, then we have good positive reason to believe that implementation +of an appropriate computation will bring conscious experience along with +it. So the outlook for machine consciousness is good in principle, if not yet +in practice. + + 332 + +Applications + +I have said little about just what sort of computation is likely to suffice +for conscious experience. In most of the arguments I have used a neuronby-neuron simulation of the brain as an example; but it is likely that many +other sorts of computations might also suffice. It might be, for example, that +a computation that mirrors the causal organization of the brain at a much +coarser level could still capture what is relevant for the emergence of conscious experience. And it is likely that computations of an entirely different +form, corresponding to entirely different sorts of causal organization, could +also give rise to rich conscious experiences when implemented. +This picture is equally compatible with the symbolic and connectionist +approaches to cognition, and with other computational approaches as well. +Indeed, one could argue that the centrality of computation in the study of +cognition stems from the way that computational accounts can capture almost +any sort of causal organization. We can see computational formalisms as +providing an ideal formalism for the expression of patterns of causal organization, and indeed (in combination with implementational methods) as an ideal +tool for their replication. Whatever causal organization turns out to be central +to cognition and consciousness, we can expect that a computational account +will be able to capture it. One might even argue that it is this flexibility that +lies behind the often-cited universality of computational systems. Proponents +of artificial intelligence are not committed to any one sort of computation +as the sort that might suffice for mentality; the AI thesis is so plausible +precisely because the class of computational systems is so wide.10 +So it remains an open question just what class of computations is sufficient +to replicate human mentality; but we have good reason to believe that the +class is not empty. + + 10 + +The Interpretation +of Quantum Mechanics + +1. Two Mysteries +The problem of quantum mechanics is almost as hard as the problem of +consciousness. Quantum mechanics gives us a remarkably successful calculus +for predicting the results of empirical observations, but it is extraordinarily +difficult to make sense of the picture of the world that it delivers. How could +our world be the way it has to be, in order for the predictions of quantum +mechanics to succeed? There is nothing even approaching a consensus on +the answer to this question. Just as with consciousness, it often seems that +no solution to the problem of quantum mechanics can be satisfactory. +Many people have thought that these two most puzzling of problems +might be intimately linked (e.g., Bohm 1980; Hodgson 1988; Lockwood 1989; +Penrose 1989; Squires 1990; Stapp 1993; Wigner 1961). Where there are two +mysteries, it is tempting to suppose that they have a common source. This +temptation is magnified by the fact that the problems in quantum mechanics +seem to be deeply tied to the notion of observership, crucially involving the +relation between a subject's experience and the rest of the world. +Most often, it has been suggested that quantum mechanics may hold the +key to a physical explanation of consciousness. But as we have seen, this +project will always fall short of its goal. At the end of the day quantum +"theories" of consciousness suffer from the same sort of explanatory gap as +classical theories. Either way experience must be taken as something over +and above the physical properties of the world. Perhaps quantum mechanics +might play a role in characterizing the psychophysical link, but quantum +theory alone cannot tell us why consciousness exists. + + 334 + +Applications + +But the problems may be linked in a more subtle way. Even if quantum +mechanics does not explain consciousness, perhaps a theory of consciousness +might shed light on the problems of quantum mechanics. After all, it is +widely agreed that these problems have something to do with observership +and experience. It is natural to suppose that a theory of experience might +help us come to grips with the issues. Some have proposed an active role +for consciousness in quantum theory—suggesting that consciousness brings +about the "collapse of the wave function," for example—but I will argue +for a more indirect role for consciousness in dealing with these questions. +In particular, I will argue that we can reconceive the problems of quantum +theory as problems about the relationship between the physical structure of +the world and our experience of the world, and that consequently an appropriate theory of consciousness can lend support to an unorthodox interpretation of quantum mechanics. + +2. The Framework of Quantum Mechanics +The basic framework of quantum mechanics consists in a calculus for predicting the results of experimental measurements. I will describe a version +of that calculus here, glossing over a number of technical details in order to +provide a simple description that covers the most crucial features. In this +section, I present the framework merely as a calculus for empirical predictions, leaving open the question of whether it provides a direct description +of physical reality. The deep problems of interpretation are discussed in the +next section. +Within a classical framework, the state of a physical system can be expressed in very simple terms. The state of a particle, for example, is expressed +by giving determinate values for each of a number of properties, such as +position and momentum. We can call this sort of simple value a basic value. +Within the quantum framework, things are not so simple. In general, the +state of a system must be expressed as a wave Junction, or a state vector. +Here, the relevant properties cannot be expressed in simple values, but +instead must be expressed as a kind of combination of basic values. A +quantum state can be seen as a superposition of simpler states. +The simplest example is a property such as spin, which has only two basic +values.1 These basic values can be labeled "up" and "down." In quantum +mechanics, the spin of a particle is not always up or down, however. Instead, +a particle's spin must in general be expressed as a combination of up and +down, each with a different complex magnitude. The spin of a particle is +therefore best regarded as a vector in a two-dimensional vector space. It is +most naturally visualized as a superposition of a spin-up state and a spindown state, with different magnitudes corresponding to each. + + The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics + +335 + +The same goes for position and momentum, except that each of these has +an infinite number of basic values. The position and the momentum of a +classical particle can each take on any of an infinite number of values in a +continuum. The position of a quantum particle, correspondingly, must be +expressed as a kind of infinite-dimensional vector with a different magnitude +for each of these locations. This vector is best regarded as a wave, with +different amplitudes at different locations in space; the function that takes +a location to the corresponding amplitude is the wave function. Similarly, +the momentum of a quantum particle can be regarded as a wave with different +amplitudes at different basic values of momentum. Again, we can think of +the position or momentum of such a particle as a superposition of basic +values of position or momentum. +Because these states are just vectors, they can be decomposed into components in many ways. While it is often useful to see a two-dimensional spin +vector as a sum of an "up" component and a "down" component, it can be +decomposed in many other ways, depending on the basis chosen for the +vector space. All of these bases are equally "natural"; none is preferred by +nature. In fact, it turns out a single vector represents both the position and +the momentum of a particle. Decomposed according to one basis, we get +the "position" amplitudes; decomposed according to a different basis, we +get the "momentum" amplitudes. In general, the decomposition that is relevant in a given case depends on which quantity we are interested in, and in +particular on which quantity we choose to measure, as I discuss shortly. +The states of systems consisting of more than a single particle are somewhat more complex, but the basic idea is the same. Take a system consisting +of two particles, A and B. The state of the system cannot generally be +expressed by combining a wave function for A and a wave function for B +in any simple way; the states of the two particles will often be nonseparable. +Rather, the state of the system must be expressed as a wave function in a more +complex space. This wave function can be seen as a kind of superposition of +simpler states of the two-particle system, however, so the general picture +still applies. The same goes for more complex systems, in which a state is +still best represented as a wave function corresponding to a superposition +of states. +All this is counterintuitive, but it is not yet paradoxical. If we take this +formalism at face value as a description of reality, it is not too hard to make +sense of. Some have supposed that it is incompatible with an "objective" +view of the world, as it implies that entities in the world do not have an +objective, determinate state. But this does not follow. On this picture, the +state of an entity is best expressed by a wave function rather than by discrete +quantities, but it is a perfectly determinate state. The picture simply tells us +that on the basic level reality is wavelike. This requires a new way of thinking, +but we can get used to it. After all, the basic level of microscopic real- + + 336 + +Applications + +ity is very far from the macroscopic level we usually deal with, and it is not +entirely surprising that it should have some unfamiliar properties. Any problems that arise stem from further properties of quantum mechanics. +The core of quantum mechanics consists of two principles that determine +the dynamics of the wave function: the Schrodinger equation and the measurement postulate. Between them, these two very different principles determine +how the wave function of a system evolves with time. +Most of the substance of quantum mechanics is found in the Schrodinger +equation. This is a differential equation that determines how the wave function of a system evolves under almost all circumstances. The detailed structure of the equation is not important for our purposes. The most important +feature here is that it is a linear differential equation: given two states +A and B such that A evolves into A' and B evolves into B', then a state +consisting in a superposition of A and B will evolve into a superposition of +A' and B'. It is also worth noting that under the dynamics of the Schrodinger +equation, relatively discrete states usually become more spread out over +time. A state that starts as a superposition of values in a limited range will +generally evolve into a superposition of values in a much wider range. Finally, the Schrodinger equation is entirely deterministic. +The Schrodinger equation is relatively straightforward and well understood. It is here that the meat and potatoes of quantum theory resides. In +applying quantum theory to a practical or experimental problem, the bulk +of the work consists in calculating how various states evolve according to +the Schrodinger dynamics. +The Schrodinger equation cannot be all there is to say, however. According +to the equation, the vast majority of physical states will soon evolve into a +superposition of a wide range of states. But this does not square with our +observations of the world. When we measure the position of a particle, we +find a definite value, not the superposition of values that the Schrodinger +equation would predict. If the Schrodinger equation were all there is to +quantum dynamics, then even at the macroscopic level the world would +evolve into a wildly superposed state. But in our experience it does not. +Pointers have definite locations, moving objects have a definite measurable +momentum, and so on. So there must be more to the story: something that +leads us from the equation to the sorts of discrete events that characterize +our experience. +The second part of the story in the standard formalism is the measurement +postulate (also known as the collapse or projection postulate). This asserts +that under special circumstances, the Schrodinger dynamics do not apply. +Specifically, it says that when a measurement is made, the wave function +collapses into a more definite form. The way that it collapses depends on +the property that is being measured. For example, if we measure the spin + + The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics + +337 + +of a particle, then even if it is in a superposed state beforehand, it will +collapse into a state in which the spin is either up or down. If we measure +the position of a particle, its wave function will collapse into a state with a +definite position.2 The resulting state still corresponds to a wave function, +but it is a wave function in which all the amplitude is concentrated at a +definite position; the amplitude everywhere else is zero. To every quantity +that we might measure there corresponds an operator, and upon measurement the state will collapse into a state which is an eigenstate of that operator. +An eigenstate of an operator is always a state in which the corresponding +measurable quantity has a definite value. It follows that when we make a +measurement of a quantity, a definite value for that quantity always results, +which squares precisely with our experience. +The dynamics of collapse are probabilistic rather than deterministic. If a +particle is in a state that is a superposition of positions, then when position +is measured we know that it will collapse into a state with definite position, +but we do not know what that position will be. Rather, for each potential +collapsed state, the measurement postulate specifies the probability that the +system will collapse into that state. This probability3 is given by the square +of the amplitude of the wave function, at the location corresponding to the +definite value in question. For example, if the spin of a particle is a superposition of spin up (with amplitude 1) and spin down (with amplitude ), then +when spin is measured it will collapse into a spin-up state with probability +1/4, and into a spin-down state with probability3/4.The amplitudes in a wave +function always have the property that the corresponding probabilities add +up to 1. + +3. Interpreting Quantum Mechanics +Together, these two principles constitute an extremely powerful calculus for +predicting the results of experimental measurements. To predict the results +of an experiment, we express the state of a system as a wave function, and +calculate how the wave function evolves over time according to the Schrodinger equation, until the point where a measurement is made. Where a +measurement is made, we use the amplitudes of the calculated wave function +to determine the probability that various collapsed states will result, and to +calculate the probability that the measurement will yield any given quantity. +Experimental results have been unwavering in their support for the predictions of the theory; few scientific theories have been as successful at a predictive task. As a calculus, the theory is all but watertight. +The problems arise when we ask how it could be that the calculus works. +What could be happening in the real world to make the predictions of the + + 338 + +Applications + +calculus so accurate? This is the problem of the interpretation of quantum +mechanics. There are many different options available in grappling with this +problem, none of which is wholly satisfactory. +Option 1: Take the calculus literally +The natural first reaction is to take the formalism of quantum mechanics at +face value, as we do with most scientific theories. The calculus involves a +wave function governed by the dynamics of the Schrodinger equation and +the measurement postulate, and the calculus works, so we should suppose +that it gives us a direct picture of what is going on in the world. That is to +say, the state of a system in reality is precisely the wave state expressed by +the wave function, evolving according to the dynamics expressed by the +two basic principles. Most of the time, the state evolves according to the +Schrodinger equation, but when a measurement is made, the state evolves +according to the measurement postulate. On this view, the world consists of +waves that usually evolve linearly in a superposition, and that occasionally +collapse into a more definite state when a measurement is made. +But it is not easy to make sense of this picture. The problems all stem +from the measurement postulate. According to this postulate, a collapse +occurs when a measurement is made, but what counts as a measurement? +How does nature know when a measurement is made? "Measurement" is +surely not a basic term in the laws of nature; if the measurement postulate +is to be remotely plausible as a fundamental law, the notion of measurement +must be replaced by something clearer and more basic. If wave function +collapse is an objectively existing process in the world, then we need clear, +objective criteria for when it occurs. +One solution that is obviously unsatisfactory is to say that a collapse +occurs whenever a quantum system interacts with a measuring apparatus. +The problem here is that it is just as implausible that the notion of "measuring apparatus" should appear in the basic laws as it is that the notion of "measurement" should. Before, we needed criteria for what counts as a measurement; now, we need criteria for what counts as a measuring apparatus. +A suggestion popular in the early days of quantum mechanics was that a +measuring apparatus is a classical system, and that a measurement occurs +whenever a quantum system interacts with a classical system. But this is +clearly unsatisfactory. Quantum theory is meant to be a universal theory, +and it should apply to processes within a measuring instrument just as much +as it applies to processes elsewhere. Unless we are to suppose that there are +two fundamentally different kinds of physical objects in the world—a supposition that would require the development of an entirely new theory— +then "classical system" cannot be a term in a fundamental law of nature +any more than "measurement" can. + + The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics + +339 + +A related suggestion is that a measurement occurs whenever a quantum +system interacts with a macroscopic system. But it is just as clear that "macroscopic" is not a notion that can figure in a basic law. It must be replaced by +something more precise: something like "system with mass one gram or +greater." It would be extraordinarily arbitrary for something like this to +figure in a basic law, however. +There is no physical criterion for collapse that seems remotely acceptable. +A criterion cast at the microscopic level—suggesting that collapse takes +place when a system interacts with a proton, for example—is ruled out by +experimental results. The alternative is that the criterion must involve a +higher-level physical property, so that collapse takes place when systems +take on a certain high-level configuration. But any such higher-level property +would seem arbitrary, and no plausible candidate has ever been proposed. +There is also something very odd about the supposition that the Schrodinger +dynamics of microscopic systems should be suddenly overridden when those +systems happen to find themselves in the context of certain special configurations. +The only remotely tenable criterion that has been proposed is that a +measurement takes place when a quantum system affects some being's consciousness. Unlike the previous criteria, this criterion is at least determinate +and nonarbitrary.4 The corresponding interpretation of the calculus is reasonably elegant and simple in its form, and it is the only literal interpretation +of the calculus that has any wide currency. This interpretation was first +suggested by London and Bauer (1939), but it is most closely associated with +Wigner (1961). +Note that this interpretation presupposes mind-body dualism. If consciousness were just another physical property, then all the previous problems +would arise. The view would turn into another "high-level property" view, +on which the wave functions of physical systems just happen to collapse in +the context of certain complex physical configurations. If dualism holds, on +the other hand, then the criterion for collapse can be truly fundamental. +Further, the fact that the cause of collapse is external to physical processing +allows for a much simpler theory. All purely physical systems are now governed by the Schrodinger dynamics alone, and the very different measurement dynamics have an independent source. +The interpretation has some counterintuitive consequences, though. Take +a measuring apparatus such as a pointer that measures the state of an electron, and suppose that the state of the electron is initially superposed. If +there is no consciousness in the vicinity, the whole system is governed by +the linear Schrodinger dynamics: given that different discrete electron states +would produce different discrete pointer states, it follows that a superposed +electron state will produce a superposed pointer state. That is, the theory +predicts that the pointer is pointing to many different locations simulta- + + 340 + +Applications + +neously! It is only when I look at the pointer that it points to a definite position. +The scenario of Schrodinger's cat brings on even stranger consequences. +In this scenario a cat is locked inside a cabinet, an electron's spin is measured +by an instrument, and an apparatus is set up so that the cat is killed if and +only if the electron's spin is "up." (Assume that the cat is anesthetized, so +that its consciousness does not enter the picture.) If the electron is initially +in a superposed state, then the cat will move into a state that is a superposition of life and death! Only when a conscious being looks inside the cabinet +will it become determinate whether the cat is dead or alive. +In this picture, any macroscopic system will usually be in a large-scale superposition if there is no consciousness in the vicinity. Before consciousness +evolved, the entire universe was in a giant superposition, until presumably +the first speck of consciousness caused its state to suddenly collapse. This +may sound crazy, but it is a direct consequence of the only tenable literal +interpretation of the principles of quantum mechanics. I hope this helps to +bring out just how strange quantum mechanics is, and how serious the problems posed by its interpretation are. +The counterintuitive consequences could perhaps be accepted, but I nevertheless do not advocate this interpretation. For a start, it is incompatible +with the view that I have advocated on which consciousness is ubiquitous. +If consciousness is associated even with very simple systems, then on this +interpretation collapse will happen at a very basic level and very frequently. +This is inconsistent with the physical evidence, which requires that low-level +superpositions often persist uncollapsed for a significant time. A second +problem is that there is nothing approaching a good theory of what sort of +effect on consciousness brings about collapse, or of what form the resulting +collapse will take. There are many different ways this might be spelled out, +but no single way of working out the details looks especially compelling. +Other problems stem from the very notion of collapse. For a start, collapse +must be nonlocal: when two particles have entangled states, measuring the +first particle will cause the state of the second to collapse simultaneously. +This leads to some tension with relativity theory. For example, it seems that +nonlocal collapse requires an appeal to a privileged reference frame. Without such a reference frame, the time of collapse of the second particle will +be underdetermined, as simultaneity across locations is not well defined. +More generally, the whole process of collapse sits uneasily with the rest +of physics. Taken literally, it is an instantaneous, discontinuous, temporally +asymmetric, nonlocal process that is entirely unlike every other process that +physical theory gives us reason to believe in. It seems odd that such a strange +process should exist alongside the straightforward, continuous, temporally +symmetric, local Schrodinger equation. Indeed, compared to the elegance +and power of the Schrodinger equation, which is at the heart of quantum + + The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics + +341 + +theory, collapse seems almost to be an arbitrary, tacked-on element. There +is something very awkward about the idea that the world has two such +entirely different sorts of dynamics at its basic level. +These are far from knockdown arguments, of course, and the interpretation +on which consciousness collapses the wave function deserves to be taken +very seriously. Nevertheless, I think there is good reason to look for another +interpretation, one that gives us a simpler and more straightforward view of +nature's basic processes. + +Option 2: Try to get the measurement postulate for free +The problems with the literal interpretation all stem from taking the measurement postulate as a fundamental law. It is tempting to suppose that +instead the postulate might be nonbasic, a consequence of more fundamental +principles. There are two ways this might go. We might try to introduce +further basic principles, less problematic than the measurement postulate, +that have the same effect. This is the strategy of option 4. Or we might try +to derive the effects as a consequence of known basic principles, such as the +Schrodinger equation. That is, we might try to get the measurement postulate +for free. +It is easy to see the intuitive motivation for this strategy. There is an +intuition that superposition effects apply primarily at a microscopic level +and might somehow "cancel out" at the macroscopic level. Perhaps when +there are many microscopic superpositions, they interact in such a way to +produce a macroscopic state that is relatively definite. Because of some +mathematical properties of complex configurations, we might be able to see +how an effective collapse could be the consequence of microscopic indefiniteness. A fundamental probabilistic collapse would then be replaced by an +emergent statistical process in a complex system. +There have been numerous attempts to work out the mathematics of this, +often appealing to the statistical principles of thermodynamics (e.g., Daneri, +Loinger, and Prosperi 1962). Unfortunately, all these attempts have failed, +and it is now widely accepted that they must fail. Because the Schrodinger +dynamics are linear, it is always possible to construct situations in which +microscopic superpositions lead to macroscopic superpositions. If an "up" +electron leads to one macroscopic state, and a "down" electron leads to +another, then a superposed electron must lead to a superposed macroscopic +state (Albert 1992, p. 75, gives a very straightforward argument for this +point). Unless further basic principles are introduced, then, we have to expect +superposition on the macroscopic level. +These strategies can offer something. This sort of appeal to statistics, as +well as more recent work on "decoherence" by Gell-Mann and Hartle (1990) +and others, suggests that a superposed wave function will often resolve into + + 342 + +Applications + +a relatively clearcut superposition of distinct macroscopic states, rather than +being a jumbled mess. These macroscopic states "decohere" from each other, +with only minimal interference effects between them. This at least helps us +find some element of the familiar classical world in the superposed wave +function. But the wave function is still a superposition, and nothing in this +sort of work tells us why only one element of the macroscopic superposition +should be actual. So more work is required in order to solve the basic +problem. This sort of work is perhaps most useful when combined with one +of the other options, such as option 5. + +Option 3: Whereof one cannot speak... +Perhaps the dominant view among working physicists is that one simply +should not ask what is going on in the real world, behind the quantum +mechanical calculus. The calculus works, and that is that. There are two +versions of this view. According to the first version, maybe something is +going on in the world, but we can never know what it is. The calculus gives +us all the empirical information that we will ever have, so that anything +further is pure speculation. We might as well stop worrying and continue to +calculate. This view makes sense for practical purposes, but it is unsatisfying +for anyone who wants physics to tell us about the basic level of reality. Given +that the calculus works, we want to have at least some idea of how it could +possibly work. Perhaps we can never know for sure, but it makes sense +to ask. +The second version takes a harder line, and says that there is no fact of +the matter about what is going on in the world. According to this view, the +facts are exhausted by the fact that the calculus works. This view is often +not put forward quite as explicitly as this, perhaps because put so straightforwardly the view is almost impossible to believe. It offers us a picture of +reality that leaves out the world! It leads to a version of idealism, on which +all that exists are our perceptions, or to something very close to this. Before +we open the cabinet containing Schrodinger's cat, it is not in a dead state, +it is not in an alive state, and it is not in a superposed state; it is simply in +no state at all. By giving up on a fact of the matter about what lies behind +our measurements, this view gives up on an independently existing reality. +The "Copenhagen interpretation" due to Bohr and his colleagues is often +taken to be a version of this view, although Bohr's writings are somewhat +ambiguous and interpretation is not easy. These writings also sometimes +suggest elements of the first option, and of the epistemological version of +this option. Bohr put great emphasis on the "classical" nature of a measuring +apparatus, and his views can be read as suggesting that only classical (or +macroscopic) objects have an objective state. Questions about the real state +of an object described by a superposition are simply proscribed. But this + + The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics + +343 + +relies on a division between classical and quantum systems that is difficult +to draw on any objective grounds, and it is hard to imagine that reality +simply "fades out" as we descend from the macroscopic to the microscopic +level. It has seemed to many that if Bohr's view is taken seriously, it leads +to the strong operationalism discussed in the last paragraph. Like that view, +it offers a picture of the basic level of reality that is no picture at all. +Option 4: Postulate further basic physical principles +Given that the literal interpretation of the measurement postulate is unacceptable, and that it cannot be derived from existing physical principles, it +is natural to suppose that something more must be going on. Perhaps if we +postulate further basic physical principles, we might be able to explain the +effectiveness of the quantum-mechanical calculus in a less problematic way. +The first way to do this is to retain the idea of collapse, but to explain it +differently. Such a strategy retains the assumption that basic physical states +are wave functions governed by the Schrodinger equation, but introduces +new principles to explain how microscopic superpositions turn into macroscopic discreteness. +The best-known example of this strategy is the "GRW" interpretation +due to Ghirardi, Rimini, and Weber (1986; see also Bell 1987a).5 This interpretation postulates a fundamental law according to which the position state +vector of any elementary particle may undergo a microscopic "collapse" at +any moment, with some very small probability (the chance that a particle +will collapse in a given second is about one in 1015). When such a collapse +occurs, it will generally lead to a collapse of the state of a macroscopic system +in which it is embedded, due to nonseparability effects. There are many such +particles in any macroscopic system, so it follows that any given macroscopic +system at any given time will usually be in a relatively discrete state. It is +possible to show that this comes very close to reproducing the predictions +of the measurement postulate. +The alternative is to eliminate the need for collapse by denying that the +basic level of reality is represented by a superposed wave function. If properties such as position have determinate values even at the basic level, then +collapse never needs to happen. Such a theory postulates "hidden variables" +at the basic level, which directly explain the discreteness of reality at the +macroscopic level. The cost of this suggestion is that new principles are +needed to explain why the principles of wave function evolution and collapse +seem to work so well. +The most prominent example here is the theory developed by Bohm +(1952). On this theory, the position of basic particles is always determinate. +The wave function retains a role as a kind of "pilot wave," guiding the evolution of a particle's position, and the wave function itself is governed by + + 344 + +Applications + +the Schrodinger equation. The probabilistic predictions of the measurement +postulate are reinterpreted as statistical laws. It turns out that on this theory +we can never know the exact position of a particle before measuring it, but +only its wave function. The measurement postulate tells us the proportion +of particles with a given wave function that will have a given position. It therefore yields the best statistical predictions we can expect, given our ignorance. +All of the proposals in this class have problems. Both the GRW interpretation and the Bohm interpretation give a special determinacy to position, +thus breaking the symmetry between position and momentum in the quantum mechanical calculus. This makes sense for predictive purposes, as it +is arguable that determinate positions always underlie our judgments of +macroscopic determinacy (think of the position of a pointer, for instance), +but it makes for a more awkward theory. For related reasons, there are +serious difficulties reconciling these approaches with relativity theory. +The GRW theory has some further difficulties, perhaps the most serious +of which is that it does not strictly imply that the macroscopic world is discrete at all. A macroscopic state is still represented by a superposed wave +function: although most of its amplitude is concentrated in one place, the +amplitude is nonzero wherever the amplitude of the uncollapsed wave function is nonzero. So the problems of superposition recur. The pointer is still +pointing to many locations, even after a measurement. It is true that the +amplitude for most of these locations is very small, but it is hard to see +why a low-amplitude superposition is any more acceptable than a highamplitude one. +Bohm's theory has fewer technical problems than the GRW interpretation, +but it has some strange consequences. Most strikingly, it is nonlocal to an +extraordinary degree. (Any hidden-variables theory satisfying the predictions of the calculus must be nonlocal, for reasons given by Bell 1964.)6 It +is not just that the properties of a particle can instantly affect the properties +of a particle some distance away. It turns out that in determining the trajectory of a particle, one may have to take into account the wave functions of +particles in other galaxies! All of these things play a role in composing the +global wave function, and that wave function simultaneously governs the +trajectories of particles all over the universe. +Perhaps the most basic reason to be suspicious of these interpretations, +however, is that they postulate complexity behind simplicity. Whatever its +problems, the quantum-mechanical calculus is extraordinarily simple and +elegant. These interpretations, on the other hand, introduce complex and +relatively ad hoc further principles to replace and explain this simple framework. This applies slightly less to the GRW interpretation, whose further +complexity consists only in introducing two new fundamental constants and +in breaking the symmetry between position and momentum; but it remains +the case that it is extraordinarily "lucky" that the values of the constants + + The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics + +345 + +just happen to be such as to almost reproduce the predictions of the standard +framework. The extra complexity of the Bohm interpretation is worse: it +postulates determinate positions and a wave function, a complex new fundamental principle by which the wave function determines the position of +particles, and it breaks the symmetry of the original framework. +We might say that these interpretations make it look like the world was +constructed by Descartes's evil demon, as they lead us to believe that the +world is one way when really it is another. As Albert and Loewer (1989) +put it, the God of the Bohm view does not play dice, but he has a malicious +sense of humor. The scenario in which the complex Bohm interpretation +happens to duplicate the predictions of the simple framework differs only +in degree from the case in which the inputs to a brain in a vat are manipulated +to produce the appearance of a straightforward external world. It is reminiscent of an "interpretation" of evolutionary theory according to which God +created the fossil record intact a few thousand years ago and ensured that +the predictions of evolutionary theory would be duplicated. The simplicity +of an explanatory framework has been sacrificed for a complex hypothesis +that happens to reproduce the results of the original theory. +The framework of quantum mechanics is so simple and elegant that a +basic theory that does not replicate that simplicity and elegance can never +be satisfying or fully plausible. If there were a few anomalies in quantum +theory, some experimental results that the framework did not predict perfectly, it might be more plausible to think that this simplicity is the tip of a +complex iceberg. As it stands, though, the framework is so robust that it +seems extraordinary that we should need to postulate a complex apparatus +to explain its simple predictions. +Given the problems with every interpretation of quantum mechanics, these +interpretations need to be taken seriously. But it is natural to look for a +simpler picture of the world. +Option 5: The Schrodinger equation is all +The centerpiece of quantum mechanics is the Schrodinger equation, and it +is present in some form in every interpretation of quantum mechanics. The +various interpretations we have considered all add something to the Schrodinger equation, in order to explain the macroscopic discreteness of the world. +But the simplest interpretation by far is the one that says that the Schrodinger +equation holds, and that is all. That is, the physical state of the world is +completely described by a wave function, and its evolution is completely +described by the Schrodinger equation. This is the interpretation given by +Everett (1957, 1973). +A strategy canvased earlier (option 2) also held that the Schrodinger +equation is all, but argued that this is compatible with discreteness at the + + 346 + +Applications + +macroscopic level. We have seen that this must fail for straightforward mathematical reasons. The Everett interpretation is much more radical. On this +view, the Schrodinger equation is taken at face value, and the state of the +world at every level is described by a wave function. It follows that contrary +to appearances, the world is in a superposed state even at the macroscopic level. + +4. The Everett Interpretation +The motivation for this interpretation is obvious. The heart of quantum +mechanics is the Schrodinger equation. The measurement postulate, and all +the other principles that have been proposed, feel like add-on extras. So +why not get rid of them? The problem with this interpretation is equally +obvious. If the Schrodinger equation is all, then the world is superposed at +every level. But it does not look superposed: we never perceive pointers +that are in a superposition of two states. Why not? +At the very least, this interpretation is highly counterintuitive. According +to this view, not only is the state of an electron best described by a superposition, but so is the state of a pointer that measures it! Objectively, it is not +strictly true to say that the pointer is pointing up, or pointing down. Rather, +it is in a superposition of the states of pointing up and down. The same goes +for the macroscopic state of almost everything, which is in a state described +by a wave function that will almost never correspond to a single "discrete" +state. Superposition, on this view, is everywhere. Why then does the world +appear discrete? +Everett's answer to this question is to extend superposition all the way to +the mind. If we take Schrodinger's equation seriously, then if the pointer +measuring an electron is in a superposition of states, the brain of a person +perceiving the pointer will itself be in a superposition. The state of the brain +will be described as a superposition of one state in which it perceives a +pointer pointing upward, and another state in which it perceives a pointer +pointing downward. Everett's key move is to suppose that each of these two +states should be associated with a separate observer. What happens after +such a measurement is that two observers are produced. One of them experiences an "up" pointer, and the other perceives a "down" pointer. It follows that each observer will experience a discrete state of the world. +Everett goes on to show that according to this framework, these observers +will have most of the properties that we expect observers to have, and that +most of the predictions of the quantum-mechanical calculus can be derived. +For example, it is not hard to see that each of the two superposed states here +will have no access to the other superposed state, so that the superposition of + + The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics + +347 + +the mind will not be betrayed in any single state. It is even possible to show +that when an observer making a measurement perceives another observer +measuring the same quantity, the perceived results of the measurements will +be in accord, so that the world will seem quite coherent. In short, any single +observer will experience the world in largely the way that we expect, even +though the world itself is in a superposed state. +This interpretation should not be confused with the splitting-worlds interpretation, according to which the world literally splits into many separate +worlds every time a measurement is made. There is one world in which the +pointer is pointing up, and an entirely separate world in which the pointer +is pointing down. Taken this way, the view is the furthest thing from simple. +For a start, it requires a new and extraordinary basic principle to describe +the "splitting" process. It is far from clear just when "splitting" should take +place (the "measurement" problem revived in a new form), and it is very +unclear what the worlds resulting from a split should be. For a literal split +to happen, a wave function has to "divide" into numerous components; but +there are many ways to decompose a wave function, and quantum mechanics delivers no preferred basis for the decomposition. This interpretation +seems even more complex and ad hoc than the various "collapse" interpretations, and there is little reason to accept it. +The splitting view is frequently attributed to Everett (largely due to the +expositions of Everett's work by DeWitt (1970,1971), but it cannot be found +in his writing. Everett's own view is not entirely clear, but it is interpreted +much more naturally along the lines I have suggested; this interpretation +is also recommended by Albert and Loewer (1988) and by Lockwood +(1989). On this view, there is no objective "splitting." Rather, the wave function evolves into a superposition of states, where the superposed states are +best regarded as components of a single world. Everett's view is sometimes +called a many-worlds interpretation (thus suggesting the splitting-worlds +view), but the view I am discussing is more accurately a one-big-world interpretation. There is only one world, but it has more in it than we might +have thought.7 +On this view, if there is any splitting, it is only in the minds of observers. +As superpositions come to affect a subject's brain state, a number of separate +minds result, corresponding to the components of the superposition. Each +of these perceives a separate discrete world, corresponding to the sort of +world that we perceive—call this a miniworld, as opposed to the maxiworld +of the superposition. The real world is a maxiworld, and the miniworlds are +merely in the minds of the subjects. Everett calls his view a relative-state +interpretation: the state of a miniworld, in which pointers point to discrete +positions, only counts as the state of the world relative to the specification +of an observer. The objective state of the world is a superposition. + + 348 + +Applications + +A key element is left unanalyzed in this interpretation, however. Why is +it legitimate to identify each component of an associated brain state with a +separate observer? Why is there not instead a single observer with a confused, +superposed mental state? Why indeed does such an incoherent brain state +give rise to any minds at all? Everett's treatment skates over these crucial +questions. Indeed, it may seem that in associating the wave function of a +brain state with a number of minds each perceiving a discrete state, Everett +is making an illegitimate appeal to a preferred basis, just as the splittingworlds interpretation did. A wave function does not come with an objective +division into components, but can be decomposed in many ways, depending on the choice of a basis for the corresponding vector space. It is often +natural for our purposes to decompose a wave function one way, according +to a particular basis, but such a decomposition does not reflect an objective +property of the wave function. Where the brain state can be decomposed +into a "perceiving up" and a "perceiving down" state, it can equally be decomposed into two states each of which have confused perceptions. In +postulating an objective decomposition, Everett seems to go beyond the +resources that the Schrodinger equation provides. +The crucial element omitted from Everett's treatment is an analysis of the +relationship between mind and body. Everett assumes that a superposed +brain state will have a number of distinct subjects of experience associated +with it, but he does nothing to justify this assumption. It is clear that this +matter depends crucially on a theory of consciousness. A similar suggestion +is made by Penrose (1989): +In particular, I do not see why a conscious being need be aware of only "one" +of the alternatives in a linear superposition. What is it about consciousness that +demands that one cannot be "aware" of that tantalizing linear combination of +a dead and a live cat? It seems to me that a theory of consciousness would be +needed before the many-worlds view can be squared with what one actually observes. (p. 296) + +Indeed, it is possible to see the central question in quantum mechanics as +a question about the relationship between physical processes and experience. +The centerpiece of quantum mechanics is the picture in which microscopic +reality is described by a superposed wave function evolved according to the +Schrodinger equation. But we experience the world as discrete. The central +question is, how is this so? Different interpretations give different answers. +Some (such as Bohm's) deny the first premise, positing that reality is discrete +even at the basic level. Some posit basic principles (the measurement postulate, or the GRW collapse law) to mediate a transition from the superposed to +the discrete. Some theories (those of option 2) try to explain how superposed +microscopic states can statistically produce a discrete macroscopic reality. + + The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics + +349 + +These last three strategies are all indirect strategies, attempting to explain +the discreteness of experience by explaining an underlying discreteness of +macroscopic reality. +An alternative strategy is to answer the question about experience directly. +If we take the primacy of the Schrodinger equation seriously, the central +question is why, given that the physical structure of the world is like this, +do we experience it like this? This is precisely a question about the way +that certain physical structures give rise to experience. That is, it is the +kind of question that I have been discussing throughout this book, and it is +the kind of question that a theory of consciousness ought to be able to +answer. +If we have to postulate an ad hoc theory of consciousness to answer +this question, the attractiveness of the Everett interpretation is diminished +significantly. Its best feature was always its simplicity, but new and arbitrary +psychophysical laws would make it as ad hoc as the Bohm interpretation. If +on the other hand an independently motivated theory of consciousness can +answer the question, then the Everett interpretation begins to look attractive indeed. +The theory of consciousness that I have advocated can answer this question, and can give the right sort of answer. It turns out that the theory predicts +that a superposed brain state should be associated with a number of distinct +subjects of discrete experience. To see this, let a maximal phenomenal state +be a phenomenal state that characterizes the entire experience of a subject +at a given time. Let a maximal physical state be a physical state that fully +characterizes the intrinsic physical state of a system at a given time. To +establish the conclusion, it suffices to establish the following superposition +principle: +If the theory predicts that a system in maximal physical state P gives rise +to an associated maximal phenomenal state E, then the theory predicts +that a system in a superposition of P with some orthogonal physical states +will also give rise to E. +If this principle holds, then a superposition of orthogonal physical states +will give rise to at least the maximal phenomenal states that the physical +states would have given rise to separately. This is precisely what the Everett +interpretation requires. If a brain is in a superposition of a "perceiving up" +state and a "perceiving down" state, then it will give rise to at least two +subjects of experience, where one is having an experience of a pointer pointing upward, and the other is experiencing a pointer pointing downward. (Of +course, these will be two distinct subjects of experience, as the phenomenal +states are each maximal phenomenal states of a subject.) The same holds in + + 350 + +Applications + +the general case. A superposition will always give rise to the ensemble of +subjects that the Everett interpretation requires. +So we need to establish that the theory I have outlined implies the superposition principle. The easiest way to see this is to appeal to the framework +of Chapter 9, and in particular to the claim that consciousness arises from +implementation of an appropriate computation. To use this to establish the +principle, we need to establish that if a computation is implemented by a +system in maximal physical state P, it is also implemented by a system in a +superposition of P with orthogonal physical states. +Accordingly, assume that the original system (in maximal physical state +P) implements a computation C. That is, there is a mapping between physical substates of the system and formal substates of C such that causal relations +between the physical substates correspond to formal relations between the +formal substates. Then a version of the same mapping will also support an +implementation of C in the superposed system. For a given substate S of +the original system, we can find a corresponding substate S' of the superposed +system by the obvious projection relation: the superposed system is in S' +if the system obtained by projecting it onto the hyperplane of P is in S. Because the superposed system is a superposition of P with orthogonal states, +it follows that if the original system is in S, the superposed system is in S'. +Because the Schrodinger equation is linear, it also follows that the statetransition relations between the substates S' precisely mirror the relations +between the original substates S. We know that these relations in turn precisely mirror the formal relations between the substates of C It follows that +the superposed system also implements C, establishing the required result. +By the principle of organizational invariance, if the original system gives rise +to a subject of experience, the superposed system will give rise to a qualitatively indistinguishable subject of experience. +It may also be possible to argue for the superposition principle by applying +the double-aspect theory of information and arguing that the relevant information embodied in the original physical state is also present in the superposition. Because of the underdetermination of that theory, however, this argument is less clear than the previous one, so I will not go into it here. +What matters is that one way or another, the theory of consciousness that +I have partially developed predicts the result that the Everett interpretation +requires. That is, it predicts that even if the world is in a giant superposition, +there will still be subjects who experience a discrete world. +If there are no other problems, it follows that a combination of the Schrodinger equation with an independently motivated theory of consciousness +can predict our manifest image of the world. That is, the only physical principle needed in quantum mechanics is the Schrodinger equation, and the +measurement postulate and other basic principles are unnecessary baggage. + + The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics + +351 + +To be sure, we need psychophysical principles as well, but we need those +principles in any case, and it turns out that the principles that are plausible +on independent grounds can do the requisite work here. This adds up to a +powerful argument for taking the Everett interpretation seriously. + +5. Objections to the Everett Interpretation +Everett's interpretation has come under frequent attack in the literature, +with some objections more powerful than others. I will group these objections +into a number of classes. +Objections based on "splitting" +Many objections arise from interpreting or misinterpreting Everett's view +as a "splitting-worlds" view. This is understandable, given that it is often +called the "many-worlds" interpretation. For example, Bell (1976) objects +that it is unclear when a "branching" event should take place, due to unclarity +in the notion of measurement, and that there is no preferred basis for the +division into worlds. It is clear that these objections do not apply to the +present interpretation, which requires no objective "branching" and no preferred basis. Similarly, Hughes (1989) objects to the "ontological cloudburst" +in the splitting process, and Healey (1984) notes that the creation of new +worlds violates the conservation of mass-energy! It is a pity that the "splitting" interpretation of Everett's view has gained such wide currency, for its +obvious difficulties have meant that the more interesting interpretation has +not received the attention it deserves. +Objections to a preferred basis +Some of the objections to the splitting-worlds interpretation arise from its +need for a preferred basis, but so also do some objections to the singleworld version. In particular, the question arises: Why do the only minds +associated with a superposed brain state correspond to its decomposition +along the preferred basis? Why are there not minds that arise from other +decompositions, or indeed from the superposed state as a whole? This is a +reasonable objection to Everett's own version, which seems to require such +a canonical decomposition. No such objection arises for the version I have +outlined, however, which entails that a superposition gives rise to the associated subjects of discrete experience without any need to postulate a preferred +basis. And I have had no need for the assumption that these are the only +minds that the superposed system gives rise to. + + 352 + +Applications + +What about superposed minds? +The question arises, "Are there other minds associated with a superposition?" To this the answer is "perhaps." If the double-aspect theory of information is accepted, then we already know that there may be experiences +associated with lower-level processes in such a system. It may also be that +there are subjects of experience associated with the structure of processing +in a superposition. Perhaps there are minds associated with other decompositions of the system. Perhaps there is a big superposed mind associated with +the whole superposed system. The existence of such minds depends on the +details of a theory of consciousness, but it is hard to see how their existence +is a problem. +One might try to parlay the possibility of superposed minds into an objection to the theory. Objection: Why is my mind not superposed? Answer: +Because I am who I am. The theory predicts that nonsuperposed minds exist, +and my mind happens to be one of them. To ask why my mind is not one +of the superposed minds is like asking why I am not a mouse. It is simply part +of the brute indexicality of my existence. Mouse minds exist, and superposed +minds may exist, but my mind is not one of them. Objection: Why don't +I have any access to superposed minds, such as memories of superposed +experiences? Answer: The theory predicts that the discrete minds in question +will experience the world as entirely discrete, and they will have no direct +access to other parts of the superposition. All their memories will be of +discrete observations, for example. +It is arguable, in any case, that the only interesting minds associated with +a superposed system are the familiar sort of discrete minds. These minds +are complex and coherent, with experience reflecting the structure of rational +processes. Any further minds that are associated will be relatively incoherent, without much in the way of interesting structure. This conclusion is lent +support by the "decoherence" framework of Gell-Mann and Hartle (1990) +and others. According to this framework, the interesting structure in a wavelike, complex adaptive system is generally found within the components of +a "natural" decomposition; the system "decoheres" naturally along certain +lines. In rational systems, then, coherent cognitive structure may be found +only in the components of this natural decomposition, and only these will +give rise to complex, coherent minds. Any other subjects of experience in +the system will not be the sort of subjects that qualify as persons. +Objections based on personal identity +There is a cluster of intuitive worries based on the identity of the observer. +Take the mind M1 that I remember being around this time yesterday. Today, +there will be a large number of minds descending from that mind, in different + + The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics + +353 + +"branches" of the superposition. My mind M2 is only one of them. I might +well ask: Why did I end up here, rather than in one of the other branches? +As Hofstadter (1985b) puts it: +Why is my unitary feeling of myself propagating down this random branch +rather than down some other? What law underlies the random choices that pick +out the branch I feel myself tracing out? Why doesn't my feeling of myself go +along with the other me's as they split off, following other routes? What attaches +me-ness to the viewpoint of this body evolving down this branch of the universe +at this moment in time? + +To this, we must again invoke brute indexicality: my mind is this one, and +that is that. There is feeling that something deeper must be going on, and +that it is somehow a deep fact about the world that yesterday's mind M1 has +evolved into today's mind M2 and not one of the others. But from an objective +point of view, there is nothing especially privileged about this branch. Even +from the point of view of M1, all of today's minds are equally privileged. +None of them is the single rightful heir of M1; all of them carry M1's "meness" to the same degree. It is only from this point of view, the point of +view of M2, that M2 seems privileged (of course, my counterparts elsewhere +in the superposition have the same feeling about themselves). This privileged role of M2 is just another indexical phenomenon, like the fact that I +am David Chalmers rather than Rolf Harris. This mind is here rather than +there. It is as puzzling as indexical facts usually are, but there is no further +asymmetry in the world. +There is a strong intuition that there must always be a fact of the matter +about personal identity: if there are numerous minds descending from my +current state, there must be a fact about which one of them will be me. But +this idea has been subjected to a powerful critique by Parfit (1984), who +argues persuasively that there is no more to the fact of personal identity +than facts such as psychological continuity, memory, and the like. If we +accept this analysis, then each of tomorrow's minds are equal candidates to +count as me, and there is no fact to distinguish them. There is something +disturbing about this conclusion, which reduces the determinate "flow" of +personal identity to an illusion, but Parfit's analysis gives reason to believe +that this determinate flow was an illusion all along. +The interpretation of probabilities +The most substantial objection to the Everett interpretation is that it cannot +make sense of the probabilities that the measurement postulate delivers.8 +In a given case the measurement postulate may tell us that on making a certain measurement, there will be a 0.9 chance of finding an "up" pointer and +a 0.1 chance of finding a "down" pointer. According to the Everett inter- + + 354 + +Applications + +pretation, what really happens is that both the pointer and the brain state +of an observer go into a superposition, with (at least) two subjects of experience resulting. One of these has an experience of an "up" pointer, and +another experiences a pointer pointing down. Exactly the same would have +happened if the probabilities had been 50:50. It is true that in the 90:10 +case, most of the amplitude of the superposed wave function is concentrated +in the area of the "up" brain state, but what does this have to do with +probabilities? +Everett deals with this question by placing a measure on the space of +observers, corresponding to the probabilities delivered by the measurement +postulate (i.e., corresponding to the square of the amplitude of the corresponding part of the wave function). Using this measure, he argues that in +the limit, most observers (that is, a subset of observers with measure one) +will have memories of observations that accord with the frequencies predicted by the probabilities in the measurement postulate. For example, +among observers who have made a measurement like the one described +above many times, most of them will remember finding an "up" pointer 90 +percent of the time and a "down" pointer 10 percent of the time. Thus a +role is found for the probabilities. The question arises, however: What justifies +this measure on the space of observers? If we measured the space differently, +then very different frequencies might arise. For example, if we assigned equal +measures every time two observers arise from a superposition (regardless of +amplitude), then most observers would recall an "up"-"down" ratio of 50:50. +Neither the Schrodinger equation nor the psychophysical laws ensures that +either of these measures is the "correct" one. +Albert and Loewer (1988) respond to this worry by dispensing with measures. Instead they postulate more radical psychophysical laws, according to +which there is an infinity of minds associated with every brain state. For +every mind postulated by the previous view, this theory postulates an infinite ensemble of qualitatively identical minds. Further, wherever the Everett +theory predicts that a mind will diverge into two minds, this theory says that +any given mind will go in one direction or the other, with the probabilities +given by the measurement postulate. So, if we take an arbitrary mind associated with the brain state before the measurement above, it will have a 90 +percent chance of evolving into a "perceiving up" state and a 10 percent +chance of evolving into a "perceiving down" state. This way the probabilistic +predictions of the quantum-mechanical calculus are preserved. +There is clearly a loss in simplicity here. The new psychophysical laws +have no independent motivation, and the theory also needs extra "intrapsychic" laws governing the evolution of minds. By making these ad hoc postulates, the theory sacrifices some of the key virtues of the Everett interpretation. It is also arguable that the intrapsychic laws are problematic, in that +they postulate deep irreducible facts about personal identity over time. It is + + The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics + +355 + +hard to know what to make of these facts. Accepting them would require +discarding Parfit's analysis of personal identity, for example. They fail to +supervene even naturally on physical facts, and so complicate the metaphysical picture. This interpretation should be kept in mind as a possibility, but +it comes at a significant cost. +The alternative is to do without the extra apparatus, and to see if the +probabilities can be recovered some other way. It is tempting to see this as +a problem about indexicality. Why is it that of all the places in the wave +function that I could have ended up, I ended up in a region where my +memories match the predictions of the calculus? One possibility is simply +to take this as a brute indexical fact: some minds are in this area, and I +happen to be one of them. But this seems unsatisfying, as the remarkable +regularity of the calculus turns out then to be a huge fluke. What we need +is some way to argue that it is not such a fluke. +Even in noting that it is a fluke that I ended up here, the idea is implicit +that there is some kind of measure on the space of minds. The suggestion +is that it is antecedently more likely that I should end up being a mind of +one type rather than another, perhaps because of the relative abundance of +those classes. This sort of implicit measure is present in much of our reasoning about the world. When I reason inductively from some evidence to a +conclusion, I know that for some observers in a similar epistemic position +the conclusion will not hold, but I assume that for most such observers the +conclusion will hold, even if there are an infinite number in each class. That +is, I assume that it is antecedently more likely that I will turn out to be in +one class rather than another. This sort of reasoning implicitly supposes +some kind of measure on the space of minds. +Perhaps we can justify the probabilities, then, by explicitly introducing +this sort of measure. Certainly the bulk of the amplitude of the wave function +is concentrated in areas where the memories of observers match the predictions of the calculus. Maybe it is more likely that my mind should turn out +to be in a high-amplitude area than in a low-amplitude area. In particular, +if we assume that the antecedent likelihood that I will turn out to be one +mind rather than another is proportional to the squared amplitude of the +associated part of the wave function, then it follows that I will almost certainly +turn out to have memories in the frequencies predicted by the quantummechanical calculus. +But to what does this measure objectively correspond? Does it need to +be taken as a basic fact about the distribution of selves? Can it somehow +be justified as the canonical measure on this space? These are difficult questions that are closely tied to the mystery of indexicality itself—why did I +turn out to be this person rather than someone else? This is one of the basic +mysteries, and it is very unclear just how it should be answered. Nevertheless, +the idea of a measure on the space of minds seems to have some promise, + + 356 + +Applications + +and may even be needed for some other purposes, such as the justification +of induction. In the meantime, the interpretation of the probabilities remains +the most significant difficulty for the Everett interpretation. + +6. Conclusion +It must be admitted that the Everett interpretation is almost impossible to +believe. It postulates that there is vastly more in the world than we are ever +aware of. On this interpretation, the world is really in a giant superposition +of states that have been evolving in different ways since the beginning of +time, and we are experiencing only the smallest substate of the world. It +also postulates that my future is not determinate: in a minute's time, there +will be a large number of minds that have an equal claim to count as me. +A minute has passed since I wrote the last sentence; who is to know what +all those other minds are now doing? +On the other hand, it is clear by now that all interpretations of quantum +mechanics are to some extent crazy. That is the fundamental paradox of +quantum mechanics. The three leading candidates for interpretation are +perhaps Wigner's interpretation on which consciousness brings about collapse, Bohm's nonlocal hidden variables interpretation, and the Everett +interpretation. Of these, Wigner's interpretation implies that macroscopic +objects are often in superpositions, until a casual look from an observer +causes them to collapse. Bohm's view implies that the trajectory of every +particle in the universe depends on the state of every other. And the Everett +view implies that there is much more in the world than we ever would +have thought. +Of these, perhaps Bohm's view is the least crazy and Everett's the most, +with Wigner's in between. Ranked in order of theoretical virtue, on the +other hand, the sequence is reversed. Bohm's view is unsatisfying due to its +complex, jury-rigged nature. Wigner's view is quite elegant, with its two +basic dynamical laws mirroring the quantum-mechanical calculus, if all the +details can be worked out. But Everett's view is by far the simplest. It +postulates only the Schrodinger equation, the principle that is accepted by +all interpretations of quantum mechanics. It also has the virtues of being an +entirely local theory, and of being straightforwardly compatible with relativity theory, virtues that the other interpretations lack. +It is also worth noting that both of the other interpretations contain elements of what is counterintuitive about the Everett interpretation. On the +Wigner view, we must accept that the universe evolved in an Everett-style +giant superposition—perhaps with superposed stars and superposed rocks, +if not with superposed cats—at least until the first conscious entity evolved + + The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics + +357 + +to collapse the wave function. On the Bohm view, Everett's uncollapsed +wave function remains present as the "pilot wave" that guides the position +of the various particles. All the structure that is present in other components +thus remains present in the state of the world, even though most of it +is irrelevant to the evolution of the particles. Given that these views, too, +require an uncollapsed wave function in central roles, one might argue that +the relative implausibility of the Everett view is diminished. +Of course, it is always possible that a new theory might be developed that +surpasses all of these in plausibility and theoretical virtue. But it does not +seem especially likely. The complete absence of experimental anomalies suggests that the quantum-mechanical calculus is here to stay as a predictive +theory. If so, we cannot expect empirical developments to solve the problem. +Perhaps conceptual developments could lead to a new and improved interpretation, but it may be that by now the most promising niches in conceptual +space have already been exploited. If so, we may be stuck with something +like the current range of options—perhaps with significant refinements, but +with advantages and disadvantages of a qualitatively similar kind. Of these +options, the Everett interpretation seems in many ways the most attractive, +but at the same time it is the hardest to accept. +I have advocated some counterintuitive views in this work. I resisted +mind-body dualism for a long time, but I have now come to the point where +I accept it, not just as the only tenable view but as a satisfying view in its +own right. It is always possible that I am confused, or that there is a new +and radical possibility that I have overlooked; but I can comfortably say +that I think dualism is very likely true. I have also raised the possibility of +a kind of panpsychism. Like mind-body dualism, this is initially counterintuitive, but the counterintuitiveness disappears with time. I am unsure whether +the view is true or false, but it is at least intellectually appealing, and on +reflection it is not too crazy to be acceptable. +The craziness of the Everett interpretation is of another order of magnitude. I find it easily the most intellectually appealing of the various interpretations of quantum mechanics, but I confess that I cannot wholeheartedly +believe it. If God forced me to bet my life on the truth or falsity of the +doctrines I have advocated, I would bet fairly confidently that experience is +fundamental, and weakly that experience is ubiquitous. But on the Everett +interpretation I would be torn, and perhaps I would not be brave enough +to bet on it at the end of the day.9 Maybe it is simply too strange to believe. +Still, it is not clear whether much weight should be put on these intuitive doubts in the final analysis. The view is simple and elegant, and it predicts that there will be observers who see the world just as I see it. Is that +not enough? We may never be able to accept the view emotionally, but we +should at least take seriously the possibility that it is true. + + This page intentionally left blank + + Notes +Chapter 1 +1. See Nagel 1974. The first use of this phrase in philosophical contexts is usually +attributed to Farrell (1950). See also Sprigge 1971. +2. Different authors use the term "qualia" in different ways. I use the term in +what I think is the standard way, to refer to those properties of mental states that +type those states by what it is like to have them. In using the term, I do not mean +to make any immediate commitment on further issues, such as whether qualia are +incorrigibly knowable, whether they are intentional properties, and so on. Qualia +can be properties of "internal" mental states as well as of sensations. It is often +convenient to speak as if qualia are properties instantiated directly by a subject, +rather than by that subject's mental states; this practice is harmless, and justified by +the fact that qualia correspond to mental state-types in their own right. +3. I use expressions such as "red sensation," "green experience," and the like +throughout this book. Of course by doing this I do not mean to imply that experiences +instantiate the same sort of color properties that are instantiated by objects (apples, +trees) in the external world. This sort of talk can always be rephrased as "experience +of the type that I usually have (in the actual world) when looking at red objects," +and so on, but the briefer locution is more natural. +4. Cook 12 cups of dried black-eyed peas in boiling water to which 4 tablespoons +of salt have been added. Cook until tender, and immerse in cold water. Combine 2 +diced red peppers, 5 diced green peppers, 2 diced large onions, 3 cups of raisins, and +a bunch of chopped cilantro in a dressing made of 1.5 cups of corn oil, 0.75 cup of +wine vinegar, 4 tablespoons of sugar, 1 tablespoon of salt, 4 tablespoons of black +pepper, 5 tablespoons of curry powder, and a half-tablespoon of ground cloves. Serve +chilled. Thanks to Lisa Thomas and the Encore Cafe. +5. For a wealth of reflection on the varieties of specific experiences, see Ackerman's A Natural History of the Senses (1990), which provides material for those +absorbed by their conscious experience to mull over for days. +6. Interestingly, Descartes often excluded sensations from the category of the +mental, instead assimilating them to the bodily, so not every phenomenal state (at +least as I am understanding the notion) would count as mental, either. +7. This common interpretation of Ryle does not do justice to the subtlety of his +views, but it is at least a useful fiction. +8. There are other forms of functionalism, such as that developed by Putnam +(1960). I do not consider these here, as they were put forward as empirical hypotheses +rather than as analyses of mental concepts. + + 360 + +Notes to pages 15-29 + +9. Nagel (1970) makes a similar point against Armstrong, with reference to the +problem of other minds. +10. Searle's argument depends on the claim that without consciousness, there is +no way to explain the "aspectual shape" that intentionality exhibits, as when someone believes something about Venus under its "morning star" aspect but not under +its "evening star" aspect. It is not clear to me that aspectual shape cannot be accounted +for in other ways; one might even argue that present-day computers exhibit something +like it, storing information about me under one "aspect" but not another (e.g., under +my name but not under my social security number). It might be objected that this +is only "as-if" aspectual shape, as the only true aspectual shape is phenomenal +aspectual shape; but this would seem to trivialize the argument. +11. Such a position is suggested by some remarks of Lockwood (1989) and Nagel +(1986), although I am not sure that either is committed to this position. +12. Some might point to arguments such as that of Kripke (1982) to the effect +that the content of a belief is not determined by psychological and phenomenal +properties. These arguments are controversial, but in any case it is notable that the +conclusion of these arguments is not that content is a further irreducible element of +the mind, but rather that content itself is indeterminate. In effect, what is going on +here is that considerations such as those in the text give us good reason to believe +there is no third, independently variable aspect of the mind; so any matters that are +not settled by the first two elements are not settled at all. +13. This is a "topic-neutral" analysis of specific phenomenal notions not unlike +those advocated by Place (1956) and Smart (1959). To be an orange experience, very +roughly, is to be the kind of experience that is generally caused by oranges. Place: +"[W]hen we describe the after-image as green ... we are saying that we are having +the sort of experience which we normally have when, and which we have learned to +describe as, looking at a green patch of light" (p. 49); Smart: "When a person says +'I see a yellowish-orange after-image', he is saying something like this: 'There is +something going on which is like what is going on when I have my eyes open, am +awake, and there is an orange illuminated in good light in front of me'" (p. 150). +But because of the occurrence of the unanalyzed notion of "experience," this analysis +is not sufficient to immediately establish an identification between phenomenal and +physical states, in the way that Place and Smart suggested. Smart's account avoids +this problem by leaving "experience" out of the analysis in favor of the equivocal +phrase "something going on." If "something going on" is construed broadly enough +to cover any sort of state, then the analysis is inadequate; if it is construed narrowly +as a sort of experience, the analysis is closer to the mark but it does not suffice for +the conclusion. +14. Jackendoff distinguishes the "phenomenological mind" and the "computational mind." This distinction comes to much the same as the phenomenalpsychological distinction outlined here, although I would not like to beg the question +about whether psychological processes are computational. +15. Nelkin (1989) distinguishes CN (consciousness in the "Nagel" sense) from Cl +(a first-order information-processing state) and C2 (second-order direct noninferential accessing of other conscious states). In another paper (Nelkin 1993), he makes +a related distinction between phenomenality, intentionality, and introspectability. +Bisiach (1988) distinguishes Cl (phenomenal experience) from C2 (the access of +parts or processes of a system to other of its parts or processes). Natsoulas (1978) + + Notes to pages 30-34 + +361 + +distinguishes a large number of senses of the term "consciousness." Dennett (1969) +distinguishes two kinds of "awareness," the first associated with verbal reports and +the second more generally with the control of behavior, although neither of these is +a clearly phenomenal notion. +16. Rosenthal explicitly separates consciousness from "sensory quality," and says +he is giving a theory only of the first, which might suggest that phenomenal aspects +are not under discussion. But he also says that a state is conscious when there is +something it is like to be in that state, which suggests that the subject is phenomenal +consciousness after all. However, there is very little in Rosenthal's account to suggest +an explanation of phenomenal consciousness. Why should the existence of a higherorder thought about a state lead to there being something it is like to be in that +state? Aside from arguing that the two phenomena plausibly go together in practice, +Rosenthal offers no answer to this question. +17. One exception is the field of psychophysics, which arguably sheds light on +various features of conscious experience, even if it does not provide a full explanation. I discuss this further in Chapter 6. + +Chapter 2 +1. The idea of supervenience was introduced by Moore (1922). The name was +introduced in print by Hare (1952). Davidson (1970) was the first to apply to the notion +to the mind-body problem. More recently, a sophisticated theory of supervenience has +been developed by Kim (1978, 1984, 1993), Morgan (1982, 1984c, 1993), Hellman +and Thompson (1975), and others. +2. I use "A-fact" as shorthand for "instantiation of an A-property." The appeal +to facts makes the discussion less awkward, but all talk of facts and their relations +can ultimately be cashed out in terms of patterns of co-instantiation of properties; +I give the details in notes, where necessary. In particular, it should be noted that the +identity of the individual that instantiates an A-property is irrelevant to an A-fact +as I am construing it; all that matters is the instantiation of the property. If the +identity of an individual were partly constitutive of an A-fact, then any A-fact would +entail facts about that individual's essential properties, in which case the definition +of supervenience would lead to counterintuitive consequences. +3. I assume, perhaps artificially, that individuals have precise spatiotemporal +boundaries, so that their physical properties consist in the properties instantiated in +that region of space-time. If we are to count spatially distinct objects as physically +identical for the purposes of local supervenience, any properties concerning absolute +spatiotemporal position must be omitted from the supervenience base (although one +could avoid the need to appeal to spatially distinct objects by considering only merely +possible objects with the same position). Also, I always talk as if the same sort of +individual instantiates low-level and high-level properties, so that a table, for example, +instantiates microphysical properties by virtue of being characterized by a distribution +of such properties. Perhaps it would be more strictly correct to talk of microphysical +properties as being instantiated only by microphysical entities, but my way of speaking simplifies things. In any case, the truly central issues will all involve global rather +than local supervenience. +4. There are various ways to specify precisely what it is for two worlds to be +identical with respect to a set of properties; this will not matter much to the discus- + + 362 + +Notes to pages 35-38 + +sion. Perhaps the best is to say that two worlds are identical with respect to their +A-properties if there is a one-to-one mapping between the classes of individuals +instantiating A-properties in both worlds, such that any two corresponding individuals +instantiate the same A-properties. For the purposes of global supervenience we then +need to stipulate that the mappings by which two worlds are seen to be both A- and +B-indiscernible are compatible with each other; that is, no individual is mapped to +one counterpart under the A-mapping but to another under the B-mapping. The +definition of global supervenience takes this form: Any two worlds that are Aidentical (under a mapping) are B-identical (under an extension of that mapping). +A more common way to do this is to stipulate that A-identical worlds must contain +exactly the same individuals, instantiating the same properties, but as McLaughlin +(1995) points out, this is unreasonably strong: it ensures that such things as the +cardinality of the world and essential properties of individuals supervene on any +properties whatsoever. The definition I propose gets around this problem, by ensuring +that only patterns of A-properties and nothing further enter into the determination relation. +5. With one exception: God could not have created a world that was not created +by God, even though a world not created by God is presumably logically possible! +I will ignore this sort of complication. +6. The relationship of this sort of possibility to deducibility in formal systems is +a subtle one. It is arguable that the axioms and inference rules of specific formal +systems are justified precisely in terms of a prior notion of logical possibility and +necessity. +7. The intuitive notion of natural possibility is conceptually prior to the definition +in terms of laws of nature: a regularity qualifies as a law just in case it holds in all +situations that could come up in nature; that is, in all situations that are naturally +possible in the intuitive sense. As it is sometimes put, for something to count as a +law it must hold not just in actual but in counterfactual situations, and the more +basic notion of natural possibility is required to determine which counterfactual +situations are relevant. +8. The terms "physical necessity" and "causal necessity" are also often used to +pick out roughly this brand of necessity, but I do not wish to beg the question of +whether all the laws of nature are physical or causal. +9. The important distinction between logical and natural supervenience is frequently glossed over or ignored in the literature, where the modality of supervenience +relations is often left unspecified. Natural (or nomological) supervenience without +logical supervenience is discussed by van Cleve (1990), who uses it to explicate a +variety of emergence. Seager (1991) spells out a related distinction between what he +calls constitutive and correlative supervenience. These correspond in a straightforward +way to logical and natural supervenience, although Seager does not analyze the +notions in quite the same way. +10. Weak supervenience requires only that "no B-difference without an A-difference" holds within a world, rather than across worlds (see Kim 1984 for details). +The lack of modal strength in this relation makes it too weak for most purposes. At +best, it may have a role in expressing conceptual constraints on nonfactual discourse +(as in Hare 1984), although as Horgan (1993) points out, even these constraints seem +to involve cross-world dependence. Seager (1988) appeals to weak supervenience to +express a kind of systematic within-world correlation that is not strictly necessary, +but natural supervenience serves this purpose much better. + + Notes to pages 38-41 + +363 + +11. Global natural supervenience without localized regularity is a coherent notion +on a non-Humean account of laws, although perhaps not on a Humean (regularitybased) account. Even on a non-Humean account, though, it is hard to see what the +evidence for such a relation could consist in. +12. Horgan (1982), Jackson (1994), and Lewis (1983b) address a related problem +in the context of denning materialism. +13. The revised definition can be spelled out more precisely along the lines of +note 4. Let B(W) be the class of individuals with B-properties in a world W. We can +say that W is B-superior to W if there is an injection /: B(W) -> B(W) (i.e., a oneto-one mapping from B(W) onto a subset of B(W')) such that for all a G B(W), f(d) +instantiates every B-property that a does. Then B-properties supervene logically on +A-properties in W if every world that is A-indiscernible from W is B-superior to +W, where the relevant B-mappings are again constrained to be extensions of the +A-mappings. +To see that the constraint is necessary, imagine that our world has a countably +infinite number of psychologically identical minds, of which one is realized in ectoplasm and the rest are physically realized. Intuitively, the psychological does not +supervene on the physical in this world, but every physically indiscernible world is +psychologically superior. Although we expect the ectoplasm-free world to count +against supervenience, there is a one-to-one mapping between the psychologies in +that world and in our world. The problem is that this mapping does not respect +physical correspondence, as it maps a physical entity to an ectoplasmic entity; so we +need the further constraint. +14. For the purposes of this definition, the containment relation between worlds +can be taken as primitive. Lewis (1983a) and Jackson (1993) have noted that it is +fruitless to analyze this sort of notion forever. Something needs to be taken as +primitive, and the containment relation seems to be as clear as any. Some might +prefer to speak, not of worlds that contain W as a proper part, but of worlds that +contain a qualitative duplicate of W as a proper part; this works equally well. +15. Note that by this definition, there are positive facts that are not instantiations +of positive properties. Think of instantiations of the property of being childless-ora-kangaroo, for example. Perhaps positive facts should be defined more strictly as +instantiations of positive properties, but as far as I can tell the weaker definition has +no ill effects. +16. Arguably, the logical supervenience of properties in our world should be a +lawful thesis. If it were the case that there would have been nonphysical living angels +if things had gone a little differently in our world (perhaps a few different random +fluctuations), even though the laws of nature were being obeyed, then it would be +a mere accident of history that biological properties are logically supervenient on +physical properties. One gets a stronger and more interesting metaphysical thesis by +replacing the references to our world and actual individuals in the definitions of +logical supervenience by a reference to naturally possible worlds and individuals. +This rules out scenarios like the one above. As a bonus, it allows us to determine +whether or not uninstantiated properties, such as that of being a mile-high skyscraper, +are logically supervenient. On the previous definition, all such properties supervene vacuously. +This yields the following definition: B-properties are logically supervenient on +A-properties iff for any naturally possible situation X and any logically possible situation Y, if X and Y are A-indiscernible then Y is B-superior to X (with the usual con- + + 364 + +Notes to pages 41-57 + +straint). Or more briefly: for any naturally possible situation, the B-facts about that +situation are entailed by the A-facts. This modification makes no significant difference +to the discussion in the text, so I omit it for simplicity's sake. The discussion can easily +be recast in terms of the stricter definition simply by replacing relevant references to +"our world" by references to "all naturally possible worlds" throughout the text, +usually without any loss in the plausibility of the associated claims. +The result resembles the standard definition of "strong" local supervenience (Kim +1984), in which there are two modal operators. According to that definition, Bproperties supervene on A-properties if necessarily, for each jc and each B-property +F, if x has F, then there is an A-property G such that x has G, and necessarily if any +y has G, it has F. (The A-properties G may be thought of as complexes of simpler +A-properties, if necessary.) The angel issue makes it clear that the first modal operator +should always be understood as natural necessity, even when the second is logical +necessity. The standard definition of global supervenience (that A-indiscernible +worlds are B-indiscernible) is less well off, and needs to be modified along the lines +I have suggested. A parallel definition of "metaphysical" supervenience can be given +if necessary. Of course, the angel problems do not arise for natural supervenience, as +there is no reason to believe that ectoplasm is naturally possible, so the straightforward +definition of natural supervenience is satisfactory. +17. Arguably, we should use the stronger definition of logical supervenience, so +that materialism is true if all the positive facts about all naturally possible worlds are +entailed by the physical facts about those worlds. Take an ectoplasm-free world in +which nonphysical ectoplasm is nevertheless a natural possibility—perhaps it would +have evolved if a few random fluctuations had gone differently. It seems reasonable +to say that materialism is false in such a world, or at least that it is true only in a +weak sense. +18. To gain the equivalence, we need the plausible principle that if world A is a +proper part of world B, then some positive fact holds in B that does not hold in A; +that is, there is some fact that holds in B and in all larger worlds that does not hold +in A. +19. It also comes to much the same thing as definitions by Horgan (1982) and +Lewis (1983b), but unlike these it does not rely on the somewhat obscure notion of +"alien property" to rule out ectoplasmic worlds from the range of relevant possible worlds. +20. In the philosophical literature multiple realizability is often pointed to as the +main obstacle to "reduction," but as Brooks (1994) argues, it seems largely irrelevant +to the way that reductive explanations are used in the sciences. Biological phenomena +such as wings can be realized in many different ways, for example, but biologists +give reductive explanations all the same. Indeed, as has been pointed out by Wilson +(1985) and Churchland (1986), many physical phenomena that are often taken to be +paradigms of reducibility (e.g., temperature) are in fact multiply realizable. +21. Some would say that one should not speak of what "water" would refer to if +the XYZ-world turned out to be actual, because in that case the word that sounds +like "water" would be a different word altogether! If one is worried about this, we +can simply talk about what the homophonous word would refer to; or better, one +can think of these scenarios as epistemic possibilities (in a broad sense) and the +conditionals as epistemic conditionals, so that worries about essential properties of +words are bypassed. In any case the general point that actual-world reference depends + + Notes to pages 57-60 + +365 + +on how the world turns out is clear no matter how we describe the scenario. In the +text I will generally ignore this nicety. +22. Not everyone is convinced that Kripke and Putnam are correct in their claim +that water is necessarily H2O, and that XYZ is not water; for some doubts, see Lewis +1994. Certainly, it would seem that most of our linguistic practices would be just as +they are even if we used the term "water" to pick out watery stuff in counterfactual +worlds. The fact that it is easy to sway both ways on this matter suggests that not +too much that is really central to the explanation of a phenomenon such as water +can turn on the nature of the secondary intension. Indeed, the fact that one is always +free to use terms such as "watery stuff" instead of "water" in these matters is a clue +that a posteriori necessity is unlikely to change anything really central to questions +about explanation, physicalism, and the like. Siewert (1994) bypasses questions about +a posteriori necessity in this fashion. I was tempted to do so myself, but in the end +I think the two-dimensional framework is independently interesting. +23. There may of course be borderline cases in which it is indeterminate whether +a concept would refer to a certain object if a given world turned out to be actual. +This is no problem: we can allow indeterminacies in a primary intension, as we +sometimes allow indeterminacies in reference in our own world. There may also be +cases in which there is more than one equally good candidate for the referent of a +concept in a world (as, perhaps, with "mass" in a relativistic world, which might +refer to rest mass or relativistic mass); just as we tolerated divided reference in +such actual cases, we should occasionally expect divided reference in the value of a +primary intension. +With some borderline cases, it may even be that whether we count an object as +falling under the extension of a concept will depend on various accidental historical +factors. A stimulating paper by Wilson (1982) discusses such cases, including for +example a hypothetical case in which druids might end up classifying airplanes as +"birds" if they first saw a plane flying overhead, but not if they first found one crashed +in the jungle. One might try to classify these two different scenarios as different ways +for the actual world to turn out, and therefore retain a fixed, detailed primary +intension; or one might regard such cases as indeterminate with respect to a core +primary intension. In any case, a little looseness around the edges of a primary +intension is entirely compatible with my applications of the framework. +24. See Field 1973.1 think an analysis in terms of primary intensions can provide +a way of regarding "meaning change" as being much less frequent than is often +supposed. The case of relativity provides no reason to believe that the primary +intension of "mass" has changed from the last century to this one, for example, +although our beliefs about the actual world have certainly changed. (For related +reasons, one might try to use an analysis in terms of primary intensions to resist +"meaning holism" about thought.) Any "development" in primary intensions is +at best likely to be of the more subtle kind suggested by the examples in Wilson +1982, where the core stays fixed but accidents of history can make a difference to +classification practices around the edges. But all this deserves a much more extensive development. +25. Some differences: (1) Kaplan's content corresponds very closely to a secondary +intension, but he presents character as a function from context to content, whereas +a primary intension is a function from context to extension. Given rigidification, +however, a primary intension is straightforwardly derivable from a character and + + 366 + +Notes to pages 60-66 + +vice versa. I use the former for reasons of symmetry and simplicity. (2) Kaplan uses +his account to deal with indexical and demonstrative terms like "I" and "that," but +does not extend it to deal with natural-kind terms such as "water," as he takes +"water" to pick out H2O in all contexts (the sound-alike word on Twin Earth is +simply a different word), and he takes the process of reference fixation here to be +part of "metasemantics" rather than semantics. As before, whether it is part of +metasemantics or semantics makes little difference for my purposes; all that matters +is that reference fixation depends in some way on how the actual world turns out. +26. It might seem that the primary intension is only well defined over possible +worlds centered on individuals thinking an appropriate thought, or making an appropriate utterance. I think the primary intension is naturally extendible to a wider +class of worlds: we can retain the concept from our own world, and consider how it +applies to other worlds considered as actual (see Chalmers 1994c), though it may +have indeterminate reference in some worlds. But this will not make much difference +in what follows. +27. Note that strictly speaking the primary intension picks out the liquid in our +historical environment: if I travel to Twin Earth and say "water," I still refer to H2O. +28. The relation between the second and third considerations in this section—that +is, between Quine's empirical reusability and Kripke's a posteriori necessity—is +complex and interesting. As Kripke observes, the framework he develops accounts +for some but not all of the problems raised by Quine. Kripke's analysis accounts for +a posteriori revisions in intensions, and therefore for changes in a certain sense of +"meaning." However, the two-dimensional analysis agrees with the single-intension +account on the truth-values it assigns at the actual world, so it does not account for +the Quinean possibility of certain purported a priori conceptual truths turning out +to be false in the actual world, in the face of sufficient empirical evidence. It seems +to me that such purported conceptual truths are simply not conceptual truths at all, +although they may be close approximations. +29. A subtle point that comes up in using the two-dimensional framework to +capture the contents of thought is that sometimes a thought can endorse a centered +world as a potential environment even if it does not contain a copy of the thought +itself. For example, if I think "I am in a coma," I endorse those centered worlds in +which the individual at the center is in a coma, whether or not they are having +thoughts. So one has to tread carefully in defining primary intensions and primary +propositions for thoughts; more carefully than I have trodden here in the case of +language. +30. Worlds should be seen prelinguistically, perhaps as distributions of basic qualities. Worlds are probably best not seen as collections of statements, as statements +describe a world, and we have seen that they can do so in more than one way. To +regard a world as a collection of statements would be to lose this distinction. Perhaps +worlds can be regarded as collections of propositions (Adams 1974), if propositions +are understood appropriately, or as maximal properties (Stalnaker 1976), or as states +of affairs (Plantinga 1976), or as structural universals (Forrest 1986), or as concrete +objects analogous to our own world (Lewis 1986a). Perhaps the notion can +simply be taken as primitive. In any case, talk of possible worlds is as well or poorly +grounded as talk of possibility and necessity in general. As with mathematical notions, +these modal notions can be usefully deployed even preceding a satisfying ontological analysis. + + Notes to pages 66-78 + +367 + +I will always be considering worlds "qualitatively," and abstracting away from +questions of "haecceity." That is, I will count two worlds that are qualitatively +identical as identical, and will not be concerned with questions about whether individuals in those worlds might have different "identities" (some have argued that they +might). These issues of transworld identity raise many interesting issues, but are +largely irrelevant to my uses of the possible-worlds framework. +31. In particular, some might deny the equation of meaning and intension for +mathematical terms. It is often held that statements such as "There are an infinite +number of primes" are not true in virtue of meaning despite being true in all possible +worlds; those who make this claim would presumably resist an equation of meaning +with intension. +Others might resist the claim that the primary intension of a term such as "water" +is part of its meaning; perhaps they think that the meaning of the term is exhausted +by its reference, and that the primary intension is part of pragmatics rather than +semantics. Still others might resist the claim that the secondary intension is part of +its meaning. In any case, nothing rests on the use of the word "meaning." It is truth +in virtue of intension that I am interested in, whether or not intensions are meanings. +32. This definition of conceivability is related to that given by Yablo (1993), according to which P is conceivable if one can imagine a world that one takes to verify +P. The difference is that Yablo's "that one takes to verify" clause allows room for +misdescription of conceived situations, so that this variety of conceivability is at +best a defeasible guide to possibility. On my definition this source of defeasibility is +removed. Of course, it reappears in the form of a larger gap between what one finds +conceivable at first glance and what is really conceivable; so one has to be more +reflective in making judgments of conceivability. +33. One can arguably apply this critique to Descartes's argument that he can +conceive of being disembodied, so it is possible that he is disembodied, so he is +nonphysical (as any physical entity is necessarily embodied). "I am disembodied" +may be 1-conceivable and therefore 1-possible, but it does not follow that it is 2conceivable or 2-possible. By contrast, the sense in which "I am embodied" would +be necessary if he were a physical object is 2-necessity, not 1-necessity. (The primary +intension of his concept "I" picks out the individual at the center of any world; the +secondary intension picks out Descartes in every world.) +34. One might say that there is nothing especially "metaphysical" about metaphysical necessity. Seen this way, it is merely a brand of conceptual necessity with an a +posteriori semantic twist, stemming from the two-dimensional nature of our concepts. +For more on the theme that a posteriori necessity reflects convention as much as +metaphysics, see Putnam 1983 and Sidelle 1989, 1992. +35. Morgan (1984c) sets out and argues for the position that all high-level facts +supervene logically on microphysical facts. As he puts it, those facts are tied to the +microphysical by "semantic constraints," so that all there is in the world is microphysics and "cosmic hermeneutics." He conspicuously avoids the problem of conscious experience, however. Others who advocate versions of the logical supervenience thesis include Jackson (1993), Kirk (1974), and Lewis (1994). +36. For arguments that facts about abstract entities are logically supervenient on +the physical, see Armstrong 1982. +37. Conscious experience arguably contributes to the primary intension, if water +is individuated partly by the kind of experience it gives rise to. Indexicality certainly + + 368 + +Notes to pages 79-84 + +contributes, as seen by the "our" in the "the clear, drinkable liquid in our environment." These facts do not undermine logical supervenience modulo conscious experience and indexicality. +38. As is familiar from the Ramsey-sentence method for the application of theoretical terms; see Lewis 1972. +39. An example suggested as a puzzle case by Ned Block. +40. A similar point about the requirement of analyzability for supervenience is +made by Jackson (1993) and Lewis (1994). +41. An alternative plausible account holds that for something to be red, it must +be the kind of thing that tends to cause Ted-judgments. This would eliminate the +problems discussed here, as judgments are plausibly logically supervenient on the +physical. +42. Except, arguably, in that where I have a belief about Bill Clinton, my duplicate +has a belief about Clinton's duplicate. As usual, these issues concerning transworld +identity can be left aside. +43. The closest thing to such an argument is that given by Kripke's (1982) version +of Wittgenstein, who argues in effect that there can be no entailment from physical +and phenomenal facts to intentional facts, as the entailment cannot be mediated by +a physical, functional, or phenomenal analysis of intentional concepts. The arguments +(particularly those against a functional analysis) are controversial, but in any case, +as noted earlier, the conclusion of the argument is not that intentional facts are further facts, but that they are not strictly facts at all. +If the Kripke-Wittgenstein argument against entailment is accepted, intentionality +stands in a position similar to that in which morality stands below. In both cases, (1) +there is arguably no conceptual entailment from A-facts to B-facts, but (2) if there +are B-facts in our world, then they hold in every conceivable A-indiscernible world. +The only reasonable conclusion is that strictly speaking there are no B-facts, and Battributions must be treated in some deflationary way. The possibility that B-facts +are fundamental further facts is ruled out by conceivability considerations, which +show that there must be an a priori link from A-facts to B-facts if B-facts are +instantiated at all. +44. If there are subjective moral facts, then moral attributions have determinate +truth conditions, but these are dependent on the ascriber. If so, moral concepts have +an indexical primary intension, and there is logical supervenience modulo indexicality. This analysis is endorsed by proponents of "subjectivist moral realism" (SayreMcCord 1989), who interpret "good" as something like "good-for-me" or "goodaccording-to-my-community." The subjectivity involved makes this a very weak kind +of realism, however. For example, on this view it turns out that two people arguing +over what is "good" might not be disagreeing at all. +45. The arguments of Kripke (1972), such as those concerning the reference of +"Godel" in various situations, suggest that the primary intension associated with the +use of a name cannot in general be summarized by a short description. They may +also suggest that the primary intension cannot be summarized by any finite description, +although I am less sure of this (certainly, they establish that any such description +must include a metalinguistic element and a condition requiring an appropriate causal +connection to the agent). But nothing in these arguments suggests that a name (as +used on any given occasion) lacks a primary intension altogether. Indeed, Kripke's +very arguments proceed by considering how the reference of a name depends on + + Notes to pages 85-103 + +369 + +the way the actual world turns out; that is, by evaluating the name's primary intension +at various centered worlds. +46. For a lucid discussion of this matter, see Nagel 1986. +47. How do negative facts evade the arguments for logical supervenience above? +The argument from conceivability fails, as the angel example shows. The argument +from epistemology fails as there clearly is an epistemological problem about how we +can know universal claims of unrestricted scope (we cannot be certain that there are +no angels). The argument from analyzability fails, as there is no analysis of these +negative facts wholly in terms of positive facts (unless we bring in the second-order +"that's all" fact). +48. How do laws evade the arguments for logical supervenience above? The argument from conceivability fails, as the example above shows. The argument from +epistemology fails, as there clearly are problems with the epistemology of laws and +causation, as witnessed by Hume's skeptical challenge. The argument from analysis +fails, as lawhood requires a counterfactual-supporting universal regularity, and the +relevant counterfactuals cannot be analyzed in terms of particular facts about a world +history (pace Lewis 1973). The particular facts about the world's spatiotemporal +history are compatible with the truth of all sorts of different counterfactuals. +49. Humean views of laws and causation can be found in Lewis 1986b, Mackie +1974, and Skyrms 1980. For arguments against such views, see Armstrong 1982, +Carroll 1994, Dretske 1977, Molnar 1969, and Tooley 1977. +50. By contrast, those who appear to hold that logical supervenience is the rule +rather than the exception include Armstrong (1982), Horgan (1984c), Jackson (1993), +Lewis (1994), and Nagel (1974). +51. For more on this, see Horgan and Timmons 1992b. + +Chapter 3 +1. Kirk (1974) provides a vivid description of a zombie, and even outlines a situation that might lead us to believe that someone in the actual world had turned into +a zombie, by specifying appropriate intermediate cases. Campbell (1970) similarly +discusses an "imitation man" that is physically identical to a normal person, but that +lacks experience entirely. +2. Kirk (1974) argues for the logical possibility of zombies in this indirect fashion. +3. Jacoby (1990) makes the excellent point that conceivability arguments pose +no more of a problem for functionalist accounts of consciousness than they do for +materialist accounts in general. He takes this to be an argument for functionalist +accounts, whereas I take it to be an argument against materialist accounts. +4. Actually, this will end up swapping red with yellow rather than blue, as both +of these are at the positive ends of their axes. The details are inessential, however. +For a lucid discussion of the intricacies of human color-space, see Hardin 1988. +5. Indeed, Hardin (1987, p. 138) concedes this point. He says that this sort of +inversion is merely "outlandish" and not "conceptually incoherent." +6. Gunderson (1970) speaks similarly of an "investigational asymmetry" between +first-person and third-person claims. +7. Thompson (1992) points out that in a black-and-white room Mary may still +have color experiences—when she rubs her eyes, for example. To get around this, +perhaps we should stipulate instead that Mary is colorblind since birth. + + 370 + +Notes to pages 108-130 + +8. Churchland (1995, p. 193) and Dennett (1991, p. 281) invoke vitalism in this +context. +9. At the end of the second part of his book, Dennett promises that in the +third part he will show why his functional account can explain everything about +consciousness that needs to be explained, but the arguments are hard to locate. Much +of the discussion consists in observations about cognitive processing with which +someone like me might happily agree. The question is not about whether his account +of processing is correct, but about whether it explains experience. The crucial argument seems to be in the dialogue on pp. 362-68, where he claims (in effect) that +what needs to be explained is how things seem, and that his theory explains how +things seem. But as I argue in Chapter 5, this equivocates between a psychological +and a phenomenal sense of "seem." What the theory might explain is our disposition +to make certain judgments about stimuli, but those judgments were never the puzzling explananda. +There are also some arguments in Chapter 12: (1) an argument against the empirical possibility of inverted qualia (while leaving behavior constant); but empirical impossibility here is compatible with the nonreductive position; (2) an argument against +Jackson's knowledge argument; I discuss this in Chapter 4; (3) a claim that epiphenomenalism about qualia is ridiculous; I discuss this issue in Chapters 4 and 5. Matters +of natural possibility and logical possibility are often run together in Dennett's discussion. For example, Dennett assumes that the "qualophile" will hold that a computational machine will not have experiences, and so devotes a lot of space to arguing +that such machines could be conscious in the way that we are. But this is entirely +compatible with the nonreductive position; I argue for the same claim myself in +later chapters. +10. More recently, Crick and Koch have begun to look beyond the 40-hertz oscillations in their search for a neural basis for consciousness, but similar considerations +apply. The oscillations have the virtue of providing a straightforward example. +11. Quoted in Discover, November 1992, p. 96. Crick (1994, p. 258) also allows +the possibility that science may not explain qualia, although he is more circumspect. +12. Edelman (1989, p. 168) is clear about this. "It is sufficient to provide a model +that explains their discrimination, variation, and consequences. As scientists, we can +have no concern with ontological mysteries concerned with why there is something +and not nothing, or why warm feels warm." He makes an analogy with quantum +field theory, which gives us a basis for discriminating energies and material states, +but which does not tell us why there is matter in the first place. This analogy is very +much compatible with the nonreductive view that I develop in later chapters. +13. Indeed, if consciousness were logically supervenient on the physical, then these +"collapse" interpretations could not get off the ground, as any justification for the +special treatment of consciousness in the laws would disappear. + +Chapter 4 +1. Edelman (1992) similarly subtitles his (purportedly materialist) book How the +Mind Originates in the Brain. +2. On my reading, Searle's view is much more naturally interpreted as property +dualism than as materialism, despite Searle's own view of the matter. The claim that +brain states cause phenomenal states and the use of zombie arguments support this + + Notes to pages 130-137 + +371 + +reading, as does the claim that "what is going on in the brain is neurophysiological +processes and consciousness and nothing more." Searle's argument about intentionality in his Chapter 8 also supports this reading. Searle argues that intentionality is +real (p. 156), but that intentional facts cannot be constituted by neurophysiological +facts (pp. 157-58). The only solution to the puzzle, he argues, is that consciousness +must be partly constitutive of intentionality, as consciousness is the only other thing +in the brain's ontology. This argument seems to presuppose property dualism +about consciousness. +In explaining his ontology in Chapter 5, Searle argues that consciousness is irreducible, but that this has no deep consequences. He says that phenomena such as heat +are reducible only because we redefine them to eliminate the phenomenal aspect (in +the way I discussed in Chapter 2), but that this sort of redefinition is trivially inapplicable to consciousness, which consists entirely in its subjective aspect. This seems +correct. As I put it in Chapter 2, phenomena such as heat are reductively explainable +only modulo conscious experience. But he goes on to say that "this shows that the +irreducibility of consciousness is a trivial consequence of the pragmatics of our +definitional practices" (p. 122). This seems to get things backward. Rather, the +practices are consequences of the irreducibility of consciousness: if we did not factor +out the experience of heat, we could not reduce heat at all! Thus irreducibility is a +source, not a consequence, of our practices. It is hard to see how any of this trivializes +the irreducibility of consciousness. +3. Closely related arguments for why a materialist cannot appeal to a posteriori +necessity have been given by Jackson (1980,1994), Lewis (1994), and White (1986). +4. Jackson (1980) makes a similar point, arguing that even it a posteriori considerations can establish the physicality of the property pain, a problem for materialism +still arises from the property pain-presents. +5. Bealer (1994) also suggests pivoting on the physical term as a strategy here, +although he does not follow the reasoning through to the natural conclusion. +6. Few have explicitly taken this position in print. Most who appeal to a posteriori +necessity in defense of materialism appeal to the Kripkean considerations (e.g., Hill +1991; Lycan 1995; Tye 1995), and almost nobody has explicitly defended the stronger +brand of metaphysical necessity to this end. On a natural reading, however, Bigelow +and Pargetter (1990), Byrne (1993), Levine (1993), and Loar (1990) are implicitly +committed to a position like this. Byrne, Levine, and Terry Horgan have advocated +the position in personal communication. +7. One sometimes hears that mathematical truths are metaphysically necessary +but not conceptually necessary. This depends on subtle issues concerning the analysis +of mathematical concepts and conceptual necessity, but it is nevertheless widely +agreed that mathematical truths are a priori (with the slight caveat mentioned in the +next section of the text). Most crucially, there is not even a conceivable world in +which mathematical truths are false. So these truths do not make the space of possible +worlds any smaller than the set of conceivable worlds. +It might be suggested that moral supervenience is an example of metaphysical +supervenience without an a priori connection, but the case for strong metaphysical +necessity seems even weaker here than in the case of experience. There are options +available here (antirealism, a priori connection) that are much more palatable than +the corresponding alternatives for conscious experience. Further, there does not even +seem to be a conceivable world that is physically and mentally identical to ours but + + 372 + +Notes to pages 138-141 + +morally distinct. So once again, moral supervenience puts no further constraints on +the space of possible worlds. +8. Jackson (1995) gives a simple argument pointing out the oddness of physicalist +positions that do not involve an a priori link from the physical to the psychological +(this might apply equally to the "strong metaphysical necessity" position and the +"cognitive limitation" position): +It is implausible that there are facts about very simple organisms that cannot +be deduced a priori from enough information about their physical nature and +how they interact with their environments, physically described. The physical +story about amoebae and their interactions with the environment is the whole +story about amoebae +But according to materialism we differ from amoebae +essentially only in complexity of ingredients and their arrangement. It is hard +to see how that kind of difference could generate important facts about us that +in principle defy our powers of deduction +Think of the charts in biology +classrooms showing the evolutionary progression from single-celled creatures +on the far left to the higher apes and humans on the far right: where in that +progression can the physicalist plausibly claim that failure of a priori deducibility +of important facts about us emerges? Or, if it comes to that, where in the +development of each and every one of us from a zygote could the materialist +plausibly locate the place in which there emerge important facts about us that +cannot be deduced from the physical story about us? +9. John O'Leary-Hawthorne and Barry Loewer independently suggested the analogy between psychophysical supervenience and complex mathematical truths in +conversation. +10. Note that this reasoning provides a disanalogy with mathematical truths even +for someone who takes the strong position that there are certain mathematical truths +so deep that they are not knowable by any class of beings a priori. +11. In an odd way, this position is quite close to that of reductionists such as +Dennett. After all, both hold that the relevant intuitions arise from cognitive impairment. The main difference is that the reductionist thinks some of us can overcome +this impairment, whereas the current objector holds that none of us can. But for all +this objector knows, enlightenment may already have been achieved by others (perhaps even by Dennett). After all, the impaired would not appreciate a solution by +the enlightened! +12. The most explicit version of the argument from logical possibility is given in +Kirk (1974). It is also present in Campbell (1970), Nagel (1974), Robinson (1976), +and elsewhere. My presentation of the argument differs mostly in the use of the +notion of supervenience to provide a unifying framework, and in consideration of +the role of a posteriori necessity. For a related argument from the possibility of +inverted spectra, see also Seager 1991. +13. There seems to be a reasonable sense in which "Water is wet" and "H2O is +wet" express different facts, as for that matter do "Water is H2O" and"H2O is H2O". +In this sense, we individuate facts by the primary intensions of the terms used to +express them, rather than by secondary intensions. +14. Lockwood (1989, pp. 136-37) makes essentially this point. As he puts it, one's +not knowing that it is the same fact that corresponds to each mode of presentation +must be attributable to one's failure to know some further substantive fact or facts, +under any mode of presentation. A related point is made by Conee (1985a). + + Notes to pages 143-144 + +373 + +15. Loar suggests that phenomenal concepts are recognitional concepts, and argues that it is reasonable to expect a recognitional concept R to "introduce" the +same property as a theoretically specified property P. He gives the example of +someone who is able to recognize certain cacti in the California desert without having +theoretical knowledge about them. But this seems wrong: if the subject cannot know +that R is P a priori, then reference to R and P is fixed in different ways and the +reference-fixing intensions can come apart in certain conceivable situations. Unless +we invoke the additional machinery of strong metaphysical necessity, the difference in primary intensions will correspond to a difference in reference-fixing properties. +At one point Loar suggests that recognitional concepts refer "directly"without the +aid of reference-fixing properties (primary intensions), but this also seems wrong. +The very fact that a concept could refer to something else (a different set of cacti, +say) in a different conceivable situation tells us that a substantial primary intension +is involved. So reference cannot be truly "direct" in the relevant sense. +16. Someone much taken with the problem of indexicality might hold that the +location of the center of a centered world can have ontological significance, or perhaps that there could be a difference in indexical facts between ordinary possible +worlds (if there were such a thing as Nagel's "objective self," perhaps?). These issues, +as with the ontological status of indexicality in general, are quite unclear to me. The +discussion in the text is premised on the opponent's assumption that indexicality +does not lead to an ontological gap, in order to note that even so, the analogy with +the gap in the phenomenal case does not go through. +17. There is one further way in which thoughts about experience can be truly +like indexicals: namely when we pick out an experience as "this experience." When +one refers to one of two qualitatively identical experiences (as in the "Two Tubes" +scenario of Austin 1990), knowing all the "objective" facts might conceivably leave +the matter of which experience is referred to undetermined. (Note that the issue +here concerns reference to tokens rather than types.) In case a materialist might like +to use this case to gain purchase against the knowledge argument, I note that (1) in +this case the epistemically further fact is independent of the phenomenal facts (even +knowing all the phenomenal facts does not tell one which is this experience); (2) it +does not provide a situation in which there is a conceivable uncentered world that +differs from this world, so it cannot be used to build an ontological argument like +the one in the text; (3) at most, the further fact serves to locate what is going on at +the center of a world, telling us which entity is this one in the way that indexical +facts tell us which entity is me. +The real moral here is that in certain cases, one needs to package more information +into the center of a world: not just marking an individual and a time (as "me" and +"here"), but also marking an experience (as "this"). Something similar arguably +applies with orienting demonstratives, such as "left" and "right" (knowing the objective facts about a world might not tell one what which direction is left and which is +right). All of these are associated with epistemic gaps of the relatively unthreatening +indexical variety: in none of these cases are there uncentered worlds in which the +basic facts hold but the further fact does not. +18. In a related objection, Churchland (1985) suggests that Jackson's argument +equivocates on "knows": Mary has complete propositional or sentential knowledge +of the physical facts, but she lacks knowledge by acquaintance with red experiences. +The reply is similar. As long as Mary's knowledge of red experience narrows down + + 374 + +Notes to pages 145-149 + +the way the world is, it is factual knowledge and the argument succeeds (no claim +that factual knowledge must be "sentential" is required). So like Lewis and Nemirow, +Churchland is committed to the implausible claim that Mary's knowledge of red +experience tells her nothing about the way the world is. +19. Lycan (1995) gives nine (!) arguments to the effect that Mary's knowledge +involves new information. +20. There are a number of other replies to the knowledge argument that I have +not discussed, but my reply to these should be predictable. To mention just one: +Dretske (1995) argues that the knowledge Mary lacks is knowledge of her environment. If she knew more about the composition of red things, she would know what +red experiences represent, and so (by Dretske's theory) she would know what red +experiences are like. Oddly, Dretske does not address the obvious objection: even +if Mary knows all about the composition of red objects, she still does not know what +it is like to see red! +21. Thanks to Frank Jackson for discussion on this point. +22. Kripke himself concedes (1972, f.74) that the mere absence of identity may +be a weak conclusion. But he notes that modal arguments may also be mounted +against more general forms of materialism. +23. In a similar way, arguments from disembodiment might establish that mental +properties are not identical to physical properties, in that physical properties can +only be instantiated by physical objects; such an argument is given by Dealer (1994). +But again, this sort of nonidentity is a weak conclusion: it is still compatible with +logical supervenience and so with materialism. Indeed, a similar sort of nonidentity +argument could be mounted for almost any high-level property. +24. In his careful analysis, Boyd (1980, p. 98) notes that the possibility of zombies, +unlike the possibility of disembodiment, entails the falsity of materialism. He therefore provides a separate argument against this possibility, but the argument is sketchy +and unconvincing. Boyd makes an analogy with a computer computing a particular +function, arguing that (1) it may seem to us that one could have all the circuits of +the computer just as they are without that function being computed, but that this is +nevertheless impossible, and (2) the apparent possibility of zombies is analogous to +this. However, the analogy fails. The situation with the computer is analogous to the +(very tenuous) "apparent possibility" that there might be a physical replica of me +that does not learn what I learn, or does not discriminate what I discriminate. Nothing +in this analogy can account for the far more compelling nature of the apparent +possibility of a replica without conscious experience. +25. Kripke's remark that the materialist must show that "these things that we can +imagine are not in fact things that we can imagine" (in the penultimate paragraph +of Kripke 1971) also suggests the weak treatment. Kripke leaves open that the apparent possibility might be explained away in some way quite unlike the standard +water/H2O cases, but says that "it would have to be a deeper and subtler argument +than I can fathom and subtler than has ever appeared in any materialist literature +that I have read." +26. Although the argument is often taken to be an application of Kripke's theory +of rigid designation, a version of it could in principle have been run ten years earlier, +before the theory was developed. One could have asked the original identity theorists +why the physical facts about H2O necessitate that it be water (or watery), whereas +the physical facts about brain states do not seem to necessitate that there is pain. + + Notes to pages 150-168 + +375 + +27. Horgan (1987) speaks of "metaphysical" supervenience in this context, as +does Byrne (1993). If I am right that metaphysical possibility and logical possibility +(of worlds) coincide, however, then logical supervenience follows. +28. For other versions of this point, see Blackburn 1990, Feigl 1958, Lockwood +1989, Maxwell 1978, and Robinson 1982. +29. A view of the world as pure causal flux is put forward by Shoemaker (1980), +who argues that all properties are "powers," with no further properties to underlie +these powers. Shoemaker's argument for this view is largely verificationist, and he +does not directly confront the problems that the view faces. +Shoemaker further argues that as the powers associated with a property are essential to it, the laws of nature must be necessary a posteriori. (Swoyer [1982] argues +similarly, and Kripke [1980] flirts with the conclusion.) The two-dimensional analysis +of a posteriori necessity suggests that there must be something wrong with this +suggestion, or at least that it is more limited than it sounds. At best, it might be that +worlds with different laws are not correctly described as containing electrons (say); +these considerations cannot rule such worlds impossible. Further, it seems implausible +to hold that all the powers associated with electrons are constitutive of electronhood. +More plausibly, for an entity to qualify as an electron only some of these powers +are required, and mildly counternomic worlds containing electrons are possible. +Shoemaker argues that there is no way to distinguish constitutive powers from nonconstitutive powers, but the two-dimensional analysis suggests that this distinction +falls out of the concept of electronhood. +A number of issues should be distinguished. (1) Is reference to physical properties +fixed relationally? (Shoemaker, Chalmers: Yes.) (2) Are physical properties identical +to relational properties (in secondary intension)? (S: Yes; C: Probably, but semantic +intuitions may differ.) (3) Are all the nomic relations of a physical property essential +to it? (S: Yes; C: No.) (4) Are there intrinsic properties underlying these relational +properties? (S: No; C: Yes). +30. This view has been advocated in recent years by Lockwood (1989) and Maxwell +(1978), both of whom put the view forward as an unorthodox version of the identity +theory. The view has been relentlessly pushed on me by Gregg Rosenberg. +31. Although see Lahav and Shanks 1992 for a contrary view. +32. Lewis (1990) reaches a similar conclusion in a quite different way. +33. This is the issue on which I have occasionally taken polls when giving talks +on consciousness, and on other occasions. The results are consistently 2:1 or 3:1 in +favor of there being something further that needs explaining. Of course philosophy +is not best done by democracy, but when we come to one of these issues that argument +cannot resolve, the balance of prior intuition carries a certain weight. +34. Biological materialism. A common view (Hill 1991; Searle 1992) is that consciousness is necessarily biological. On this view, materialism is true, but unconscious +systems with the same functional organization as conscious systems are logically +possible and probably even empirically possible. Once we have admitted the logical +possibility of an unconscious functional isomorph of me, however, we must surely +admit the logical possibility of an unconscious biological isomorph of me, as there +is no more of a conceptual link from neurophysiology to conscious experience than +there is from silicon. This view is therefore probably best seen as a version of property +dualism, with consciousness as a further fact over and above the physical facts. If +not, then at best it must be combined with an appeal to strong metaphysical necessity + + 376 + +Notes to page 168 + +in supporting the link between biochemistry and consciousness, inheriting all the +problems with that view. +(Searle [1992] admits the logical possibility of zombies, and in fact holds that there +is merely a causal connection between the microphysical and conscious experience, +so he is perhaps best seen as a property dualist. Hill [1991] tries to avoid the possibility +of zombies with an appeal to rigid designators, but we have seen that this strategy +does not help.) +35. Physicalist-functionalism. On this popular view (e.g., Shoemaker 1982), the +property of having a conscious experience is a functional property, but that of having +a specific conscious experience (a red sensation, say) is a neurophysiological property. On this view, inverted spectra between functional isomorphs are logically and +perhaps empirically possible, but wholly unconscious functional isomorphs are not. +But again, once we have accepted that an inverted functional isomorph is logically +possible, we must also accept that an inverted physical isomorph is logically possible, +as neurophysiology gives no more of a conceptual connection to a particular experience than does silicon. So once again, it seems that the physical facts do not determine all the facts, and some sort of property dualism follows. Again, physicalism +can be maintained only by embracing the problematic notion of strong metaphysical +necessity. +This view is often put forward as an a posteriori identification of phenomenal +properties with neurophysiological properties. As such, it is vulnerable to the usual +problems with such a posteriori identification (what is the primary intension?) as +well as to the argument above. As White (1986) notes in a critique along these +lines, those who advocate this view would do better to stick with an across-theboard functionalism. +36. Psychofunctionalism. On this view, mental properties are identified with functional properties a posteriori, on the basis of their roles in a mature empirical psychology (see Block 1980). If this view applied to phenomenal properties, phenomenal +notions would have the same secondary intensions as functional notions, despite a +difference in primary intension. The problems with this position are best analyzed +along the lines suggested in section 2; that is, by focusing on primary intensions. If +the primary intension of phenomenal notions is itself functional, then the position +is underwritten by some sort of analytic functionalism after all; but if it is not, then +focusing on the property introduced by this intension will invariably lead us to a +variety of dualism. Either way, this view does no further work in saving materialism. +Advocates of this view have often ignored the role of concepts in fixing reference +via primary intensions. Even given a scientific theory with "belief" as a theoretical +term, there will be a conceptual story to tell about why that sort of state qualifies as +a belief, rather than as a desire or something else entirely. Most likely, this referencefixing intension will itself be functional, picking out something like the state that +plays the most belief-like role within the theory, where "belief-like" is cashed out +according to our prior concept. Whatever the nature of the primary intensions for +phenomenal properties, the problems will arise there. To concentrate on secondary +intensions is just to sweep the problems under the rug. +Another problem with psychofunctionalism: It implies a kind of chauvinism, by +giving an extra weight to human psychology in deciding what counts as a belief, say. +See Shoemaker 1981 for an excellent critique, although see Clark 1986 for a response. +It seems more plausible that for most mental notions, the primary and secondary + + Notes to page 168 + +377 + +intensions coincide. Otherwise, we get into situations where we and our Twin Earth +counterparts mean different things by "belief," despite our prior concepts being +identical. +37. Anomalous monism. On this view, each mental state is token-identical to a +physical state, but there are no strict psychophysical laws. Anomalous monism was +put forward by Davidson (1970) as an account of intentional states rather than +phenomenal states, but it might still be thought relevant for two reasons: first, it +offers an a priori argument for physicalism based simply on the causal interaction +(even a one-way interaction) between physical and mental states, and second, it +denies the psychophysical laws that my view requires. +To see that my position is not threatened by Davidson's arguments, note that +nothing in the arguments counts against the existence of pointwise laws of the form +"If a system is in maximally specific physical state P, it is in (maximally specific) +mental state M." Indeed, Davidson endorses the supervenience of the mental on the +physical, which seems to have the existence of such laws as a consequence, upon a +natural interpretation (see Kim 1985 for discussion). Davidson might be most charitably interpreted not as denying pointwise laws but as denying more interesting typewise +laws connecting mental states to physical states under broad types such as those of +folk psychology. Certainly that is the most that seems to follow from his arguments +from the holism of the mental. If so, natural supervenience is not threatened. It also +follows that the argument for token identity cannot go through. This argument relied +on there being no strict laws to support a causal connection between the physical +and the mental (so that an identity is required instead). But even a strict pointwise +law is sufficient to underwrite the kind of connection I endorse, from physical states +to phenomenal states. So dualism is not threatened either. +38. Representationalism. A recently popular position (e.g., Dretske 1995; Harman +1990; Lycan 19%; Tye 1995) has been that phenomenal properties are just representational properties, so that yellow qualia are just perceptual states that represent yellow +things, or something similar. Of course the interpretation of this suggestion depends +on just what account is given of representational properties in turn. Most often, the +suggestion is combined with a reductive account of representation (usually a functional or teleofunctional account), in which case it becomes a variant of reductive +functionalism and meets the usual problems. A nonreductive account of representation might avoid these problems (though it might have others), but would lead to a +nonreductive account of experience. +The surface plausibility of some representationalist accounts may well arise from +a slide between inflationary and deflationary readings of "representation," where +the second is a purely functional (or teleofunctional) notion, but the first is not. The +link between phenomenology and representation is made plausible on the first reading, but the reduction of representation is made plausible on the second. Alternatively, +strong metaphysical necessity may be invoked to make the connection between +representational states and phenomenal states, with the associated problems. (Among +contemporary representationalists, Dretske [1995] and Harman [1990] appear to +endorse a strongly reductive type-A position, whereas Lycan [19%] and Tye [1995]) +appear to endorse a type-B position that leans on a posteriori necessity.) +Another way to approach representationalism is to note that almost everyone +agrees that not all representational states are phenomenal states (those who disagree +are almost certainly nonreductivists about both), so one can ask: What is it that + + 378 + +Notes to page 168 + +makes some representational states phenomenal states? It is this further criterion +that really does the work in a representationalist theory of consciousness. Often the +criterion will be something along the lines of the requirement that the representational +state be made available to central processes in an appropriate sort of way, in which +case it is made clear that we are dealing with a reductive functionalist account with +the usual problems (why should that make a representational state phenomenal?). +The alternative is to single out the relevant states just as those representational states +that are phenomenal, but then the road leads straight back to property dualism. +39. Consciousness as higher-order thought. The proposal that a conscious state is +one that is an object of a higher-order thought (see e.g., Rosenthal 1996, among +others) can be treated in a similar way. If this is combined with a reductive view of +what it is to have a higher-order thought, this is essentially a reductive functionalist +view with the usual problems. If not, then it will lead to a nonreductive view of +experience (type B or type C), and so is compatible with the property dualism I +suggest, although it may have other problems (as I discuss in Chapter 6). +40. Reductive teleofunctionalism. It is worth mentioning the view of Dretske (1995), +on which a Ideological component is also included in the criteria for having an +experience: To have experiences, not only must a system function in a certain way, +but the relevant processes must have been selected for appropriately in their history. +This position is said to be able to avoid some of the problems of standard functionalism, in that for example it allows for (and explains) the possibility of functionally +identical zombies: these are just systems with the wrong history. But it suffers from +its own versions of the central problems. For example, it seems no less logically +possible that a functionally identical system with the relevant history could lack +consciousness; likewise, knowledge of organization plus history fails to give one +knowledge of experience. One might say that this view "avoids" the problems with +reductive functionalism in the wrong sort of way. Ultimately this view is closer in +flavor to a type-A reductive functionalist view than to a view that takes consciousness seriously. +41. Emergent causation. Many have wanted to reject a reductive account of consciousness while giving it a central causal role. A popular way to do this has been +to argue for emergent causation—the existence of new sorts of causation in physical +systems of a certain complexity. For example, Sperry (1969, 1992) has argued that +consciousness is an emergent property of complex systems that itself plays a causal +role; the British emergentists such as Alexander (1920) held a similar view (see +McLaughlin 1992 for discussion). Similarly, Sellars (1981; see also Meehl and Sellars +(1956) suggested that new laws of physical causation might come into play in certain +systems, such as those made of protoplasm or supporting sentient beings. (He called +this view "physicalisni!," as opposed to "physicah'sm2" on which the basic physical +principles found in inorganic matter apply across the board.) These views should not +be confused with the "innocent" view of emergent causation found in complex +systems theory, on which low-level laws yield qualitatively novel behavior through +interaction effects. On the more radical view, there are new fundamental principles +at play that are not consequences of low-level laws. +There are two problems with the view. First, there is no evidence for such emergent +principles of causation. As far as we can tell, all causation is a consequence of lowlevel physical causation, and "downward causation" never interferes with low-level +affairs. Second and perhaps more important: on a close analysis, the view leaves + + Notes to pages 168-190 + +379 + +consciousness as superfluous as before. To see this, note that nothing in the story +about emergent causation requires us to invoke phenomenal properties anywhere. +The entire causal story can be told in terms of links between configurations of physical +properties. There will still be a possible world that is physically identical but that +lacks consciousness entirely. It follows that at best phenomenal properties correlate +with causally efficacious configurations. If there is a way to see phenomenal properties +as efficacious on this view, the same maneuver will apply to my view. In fact, this +view is best seen as a version of my view, with consciousness supervening on the +physical by a contingent nomic link. It is modified by the addition of new laws of +emergent physical causation, but these simply complicate matters rather than changing anything fundamental. +42. Mysterianism. Those unsympathetic to reductive accounts of consciousness +often hold that consciousness may remain an eternal mystery. Such a view has been +canvased by Nagel (1974) and Jackson (1982) and developed by McGinn (1991). On +this view, consciousness may be as far beyond our understanding as knowledge of +astronomy is beyond sea slugs. +Such a view can be tempting, but it is premature. To say that there is no reductive +explanation of consciousness is not to say that there is no explanation at all. In +particular, an account of the principles in virtue of which consciousness supervenes +naturally on the physical might provide an enlightening theory of consciousness even +on a nonreductive view. +McGinn (1989) argues that there is a necessary connection between brain states +and conscious states (otherwise the emergence of consciousness would be a miracle), +but that we can never know what this connection is. His discussion suggests that he +has logical or metaphysical necessity in mind; but the argument establishes at most +natural necessity. Certainly a contingent nomic connection between consciousness +and the physical is no more miraculous than any contingent law, and indeed such a +connection seems far less mysterious than a logically or metaphysically necessary +connection that is beyond our understanding. And it is not obvious why we could +not use our knowledge of regularities connecting physical processes and experience +to infer such laws. In the next few chapters I will go some way toward characterizing +the relevant laws. In this way, we can see that a nonreductive view of consciousness +need not lead to pessimism. + +Chapter 5 +1. Elitzur credits his discussion to Penrose (1987). +2. I leave aside religious experiences here. Arguably, what truly needs explaining +here is the experience of deep spirituality and awe. +3. I am not sure whether this line is found explicitly in the literature, but there are +related arguments. For example, Foss (1989) responds to Jackson's (1982) knowledge +argument by noting that Mary could know everything that a subject with color vision +would say about various colors, and even everything that a subject might say. But +of course this falls far short of knowing all there is to know. +4. Of course, this would not really help. +5. Dretske (1995) makes a similar sort of argument, arguing that his theory +explains the way things seem and so explains what needs to be explained. Once +again, there is an equivocation between psychological and phenomenal senses of + + 380 + +Notes to pages 197-205 + +"seem." In general, "seeming" is a poor term to use in characterizing the explananda +of a theory of consciousness, precisely because of this ambiguity. It is interesting that +it is usually used only by proponents of reductive accounts. +6. There have, of course, been various attacks on the idea of the "Given" and +on the idea of "sense-data" in the literature. But I do not think that any of these +succeed in overturning the idea that to have an experience provides a source of +justification for a belief about experience. They provide good reasons to reject various +stronger claims, such as the claim that all knowledge is derivative on knowledge of +experience, and the claim that we perceive the world by perceiving sense-data, and +the claim that to have an experience is automatically to bring the experience under +a concept. But I am not making any of these claims. +Sellars (1956) plausibly criticizes the idea that "sensing a sense content s" entails +noninferential knowledge of s. He notes that knowledge is a conceptual state, so this +sort of knowledge is unlikely to be primitive; but experience seems to be more +primitive. Having an experience is arguably a nonconceptual state, and our acquaintance with experience is a nonconceptual relation (although this matter depends on +how one defines what it is to be "conceptual"). The residual question is therefore +that of how a nonconceptual state can provide evidence for a conceptual state. This +is a difficult question, but it is not a question unique to the nonreductionist about +consciousness. It arises even in the case of standard perceptual knowledge of the +world, where even a reductionist must accept that justification for a belief is partly +grounded in a nonconceptual source, unless one is willing to accept alternatives that +seem to face even greater difficulties. I think that an account of such justification +might be given, but that is a lengthy separate project. Here, I simply note that +nonreductionism about consciousness does not raise a special worry in this area. +7. This general line is taken by Hill (1991) in his detailed response to skeptical +arguments concerning experience based on the possibility of "ersatz pain," in particular to the argument of Shoemaker (1975a). Hill makes a number of points that are +congenial to the treatment I give of these issues, although he advocates type-B +biological materialism rather than property dualism. These include a comparison +between skeptical arguments concerning experience and skeptical arguments concerning the external world, and arguments against a "discernibility condition" holding +that one is not justified in believing that P unless in every situation in which one +lacks evidence for P, one would be able to recognize that one lacks evidence for P. +8. This suggestion was made by John O'Leary-Hawthorne in discussion. +9. It might be thought that the opposing line—in which a zombie's belief "I am +conscious" comes out true because his concept picks out a functional property—could +be helpful in handling the property dualist's epistemological problems, as it would +no longer follow that I have beliefs that are justified where a zombie's belief is not. +But whatever line we take here, the zombie will still have some false beh'efs, such +as the belief that he has properties over and above his physical and functional +properties, and the problem of justifying my corresponding beliefs would recur in +this form. +10. E.g., by Bill Lycan in personal communication. One can also retreat to a +concept such as "Experience of the sort typically caused (in most of us) by red +things"—although here one escapes relativism at the cost of the possibility of being +systematically wrong about the category of one's own experiences. +11. This sort of relativism does not occur with external color concepts, such as + + Notes to pages 205-207 + +381 + +redness as a property of objects rather than experiences. To a first approximation, +reference is fixed to red things as things that typically give rise (in most of us) to +the same sort of color experiences as some paradigm examples. This is more "public" +in two ways: because of the reference to public paradigm examples, and because of +the reference to experiences across a community. Thus someone with an inverted +spectrum would use "red things" to refer to the same things as I do, even if his term +"red experiences" picks out something different. +One might wonder about individuals with different boundaries in their color space, +e.g., someone who thinks that carrots look the same color as roses and tomatoes. It +seems most natural to say that her utterance of "Carrots are red" is false, because +of the communal element in the concept "red," but perhaps there is also a less +communal sense in which it can be taken as true (where "red" comes to "red-forme"). Even here, though, there is not much room for relativism, because for any +individual the term will still be tied to external paradigms. Even using this relativistic +sense, anyone's term "red" must pick out a good many red things, and similarly for +other concepts. +One might also remove all dependence on experience from the characterizations +of external color concepts, by characterizing them in terms of judgments instead: so +red things are those that are typically judged as the same color as paradigm examples. +This has the advantage of allowing zombies to speak truly of green objects, as may +be reasonable. After all, it seems that intersubjective similarity in judgments, rather +than similarity in experience, is all that is required to get the reference of color +terms going. +12. The distinction between the qualitative concept and the relational concept of +"red experience" is closely related to Nida-Rumelin's (1995) distinction between the +"phenomenal" and "nonphenomenal" reading of belief ascriptions such as "Marianna believes that the sky appears blue to Peter." Nida-Rumelin's "phenomenal" +reading ascribes a belief involving the relevant qualitative concept of the ascriber; +whereas the nonphenomenal reading ascribes a belief involving a relational concept. +(The relevant relational concept in Nida-Rumelin's examples seems to be something +like the community-based concept mentioned in note 10.) +13. Of course my use of the symbol "fl" for the concept is deliberately reminiscent +of the "E" in Wittgenstein's private language argument. I will not even try to analyze +that argument here; that project would be made especially difficult by the fact that +there is no widely accepted interpretation of just what the argument is. Suffice to +say that every version of the argument that I have seen either rests on very dubious +premises, or applies as strongly to everyday concepts as to private experiential concepts, or both. +14. Indeed, if one does a little introspection, it is notable that there is little one +can even "say to oneself" that distinguishes red and green experiences, again apart +from pointing to relational properties, despite one's awareness of their rich intrinsic +difference. This might be seen as further evidence that the qualities inhere in the +phenomenal realm and are not directly reflected in the psychological. +15. To a certain extent this line of thought mirrors a line in Shoemaker (1975): +that if inverted spectra are possible, neither qualitative states nor qualitative beliefs +can be functionally defined, although Shoemaker puts things in terms of rigid designation with relational fixation of reference, so in effect he is focusing on secondary +intensions here. + + 382 + +Notes to pages 207-233 + +16. This observation parallels Nida-Rumelin's observation (1995) that the distinction between phenomenal and nonphenomenal beliefs is not an ordinary instance of +the de relde dicto distinction. +17. Note that this is not the simple indexical "this," whose primary intension is +the same whether the experience is R or 5, and for which it is an uninformative +triviality that this experience is this sort of experience. Rather, this is the meaty +"this" with a primary intension that picks out 5 experiences in every centered world. +18. Conee (1985b) leans on this sort of constitution relation between qualia and +qualitative beliefs in his response to Shoemaker's (1975a) epistemological argument. + +Chapter 6 +1. Note that in order for these principles to provide psychophysical laws, we must +read second-order judgments such as "I am having a red experience" by the relational +reading discussed in the final section of Chapter 5, along the lines of "I am having +the sort of experience usually caused by red objects." The relational elements of the +"red experience" concept, unlike the intrinsic qualitative elements, will be reflected +in physical processing: the corresponding belief involving the qualitative concept of +"red experience" will not logically supervene on the physical, so the correctness of +such beliefs will not provide a psychophysical law. I do not make too much of this, +as my discussion will focus on first-order judgments, for which these issues do not arise. +2. For a rich analysis of the phenomenology associated with occurrent thought, +see Siewert 1994. +3. Compare also the observation by Nagel (1974) that "structural features of +perception might be more accessible to objective description, even though something +would be left out." +4. This is closely related to Jackendoff's hypothesis of computational sufficiency: +"Every phenomenological distinction is caused by/supported by/projected from a +corresponding computational distinction" (Jackendoff 1987, p. 24). +5. For related discussions of blindsight, see Tye 1993, Block 1995, and especially +Dennett 1991. +6. For a discussion of the dangers of conflating conscious experience and consciousness of an experience, and also for an excellent critique of higher-order thought +approaches in general, see Siewert 1994. For a parallel sort of critique from a reductive standpoint, see also Dretske 1995. +7. The distinction between first-order and second-order accounts reflects Nelkin's +distinction between the two functional concepts of consciousness, Cl and C2 (Nelkin 1989). +8. A proposal like this is canvassed by Carruthers (1992), who argues that availability for reflexive thinking is naturally necessary and sufficient for a qualitative feel. +(Carruthers seems to have a stronger variety of availability in mind, however, insofar +as Armstrong's inattentive truck-driver fails to meet his criterion.) Insofar as he +explicitly claims that the connection holds with only natural necessity, the proposal +seems nonreductive, although Carruthers also characterizes the view as physicalist. +Alvin Goldman has suggested a similar account in conversation, intended as a characterization of those states that are conscious in familiar systems, rather than as a reductive proposal. +9. The distinction between first-order registrations and first-order judgments parallels Dretske's (1995) distinction between the phenomenal and doxastic varieties of + + Notes to page 233 + +383 + +cognitive states. The latter corresponds to the way the system takes things to be, +and the former corresponds to the way things are represented to the system. Of +course there is a significant difference between Dretske's framework and mine, in +that Dretske is essentially a reductive functionalist (actually a reductive teleofunctionalist), identifying experiences with (teleo)functionally defined first-order registrations. I resist the identification for the usual reasons, but it remains plausible that +experiences correspond to first-order registrations. My framework simply has an extra +distinction, recognizing three different sorts of states—judgments, registrations, and +phenomenal states, with registrations and phenomenal states correlated but distinct—where Dretske's recognizes two: judgments and phenomenal states, without +even a conceptual distinction between phenomenal states and the corresponding +registrations. +10. There are an enormous number of interesting questions about the sort of +representational content possessed by the first-order registrations that constitute +awareness, and about the sort of content that is possessed in parallel by the corresponding experiences. Issues about content are not central to my discussion, so I raise +them only briefly here, but they are among the deepest and most subtle questions +about experience and deserve a much more detailed treatment elsewhere. +A central feature of the contents of awareness and of experience is that the content +here is generally nonconceptual—it is content that does not require an agent to possess +the concepts that might be involved in characterizing that content. For example, +it is plausible that a simple system—perhaps a dog or a mouse—might have finegrained color experiences, with a correspondingly fine-grained representation of color +distinctions in the cognitive system, while having only the simplest system of color +concepts. In humans, similarly, it is common for states of consciousness and awareness +in musical perception to have contents that go far beyond the musical concepts in +the subject's repertoire. +(For discussion of nonconceptual content, see Crane 1992, Cussins 1990, Evans +1982, Peacocke 1992. There seems to be a consensus in the literature that the contents +of experience are nonconceptual. An exception is McDowell [1994], who argues from +our ability to reidentify experiences under concepts such as "that shade" to the +conclusion that all experiential content is conceptual. It is not clear that such an +ability is a requirement for the possession of experience: it is plausible, for example, +that certain subtle aspects of musical experience in some subjects [e.g., subtle changes +of key] might resist conceptualization and reidentification altogether. Experiences +in animals provide another example. McDowell appears happy to embrace the conclusion that animals do not have experiences, but one might find the modus tollens at +least as compelling as the modus ponens. Even if one were to accept McDowell's +point, I think that something like the relevant distinction might be rehabilitated in +the guise of two grades of conceptual content.) +Of course, there may be a causal relationship between concepts and consciousness; +it is not uncommon for conceptual change to significantly affect the character of +experience. But such conceptual resources do not seem to be a requirement for +conscious experience. The same goes for awareness, insofar as it is parallel to consciousness. The contents represented by the first-order registrations that correspond +to conscious experiences, in visual perception for example, do not require corresponding rich conceptual resources. In this way, the contents of experience and of awareness +are in general more primitive than that of judgments, whose contents are most +naturally seen as conceptual. + + 384 + +Notes to page 233 + +One of the most interesting questions about content is whether experience has +representational content intrinsically, or whether its content somehow derives from +that of an underlying cognitive state. The latter position can be tempting, but it does +not seem quite right: for example, it seems that my visual experience right now +represents the world as having a large square object in front of me, and does so +simply by virtue of being the experience it is. Even a hypothetical disembodied mind +that was having a similar experience would have a similar sort of representational +content. Siewert (1994) makes a compelling case that experience by its nature is +informative about the state of the world: a visual experience, for example, is something that is assessable for accuracy (it can represent the world correctly and incorrectly), and indeed is assessable in virtue of its very nature as a visual experience. +So it may be reasonable to say that experience is intrinsically laden with representational content. +One might be tempted to take the reverse line, and hold that the only true content +is present in experience, and that the content of an underlying first-order registration +is itself dependent on the content of the associated experience. There might be +something to this, but it is not entirely satisfactory either; there is a sense in which +one wants to say that even a zombie's first-order registrations represent the world +as being a certain way. We certainly have contentful states that are not associated +with experiences, and it is hard to see that all of our contents are somehow dependent +on the contents of experience. An intermediate line that one might take is that (1) +in a certain sense the original sort of content was that found within experience, but +(2) we evolved a framework for attributing content to cognitive states based in part +on coherence with the content of associated experiences, and (3) once in place, this +framework became autonomous so that we can speak of the content of cognitive +states even in the absence of experience. This would mean that experiences and +associated registrations could both have content autonomously, without there being +a strange, coincidental overdetermination whereby the same content is constituted +twice over. The issues here are quite subtle and would likely repay a detailed analysis. +Another interesting issue is whether the relevant sort of content is "wide" (dependent on objects in the environment) or "narrow" (dependent only on internal processes). Insofar as experience is intrinsically laden with content, and insofar as experience is supervenient on a subject's organization, then the relevant sort of content +here must be narrow. (Experiences might still have wide content, but this could not +be content fixed by the experience alone.) Sometimes it has been thought that the +only true representational content is wide content, but I think there is a natural way +to understand narrow representational content (see Chalmers 1994c). Such an account +could be elaborated to give an account of the narrow, nonconceptual content of +experience and of awareness, as a kind of content that puts constraints on the centered worlds that are candidates to be a subject's actual world. +A further question is whether all experiences have representational content. It is +plausible that many or most do; certainly most perceptual experiences seem to be +intrinsically informative about the world. There are some tricky cases, however: What +about orgasms, or nausea, or certain experiences of emotion (see Block 1995 and +Tye 1995)? But even in these cases one might find some representational content, +as the experiences often carry content concerning location (in here, down there) or +quality (good, bad). It is not clear that there could be experiences that are devoid +of representational content altogether; on the other hand, it is not obvious that there +could not be. + + Notes to pages 233-236 + +385 + +Some philosophers have put forward the proposal that phenomenal properties are +just representational properties, so that experiences are exhausted by their representational content (e.g., Dretske 1995; Harman 1990; Lycan 1996; Tye 1992). Most +often this is put forward alongside a reductive view of representational content, so +that this view comes down to a version of reductive functionalism, and is implausible +for the usual reasons. Another version of the proposal might set it alongside a +nonreductive view of representational content, perhaps one in which the only true +representation is in experience. This would be more compatible with taking consciousness seriously, but it would still have difficulties. In particular, it would seem that +representational content might stay constant between functional isomorphs with +spectrum inversion, in which case phenomenology outstrips representational content. +The cases in the previous paragraph also tend to suggest that even if all experiences +have representational content, they also have features that outstrip their representational content. So it is not clear that even the nonreductive version of this proposal +will be successful. +11. In personal communication and forthcoming work. +12. Occasionally, principles such as those I have mentioned have been formulated +explicitly as part of the methodology of empirical work on the mind. Not surprisingly, +this has happened most often in the area of mainstream psychology that is most +concerned with conscious experience, namely psychophysics. This field is often construed as relating the properties of our sensations to properties of associated physical +stimuli. Typical results here include the Weber-Fechner law and Stevens's power law +(Stevens 1975), which give two ways of relating the intensity of a stimulus to the +intensity of a corresponding sensation. Although it is sometimes held that the primary +explananda in psychophysics are third-person data such as subjective reports, it seems +undeniable that features of first-person experience—such as the experience of certain +optical illusions—are among the central phenomena that the field seeks to account for. +(Horst [1995] makes a strong case that the primary data in the field are often firstperson experiences of various phenomena such as illusions. At conferences, for +example, researchers place a premium on being able to "see" various effects for +themselves. One might also argue that the disputes between Fechner's and Stevens's +approaches to the measurement of sensation [see Stevens 1975] only make sense if one +assumes that there is an aim to measure a common target, phenomenal experience; +otherwise we simply have noncompeting measurements of different functional +phenomena.) +Within psychophysics, there has been occasional discussion of the means by +which empirical observations can help in the explanation of subjective sensations. +Some researchers have been led to formalize explicit principles on which this work +relies—known variously as "psychophysical linking hypotheses" (Brindley 1960) or +"general Unking propositions" (Teller 1984). The "Axioms of Psychophysical Correspondence" put forward by Muller (1896; quoted in Boring 1942, p. 89) are a +good example: +1. The ground of every state of consciousness is a material process, a psychophysical process so-called, to whose occurrence the presence of the conscious state +is joined. +2. To an equality, similarity, or difference in the constitution of sensations... +there corresponds an equality, similarity, and difference in the constitution of +the psychophysical process, and conversely. Moreover, to a greater or lesser + + 386 + +Notes to pages 236-252 + +similarity of sensations, there also corresponds respectively a greater or lesser +similarity of the psychophysical process, and conversely. +3. If the changes through which a sensation passes have the same direction, or if +the differences which exist between series of sensations are of like direction, +then the changes through which the psychophysical process passes, or the differences of the given psychophysical process, have like direction. Moreover, if a +sensation is variable in n directions, then the psychophysical process lying at +the basis of it must also be variable in n directions, and conversely. +It is clear that these principles are closely related to the principle of structural +coherence. Allowing for certain differences in language, we can see all the propositions along the lines of those above are straightforward consequences of the coherence principle; and together, they constitute a good deal of its force. So once again, +we can see that the principle of structural coherence and its variants are playing +a central role in allowing empirical research to yield explanatory accounts of various +features of experience. +Not surprisingly, the status of such principles has met with debate within psychophysics that parallels the sorts of debate found in the philosophy of mind (see e.g., +Brindley 1960; Marks 1978; D. Teller 1984, 1990). Some have regarded them as +empirical hypotheses, but it does not appear that they are derived or falsified +through empirical test, at least of the third-person variety. Others, especially those +of an operationalist bent, have regarded them as definitional claims; this corresponds to a reductive functionalist position in philosophy. Often they have been +taken simply as background assumptions, or premises, concerning the nature of +the psychophysical connection. In any case, the science has managed to proceed +quite nicely without any real resolution of these questions. For explanatory purposes, the shape of the bridge is more important than its metaphysical status. +In general, "philosophical" issues concerning the relationship between physical +processes and experience are bubbling just beneath the surface in many theoretical +discussions in psychophysics. As far as I can tell, this has not met with much +discussion in the philosophical literature (although see Savage 1970 for a philosophical critique of methodology in the measurement of sensation). It would likely make +a worthwhile object of extended study. + +Chapter 7 +1. Lycan 1987, for example. +2. Churchland and Churchland (1981) have objected to the "Chinese nation" +arguments on the grounds that such a system would need to handle around 1030,000,000 +inputs to the retina, and an even vaster number of internal states of the brain. The +population simulation, requiring one person per input and one person per state, +would therefore require vastly more people than a population could provide. +This objection overlooks the fact that both inputs and internal states are combinatorially structured. Instead of representing each input pattern (over 108 cells) with a +single person, thus requiring 2108 people, we only need 108 people to represent the +input as a structured pattern. The same goes for internal states. We therefore need +no more people than there are cells in the brain. +3. Bogen (1981) and Lycan (1987) make the suggestion that such "accidental" +situations would not have qualia, as qualia require teleology. This would have the + + Notes to pages 252-265 + +387 + +odd consequence of making the presence or absence of qualia dependent on the +history of a system. Better, I think, to concede that such a system would have qualia +while pointing out just how unlikely it is that such a system could arise by chance. +4. I discuss this further in Chalmers 1994a. +5. This figure comes from noting that there are 10109 possible choices for the +consequent of each conditional, representing the global state into which the system +transits. The chance that a given global state will transit into the correct following +state is therefore 1 in 10109. In fact it will be lower, as any given global state will be +realizable by many different "maximal" states of the physical system, each of which +is required to transit appropriately. There are 10109 such conditionals to be satisfied, +so the figure above falls out. +6. For some related fables, see also Harrison 1981a, 1981b. +7. Perhaps some element of this situation could be explained away via the constitution of belief by experience of the sort discussed in section 7 of Chapter 5: perhaps +Joe's concept "red experience" now refers to pink experiences, for example, so he +is not entirely wrong. This strategy would certainly not help with the errors in his +judgments about distinctions, however. +8. Cuda (1985) claims that a description of systems with such mistaken beliefs is +senseless. He offers no argument for this apart from the claim that if the description +made sense, it would make sense to think that we are mistaken in such a way, which +(he says) it clearly does not. But this seems fallacious. It makes sense to suppose +that I could be mistaken in this way, in that the hypothesis is coherent; it is just that +my epistemic situation shows me that the hypothesis is not true in my own case, +because I have direct experience of bright red qualia and the like. +9. This is not to say that there are no Sorites arguments to be found in the +ballpark; for an example, see Tienson 1987. +10. This position is mostly closely associated with Shoemaker (1982), but has also +been advocated by Horgan (1984a), Putnam (1981), and various others. +11. It may even be that such cases exist in the actual world. In a stimulating paper, +Nida-Rumelin (1996) notes that research in color vision leads us to expect that there +should be cases of "pseudonormal" color vision, in which (1) R-cones in the retina +have the response pattern usually associated with G-cones, and (2) G-cones have +the response pattern usually associated with R-cones. Taken separately, (1) and +(2) are the standard causes of red-green color blindness. In theory, the genetic +abnormalities responsible for (1) and (2) can occur together, giving a subject who +will be behaviorally very similar to a normal subject, but who may well have color +experiences that are inverted with respect to the rest of the population. +12. Putnam (1981) and Shoemaker (1982) use this example to argue against functionalist accounts of qualia, but at best their arguments count against a "coarsegrained" invariance principle, on which for example the same sort of experience is +held to always arise from states that are triggered by blue things and lead to "blue" +reports. The fine-grained principle is unthreatened. (Levine [1988] makes a related +point.) +There is a variant of this scenario in which the rewired subjects undergo a process +of adaptation, learning, and finally amnesia (forgetting that things ever looked different), ending up behaviorally identical to their original state. There is little reason +to believe that they will be organizationally identical, however, especially given that +the rewiring is still reflected in the state of their brain. If by some special process +the organization ended up just as it started, it would not seem implausible that the + + 388 + +Notes to pages 266-303 + +experiences should also revert to their original state. (Cole [1990] and Rey [1992] +advocate versions of a reversion hypothesis here.) +13. A related argument is given by Seager (1991, pp. 39-41), who describes a case +in which retinal cells are "tuned" to a higher range on the optical spectrum. This +argument can be treated in the same way as Block's. +14. Block responds to a related objection by noting that we can move the "lenses" +inward in the system, rewiring things at the optic nerve or in the visual cortex, for +instance. As before, however, this does not provide any cases of organizational +isomorphs with different experiences. Indeed, Block's description of such cases appears straightforwardly compatible with the view that qualia are dependent on the +organization of "central" systems. We are asked to believe that experiences are the +same in certain cases precisely because central processing is unaffected; we are +supposed to believe that experiences differ in cases where central processing differs. +Such arguments cannot refute the invariance principle. +15. The argument in this section is distantly inspired by Dennett's story "Where +Am I?" (1978d). A situation bearing a certain resemblance to the one I describe +below is considered by Shoemaker (1982). A more closely related discussion can be +found in Seager (1991, p. 43), although Seager does not advocate the invariance +principle. As this book was going to press, I discovered a stimulating recent article +by Arnold Zuboff (1994) that makes what is essentially the dancing qualia argument +to support a version of reductive functionalism, by arguing that dancing qualia are +impossible a priori. +16. White (1986) makes this sort of point, suggesting that if nonfunctional physical +differences are relevant to qualia, then even tiny differences in DNA might affect qualia. +17. Shoemaker (1982) gives a complex criterion for how specific a physiological +property needs to be to fix qualia, or to "realize a quale," as he puts it. However, +it seems to me that if my discussion here has been correct, his criterion will in fact +pick out a fine-grained functional property. +18. This suggestion was made by Terry Horgan in conversation. + +Chapter 8 +1. Others who have suggested links between consciousness and information include +Bohm (1980), Sayre (1976), and Velmans (1991), though the details of their proposals +are quite different from mine. Sayre's idea of a "neutral monism" of information is +quite suggestive, however (thanks to Steve Horst for pointing this out to me). Something quite like the double-aspect principle is discussed in Lockwood 1989, chap. 11, +although he does not put it in terms of information. +2. An unpublished paper of mine (Chalmers 1990) focuses on this strategy in +understanding the relation between consciousness and judgments about consciousness, and uses it to come up with a basic "theory" of consciousness (involving pattern +and information) that is a predecessor of some of the ideas in this chapter. In this +paper I call the requirement of explanatory coherence the "Coherence Test" that +any theory of consciousness must pass. +3. But for the claim that thermostats have beliefs and desires, see McCarthy 1979. +4. Wheeler's approach focuses on measurement outcomes, or "answers to yesno questions," as the basis for everything, and as such may be closer to a form of +idealism than the view I am putting forward here. +5. See also the interesting account of Fredkin's ideas in Wright (1988) for more +on the underlying metaphysics. + + Notes to pages 306-331 + +389 + +6. There are stimulating discussions of these problems for the Russellian view in +Foster (1991, pp. 119-30) and Lockwood (1992). +7. Lockwood (1992) suggests that a Russellian view can invoke brute laws for this +sort of purpose. He does not address the objection that introducing further laws in +this capacity seems to compromise the original attractions of the Russellian view. +They raise the problems of epiphenomenalism that the Russellian view held promise +of avoiding, for example, and they also require a considerable expansion in the +ontology over and above the intrinsic properties that are required to ground physics. (I should note that Lockwood does not rely on these laws to solve the grain +problem; his main idea about solving the problem is an intriguing separate suggestion +involving quantum mechanics). + +Chapter 9 +1. The material in this section is largely drawn from Chalmers (1994a). +2. Putnam (1988, pp. 120-25) gives a separate argument for the conclusion that +every ordinary open system implements every finite-state automaton. I analyze this +argument in detail in Chalmers 1995a. Upon analysis, the argument appears to gain +its force by allowing the physical state transition conditionals in the definition of implementation to lack any strong modal force. +3. I pursue this way of understanding the explanatory role of computation in +cognitive science in Chalmers (1994b). +4. Related points are made by Korb (1991) and Newton (1989), both of whom +suggest that the Chinese room may provide a good argument against machine consciousness if not against machine intentionality. +5. Hofstadter (1981) outlines a similar spectrum of cases intermediate between +a brain and the Chinese room. +6. The idea that the homunculus in the Chinese room is analogous to a demon +running around inside the skull is suggested by Haugeland (1980). +7. It is notable that although Dreyfus (1972) entitled his book making this sort +of objection What Computers Can't Do, he later conceded that the right sort of +computational system (such as a connectionist system) would escape these objections. +In effect, "what computers can do" is identified with what a very narrow class of +computational systems can do. +8. This straightforward counter to Godelian arguments was first made in print +by Putnam (1960), I believe, and as far as I can tell it has never been overturned, +despite the best efforts of Lucas and Penrose. Penrose (1994, sec. 3.3) argues that +he must be able to determine the consistency of the formal system that captures his +own reasoning, as he could surely determine the truth of the axioms and the validity +of the inference rules. This seems to depend on the assumption that the computational +system is an axiom-plus-rules system in the first place, which it need not be in the +general case (witness the neural simulation of the brain). Even in the axiom-plusrules case, it is not clear to me that we would be able to determine the validity of +every rule that our system might use, especially those applying to the outer limits of +ordinal counting in iterated Godelization, which is where the Godelian arguments +in the human case will really have their force. +9. Probably it is a good idea to do this, just in case a specific pattern of roundoffs at the 10-10 level produces a biased distribution of behavior. To be safe, given +that there is noise at the 10-10 level, we might approximate the system to the 10-20 +level, approximating the distribution of noise to the 10-20 level, too. + + 390 + +Notes to pages 332-357 + +10. Sometimes—usually only in the philosophy of mind—terms such as "computation" are used to refer only to the class of symbolic computations, or computations +over representations (that is, systems in which the basic syntactic objects are also +the basic semantic objects). Of course little rests on this terminological issue: what +counts from the point of view of artificial intelligence is that there be some sort of +formal system such that implementation suffices for mentality, whether or not it +counts as a "computation" by this criterion. But it should be noted in any case that +to use the term in this way is to lose touch with its origins in the theory of computation. Even most Turing machines will not count as "computational" in this sense, as +only a few of these can be interpreted as performing computations over conceptual +representations. For similar reasons, to limit the class of "computations" in this way +is to lose hold of the (Church-Turing) universality of computation, which provides +perhaps the best reason for believing in the (functional) AI thesis to begin with. + +Chapter 10 +1. At least for a spin particle such as an electron. I leave aside cases in which +spin has further basic values. +2. I simplify here, as elsewhere. No measurement is perfectly precise, so a state +with a truly definite position never emerges. Instead, the wave function will collapse +into a state in which all the amplitude is concentrated in a very narrow range of +locations. It is easier to speak as if collapsed positions are truly definite, however. +3. A probability density, in the continuous case. +4. Albert (1992) suggests that "consciousness" is as vague as "measurement" and +"macroscopic"; but it seems to me that this criterion is attractive partly because there +is plausibly a fact of the matter about whether a system is conscious. +5. I am indebted to Albert and Loewer (1990) and Albert (1992) in my discussion +of the GRW interpretation. +6. Note that this is the only point at which Bell's theorem and the EinsteinPodolsky-Rosen (EPR) results come up in this chapter. Sometimes these results are +taken to be the main source of the philosophical problems with quantum mechanics, +but I think the problems arise prior to EPR considerations. Even without EPR, the +difficult choice between collapse, hidden variables, and Everett would come up. EPR +simply adds to the difficulties of hidden-variables theories, by showing that they (like +collapse) must be nonlocal; and arguably, it increases the attractiveness of the Everett +interpretation, which is the only local interpretation compatible with the result. +7. The one-big-world view appears to be the most common understanding of the +Everett interpretation among physicists (especially among quantum cosmologists, +who use this framework all the time). The "splitting-worlds" understanding is largely +an artifact of popularizations. Sometimes even proponents of the one-big-world view +talk of "splitting," but this is just a vivid way of talking about the fact that a wave +function evolves into a superposition. There is no special process of splitting of +worlds; at most, there is a sort of local split of the wave function. In any case I think +that talk of "splitting" is best avoided, as it inevitably promotes confusion. +8. This objection has been made by Bell (1981), Bohm and Hiley (1993), and +Hodgson (1988), among many others. +9. The most sensible strategy might be to make my bet according to a quantum +device that produces a "no" answer with probability 0.999, and "yes" with probability +0.001. That way, if the Everett view is false I will almost certainly be right, and if it +is true, at least one of my descendant minds will survive. + + Bibliography +Ackerman, D. 1990. A Natural History of the Senses. New York: Random House. +Adams, R. M. 1974. Theories of actuality. Nous 8:211-31. +Akins, K. 1993. What is it like to be boring and myopic? In B. Dahlbom, ed., Dennett +and His Critics. Oxford: Blackwell. +Albert, D. 1992. Quantum Mechanics and Experience. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard +University Press. +Albert, D., and B. Loewer. 1988. Interpreting the many-worlds interpretation. Synthese 77:195-213. +. 1989. Two no-collapse interpretations of quantum mechanics. Nous 23: +169-86. +. 1990. Wanted dead or alive: Two attempts to solve Schrodinger's paradox. +PSA 1990, vol. 1, pp. 277-85. +Alexander, S. 1920. Space, Time, and Deity. London: Macmillan. +Armstrong, D. M. 1968. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. London: Routledge and +Kegan Paul. +. 1973. Belief, Truth, and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +. 1981 .What is consciousness? In The Nature of Mind. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell +University Press. +. 1982. Metaphysics and supervenience. Critica 42:3-17. +. 1983. What Is a Law of Nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +. 1990. A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +Austin, D. F. 1990. What's the Meaning of "This"? Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. +Baars, B. J. 1988. A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge +University Press. +Bacon, J. 1986. Supervenience, necessary coextension, and reducibility. Philosophical +Studies 49:163-76. +Barwise, J., and J. Perry. 1983. Situations and Attitudes. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +Bateson, G. 1972. Steps to an Ecology of Mind. San Francisco: Chandler. +Bealer, G. 1994. Mental properties. Journal of Philosophy 91:185-208. +Bell, J. S. 1964. On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox. Physics 1:195-200. [Reprinted in Bell 1987b] +. 1976. The measurement theory of Everett and de Broglie's pilot wave. In +M. Flato, ed., Quantum Mechanics, Determinism, Causality, and Particles. +Dordrecht: Reidel. [Reprinted in Bell 1987b] + + 392 + +Bibliography + +. 1981. Quantum mechanics for cosmologists. In C. Isham, R. Penrose, and +D. Sciama, eds., Quantum Gravity. Vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press. +[Reprinted in Bell 1987b] +. 1987a. Are there quantum jumps? In Schrodinger: Centenary of a Polymath. +Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +. 1987b. Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +Bigelow, J., and R. Pargetter. 1990. Acquaintance with qualia. Theoria 56:129-47. +Bisiach, E. 1988. The (haunted) brain and consciousness. In A. Marcel and E. Bisiach, +eds., Consciousness in Contemporary Science. Oxford: Oxford University +Press. +Blackburn, S. 1971. Moral realism. In J. Casey, ed., Morality and Moral Reasoning. +London: Methuen. +. 1985. Supervenience revisited. In I. Hacking, ed., Exercises in Analysis: Essays +by Students of Casimir Lewy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +. 1990. Filling in space. Analysis 50:62-65. +Block, N. 1978. Troubles with functionalism. In C. W. Savage, ed., Perception and +Cognition: Issues in the Foundation of Psychology. Minneapolis: University +of Minnesota Press. [Reprinted in N. Block, ed., Readings in the Philosophy +of Psychology. Vol. 1. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1980] +. 1980. What is functionalism? In N. Block, ed., Readings in the Philosophy +of Psychology. Vol. 1. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. +. 1981. Psychologism and behaviorism. Philosophical Review 90:5-43. +. 1990. Inverted earth. Philosophical Perspectives 4:53-79. +. 1995. On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and +Brain Sciences 18:227-47. +Boden, M. 1988. Escaping from the Chinese Room. In Computer Models of Mind. +Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +Bogen, J. 1981. Agony in the schools. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11:1-21. +Bohm, D. 1952. A suggested interpretation of quantum mechanics in terms of "hidden variables," pts. 1 and 2. Physical Review 85:166-93. +. 1980. Wholeness and the Implicate Order. London: Routledge. +Bohm, D., and B. Hiley. 1993. The Undivided Universe: An Ontological Interpretation +of Quantum Theory. London: Routledge. +Boring, E. G. 1942. Sensation and Perception in the History of Experimental Psychology. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. +Boyd, R. N. 1980. Materialism without reductionism: What physicalism does not +entail. In N. Block, ed., Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology. Vol. 1. +Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. +. 1988. How to be a moral realist. In G. Sayre-McCord, ed., Essays on Moral +Realism. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. +Brindley, G. S. 1960. Physiology of the Retina and Visual Pathway. London: Edward Arnold. +Brink, D. 1989. Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge +University Press. +Broad, C. D. 1925. Mind and Its Place in Nature. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. +Brooks, D. H. M. 1994. How to perform a reduction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54:803-14. + + Bibliography + +393 + +Byrne, A. 1993. The emergent mind. Ph.D. diss., Princeton University. +Campbell, K. K. 1970. Body and Mind. New York: Doubleday. +Carroll, J. W. 1990. The Humean tradition. Philosophical Review 99:185-219. +. 1994. Laws of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +Carruthers, P. 1992. Consciousness and concepts. Proceedings of the Aristotelian +Society, suppl., 66:41-59. +Chalmers, D. J. 1990. Consciousness and cognition. Technical Report 38, Center for +Research on Concepts and Cognition, Indiana University. +. 1994a. On implementing a computation. Minds and Machines 4:391-402. +. 1994b. A computational foundation for the study of cognition. PNP Technical +Report 94-03, Washington University. +. 1994c. The components of content. PNP Technical Report 94-04, Washington +University, [http://ling.vcsc.edu/~chalmers/papers/content.html] +. 1995a. Does a rock implement every finite state automation? Synthese. +. 1995b. Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness +Studies 2:200-219. [Also in S. Hameroff, A. Kaszniak, and A. Scott, eds., +Toward a Science of Consciousness. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996] +. 1995c. Minds, machines, and mathematics. PSYCHE 2:1. +-. 1995d. The puzzle of conscious experience. Scientific American 273:80-86. +Cheney, D. L., and R. M. Seyfarth. 1990. How Monkeys See the World. Chicago: +University of Chicago Press. +Chisholm, R. 1957. Perceiving. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. +Churchland, P. M. 1985. Reduction, qualia and the direct introspection of brain states. +Journal of Philosophy 82:8-28. +. 1995. The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey +into the Brain. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +Churchland, P. M., and P. S. Churchland. 1981. Functionalism, qualia and intentionality. Philosophical Topics 12:121-32. +Churchland, P. S. 1986. Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the MindBrain. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +. 1988. The significance of neuroscience for philosophy. Trends in the Neurosciences 11:304-7. +Clark, A. 1986. Psychofunctionalism and chauvinism. Philosophy of Science 53: +535-59. +. 1993. Sensory Qualities. Oxford: Oxford University Press. +Cole, D. 1990. Functionalism and inverted spectra. Synthese 82:207-22. +Conee, E. 1985a. Physicalism and phenomenal properties. Philosophical Quarterly +35:296-302. +. 1985b. The possibility of absent qualia. Philosophical Review 94:345-66. +Cowey, A., and P. Stoerig. 1992. Reflections on blindsight. In D. Milner and M. +Rugg, eds., The Neuropsychology of Consciousness. London: Academic Press. +Crane, T. 1992. The nonconceptual content of experience. In T. Crane, ed., The +Contents of Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +Crick, F. H. C. 1994. The Astonishing Hypothesis: The Scientific Search for the Soul. +New York: Scribner. +Crick, F. H. C., and C. Koch. 1990. Towards a neurobiological theory of consciousness. +Seminars in the Neurosciences 2:263-75. +Cuda, T. 1985. Against neural chauvinism. Philosophical Studies 48:111-27. + + 394 + +Bibliography + +Cussins, A. 1990. The connectionist construction of concepts. In M. Boden, ed., The +Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. +Daneri, A., A. Loinger, and G. M. Prosperi. 1962. Quantum theory of measurement +and ergodicity conditions. Nuclear Physics 33:297-319. [Reprinted in Wheeler +and Zurek 1983] +Davidson, D. 1970. Mental events. In L. Foster and J. Swanson, eds., Experience and +Theory. London: Duckworth. +Davies, M. K., and I. L. Humberstone. 1980. Two notions of necessity. Philosophical +Studies 38:1-30. +Dennett, D. C. 1969. Content and Consciousness. London: Routledge and Kegan +Paul. +. 1978a. Brainstorms. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +. 1978b. Are dreams experiences? In Dennett 1978a. +. 1978c. Toward a cognitive theory of consciousness. In Dennett 1978a. +. 1978d. Where am I? In Dennett 1978a. +. 1979. On the absence of phenomenology. In D. Gustafson and B. Tapscott, +eds., Body, Mind, and Method. Dordrecht: Kluwer. +. 1987. The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +. 1988. Quining qualia. In A. Marcel and E. Bisiach, eds., Consciousness in +Contemporary Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press. +. 1991. Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown. +. 1993a. Back from the drawing board. In B. Dahlbom, ed., Dennett and His +Critics. Oxford: BlackweU. +. 1993b. The message is: There is no medium. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53:919-31. +Descartes, R. 1984. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University +Press. +DeWitt, B. S. 1970. Quantum mechanics and reality. Physics Today 23:30-35. [Reprinted in DeWitt and Graham 1973] +. 1971. The many-universes interpretation of quantum mechanics. In B. d'Espagnat, ed., Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. New York: Academic Press. +[Reprinted in DeWitt and Graham 1973] +DeWitt, B. S., and N. Graham, eds., 1973. The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton: Princeton University Press. +Dretske, F. I. 1977. Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science 44:248-68. +. 1981. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +. 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +Dreyfus, H. 1972. What Computers Can't Do. New York: Harper & Row. +Eccles, J. C. 1986. Do mental events cause neural events analogously to the probability fields of quantum mechanics? Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B227:411-28. +Edelman, G. 1989. The Remembered Present: A Biological Theory of Consciousness. +New York: Basic Books. +. 1992. Bright Air, Brilliant Fire. New York: Basic Books. +Elitzur, A. 1989. Consciousness and the incompleteness of the physical explanation +of behavior. Journal of Mind and Behavior 10:1-20. +Evans, G. 1979. Reference and contingency. The Monist 62:161-89. + + Bibliography + +395 + +-. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press. +Everett, H. 1957. "Relative-state" formulations of quantum mechanics. Reviews of +Modern Physics 29:454-62. [Reprinted in Wheeler and Zurek 1983] +. 1973. The theory of the universal wave function. In B. S. deWitt and +N. Graham, eds., The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. +Princeton: Princeton University Press. +Farah, M. 1994. Visual perception and visual awareness after brain damage: A tutorial overview. In C. Umilta and M. Moscovitch, eds., Conscious and Nonconscious Information Processing: Attention and Performance 15. Cambridge, +Mass.: MIT Press. +Farrell, B. A. 1950. Experience. Mind 59:170-98. +Feigl, H. 1958. The "mental" and the "physical." In H. Feigl, M. Scriven, and +G. Maxwell, eds., Concepts, Theories, and the Mind-Body Problem. Minnesota +Studies in the Philosophy of Science , vol. 2. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. +Feldman, F. 1974. Kripke on the identity theory. Journal of Philosophy 71:665-76. +Field, H. 1973. Theory change and the indeterminacy of reference. Journal of Philosophy 40:762-81. +Flanagan, O. 1992. Consciousness Reconsidered. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +Fodor, J. A. 1980. Searle on what only brains can do. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:431-32. +. 1987. Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. +Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +. 1992. The big idea: Can there be a science of mind? Times Literary Supplement, July 3, pp. 5-7. +Forrest, P. 1986. Ways worlds could be. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64:15-24. +Foss, J. 1989. On the logic of what it is like to be a conscious subject. Australasian +Journal of Philosophy 67:305-20. +Foster, J. 1991. The Immaterial Self: A Defence of the Cartesian Dualism Conception +of Mind. London: Routledge. +Fredkin, E. 1990. Digital mechanics. Physica D45:254-70. +Geach, P. 1957. Mental Acts. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. +Gell-Mann, M., and J. B. Hartle. 1990. Quantum mechanics in the light of quantum +cosmology. In W. Zurek, ed., Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Redwood City, Calif.: Addison-Wesley. +Gert, B. 1965. Imagination and verifiability. Philosophical Studies 16:44-47. +Ghirardi, G. C., A. Rimini, and T. Weber. 1986. Unified dynamics for microscopic +and macroscopic systems. Physical Review D34:470. +Goldman, A. 1986. Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. +. 1993. The psychology of folk psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences +16:15-28. +Gunderson, K. 1970. Asymmetries and mind-body perplexities. In M. Radner and +S. Winokur, eds., Analyses of Theories and Methods of Physics and Psychology. +Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 4. Minneapolis: University +of Minnesota Press. +Hameroff, S. R. 1994. Quantum coherence in microtubules: A neural basis for an +emergent consciousness? Journal of Consciousness Studies 1:91-118. + + 396 + +Bibliography + +Hardin, C. L. 1987. Qualia and materialism: Closing the explanatory gap. Philosophy +and Phenomenological Research 48:281-98. +. 1988. Color for Philosophers: Unweaving the Rainbow. Indianapolis: Hackett. +Hare, R. M. 1952. The Language of Morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press. +. 1984. Supervenience. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl., 58:1-16. +Harman, G. 1982. Conceptual role semantics. Notre Dame Journal of Formal +Logic 28:242-56. +. 1990. The intrinsic quality of experience. Philosophical Perspectives 4:31-52. +Harnad, S. 1989. Minds, machines and Searle. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 1:5-25. +Harrison, B. 1967. On describing colors. Inquiry 10:38-52. +. 1973. Form and Content. Oxford: Blackwell. +Harrison, J. 1981a. Three philosophical fairy stories. Ratio 23:63-67. +. 1981b. Gulliver's adventures in Fairyland. Ratio 23:158-64. +Haugeland, J. 1980. Programs, causal powers, and intentionality. Behavioral and +Brain Sciences 4:432-33. +. 1982. Weak supervenience. American Philosophical Quarterly 19:93-103. +Healey, R. A. 1984. How many worlds? Nous 18:591-616. +Heil, J. 1992. The Nature of True Minds. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +Hellman, G., and F. Thompson. 1975. Physicalism: Ontology, determination and +reduction. Journal of Philosophy 72:551-64. +Hill, C. S. 1991. Sensations: A Defense of Type Materialism. Cambridge: Cambridge +University Press. +Hodgson, D. 1988. The Mind Matters: Consciousness and Choice in a Quantum World. +Oxford: Oxford University Press. +Hofstadter, D. R. 1979. Godel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid. New York: +Basic Books. +. 1981. Reflections on Searle. In D. R. Hofstadter and D. C. Dennett, eds., +The Mind's I. New York: Basic Books. +. 1985a. Who shoves whom around inside the careenium? In Metamagical +Themas. New York: Basic Books +. 1985b. Heisenberg's Uncertainty Principle and the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. In Metamagical Themas. New York: Basic Books. +Honderich, T. 1981. Psychophysical law-like connections and their problems. +Inquiry 24:277-303. +Horgan, T. 1978. Supervenient bridge laws. Philosophy of Science 45:227-49. +. 1982. Supervenience and microphysics. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 63: +29-43. +. 1984a. Functionalism, qualia, and the inverted spectrum. Philosophy and +Phenomenological Research 44:453-69. +. 1984b. Jackson on physical information and qualia. Philosophical Quarterly 34:147-83. +. 1984c. Supervenience and cosmic hermeneutics. Southern Journal of Philosophy, suppl., 22:19-38. +. 1987. Supervenient qualia. Philosophical Review 96:491-520. +. 1993. From supervenience to superdupervenience: Meeting the demands of +a material world. Mind 102:555-86. +Horgan, T., and M. Timmons. 1992a. Troubles for new wave moral semantics: The +"open question argument" revived. Philosophical Papers. + + Bibliography + +397 + +. 1992b. Trouble on moral twin earth: Moral queerness revived. Synthese +92:223-60. +Horst, S. 1995. Phenomenology and psychophysics. Manuscript, Wesleyan University. +Hughes, R. I. G. 1989. The Structure and Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. +Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. +Humphrey, N. 1992. A History of the Mind: Evolution and the Birth of Consciousness. +New York: Simon and Schuster. +Huxley, T. 1874. On the hypothesis that animals are automata. In Collected Essays. +London, 1893-94. +Jackendoff, R. 1987. Consciousness and the Computational Mind. Cambridge, Mass.: +MIT Press. +Jackson, F. 1977. Perception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +. 1980. A note on physicalism and heat. Australasian Journal of Philosophy +58:26-34. +. 1982. Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly 32:127-36. +. 1993. Armchair metaphysics. In J. O'Leary-Hawthorne and M. Michael, eds., +Philosophy in Mind. Dordrecht: Kluwer. +. 1994. Finding the mind in the natural world. In R. Casati, B. Smith, and +G. White, eds., Philosophy and the Cognitive Sciences, Vienna: HolderPichler-Tempsky. +. 1995. Postscript to "What Mary didn't know." In P. K. Moser and J. D. +Trout, eds., Contemporary Materialism. London: Routledge. +Jacoby, H. 1990. Empirical functionalism and conceivability arguments. Philosophical Psychology 2:271-82. +Jaynes, J. 1976. The Origins of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral +Mind. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. +Johnson-Laird, P. 1983. A computational analysis of consciousness. Cognition and +Brain Theory 6:499-508. +Kaplan, D. 1979. Dthat. In P. Cole, ed., Syntax and Semantics. New York: Academic Press. +. 1989. Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, and H. Wettstein, ed., Themes +from Kaplan. New York: Oxford University Press. +Kim, J. 1978. Supervenience and nomological incommensurables. American Philosophical Quarterly 15:149-56. +. 1984. Concepts of upervenience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45:153-76. +. 1985. Psychophysical laws. In B. McLaughlin and E. LePore, eds., Action +and Events. Oxford: Blackwell. +. 1989. Mechanism, purpose, and explanatory exclusion. Philosophical Perspectives 3:77-108. +. 1993. Supervenience and Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +Kirk, R. 1974. Zombies versus materialists. Aristotelian Society 48(suppl.):13552. +. 1979. From physical explicability to full-blooded materialism. Philosophical +Quarterly 29:229-37. +. 1992. Consciousness and concepts. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society +66(suppl.):23-40. +. 1994. Raw Feeling: A Philosophical Account of the Essence of Consciousness. +Oxford: Oxford University Press. + + 398 + +Bibliography + +Korb, K. 1991. Searle's AI program. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial +Intelligence 3:283-96 +Kripke, S. A. 1971. Identity and necessity. In M. Munitz, ed., Identity and Individuation. New York: New York University Press. +. 1972. Naming and necessity. In G. Harman and D. Davidson, eds., The +Semantics of Natural Language. Dordrecht: Reidel. [Reprinted as Kripke 1980] +. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. +. 1982. Wittgenstein on Rule-Following and Private Language. Cambridge, +Mass.: Harvard University Press. +Lahav, R., and N. Shanks. 1992. How to be a scientifically respectable "property +dualist." Journal of Mind and Behavior 13:211-32. +Langton, C. G. 1989. Artificial Life: The Proceedings of an Interdisciplinary Workshop +on the Synthesis and Simulation of Living Systems. Redwood City, Calif.: +Addison-Wesley. +Leckey, M. 1993. The universe as a computer: A model for prespace metaphysics. +Manuscript. Philosophy Department, Monash University. +Levine, J. 1983. Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical +Quarterly 64:354-61. +. 1988. Absent and inverted qualia revisited. Mind andLanguage 3:271-87. +. 1991. Cool red. Philosophical Psychology 4:27^0. +. 1993. On leaving out what it's like. In M. Davies and G. Humphreys, eds., +Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Blackwell. +Lewis, D. 1966. An argument for the identity theory. Journal of Philosophy 63:17-25. +. 1972. Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of +Philosophy 50:249-58. +. 1973. Counterfactuals. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. +. 1974. Radical interpretation. Synthese 23:331-44. +. 1979. Attitudes de dicto and de se. Philosophical Review 88:513-45. +. 1983a. Extrinsic properties. Philosophical Studies 44:197-200. +. 1983b. New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61:343-77. +. 1986a. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell. +. 1986b. Philosophical Papers. Vol. 2. New York: Oxford University Press. +. 1990. What experience teaches. In W. Lycan, ed., Mind and Cognition. +Oxford: Blackwell. +. 1994. Reduction of mind. In S. Guttenplan, ed., A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Blackwell. +Libet, B. 1993. The neural time factor in conscious and unconscious events. In +Experimental and Theoretical Studies of Consciousness. Ciba Foundation +Symposium 174. New York: Wiley. +Loar, B. 1990. Phenomenal states. Philosophical Perspectives 4:81-108. +Lockwood, M. 1989. Mind, Brain, and the Quantum. Oxford: Blackwell. +. 1992. The grain problem. In H. Robinson, ed., Objections to Physicalism. +Oxford: Oxford University Press. +Logothetis, N., and J. D. Schall. 1989. Neuronal correlates of subjective visual perception. Science 245:761-63. +London, F., and E. Bauer. 1939. The theory of observation in quantum mechanics +(in French). Actualites scientifiques etindustrielles, no. 775. [English translation +in Wheeler and Zurek 1983] + + Bibliography + +399 + +Lucas, J. R. 1961. Minds, machines and Godel. Philosophy 36:112-27. +Lycan, W. G. 1973. Inverted spectrum. Ratio 15:315-19. +. 1987. Consciousness. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +. 1995. A limited defense of phenomenal information. In T. Metzinger, ed., +Conscious Experience. Paderborn: Schoningh. +. 1996. Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +Mackay, D. M. 1969. Information, Mechanism, and Meaning. Cambridge, Mass.: +MIT Press. +Mackie, J. L. 1974. The Cement of the Universe. Oxford: Oxford University Press. +. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. +Marks, L. E. 1978. The Unity of the Senses: Interrelations among the Modalities. New +York: Academic Press. +Matzke, D., ed. 1993. Proceedings of the 1992 Workshop on Physics and Computation. +Los Alamitos, Calif.: IEEE Computer Society Press. +, ed. 1995. Proceedings of the 1994 Workshop on Physics and Computation. +Los Alamitos, Calif.: IEEE Computer Society Press. +Maxwell, G. 1978. Rigid designators and mind-brain identity. In C. W. Savage, ed., +Perception and Cognition: Issues in the Foundations of Psychology. Minnesota +Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 9. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. +McCarthy, J. 1979. Ascribing mental qualities to machines. In M. Ringle, ed., Philosophical Perspectives in Artificial Intelligence. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press. +McDowell, J. 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. +McGinn, C. 1977. Anomalous monism and Kripke's Cartesian intuitions. Analysis +2:78-80. +. 1989. Can we solve the mind-body problem? Mind 98:349-66. +McLaughlin, B. P. 1992. The rise and fall of the British emergentists. In A. Beckermann, H. Flohr, and J. Kim, eds., Emergence or Reduction? Prospects for +Nonreductive Physicalism. Berlin: De Gruyter. +. 1995. Varieties of supervenience. In E. E. Savellos and U. D. Yalcin, eds., +Supervenience: New Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +McMullen, C. 1985. "Knowing what it's like" and the essential indexical. Philosophical Studies 48:211-33. +Meehl, P.E., and W. Sellars. 1956. The concept of emergence. In H. Feigl and +M. Scriven, eds., The Foundations of Science and the Concept of Psychology +and Psychoanalysis. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 1. +Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. +Molnar, G. 1969. Kneale's argument revisited. Philosophical Review 78:79-89. +Moore, G. E. 1922. Philosophical Studies. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. +Muller, G. E. 1896. Zur Psychophysik der Gesichtsempfindungen. Zeitschrift +fur Psychologic und Physiologic der Sinnesorgane 10:1-82. +Nagel, T. 1970. Armstrong on the mind. Philosophical Review 79:394-403. +. 1974. What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 4:435-50. +. 1983. The objective self. In C. Ginet and S. Shoemaker, eds., Knowledge and +Mind: Philosophical Essays. New York: Oxford University Press. +. 1986. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press. +Natsoulas, T. 1978. Consciousness. American Psychologist 33:906-14. +Nelkin, N. 1989. Unconscious sensations. Philosophical Psychology 2:129-41. + + 400 + +Bibliography + +. 1993. What is consciousness? Philosophy of Science 60:419-34. +Nemirow, L. 1990. Physicalism and the cognitive role of acquaintance. In W. Lycan, +ed., Mind and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell. +Newell, A. 1992. SOAR as a unified theory of cognition: Issues and explanations. +Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15:464-92. +Newton, N. 1989. Machine understanding and the Chinese Room. Philosophical Psychology 2:207-15. +Nida-Rumelin, M. 1995. What Mary couldn't know: Belief about phenomenal states. +In T. Metzinger, ed., Conscious Experience. Paderborn: Schoningh. +. 1996. Pseudonormal vision: An actual case of qualia inversion? Philosophical Studies. +Papineau, D. 1993. Philosophical Naturalism. Oxford: Blackwell. +Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press. +Peacocke, C. 1992. Scenarios, concepts, and perception. In T. Crane, ed., The Contents +of Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +Penrose, R. 1987. Quantum physics and conscious thought. In B. Hiley and Peat, eds., +Quantum Implications: Essays in Honor of David Bohm. New York: Methuen. +. 1989. The Emperor's New Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. +. 1994. Shadows of the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. +Perry, J. 1979. The problem of the essential indexical. Nous 13:3-21. +Petrie, B. 1987. Global supervenience and reduction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48:119-30. +Place, U. T. 1956. Is consciousness a brain process? British Journal of Psychology +47:44-50. +Plantinga, A. 1976. Actualism and possible worlds. Theoria 42:139-60. +Putnam, H. 1960. Minds and machines. In S. Hook, ed., Dimensions of Mind. New +York: New York University Press. +. 1975. The meaning of "meaning." In K. Gunderson, ed., Language, Mind, +and Knowledge. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. +. 1981. Reason, Truth, and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +. 1983. Possibility and necessity. In Philosophical Papers. Vol. 3. Cambridge: +Cambridge University Press. +. 1988. Representation and Reality. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +Pylyshyn, Z. 1980. The "causal power" of machines. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:442-44. +Quine, W. V. 1951. Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review 60:20-43. +. 1969. Propositional objects. In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New +York: Columbia University Press. +Rensink, R. A., J. K. O'Regan, and J. J. Clark. 1995. Image flicker is as good as +saccades in making large scene changes invisible. Perception 24 (suppl.):26-27. +Rey, G. 1982. A reason for doubting the existence of consciousness. In R. Davidson, +S. Schwartz, and D. Shapiro, eds., Consciousness and Self-Regulation. Vol 3. +New York: Plenum. +. 1986. What's really going on in Searle's "Chinese Room." Philosophical +Studies 50:169-85. +. 1992. Sensational sentences reversed. Philosophical Studies 68:289-319. +Reynolds, C. 1987. Flocks, herds, and schools: A distributed behavioral model. Computer Graphics 21:25-34. + + Bibliography + +401 + +Robinson, H. 1976. The mind-body problem in contemporary philosophy. Zygon +11:346-60. +. 1982. Matter and Sense. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +Robinson, W. S. 1988. Brains and People: An Essay on Mentality and Its Causal +Conditions. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. +Rosenberg, G. H. 1996. Consciousness and causation: Clues toward a double-aspect +theory. Manuscript, Indiana University. +Rosenthal, D. M. 1996. A theory of consciousness. In N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. +Guzeldere, eds., The Nature of Consciousness. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +Russell, B. 1927. The Analysis of Matter. London: Kegan Paul. +Ryle, G. 1949. The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson. +Savage, C. W. 1970. The Measurement of Sensation. Berkeley: University of California Press. +Savitt, S. 1982. Searle's demon and the brain simulator reply. Behavioral and Brain +Sciences 5:342-43. +Sayre, K. M. 1976. Cybernetics and the Philosophy of Mind. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: +Humanities Press. +Sayre-McCord, G. 1988. Introduction: The many moral realisms. In G. SayreMcCord, ed., Essays on Moral Realism. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University +Press. +Schacter, D. L. 1989. On the relation between memory and consciousness: Dissociable +interactions and conscious experience. In H. Roediger and F. Craik, eds., +Varieties of Memory and Consciousness: Essays in Honor of Endel Tulving. +Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum. +Schlick, M. 1932. Positivism and Realism. Erkenntnis 3. +. 1938. Form and content: An introduction to philosophical thinking. In Gesammelte Aufsatze 1926-1936. Vienna: Gerold [Reprinted in H. L. Mulder and +B. van de Velde-Schlick, eds., Philosophical Papers. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979] +Seager, W. E. 1988. Weak supervenience and materialism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48:697-709. +. 1991. Metaphysics of Consciousness. London: Routledge. +Searle, J. R. 1980. Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: +417-24. +. 1984. Minds, Brains and Science. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. +. 1990a. Consciousness, explanatory inversion and cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13:585-642. +. 1990b. Is the brain a digital computer? Proceedings and Addresses of the +American Philosophical Association 64:21-37. +. 1992. The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +Sellars, W. 1956. Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In H. Feigl and M. Scriven, +eds., The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 1. Minneapolis: +University of Minnesota Press. +. 1965. The identity approach to the mind-body problem. Review of Metaphysics 18:430-51. +. 1981. Is consciousness physical? Monist 64:66-90. +Shallice, T. 1972. Dual functions of consciousness. Psychological Review 79:383-93. +. 1988a. Information-processing models of consciousness: Possibilities and + + 402 + +Bibliography + +problems. In A. Marcel and E. Bisiach, eds., Consciousness in Contemporary +Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press. +. 1988b. From Neuropsychology to Mental Structure. Cambridge: Cambridge +University Press. +Shannon, C. E. 1948. A mathematical theory of communication. Bell Systems Technical Journal 27:379-423. [Reprinted in C. E. Shannon and W. Weaver, +The Mathematical Theory of Communication. Urbana: University of Illinois +Press, 1949] +Shepard, R. N. 1993. On the physical basis, linguistic representation, and conscious +experience of colors. In G. Harman, ed., Conceptions of the Human Mind: +Essays in Honor of George A. Miller. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum. +Shoemaker, S. 1975a. Functionalism and qualia. Philosophical Studies 27:291-315. +. 1975b. Phenomenal similarity. Critica 7:3-37. +. 1980. Causality and properties. In P. van Inwagen, ed., Time and Cause. +Dordecht: Reidel. +. 1981. Some varieties of functionalism. Philosophical Topics 12:93-119. +. 1982. The inverted spectrum. Journal of Philosophy 79:357-81. +Sidelle, A. 1989. Necessity, essence, and individuation. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. +. 1992. Rigidity, ontology, and semantic structure. Journal of Philosophy +8:410-30. +Siewert, C. 1993. What Dennett can't imagine and why. Inquiry 36:93-112. +. 1994. Understanding consciousness. Ph.D. diss. University of California, +Berkeley. [Forthcoming as a book from Princeton University Press] +Skyrms, B. 1980. Causal Necessity. New Haven: Yale University Press. +Smart, J. J. C. 1959. Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review 68:141-56. +Sperling, G. 1960. The information available in brief visual presentations. Psychological Monographs 74. +Sperry, R. W. 1969. A modified concept of consciousness. Psychological Review +76:532-36. +. 1992. Turnabout on consciousness: A mentalist view. Journal of Mind and +Behavior 13:259-80. +Sprigge, T. L. S. 1971. Final causes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 45 +(suppl.):149-70. +. 1994. Consciousness. Synthese 98:73-93. +Squires, E. 1990. Conscious Mind in the Physical World. Bristol: Hilger. +Stalnaker, R. 1976. Possible worlds. Nous 10:65-75. +. 1978. Assertion. In P. Cole, ed., Syntax and Semantics: Pragmatics. Vol. 9. +New York: Academic Press. +Stapp, H. P. 1993. Mind, Matter, and Quantum Mechanics. Berlin: SpringerVerlag. +Stevens, S. S. 1975. Psychophysics: Introduction to Its Perceptual, Neural, and Social +Prospects. New York: Wiley. +Sutherland, N. S., ed. 1989. The International Dictionary of Psychology. New +York: Continuum. +Swoyer, C. 1982. The nature of natural laws. Australasian Journal of Philosophy +60:203-23. +Teller, D. Y. 1984. Linking propositions. Vision Research 24:1233-46. + + Bibliography + +403 + +. 1990. The domain of visual science. In L. Spillman, and J. S. Werner, eds., +Visual Perception: The Neurophysiological Foundations. New York: Academic Press. +Teller, P. 1984. A poor man's guide to supervenience and determination. Southern +Journal of Philosophy, suppl., 22:137-62. +. 1992. A contemporary look at emergence. In A. Beckermann, H. Flohr, and +J. Kim, eds., Emergence or Reduction? Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism. +Berlin: De Gruyter. +Thagard, P. 1986. The emergence of meaning: An escape from Searle's Chinese +Room. Behaviorism 14:139-46. +Thompson, E. 1992. Novel colours. Philosophical Studies 68:321-49. +Tienson, J. L. 1987. Brains are not conscious. Philosophical Papers 16:187-93. +Tooley, M. 1977. The nature of laws. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7:667-98. +. 1987. Causation: A Realist Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press. +Tye, M. 1986. The subjective qualities of experience. Mind 95:1-17. +. 1992. Visual qualia and visual content. In T. Crane, ed., The Contents of +Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. +. 1993. Blindsight, the absent qualia hypothesis, and the mystery of consciousness. In C. Hookway, ed., Philosophy and the Cognitive Sciences. Cambridge: +Cambridge University Press. +. 1995. Ten Problems of Consciousness. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. +van Cleve, J. 1990. Mind-dust or magic? Panpsychism versus emergence. Philosophical +Perspectives 4:215-26. +van Gulick, R. 1988. A functionalist plea for self-consciousness. Philosophical Review 97:149-88. +. 1992. Nonreductive materialism and the nature of intertheoretical constraint. +In A. Beckermann, H. Flohr, and J. Kim, eds., Emergence or Reduction? +Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism. Berlin: De Gruyter. +. 1993. Understanding the phenomenal mind: Are we all just armadillos? In +M. Davies and G. Humphreys, eds., Consciousness: A Mind and Language +Reader. Oxford: Blackwell. +Velmans, M. 1991. Is human information processing conscious? Behavioral and Brain +Sciences 14:651-69. +Weinberg, S. 1992. Dreams of a Final Theory. New York: Pantheon Books. +Weiskrantz, L. 1986. Blindsight: A Case Study and Implications. Oxford: Oxford +University Press. +. 1992. Introduction: Dissociated issues. In D. Milner and M. Rugg, eds., The +Neuropsychology of Consciousness. London: Academic Press. +Wheeler, J. A. 1990. Information, physics, quantum: The search for links. In W. H. +Zurek, ed., Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Redwood +City, Calif.: Addison-Wesley. +. 1994. It from bit. In At Home in the Universe. Woodbury, N.Y.: American +Institute of Physics Press. +Wheeler, J. A., and W. H. Zurek. 1983. Quantum Theory and Measurement. Princeton: +Princeton University Press. +White, S. L. 1986. Curse of the qualia. Synthese 68:333-68. +Wigner, E. P. 1961. Remarks on the mind-body question. In I. J. Good, ed., The +Scientist Speculates. New York: Basic Books. + + 404 + +Bibliography + +Wilkes, K. V. 1984. Is consciousness important? British Journal for the Philosophy +of Science 35:223-43. +Wilson, M. 1982. Predicate meets property. Philosophical Review 91:549-89. +. 1985. What is this thing called "pain"? The philosophy of science behind +the contemporary debate. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 66:227-67. +Winograd, T. 1972. Understanding Natural Language. New York: Academic Press. +Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophical Investigations. London: Macmillan. +. 1968. Notes for lectures on "private experience" and "sense data." Philosophical Review 77. +Wright, R. 1988. Three Scientists and Their Gods. New York: Times Books. +Yablo, S. 1993. Is conceivability a guide to possibility? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53:1-42. +Zuboff, A. 1994. What is a mind? In P. A. French, T. E. Uehling, and H. K. Wettstein, +eds., Philosophical Naturalism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 19. Notre +Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press. +Zurek, W. H. 1990. Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Redwood +City, Calif.: Addison-Wesley. + + Index +A posteriori necessity, 38, 52, 55-65, 366n28, +367n34; irrelevance to reductive +explanation, 45,57,69, 94,98,101,365n22; +and knowledge argument, 141-44; and +Kripke's argument against materialism, +146-49,374n25; and logical supervenience, +78-79,94,98; and materialism, 129,131-38, +162,164, 371nn3-8; and moral properties, +83-84, 371n7; two-dimensional account of, +56-65, 365n67, 374n25, 375n29 +A priori truth, 63,64,69,88,138,366n28; link +with necessary truth, 62-^64, 69. See also +Conceptual truth +Ability analysis, 104, 144-45,166 +Absent qualia, 249-50, 274-75; arguments +against, 253-63,270; arguments for, 251-53; +logical possibility of (see Chinese +population; Zombie) +Abstract entities, 71, 280, 315, 367n36 +Access consciousness, 29, 228-29 +Accessibility, 105, 112, 185-86, 290-92, 22033, 253, 360nl5 +Ackerman, D., 8, 359 +Adams, R. M., 366 +Aesthetic properties, 83-84 +Akins, K., 236 +Albert, D., 341, 345, 347, 354, 391 +Alexander, S., 49, 378 +Analysis. See Conceptual analysis +Analytic truth. See Conceptual truth +Angel world, 39-40, 81, 85, 363nl6, 369n47 +Animal consciousness, 8,27,28,103,105,225, +226, 228, 231, 236-38, 242, 246, 257, 29495, 383nlO +Anomalous monism, 168, 377n37 +Armstrong, D. M., 14-15, 30,166, 360, 367, +369, 382 +Artificial intelligence, 184-86, 275, 313-32; +external objections to, 313-14,322,328-31, +389nn7-8; internal objections to, 314,322-28 +Artificial life, 121, 129 +Aspectual shape, 360nlO +Attention, 27, 29, 112, 219, 269, 272-73 +Auditory experience, 7-8, 220, 234 +Austin, D. F., 373 + +Availability, 220, 223-33, 236-42, 276, 288, +300-301, 377n38, 382n8 +Awakeness, 6, 26, 29 +Awareness: coherence with consciousness, +28-29, 220-46, 276; definition of, 28, 29, +116, 222, 225-29, 246, 361nl5; distinctness +from consciousness, 105,165, 239; +explanation of, 29-31,112, 239-42; made +up of judgments/registrations, 175-76, +383-84; structure of, 223-25, 234-36, +242-43, 287-88 +Baars, B. J., 112-13, 238, 241 +Backup circuit, 267-68, 270, 325 +Bacon, J., 88 +Barwise, J., 280 +Basic laws. See Fundamental laws +Bateson, G., 281 +Bats, 103, 236, 294 +Bauer, E., 339 +Bealer, G., 371, 374 +Behavioral dispositions, 14, 191, 248, 255, +268-69 +Behavioral invariance, 261-62 +Behaviorism, 13,166 +Belief: about consciousness (see Phenomenal +judgments); content of, 19, 65, 360nl2, +366n29,368nn42-43; and fading qualia, 256, +258-59; functionalist analysis of, 13-15, +19-20, 256, 269, 376n36; inflationary/ +deflationary construals of, 20,175,178,192, +199,377n38; vs. judgment, 174-75,191-92, +203, 207-8, 232; phenomenal aspects of, +19-20, 174, 360nl2; relational element of, +21 +Bell's theorem, 119, 344, 390n6 +Bell, J. S., 343-44, 351, 391 +Berkeley, G., 155 +Bigelow, J., 143, 371 +Bill, 267-68 +Binding, 115-16, 238 +Biological materialism, 168, 244, 375n34, +380n7 +Bisiach, E., 360 +Bit, 278-82 + + 406 + +Index + +Black-and-white room. See Knowledge +argument +Blackburn, S., 83, 88, 375 +Blindness denial, 219, 260-61 +Blindsight, 190, 226-27, 253, 291, 382n5 +Block, N., vi, 29,95,97,132,228,250-53,262, +368, 375, 382, 388 +Boden, M., 323 +Bodily sensation, 9 +Bogen, J., 386 +Bohm interpretation, 343-45, 348, 349, 35657 +Bohm, D., 333, 343-45,348, 356-57, 388, 391 +Bohr, N., 342-43 +Boring, E., 385 +Boyd, R. N., 84,148, 374 +Brain in vat, 75, 195, 202, 345 +Bridging principles, 107-8,121,138,164,234, +236-42, 385-86 +Brindley, G. S., 385-86 +Brink, D., 84, 88 +Broad, C. D., 49,129 +Brooks, D. H. M., 364 +Byrne, A., 166, 371, 375 +Campbell, K. K., 166, 369, 372 +Carroll, J. W., 369 +Carruthers, P., 382 +Cartesian dualism, 124-25. See also +Interactionist dualism +Causal efficacy. See Consciousness, causal +efficacy of +Causal flux, 153-54, 304-5, 375n29 +Causal organization, 317-21, 325, 327, 328, +332 +Causal overdetermination, 152 +Causal pathway, 281-83, 301, 309 +Causal theory of knowledge, 193-96, 200,202 +Causal theory of reference, 59, 201-3, 208, +368n25 +Causal-role concept, 45 +Causation: active vs. passive, 298, 301; and +consciousness, 86,152-53,293,297-98,301; +emergent, 168, 378n41; epistemology of, +74-75, 151-52, 159; Humean views of, 86, +151-52; vs. regularity, 74-75, 86, 151-52, +159; supervenience of, 75, 86, 152-53 +Cellular automaton, 303, 316-17, 319 +Centered worlds, 60-61, 72, 133, 144, 201, +203-6, 366n29, 373nnl6-17, 384 +Cerebral celebrity, 229-30, 240 +Chalmers, D. J., 65,85,244,248,284,387,388 +Character, 60, 365n25 +Cheney, D. L., 236 +Chinese population, 97, 244, 250-52, 259, +386n2 +Chinese room, 314, 322-26, 389nn4-6 +Chisholm, R., 14 +Churchland, P. M., 114,141,370,373-74, 386 +Churchland, P. S., 169-70, 364, 386 + +Circumstances of evaluation, 60, 61 +Claims about consciousness, 173-75,177-88, +198-99, 203-4. See also Phenomenal +judgments +Clark, A., 235, 376 +Clark, J. J., 272 +Cognition, 172 +Cognitive limitations, 137,149, 372nn8-9,11 +Cognitive model, 31, 46, 111-14, 240-41 +Cognitive science, 11, 14, 29, 46-47, 111-14, +184, 289, 320, 332, 389n3 +Coherence principles: between consciousness +and awareness, 219-48, 276; between +consciousness and cognition, 218-29, +257-59, 269, 294-95; epistemology of, 226, +238, 241-46; explanatory coherence, +288-89, 292, 388nl; explanatory role of, +233-42; as psychophysical laws, 242-46, +276-77, 382nl; structural coherence, +222-25, 234-36, 242-43, 276, 287-88, +386nl2 +Cole, D., 388 +Collapse of wave function, 119, 336-37, +338-41, 343-44, 390n6; by consciousness, +120, 157, 334, 339-41, 356-57, 370nl3; +criteria for, 338-41 +Color concepts, 205-6, 264-65, 359n3, +380nnlO-ll, 381nl2, 382nl, 387n7 +Color experiences, 6-7 +Color space, 100-101, 223-24, 234-35, 264, +284-85, 290-91, 308-9, 369n4 +Colorblindness, 369n7, 383n7, 387nll +Combinatorial-state automaton (CSA), +316-22, 324; vs. FSA, 317, 318-19 +Communicability, 22,177,206-7,224,236,291 +Compact disk, 281-82, 293, 300 +Complexity, 98, 294-97, 344-45, 372n8, +378n41 +Computation, 315-19; and consciousness, +275, 313-32; implementation of, 315-20, +350; observer-relativity of, 316, 319-20, +389n2; symbolic, 329, 332, 390nl0; +universality of, 332, 390nl0 +Computer, 103-4,177,184-86, 249, 275, 303, +313-32, 389n7 +Conceivability, 35, 66-68, 369n3; a priori +and a posteriori varieties of, 67-68; in +establishing supervenience claims, 70, 73, +93-101; as a guide to possibility, 66-68, 98, +109-10, 130-31, 131-40, 146-47, +367nn22-23, 371n7; and logical possibility, +35, 66-68, 367n22; and reductive +explanation, 109-10; unreliability of, 98-99, +367n22; various senses of, 66-67 +Conceptual analysis: critiques of, 52, 5356, 59-60, 80-81, 88; in establishing +supervenience claims, 77-81, 139, 368n40; +and a posteriori necessity, 59-60, 78-79 +Conceptual truth, 52-71; and absence of +definitions, 52, 53-55; and a posteriori + + Index +necessity, 56,62,66, 367n35; a priori and a +posteriori varieties, 62, 66; and necessity, +66; Quine's critique of, 52, 55-56, 88, +366n28 +Conee, E., 372, 382 +Connectionism, 46,121, 316, 329, 332, 389n7 +Conscious experience. See Consciousness +Consciousness: acquaintance with, 196-98, +200, 208, 230, 292; against functional +analysis of, 15, 104-5, 110, 164-65,167; +causal efficacy of, 150-60, 177, 191-203, +378n41; content of, 175-76, 221, 383-85; +criteria for, 217, 226-29, 236-38, 239-42; +definition of, 3-4; determinacy of, 105,165, +297, 390n4; different meanings of term, 6, +25-28, 360nl5; evolution of, 120-21,160, +171; examples of, 4, 6-11, 359n5; +explanatory irrelevance of, 156,177-84, +191-203, 208; failure of reductive +explanation, 46-47, 93-122, 235, 379n42; +failure to logically supervene, 37-38, 88, +93-106; as fundamental property, 126-29, +357; holism of, 299; knowledge of (see +Epistemology); local supervenience of, 34, +93, 217; natural supervenience of, 37-38, +124-27; neural correlates of, 115-18, 234, +237, 238-42; no analysis of concept, 94, +104-6; phenomenal and psychological +varieties, 25-31; reference to, 201-8; +semantics of concept, 133-34, 149, 203-8; +specific character of, 5,101, 263, 276-77, +308, 373nl5, 376n35; stream of, 10; +structure of, 107, 223-25, 234-36, 242-43, +256, 266, 284-85, 287-88, 308-9, 382n3; +subject of, 296-97,309,349,352; surprising +nature of, 5,101,186,314; ubiquity of (see +Panpsychism); unity of, 10-11, 309 +Consciousness-dependent properties, 81-82 +Considering a world as actual/ +counterfactual, 60 +Context of utterance, 60, 61, 63, 363n25 +Continuity and discreteness, 255-56, 278-79, +281-82, 322, 330-31, 340, 390n9 +Copenhagen interpretation, 342 +Cowey, A., 228 +Crane, T., 383 +Creation myth, 87 +Creativity, 313, 329 +Crick, F., 115-16, 235-36, 238-39, 370 +Cuda, T., 253, 387 +Cussins, A., 383 +Dancing qualia, 250-51, 253, 262, 266-75, +321-22, 324-26, 388nl5 +Daneri, A., 341 +Davidson, D., 361, 377 +Davies, M. K., 56, 63 +Decoherence, 341-42, 353 +Decomposition, 318 +Deep necessity, 63, 64 + +407 + +Definitions, absence of, 52, 53-55, 77-78, +80,106 +Deflationary construal. See Belief +Dennett, D. C, vi, 30, 82, 113-14,145,166, +170,189-91,227,229-30,240,361,370,372, +382, 388 +Depth experience, 7 +• +Descartes, R., 12-13,15,75,124,130-31,186, +195,359,367 +Descriptive theory of reference, 58-59, +368n45 +Detectability principle, 219 +Dewitt, B. S., 347 +Diagonal proposition, 64 +Difference structure, 224, 278, 281-82, 284 +Difference that makes a difference, 281-83, +284, 292, 302 +Direct availability. See Availability +Disembodiment, 130, 146-49, 258, 367n23, +374nn23-24, 384 +Don't-have-a-clue materialism, 162 +Double-aspect principle, 283-87, 350, 388nl; +arguments against, 293-99; arguments for, +287-92; constraints on, 293, 299-300, 310; +ontology of, 286, 301-8; open questions +about, 308-10 +Double-aspect theory, 129, 130,155 +Doxastic/phenomenal distinction, 382n9 +Dreams, 227-28, 257 +Dretske, F. I., 82,166, 232-33, 280, 369, 374, +377, 378, 379, 382, 382-83 +Dreyfus, H., 313, 389 +Drug-induced experiences, 10, 173-74, +176 +Dthat, 59, 79, 61-62,132,134,135,141 +Dualism, 245, 264, 357; arguments against, +168-71, 377n37; arguments for, 123-24, +129-49, 161-68; varieties of, 124-29 +Easy problems, xii, xiii +Eccles, J. C., 157-58 +Ectoplasm, 39-41, 85,158, 363-64 +Edelman, G., 116-18, 370 +Eliminativism, xiii, 102,161-62,164-68,184, +186-89, 195-96 +Elitzur, A., 177, 183, 379 +Emergence, 49, 129-30,168, 378n41 +Emotions, 10, 19, 224, 309, 384 +Entailment, 36, 54, 70, 78-81 +Epiphenomenalism, 150-60, 165, 370n9, +389n7; arguments against, 158-60; +strategies for avoiding, 151-58 +Epistemic asymmetry, 101-3,108, 369n6 +Epistemic lever, 234, 236-38 +Epistemological myth, 87 +Epistemology: in establishing supervenience +claims, 70, 73-77, 93-94, 101-4; of one's +own consciousness, 74, 160, 169, 182-83, +191-200, 207-8, 292, 380; of others' +consciousness, 72,102,226-29,234,236-38, + + 408 + +Index + +Epistemology (cont.) +239-42, 243-46. See also Knowledge; +Skeptical problems +EPR paradox, 119, 390n6 +Essential properties, 135, 147-49, 361n2, +362n4, 375n29 +Evans, G., 56, 63-64, 383 +Everett interpretation, 345-57, 390; +counterintuitiveness of, 346, 356-57; +different versions of, 347,351,354; personal +identity in, 352-53,354-56; preferred basis +problem, 348-51; probabilities in, 353-56, +390n8; and theory of consciousness, 34851, 354-55 +Everett, H., 345-48, 356-57 +Evolution, 120-21,160, 170, 171, 231, 257, +300, 345, 372n8 +Experience. See Consciousness +Experience meter, 112, 226, 239 +Experimental research, 112, 115, 216-18, +226-29, 233-42, 270, 272 +Explanatory coherence, 288-89, 292, 388n2 +Explanatory exclusion, 178 +Explanatory gap, 47,107, 119, 234-35, 333 +Explanatory irrelevance, 156, 158,163-65, +177-84, 186, 207; arguments against, +191-203, 208-9; problems with, 158-60, +182-83 +Extrospection, 190 +Facts, 33, 361n2, 372nl3 +Fading qualia, 250-51, 253-63, 266, 270, +274-75, 321-22, 324-26, 387nn7-8 +Falsifiability. See Testability +Farah, M., 238-39, 241 +Farrell, B. A., 359 +Fechner, G., 382 +Feigl, H., 166, 375 +Feldman, F., 148 +Fermat's last theorem, 99 +Field, H., 365 +Fine-grained organization, 248, 265, 274-75, +387nl2, 388nl7 +Finite-state automaton, 315-19, 389n2 +First-order judgment, 175-76,182, 219-21, +231,382nl; content of, 220,383-84; vs. firstorder registration, 220, 232-33, 382n9 +First-order registration, 220, 232-33, 382n9, +383nlO +Flanagan, O., 166 +Fodor, J., 82,162, 323 +Forrest, P., 366 +Foss, J., 379 +Foster, J., 389 +Fredkin, E., 302-3, 389 +Frege, G., 56-57, 59 +Freud, S., 13 +Functional analysis, 43-46, 79-81 +Functional isomorph, 97,166-67,245-75,288, +375n34, 376n35, 385nlO + +Functional organization: and computation, +315,320-22; and consciousness, 97,243-46, +247-75, 288, 315; definition of, 247-48 +Functional properties, 79-81,107, 163, +375nn35-36 +Functionalism (nonreductive), 227, 229-32, +243-46,249,274-75; arguments for, 243-46, +253-63, 266-75 +Functionalism (reductive): appropriateness +for psychological, 15-16; arguments for, +187-89, 193, 369n3; criticism of, 15, 30, +104-5,164-65,167,188, 274-75; definition +of, 14; first-order vs. second-order, 231-32; +vs. nonreductive, 229,249,274-75; varieties +of, 29-32, 359n8, 376nn35-36, 378n40 +Fundamental laws, 76, 88-89, 111, 126-30, +170-71, 213-18, 243, 256, 275, 276-77, +286-88, 343-45, 378n41; simplicity of, 127, +214-16, 288 +Fundamental properties, 126,136, 143, 155, +286-87, 297, 302-4 +Fundamental theory, 126-29,213-18,267-77, +287-88, 310 +Further fact, 41, 83, 85, 86, 107, 245, 368n43, +373nl7 +Further question, 47, 106-7, 110, 111 +Gas law, 36-37 +Geach, P., 14 +Gell-Mann, M., 341, 352 +Geometry of experience, 107, 223-24, 236, +284 +Gert, B., 265 +Ghirardi, G. C, 343 +Ghost in the machine, 125, 128, 186 +Given, 380n6 +Global availability. See Availability +Global workspace, 112, 238-41 +God, 45, 73, 138, 345, 357, 362n5; belief in, +183,187-88,379n2; in characterizing logical +possibility, 35, 66; work to do in creation, +38-41, 87, 124, 148 +Godel's theorem, 139 +Goldbach's conjecture, 67, 68, 139 +Goldman, A., 382 +Grain problem, 306-8, 389nn6-7 +Gravity, 111, 119,171, 330 +Great Divide, xv, 167 +GRW interpretation, 343-45, 348, 390n5 +Gunderson, K., 369 +Haecceity, 367n30 +Hallucination, 34, 75, 194, 220 +Halting problem, 331 +Hameroff, S. R., 119 +Hard problem, xii, xiii +Hardin, C. L., 100, 224, 264, 369 +Hare, R. M., 83, 361, 362 +Harman, G., 377, 385 +Harnad, S. R., 327 + + Index +Harris, R., 84, 353 +Harrison, B., 100, 264 +Harrison, J., 387 +Hartle, J. B., 341, 352 +Haugeland, J., 39, 88, 389 +Healey, R. A., 351 +Heil, J., 88 +Hellman, G., 88, 361 +Hidden variables, 343-45, 356, 390n6 +High-quality representations, 238-41 +Higher-order thought, 30, 168, 230-31, +361nl6, 378n39, 382nn6, 8 +Hiley, B., 391 +Hill, C. S., 166, 371, 375-76, 380 +History-dependence, 271, 378n40, 387n3 +Hodgson, D., 120, 333, 391 +Hofstadter, D. R., 30, 185-86, 329, 353, 389 +Homogeneity, 217, 219, 226, 246, 306 +Homunculus, 97,170, 244, 252, 299, 324-26, +389n6 +Honderich, T., 166 +Horgan, T., vi, 84, 88,108,141,150,166,361, +362, 363, 364, 367, 369, 371, 375, 387, 388 +Horst, S., 385 +Hughes, R. I. G., 351 +Humberstone, I. L., 56, 63 +Hume, G., 74-75, 151-52, 170, 363, 369 +Humean views, 86, 151-52, 363nll, 369n49 +Humphrey, N., 228 +Huxley, T., 150 +Idealism, 75,155, 388n4 +Identity, xvii, 33,130-31,146-49, 361n4, +367n30, 374nn22-23 +Identity theory, 146-48, 374n26, 375n30, +377n37 +Illuminating explanation, 48-50 +Illusion, 34, 233, 385nl2 +Implementation, 315-20, 326-27, 350, 389n2 +Incorrigibility, 197, 207-8, 219 +Indeterminacy, 53-55,72,77,80,105, 365n23 +Indexicality, 60-61, 72, 205, 352, 353, 355, +382nl7; indexical fact, 85, 87, 373nnl617; in knowledge argument, 142-44, +373nnl6-17; primitiveness of, 84-85, +369n46 +Induction, problem of, 75, 355-56 +Ineffability, 22-23, 206-7, 224, 246, 291 +Inference to the best explanation, 75, 76, +216, 246 +Inflationary construal. See Belief +Information, 277-310, 388-89; amount of, +280-82; aspects of, 284-87 (see also Doubleaspect principle); and consciousness, +283-310; direct access to, 290-92; in +explaining phenomenal judgments, 288-92; +microscopic vs. macroscopic, 305-8; +ontology of, 286-87, 301-5; phenomenally +realized, 283-84; physically realized, +280-87; and physics, 302-5, 350; pure, + +409 + +302-5, 308; semantic notion of, 278, 280; +syntactic notion of, 278-80; transmittability +of, 282-83, 285; ubiquity of, 293, 297, +299-301 +Information space, 278-310; combinatorial +and relational structure of, 278-80, 282, +284, 287-88, 309 +Information state, 278-310; in cognitive +processing, 289-92; grounding of, 303-7 +Intension, 55, 56, 66, 77-81, 201-3, 367n31. +See also Primary intension; Secondary +intension +Intensionality, 140-44 +Intensity, 224, 235, 301, 385nl2 +Intentionality, 19, 360nl5; connection to +consciousness, 19-22,82,174,208, 322-23, +327, 360nlO, 371n2, 384-85; functionalist +analysis of, 19-20, 82; supervenience of, +82-83, 368n43 +Interactionist dualism, 124-25,128, 162-63, +177,183; arguments against, 156-58,163 +Intrinsic properties, 135-36,153-55,158,163, +235, 304-5, 310, 375n29, 389n7 +Introspection, 26, 29, 30, 31,189-90, 231, +381n!4 +Intuition, xv, 83, 96-98,110,139,147^8, +167, 375n33 +Invariance principle. See Organizational +invariance +Inverted Earth, 265-66, 387nnl3-14 +Inverted qualia, 108,235,308,376n35,385nlO; +actual cases of, 378nll; arguments against +natural possibility of, 266-74, 370n9; +arguments for natural possibility of, 250, +263-66, 387nnll-12; logical possibility of, +99-101,166,250,263-64,274-75,369nn4-5; +and materialism, 124, 140, 372nl2; and +phenomenal concepts, 205-7, 381nnll,15 +Inverted spectrum. See Inverted qualia +It from bit, 302-5, 308, 388nn4-5 +Jackendoff, R., 25, 360, 382 +Jackson, F., vi, 42, 103-4,140, 149,166, 363, +367, 368, 369, 370, 371, 372, 373, 374, 379 +Jacoby, H., 369 +James, W., 13 +Jaynes, J., 30 +Joe, 256-57, 259, 261, 262 +Johnson-Laird, P., 114 +Judgment, 159-60,174,175,183-84,189-92, +203, 220, 232-33, 262, 383nlO +Judgments about consciousness. See +Phenomenal judgments +Kaplan, D., 56, 59, 60, 64, 84, 365-66 +Kim, J., 178, 361, 362, 364, 377 +Kirk, R., vi, 150, 231-32, 367, 369, 372 +Knowledge, 27,182-83, 373nl8 +Knowledge argument, 103-4,140-46, 206, +369n7, 370n9, 372-74, 379n3 + + 410 + +Index + +Knowledge of consciousness. See +Epistemology +Koch, C, 115-16, 235-36, 238-39, 370 +Korb, K., 389 +Kripke, S. A., vi, 38,45,52,56-57,59,64,124, +131,133-34,140,146-50,164,360,365,366, +368, 374, 375 +Kripke/Wittgenstein argument, 360nl2, +368n43 +Kripkean argument against materialism, 140, +146-50, 374 +Kripkean necessity. See A posteriori necessity +Lahav, R., 119, 375 +Langton, C. G., 129 +Language: about consciousness (see +Phenomenal concepts); and consciousness, +28, 116-17, 237-38 +Laplace's demon, 35, 36 +Laws of nature, 33, 36-38,71, 75-76, 87, 111, +170-71, 362n7; Humean views of, 86, +363nll, 369n49; necessity of, 375n29; +supervenience of, 86, 369n48. See also +Fundamental laws; Psychophysical laws +Learning: as example of reductive +explanation, 42-47, 51, 111; as functional +concept, 12, 15, 16, 18, 51 +Leckey, M., 303 +Levine, J., vi, 47,100,107,166, 371, 387 +Lewis, D., vi, 14-15, 56, 60, 82, 104, 123, +143-45,166, 363, 364, 365, 366, 367, 368, +369, 371, 374, 375 +Libet, B., 238-39 +Life, 25,148, 296; logical supervenience of, +79, 108-9; reductive explanation of, 79, +108-9; vagueness of concept, 53-54 +Linguistic division of labor, 58 +Linking proposition, 385-86 +Loar, B., 142-43, 145, 166, 371, 373 +Locke, J., 263 +Lockwood, M., vi, 135,166,333,347,360,372, +375, 388, 389 +Loewer, B., 345, 347, 354, 372, 390 +Logic, 35, 52, 76, 362n6 +Logical necessity (of statements), 66; a priori +vs. a posteriori varieties, 65; and a priori +truth, 68-69; broad vs. strict, 35, 52, 362n6; +and conceivability, 66; and conceptual +truth, 66 +Logical possibility, 35, 47, 65-71, 362n5; +arguing for, 96-97; and conceivability, +66-68; vs. natural possibility, 37-38, 250, +257,314-15, 370n9 +Logical supervenience: and a priori +entailment, 70,372n8; of almost everything, +71-89, 367-69, 372n8; definition of, 35, +40-41, 363nnl3,16; equivalence of +formulations, 70-71; and explanatory +relevance, 178-79; and logical necessity, +69-71; and materialism, 41-42, 123-24, + +129-31; modulo consciousness, 72, 78, +81-83, 367n37; modulo indexicality, 72, +367n37, 368n24; vs. natural supervenience, +37-38, 362n9; primary and secondary +versions, 69-70; problems and doubts, +81-86, 88; and reductive explanation, +47-51; ways to establish, 70 +Logothetis, N., 237 +Loinger, A., 341 +London, F., 339 +Look-up table, 254, 262, 325 +Lucas, J. R., 313-14, 330, 389 +Lycan, W. G., 141, 145, 166, 231, 252, 265, +371, 374, 377, 380, 385, 386 +Machine consciousness, 275, 313-32, 370n9 +Mackay, D. M., 282 +Mackie, J. L., 369 +Macroscopic phenomenology, 305-7, 310 +Many-worlds interpretation, 347, 351. See +also Everett interpretation +Marks, L. E., 386 +Mary, 103-4, 133, 139, 140-46, 166-67, 206, +369n7, 373nl8, 374nnl9-20, 379n3 +Materialism, 245, 264, 370-75; arguments +against, 123-24, 129-49, 161-68, 369n3, +371-74; arguments for, 168-71,186-91,193, +377n37; definition of, 41-42, 124, 126, +363nl2, 364nnl7, 19 +Mathematical truths, 67-69, 71, 99,139, +367n31, 371n7, 372nn9-10 +Matzke, D., 302 +Maximal state, 349-50, 377n37, 387n5 +Maxiworld, 347 +Maxwell, G., 135, 166, 375 +Maxwell, J. C., 127-28, 169 +McCarthy, J., 388 +McDowell, J., 383 +McGinn, C., vi, 139,148, 379 +McLaughlin, B. P., 362, 378 +McMullen, C., 141,143 +Meaning, 52, 55, 56, 62, 66, 367n31 +Meaning holism, 365n24 +Measure on space of observers, 354-56 +Measurement postulate, 336-39,341,343-44, +346, 348, 350, 354 +Measurement problem, 338-39, 347 +Measuring apparatus, 338, 342 +Meehl, P. E., 378 +Memory, 10,12, 102, 115-16, 200-201, 217, +221, 326, 352, 354 +Memory of consciousness, 191, 200-201 +Mental causation, 14,150-60. See also +Epiphenomenalism +Mental concepts: division into phenomenal +and psychological concepts, 11-22; double +life of terms, 16-22 +Mental imagery, 9 +Metaphysical necessity, 38-39, 42, 67-68, +131-38,141,143,162,164,166,181,367n34, + + Index +371n7; strong, 136-38, 143,149,156,164, +166,181, 264, 371nn6-7, 372n8, 373nl5, +374n25, 376n35, 377n38; weak, 137,149, +374n25. See also A posteriori necessity; +Logical necessity; +Microjudgment, 232 +Microphenomenal properties, 305-8 +Microtubules, 119 +Mile-high unicycle, 96-97 +Mind-body problem, 4, 24-25, 188 +Mind-mind problem, 25 +Miniworld, 347 +Misdescription of worlds, 67, 99,134,146-49 +Modes of presentation, 141-44, 372nl4 +Module, 113-14, 241, 326 +Molnar, G., 369 +Monism, 129, 130,155, 166 +Moore, G. E., 83, 361 +Moral properties, 83-84, 368nn23-24, 371 n7 +Moral realism, 83-84, 368nn23-24 +Mliller, G. E., 385 +Multiple realizability, 43, 97-98, 364n20 +Musical experience, 7-8, 10, 224, 235 +Mysterianism, 168, 379n42 +Mystery-removing explanation, 48-50 +Nagel, T., vi, 4, 82,103,144, 236, 307, 359, +360, 369, 379, 382 +Names, 84, 368n45 +Narrow content, 65, 384 +Natsoulas, T., 360 +Natural necessity. See Natural possibility +Natural possibility: characterization of, +36-37, 362nn7-8; vs. logical possibility, +37-38, 250, 257, 314-15, 370n9 +Natural supervenience, 88-89, 213, 299, +362nn9-10, 364nl6, 379n42; and dualism, +124-31; and epiphenomenalism, 150-60; +introduction to, 34, 36-38 +Naturalistic dualism, 128,162,168-71, 299 +Necessary and sufficient conditions, 52, +53-55, 77-78, 106 +Necessary truth. See Logical necessity +Negative facts and properties, 40-41, 85, +369n47 +Nelkin, N., 360, 382 +Nemirow, L., 104,144-45, 374 +Neural correlates of consciousness, 115-18, +234, 237, 238-42 +Neural replacement, 248, 253-63, 265-74, +322, 324-26 +Neural rewiring, 100, 265, 273-74, 387nl2 +Neural "time-on" theory, 238-40 +Neuroscience, 46,103,170,289; in explaining +consciousness, 115-18, 234-42 +Neutral monism, 155, 388nl +New physics, 118-20,161-63 +Newell, A., 29 +Newton, I., 118, 171, 245 +Newton, N., 389 + +411 + +Nida-Rumelin, M., 381, 382, 387 +Nietzsche, F., 181 +Noise, 331, 390n9 +Nomic possibility. See Natural possibility +Nomic supervenience. See Natural +supervenience +Nomological danglers, 155, 160 +Nonconceptual content, 220,233,383nlO, 384 +Nonlinear dynamics, 121,157, 255-56, 33031 +Nonlocality, 119, 271, 340, 344, 356, 390n6 +Nonreductive explanation, 107, 111, 120,122, +213-18, 235, 379n42 +Nonreductive materialism, 162,164,166 +Nonseparability, 335, 343 +O'Leary-Hawthorne, J., 372, 380 +O'Regan, J. K., 272 +Occurrent thoughts, 10,20,221-22,309,382n2 +Ockham's razor, 169 +Olfactory experience, 8, 9, 10 +One-big-world interpretation, 347, 390n7. +See also Everett interpretation +1-conceivability, 67-68, 367n23 +1-necessity, 65, 67-69, 132, 367n23 +Ontology, 41-42, 68, 87, 89, 94,110, 123-71, +286-87, 301-8 +Organizational invariance, 248-49, 274-75, +276-77; arguments against, 249-53,263-66, +387nl2, 388nnl3-14; arguments for, +253-63, 266-74; and artificial intelligence, +315,321,328; and information, 287-88; and +quantum mechanics, 350 +Organizational properties, 275, 288, 328 +Orgasm, 9, 384 +Oscillations, 115-16, 238-42, 370nl9 +Other minds, problem of, 74,102,246, 360n9 +Pain, 9, 17, 146-49, 179,182, 221, 224 +Panpsychism, 152-53, 216, 293-301,305, 315, +316, 340, 357 +Papineau, D., 141,143, 166 +Paradox of phenomenal judgment, 177-84, +188,191 +Parfit, D., 353, 355 +Pargetter, R., 143, 371 +Peacocke, C, 383 +Penrose, R., 119, 313-14, 330, 333, 348, 379, +389 +Perception, 3,18,116,184-85,194, 220, 233, +237, 289-91 +Perceptual manifold, 294 +Perry, J., 143, 280 +Person, 300, 352 +Personal identity, 85, 272, 296-97, 352-53, +354-55 +Petrie, B., 39, 88 +Phenomenal concepts, 11-24,133-34,149, +203-8, 360nl3, 380-82, 387n7. See also +Phenomenal judgments + + 412 + +Index + +Phenomenal judgments, 159-60, 172-209, +244, 379-82; in coherence principles, +218-33; content of, 174, 178, 180, 203-8, +380-81; definition of, 173-76; as exhausting +consciousness, 189-91; explanation of, +177-78,184-89, 288-92, 310, 370n9; firstorder, 175-76,182,219-21,231-33,382nnl, +9; justification of, 183,192-200,207-8,292, +380nn6-7, 9; paradox of, 177-84,188, 191; +reliability of, 218-19, 226,257,259,260-61; +second-order, 176, 182, 218-21, 230-32, +382nl; third-order, 176, 182, 291 +Phenomenal manifold, 189, 294 +Phenomenal properties, 11-12, 16-25, +125-28, 135-36, 153-55, 158, 163-64, 166, +304-5, 328, 376-79, 385nlO +Phenomenal quality. See Qualia +Phenomenal/nonphenomenal beliefs, +381nl2, 382nl6 +Phenomenal/psychological states: cooccurrence of, 17-18, 22-24; distinction +between, 11-16, 18, 22, 23; as exhausting +the mental, 16-22; problems posed by, +24-25, 29-30 +Physical properties: definition of, 32-33, +128-29; intrinsic/extrinsic nature of, +135-36, 143, 153-55, 163, 166, 375n29 +Physicalism. See Materialism +Physicalist-functionalism, 168, 376n35, +387nlO, 388nnl6-17 +Physics, 33; autonomy and simplicity of, 49; +causal closure of, 125,128,150,151,156-58, +161-63,178, 183-84; definition of, 118-19, +128-29; in explaining consciousness, +118-20, 126,161-63; as fundamental +theory, 126-29, 213-15, 277; informational +view of, 302-5 +Place, U. T., 146, 148, 360 +Plantinga, A., 366 +Plausibility constraints, 216-18, 219, 226 +Positive facts and properties, 40-41, 42, +123-24, 134, 363nl5, 364nl8 +Possibility of statements vs. of worlds, 63, +65-68 +Possible worlds: characterization of, 35, 66, +361n4, 366n30; containment between, 40, +42, 363nl5, 364nl8; identity between, +361n4, 367n30 +Primary intension, 57-70,365-68; and a priori +conceptual truth, 62, 66, 88; a priori +determination of, 57-58, 61; in arguments +against materialism, 132-37, 372-73; +centrality in reductive explanation, 57, 69, +94,98; of concept of consciousness, 132-34, +202-8, 376nn35-36, 382nl7; definition of, +57, 366n29; indeterminacy of, 365nn23-24, +366n26; indexical nature of, 60-61; in +logical supervenience, 69-70,78-79, 88-89; +and reference-fixation, 57-59,81-82,201-3, +208, 365n23, 373nl5 + +Primary proposition, 63-65 +Private language argument, 360nl2, 368n43, +381nl3 +Program, 315-17, 322-27 +Property dualism, 125, 130,136, 138,155, +164-68, 339, 370n2, 375-78 +Property terms, 62, 69 +Proposition, 19, 63-65, 69, 366n30, 373nl8 +Prepositional attitudes, 19-22. See also Belief +Prosperi, G. M., 341 +Protophenomenal properties, 126-27, +135-36,143, 154-55,166,168, 298-99, 305 +Pseudonormal color vision, 387nll +Psychofunctionalism, 132, 168, 376n36 +Psychological states. See Phenomenal/ +psychological states +Psychology, 12, 13, 31, 112 +Psychons, 158 +Psychophysical laws, 87, 127-29, 138, 155, +170-72, 213-18, 242-46, 275, 276-77, +286-87, 307-10, 316, 377n37, 385-86; +epistemology of, 215-18, 226, 243-46, +310, 386nl2 +Psychophysics, 236, 361nl7, 385-86 +Putnam, H., 56-57, 359, 365, 367, 387, 389 +Pylyshyn, Z., 253 +Qualia, 4, 6, 235, 249-75, 386-88; definition +of, 4, 359n2; natural history of, 235 +Quantum mechanics, 247, 320, 333-57; in +explaining consciousness, 119-21, 333-34, +389n7; framework of, 334-37; and +interactionist dualism, 156-58; +interpretation of, 157, 251,333-34,337-57, +390; measurement in, 335-39, 390n2; +probability in, 337, 341, 343, 344, 353-56, +390nn3,9; and relativity, 119, 340, 344, 356 +Quine, W. V., 52, 55, 60, 88, 366 +Ramsey sentence, 368n38 +Recognitional concept, 373nl5 +Reduction, 43, 88, 364n20 +Reductive explanation, 42-51, 364n20; in +cognitive science, 46-47; by functional +analysis, 43-46; illuminating vs. mysteryremoving explanation, 48-50; link with a +priori analysis, 43-45,51,57,69,94,98,110; +modulo consciousness, 45-46,47,72,371 n2 +Reductive functionalism, 161-62, 164-68 +Reductive materialism, 161-62, 164 +Reference-fixation, 57-59, 61, 81-82, 84-85, +365n23, 366n25, 368n45, 373nl5, 376n36. +See also Primary intension +Reference to consciousness, 191, 201-3, 208 +Registration, 220, 232-33 +Relational properties, 20-21, 80, 153-55, +375n29 +Relative-state interpretation, 347 +Relativity, 58, 118-19, 340, 344, 356, 365n24 +Reliabilism, 194-96 + + Index +Reliability principle, 218-19, 226 +Religious belief, 183,187-88, 379n2 +Rensink, R. A., 272 +Reportability, 26, 28, 30,114, 216-29, 237, +239-40, 285, 290, 385nl2 +Representationalism, 168, 265, 377n38, +384-85 +Revisability, 52, 55-56, 366n28 +Rey, G., 166, 323, 388 +Reynolds, C, 129 +Rigid designation, 59,62,79,132-36,141-12, +146-49, 365n25, 374n26, 376n34, 381nl5 +Rimini, A., 343 +Robinson, H., 166, 372, 375 +Robinson, W. S., 166 +Robot, 249, 253-55, 259 +Rock, 297-99 +Rosenberg, G. H., 152, 375 +Rosenthal, D. M., 30, 166, 230-31, 361, +378 +Rule-following, 313, 329 +Russell, B., 153-54, 166, 305 +Russellian view, 134-36,143,153-55,166-67, +181, 302, 305-8, 310, 375n30, 389nn6-7 +Ryle, G., 14-15, 22-23, 166, 359 +Savage, C. W., 386 +Savitt, S., 253 +Sayre, K. M., 388 +Sayre-McCord, G., 368 +Schacter, D. L., 241 +Schall, J. D., 237 +Schlick, M., 224, 264 +Schrodinger equation, 336-41, 343-50, 354, +356 +Schrodinger's cat, 251, 340, 342 +Seager, W. E., 88, 150, 362, 372, 388 +Searle, J. R., vi, 19,82,130,164,258,314,316, +319, 322-27, 360, 370-71, 375-76 +Second-order judgment, 176,182, 218-21, +230-32, 382nl +Secondary intension, 57-70, 365-67, 372nl3; +a posteriori determination of, 59, 61-62; in +arguments against materialism, 132-37, +141-44,148; of concept of consciousness, +132-34, 205-7, 381nl5; definition of, 59; in +logical supervenience, 69-70, 78-79 +Secondary proposition, 63-65 +Seeming, 190-91, 370n9, 379n5 +Self-consciousness, 3, 10, 27, 29, 30, 116-17, +185, 246, 294-95 +Sellars, W., 306, 378, 380 +Semantic deference, 58 +Sensation, 5-9, 12,18, 22, 45,176, 359n6, +385-86 +Sense and reference, 56, 207 +Sensitive dependence on initial conditions, +255-56, 330-31 +Seyfarth, R. M., 236 +Shallice, T., 114, 241 + +413 + +Shanks, N., 119, 375 +Shannon, C. E., 277-78, 280, 282-83 +Shepard, R. N., 177 +Shoemaker, S., vi, 101,193,375,376,380,381, +382, 387, 388 +SHRDLU, 185 +Sidelle, A., 367 +Siewert, C., 197, 365, 382, 384 +Silicon isomorph, 97, 248, 253-63, 266-74 +Simplicity, 49,169, 214-16, 219, 244-46, +344-45 +Simulation, 76, 157, 313, 327-28 +Skeptical problems, 73-76,194-95, 246, +269-70, 369n48, 380n7 +Skyrms, B., 369 +Sleep, 26, 219, 227-28, 257 +Smart, J. J. C., 146,148,166, 360 +Solipsism, 85, 216, 244, 262 +Sorites arguments, 261, 387n9 +Space-time, 118,126, 303 +Sperling, G., 228 +Sperry, R. W., 378 +Spin, 126, 334-37, 340, 390nl +Splitting-worlds interpretation, 347, 351, +390n7 +Sprigge, T. L. S., 166, 359 +Squires, E., 333 +Stalnaker, R., 56, 64, 366 +Stapp, H. P., 120, 333 +State-transition, 317-20, 324, 389n2 +Stevens, S. S., 385 +Stoerig, P., 228 +Strong artificial intelligence, 314-15,316,319; +arguments against, 322-31, 389nn7-8; +arguments for, 321-22 +Strong metaphysical necessity, 136-38,143, +149,156,164,166,181, 264, 371nn6-7, +372n8, 373nl5, 374n25, 376n35, 377n38 +Structural coherence, 222-25,234-36,242-43, +276, 287-88, 386nl2 +Structural properties, 79-81,107,121, 163 +Subjective experience. See Consciousness +Subspaces, 279, 282, 285 +Substance dualism, 124-25. See also +Interactionist dualism +Substate, 317-19, 350 +Suddenly disappearing qualia, 255-56, 259, +261, 262 +Superbeing, 49, 68, 73, 76 +Superblindsight, 228 +Superficial necessity, 63, 64 +Supermemory module, 326 +Superposition, 334-44,346-57,390; observers +in, 346-51,352-56; preferred basis for, 335, +347, 348 +Superposition principle, 349-50 +Supervenience, xvi-xvii, 32, 361nl, 363nl3, +372nl3; definition of, 32, 40-4l, 361n4; +explaining supervenience relations, 88-89; +local/global distinction, 33-34, 38, 40, 51, + + 414 + +Index + +Supervenience (cont.) +93, 361n3, 362n4, 363n11, 364nl6; logical/ +natural distinction, 34-38,39; and ontology, +41-42; strong and weak, 38,362nl0, 364nl6. +See also Logical supervenience; Natural +supervenience +Supervenience conditionals, 52-56, 108 +Supervenience laws, 127, 128 +Sutherland, N. S., 3 +Swoyer, C, 375 +Syntax vs. semantics, 278, 280, 326-27 +Systems reply, 323-36 +Tactile experience, 8 +Taking consciousness seriously, xiv-xv, 110, +131, 158, 164-65, 167-68,171 +Taste experiences, 9,10, 224, 308 +Teleofunctionalism, 168, 377n38, 378n40, +383nlO +Teleology, 44, 378n40, 386n3 +Teller, D. Y., 385-86 +Teller, P., 39, 88, 141 +Temporally extended activity, 238-40 +Testability, 111, 157,215-18,237,310,386nl2 +Thagard, P., 323 +"That's all" fact, 41, 85-86, 87, 369n47 +Theoretical entities, 75, 158 +Theory of everything, 126 +Thermodynamics, 183, 215, 341 +Thermostat, 281, 293-99, 301, 388n3 +Third-order judgment, 176, 182, 291 +Thomas, L., 359 +Thompson, E., 369 +Thompson, R, 88, 361 +Thought experiments, 251 +Tienson, J. L., 387 +Timmons, M., 84, 369 +Token identity, 147-48, 377n37 +Tooley, M., 152, 369 +Topic-neutral analyses, 135, 360nl3 +Topological structure, 279, 282, 309 +Transworld identity, 367n30, 368n22 +Truth-conditions, 55, 63, 203-4 +Turing machine, 315-19, 331, 390nl0 +Twin Earth, 59, 60, 205, 366n27 +2-conceivability, 67-68, 367n23 +Two-dimensional account of a posteriori +necessity, 56-65; applied to semantics of +thought, 65, 366n29; in arguments against +materialism, 132-38,141-44, 148; +formalization of, 61-62 +2-necessity, 65, 67-69, 132, 367n23 +Two Tubes puzzle, 373nl7 +Tye, M., 141,166, 232, 371, 377, 382, 384-85 +Type identity, 147-48 +Type-A views, 165-68, 377n38, 378n40 +Type-B views, 165-68,181, 377n38, 380n7 +Type-C views, 166-68 +Type-C' views, 166-68, 181 + +UFO, 183, 187 +Uncomputability, 119, 260, 313-14, 322, +329-31 +Unconscious mental states, 3, 13,17, 18 +Vagueness, 53, 77 +Van Cleve, J., 362 +Van Gulick, R., 30, 166, 235 +Velmans, M., 388 +Visual cortex, 115, 226, 234, 238, 240, 272, +284-85, 290, 388nl4 +Visual experiences, 6-7, 220, 223-24, 229, +232-33, 289-91, 384 +Vital spirit, 102, 109 +Vitalism, 108-9, 370n8 +Watery stuff, 57 +Wave function, 119-20, 334-57, 390 +Weber, T., 343 +Weber-Fechner law, 385nl2 +Weinberg, S., 126 +Weiskrantz, L., 226, 228 +"What it is like," 4-6, 145, 231, 359nl +Wheeler, J. A., 302, 388 +White, S. L., 166, 371, 376, 388 +Wigner interpretation, 339, 356-57 +Wigner, E. P., 333, 339, 356 +Wilkes, K. V., 166 +Wilson, M., 364, 365 +Winograd, T., 185 +Wittgenstein, L., 23, 52, 206, 265, 368, 381 +Worlds. See Possible worlds +Wright, R., 389 +X-factor, 244-45, 249 +XYZ, 56 +Y-factor, 247 +Yablo, S., 367 +Zombie: definition of, 94; and evolution, +120-21; and explanatory gap, 107-10; and +explanatory irrelevance, 156, 158; and +knowledge of consciousness, 192-99; +logical possibility of, 94-99, 166, 228, +369nnl-2, 374n24, 376n34, 378n40; and +materialism, 123-24, 130, 140, 146^8; +phenomenal and psychological, 95; +varieties of, 95, 190, 254, 314, 379n4 +Zombie concept of consciousness, 133, 178, +180, 203-5, 380n9 +Zombie judgments, 174, 178, 180-81, 203-4, +208, 289, 384 +Zombie world, 94, 99, 128, 161-63; and +epiphenomenalism, 150, 153, 379n41; and +materialism, 123-24,130-38 +Zuboff, A., 388 +Zurek, W. H., 302 + + \ No newline at end of file