text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
the last effect. |
P5. If a cause is removed from an ordered series of effi cient causes, then |
the effects after that cause are removed as well. |
C3. If there were no fi rst cause, then there would be no subsequent effects |
(instantiation, P4, P5). |
P6. If an ordered series of effi cient causes could precede infi nitely, then there |
would be no fi rst cause. |
C4. If an ordered series of effi cient causes could precede infi nitely, then |
there would be no subsequent effects (hypothetical syllogism, C3, P6). |
P7. But there are subsequent effects. |
C5. An ordered series of effi cient causes cannot precede infi nitely ( modus |
tollens , C4, P7). |
P8. An ordered series of effi cient causes either precedes infi nitely, terminates |
in a cause that causes itself, or terminates in an uncaused cause. |
C6. An ordered series of effi cient causation terminates in an uncaused |
cause (disjunctive syllogism, C2, C5, P8). |
C7. We call that uncaused cause β God β (defi nition). |
14 Timothy J. Pawl |
The Third Way β The Argument from Possibility |
and Necessity |
Aquinas has a specifi c understanding of possibility and necessity in mind |
in the Third Way, and it is not the common understanding in today β s philosophical |
discussions. When Aquinas calls something β necessary, β in this |
argument, he means that it is not subject to generation or corruption. A |
necessary being exists, but it does not come into existence by composition, |
and it cannot cease existing by way of decomposition. Similarly, a possible |
being, in this context, exists, but it does or could have come into existence |
by way of composition, and it can cease to exist by way of decomposition. |
The most debated inference in this argument is the inference from P3 to |
C2. Most commentators who attempt to justify it do so by arguing that |
Aquinas had in mind an implicit premise which, together with P3, entails |
C2. As it stands, without the help of an implicit premise, the inference is |
invalid and commits the fallacy of composition. |
Certain of the things we fi nd in the world are able to exist and able not |
to exist; for some things are found to be generated and corrupted and, as a |
result, they are able to exist and able not to exist. |
But it is impossible that everything should be like this; for that which is |
able not to exist is such that at some time it does not exist. Therefore, if |
everything is such that it is able not to exist, then at some time nothing existed |
in the world. But if this were true, then nothing would exist even now. For |
what does not exist begins to exist only through something that does exist; |
therefore, if there were no beings, then it was impossible that anything should |
have begun to exist, and so nothing would exist now β which is obviously |
false. Therefore, not all beings are able to exist [and able not to exist]; rather, |
it must be that there is something necessary in the world. |
Now every necessary being either has a cause of its necessity from outside |
itself or it does not. But it is impossible to go on to infi nity among necessary |
beings that have a cause of their necessity β in the same way, as was proved |
above, that it is impossible to go on to infi nity among effi cient causes. |
Therefore, one must posit something that is necessary per se , which does not |
have a cause of its necessity from outside itself but is instead a cause of necessity |
for the other [necessary] things. But this everyone calls God. (ST I, q2, |
a3, response) |
P1. Some things are able to be generated or corrupted. |
P2. If some things are able to be generated or corrupted, then it is possible |
for those things either to exist or not to exist. |
C1. It is possible for some things to exist or not to exist ( modus ponens , |
P1, P2). |
Aquinasβ Five Ways 15 |
P3. If, for each thing, it is possible that it not exist, then at some time it |
does not exist. |
C2. If, for each thing, at some time it does not exist, then at some time |
nothing exists (universal generalization, P3). |
P4. If at some time nothing exists, then there would have been nothing to |
cause another thing to exist. |
P5. If there had been nothing to cause another being to exist, then nothing |
could have come into existence. |
P6. If nothing could have come into existence, then nothing would exist |
even now. |
P7. But something does exist now. |
C3. Something could have come into existence ( modus tollens , P6, P7). |
C4. There had to have been something to cause another thing to exist |
( modus tollens, P5, C3). |
C5. At no time did nothing exist ( modus tollens , P4, C4). |
C6. It is not true that, for each thing, at some time it does not exist |
( modus tollens , C2, C5). |
C7. There must be something that is not possible not to exist β that is, |
there must be a necessary being ( modus tollens , P3, C6). |
P8. A necessary being has a cause for its necessity from something else or |
it does not. |
P9. It is not possible for there to be an infi nite series of beings with their |
necessity from something else. |
C8. There must be some necessary being with its necessity not from |
something else (disjunctive syllogism, P8, P9). |
C9. We call that necessary being whose necessity comes from nothing |
else β God β (defi nition). |
The Fourth Way β The Argument from Gradation |
In the Fourth Way, Aquinas relies on two arguments from Aristotle, which |
he does not provide in the text, to justify two of his premises (P3 and P4). |
P1 is observably true. P2 requires a scope restriction. Aquinas seems to be |
saying that any comparative predications of a property entail that there |
exists something that is maximally that property. If this were true, then if |
Bob is fatter than Tom, then there must be something that is maximally fat. |
Worse still, from P4, it would follow that this fattest thing would be the |
cause of all other fat things. It seems better to restrict P2 to perfections and |
then take heat (his example) to be a form of perfection (note that this is |
just an example; one can grant his point while denying that heat is a perfection). |
C4 seems to commit the fallacy of composition. Even if it were proven |
16 Timothy J. Pawl |
that there is a thing that is most good, and a thing that is most noble, and |