Datasets:
Tasks:
Text Generation
Modalities:
Text
Sub-tasks:
language-modeling
Languages:
English
Size:
100K - 1M
License:
section \<open>Introduction\<close> | |
theory AnselmGod | |
imports Main | |
begin | |
text \<open>This paper presents an automated verification of Anselm's ontological argument, as | |
reconstructed by Paul Oppenheimer and Edward Zalta @{cite "oppenheimer_logic_1991"}, in | |
Isabelle/HOL, an interactive theorem prover for higher-order logic. Previously, the argument has being | |
automated by Oppenheimer and Zalta in Prover9 @{cite "oppenheimer_computationally-discovered_2011"}, | |
an automated theorem prover for first-order logic, and by John Rushby in PVS | |
@{cite "rushby_ontological_2013"}, an automated theorem prover for higher-order logic. Automations of | |
other versions of the argument include @{cite "benzmuller_godels_2013"}, @{cite "rushby_mechanized_2016"} | |
and @{cite "fuenmayor_types_2017"}. My purpose here is to present a basis for comparison in the spirit | |
of @{cite "wiedijk_seventeen_2006"}, which compares automated proofs of the irrationality | |
of $\sqrt 2$.\<close> | |
text \<open>Oppenheimer and Zalta's reconstruction is based on the idea of treating `that than | |
which nothing greater can be conceived' as a definite description, and treating definite | |
descriptions as singular terms. But in Isabelle/HOL all terms, including definite descriptions, | |
are assumed to denote. So the main task is to embed a free logic for definite descriptions within | |
Isabelle/HOL. (Previously, a free logic has been embedded into Isabelle/HOL by Christoph | |
Benzmuller and Dana Scott @{cite "benzmuller_automating_2016"}. But theirs differs from Zalta | |
and Oppenheimer's in several ways). Once Isabelle/HOL is equipped with free definite descriptions, | |
reconstructing the argument is straightforward.\<close> | |
section \<open>Free Logic\<close> | |
text \<open>Isabelle treats definite descriptions as singular terms of the form @{term "THE x. \<phi> x"}. | |
However, all terms in Isabelle are assumed to denote, and so from universal elimination we have | |
the validity of the argument form:\<close> | |
lemma "\<forall> x. \<psi> x \<Longrightarrow> \<psi> (THE x. \<phi> x)" by (rule allE) | |
text \<open>In the presence of definite descriptions which do not denote, this argument form is invalid; | |
for example, from `everyone has hair' we should not infer `the present King of France has hair', | |
since the present King of France does not exist.\<close> | |
text \<open>This problem can be avoided by introducing a null individual @{term "n"} to serve as the | |
reference of non-denoting definite descriptions, as follows:\<close> | |
typedecl i \<comment> \<open>the type of individuals\<close> | |
consts n:: "i" ("n") \<comment> \<open>the null individual\<close> | |
text \<open>Then the universal and particular quantifiers can be restricted to | |
individuals excluding the null-individual as follows, where the new free quantifiers | |
are distinguished from the classical quantifiers by bold type:\<close> | |
abbreviation universal_quantifier:: "(i \<Rightarrow> bool) \<Rightarrow> bool" ("\<^bold>\<forall>") | |
where "\<^bold>\<forall> \<phi> \<equiv> \<forall>x::i. (\<not> x = n \<longrightarrow> \<phi> x)" | |
abbreviation universal_syntax:: "(i \<Rightarrow> bool) \<Rightarrow> bool" (binder "\<^bold>\<forall>" [8] 9) | |
where "\<^bold>\<forall> x. \<phi> x \<equiv> \<^bold>\<forall> \<phi>" | |
abbreviation particular_quantifier:: "(i \<Rightarrow> bool) \<Rightarrow> bool" ("\<^bold>\<exists>") | |
where "\<^bold>\<exists> \<phi> \<equiv> \<exists>x::i. (x \<noteq> n \<and> \<phi> x)" | |
abbreviation particular_syntax:: "(i \<Rightarrow> bool) \<Rightarrow> bool" (binder "\<^bold>\<exists>" [8] 9) | |
where "\<^bold>\<exists> x. \<phi> x \<equiv> \<^bold>\<exists> \<phi>" | |
text \<open>Note that the quantifiers here range over both existent and non-existent individuals, whereas | |
the quantifiers in @{cite "benzmuller_automating_2016"} range only over existent individuals.\<close> | |
text \<open>In the free logic employed by Oppenheimer and Zalta, statements of identity in which terms | |
do not denote are always false @{cite "oppenheimer_logic_1991"}, p. 511. So the domain of the identity | |
relation should be restricted to exclude the null-individual:\<close> | |
abbreviation identity:: "i \<Rightarrow> i \<Rightarrow> bool" ("is") | |
where "is x y \<equiv> x \<noteq> n \<and> x = y" | |
abbreviation identity_syntax:: "i \<Rightarrow> i \<Rightarrow> bool" (infix "\<^bold>=" 50 ) | |
where "x \<^bold>= y \<equiv> is x y" | |
text \<open>Once identity is introduced, the uniqueness quantifier can then be defined in the usual way:\<close> | |
abbreviation uniqueness_quantifier:: "(i \<Rightarrow> bool) \<Rightarrow> bool" ("unique") | |
where "unique \<phi> \<equiv> (\<^bold>\<exists> x::i. \<phi> x \<and> (\<^bold>\<forall> y::i. \<phi> y \<longrightarrow> x \<^bold>= y))" | |
abbreviation uniqueness_syntax:: "(i \<Rightarrow> bool) \<Rightarrow> bool" (binder "unique" [8] 9) | |
where "unique x. \<phi> x \<equiv> unique \<phi>" | |
text \<open>Finally, the logic employed by Oppenheimer and Zalta is a negative free logic, in that | |
applications of atomic predicates to non-denoting terms are always false | |
@{cite "oppenheimer_logic_1991"}, p. 511. So it's necessary to introduce a higher-order predicate | |
distinguishing between atomic and non-atomic predicates, and to introduce an axiom stipulating that | |
no atomic predicate is true of the null individual:\<close> | |
consts atomic_predicates:: "(i \<Rightarrow> bool) \<Rightarrow> bool " ("atomic") | |
axiomatization where negativity_constraint: "atomic \<phi> \<Longrightarrow> \<not> \<phi> n" | |
text \<open>In addition, it has to be stated that identity is atomic:\<close> | |
axiomatization where identity_atomic: "\<And> x. atomic (is x)" | |
text \<open>One of the most controversial premises of the ontological argument is that `exists' | |
is a genuine or atomic predicate. But surprisingly, we shall see below that the argument | |
does not require this premise.\<close> | |
section \<open>Definite Descriptions\<close> | |
text \<open>The main idea of Oppenheimer and Zalta's reconstruction of the ontological argument is to | |
treat definite descriptions as genuine singular terms, which leads to the following syntax in | |
Isabelle/HOL:\<close> | |
consts definite_description:: "(i \<Rightarrow> bool) \<Rightarrow> i" ("\<^bold>\<tau>") | |
abbreviation description_syntax:: "(i \<Rightarrow> bool) \<Rightarrow> i" (binder "\<^bold>\<tau>" [8] 9) | |
where "\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<phi> x \<equiv> \<^bold>\<tau> \<phi>" | |
text \<open>In Oppenheimer and Zalta's reconstruction of the argument, definite descriptions | |
are governed by the Russellian axiom schema @{cite "oppenheimer_logic_1991"}, p. 513:\<close> | |
axiomatization where description_axiom: | |
"atomic \<psi> \<Longrightarrow> \<psi> (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<phi> x) \<equiv> (\<^bold>\<exists> x. \<phi> x \<and> (\<^bold>\<forall> y. \<phi> y \<longrightarrow> x \<^bold>= y) \<and> \<psi> x)" | |
text \<open>From this axiom schema, Oppenheimer and Zalta derive two intermediary theorems | |
to be used in the reconstruction of their argument @{cite "oppenheimer_logic_1991"}, pp. 513-4. | |
According to the first:\<close> | |
theorem description_theorem_1: "unique x. \<phi> x \<Longrightarrow> \<^bold>\<exists> y. y \<^bold>= (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<phi> x)" | |
using description_axiom identity_atomic by blast | |
text \<open>The second theorem follows directly from the following lemma:\<close> | |
lemma lemma_1: "a \<^bold>= (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<phi> x) \<Longrightarrow> \<phi> (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<phi> x)" | |
using description_axiom identity_atomic by blast | |
theorem description_theorem_2: "\<^bold>\<exists> x. x \<^bold>= (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<phi> x) \<Longrightarrow> \<phi> (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<phi> x)" | |
by (simp add: lemma_1) | |
text \<open>In the course of verifying the argument using Prover9, Oppenheimer and Zalta discovered | |
a simplified proof which uses instead @{cite "oppenheimer_computationally-discovered_2011"}, p. 345:\<close> | |
theorem description_theorem_3: | |
"atomic \<psi> \<Longrightarrow> \<psi> (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<phi> x) \<Longrightarrow> \<^bold>\<exists> y. y \<^bold>= (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<phi> x)" | |
using negativity_constraint by fastforce | |
text \<open>Notice that it is only this last theorem which presupposes the negativity constraint, | |
whereas the first two theorems depend only on the atomicity of identity.\<close> | |
section \<open>Anselm's Argument\<close> | |
text \<open>The argument proper employs the following non-logical vocabulary:\<close> | |
consts existence:: "i \<Rightarrow> bool" ("E") \<comment> \<open>exists in reality\<close> | |
consts greater_than:: "i\<Rightarrow>i\<Rightarrow>bool" ("G") \<comment> \<open>is greater than\<close> | |
consts conceivable:: "i\<Rightarrow>bool" ("C") \<comment> \<open>exists in the understanding\<close> | |
text \<open>Note that @{term "E a"} is not intended by Oppenheimer and Zalta to be equivalent to | |
@{term "\<^bold>\<exists> x. a = x"} since according to their reading of the argument, some things do not exist | |
in reality @{cite "oppenheimer_logic_1991"}, p. 514.\<close> | |
text \<open>Finally, the presentation of the argument is simplified by introducing | |
the following abbreviation for the predicate `is a being greater than which none can be conceived':\<close> | |
abbreviation none_greater_than :: "i\<Rightarrow>bool" ("\<Phi>") | |
where "\<Phi> x \<equiv> (C x \<and> \<not>(\<^bold>\<exists> y. G y x \<and> C y))" | |
text \<open>With this vocabulary in place, a name for God can be introduced as an abbreviation | |
for the description `the being greater than which none can be conceived':\<close> | |
definition g :: "i" where "g \<equiv> (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x)" | |
text \<open>In Oppenheimer and Zalta's presentation every name is assumed to denote, so a name for | |
God cannot be introduced until it is proved that the description @{term "(\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x)"} denotes | |
@{cite "oppenheimer_logic_1991"}, p, 520. But since it's not assumed in this presentation that every | |
name denotes or, in other words, since it's not assumed that no names denote the null individual, | |
it's not necessary to postpone this step.\<close> | |
text \<open>The final quasi-logical premise in Oppenheimer and Zalta's reconstruction of the argument | |
is the connectivity of `is greater than', which is used in the proof of the following lemma | |
@{cite "oppenheimer_logic_1991"}, p. 518:\<close> | |
lemma lemma_2: | |
assumes connectivity: "\<^bold>\<forall> x. \<^bold>\<forall> y. G x y \<or> G y x \<or> x \<^bold>= y" | |
shows "\<^bold>\<exists> x. \<Phi> x \<Longrightarrow> unique x. \<Phi> x" | |
using connectivity by blast | |
text \<open>Note that \<open>connectivity\<close> disallows any ties with respect to greatness. This is | |
implausible, since you and I, for example, may be equally great, without being the same person. So | |
\<open>connectivity\<close> should not be thought of as merely stipulative, and a weaker premise would | |
be desirable.\<close> | |
text \<open>With this vocabulary in place, Anselm's ontological argument, as reconstructed by | |
Oppenheimer and Zalta, can be stated as follows:\<close> | |
theorem | |
assumes premise_1: "\<^bold>\<exists> x. \<Phi> x" | |
\<comment> \<open>there exists in the understanding a being greater than which | |
none can be conceived\<close> | |
and premise_2: "\<not> E (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<longrightarrow> (\<^bold>\<exists> y. G y (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<and> C y)" | |
\<comment> \<open>if the being greater than which none can be conceived does not exist in reality, | |
then a being exists in the understanding which is greater than the being greater than | |
which none can be conceived\<close> | |
and connectivity: "\<^bold>\<forall> x. \<^bold>\<forall> y. G x y \<or> G y x \<or> x \<^bold>= y" | |
shows "E g" \<comment> \<open>God exists.\<close> | |
text \<open>Isabelle can verify the argument in one line with the command \<open>using premise_1 premise_2 connectivity lemma_1 g_def description_theorem_1 by smt\<close>. | |
But since proofs in Isabelle using \<open>smt\<close> are currently considered impermanent, I instead give Zalta | |
and Oppenheimer's handwritten proof @{cite "oppenheimer_computationally-discovered_2011"}, p. 337:\<close> | |
proof (rule ccontr) | |
assume atheism: "\<not> E g" | |
from premise_1 and connectivity and lemma_2 have "unique x. \<Phi> x" by simp | |
with description_theorem_1 have "\<^bold>\<exists> y. y \<^bold>= (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x)" by simp | |
with description_theorem_2 have "\<Phi> (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x)" by simp | |
hence god_is_greatest: "\<not>(\<^bold>\<exists> y. G y (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<and> C y)" by (rule conjE) | |
from atheism and premise_2 and g_def have "(\<^bold>\<exists> y. G y (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<and> C y)" by simp | |
with god_is_greatest show False.. | |
qed | |
text \<open>Note that neither Oppenheimer and Zalta's proof nor the one line \<open>smt\<close> proof | |
depend on the negativity constraint or whether any of the non-logical vocabulary is atomic | |
(though they do depend indirectly on the atomicity of identity).\<close> | |
section \<open>The Prover9 Argument\<close> | |
text \<open>In the course of verifying the argument using Prover9, Oppenheimer and Zalta | |
discovered a simplified version which employs only \<open>premise_2\<close>, but not \<open>premise_1\<close> | |
or the connectivity of `greater than' @{cite "oppenheimer_computationally-discovered_2011"}.\<close> | |
theorem | |
assumes premise_2: "\<not> E (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<longrightarrow> (\<^bold>\<exists> y. G y (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<and> C y)" | |
shows "E g" nitpick [user_axioms] oops | |
text \<open>However, Isabelle not only fails to verify this argument, but finds a counterexample | |
using \<open>nitpick\<close>. The reason is that it needs to be specified that `greater than' is atomic, | |
in order for \<open>description_theorem_3\<close> to be applicable:\<close> | |
theorem Prover9Argument: | |
assumes premise_2: "\<not> E (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<longrightarrow> (\<^bold>\<exists> y. G y (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<and> C y)" | |
and G_atomic: "\<And> x. atomic (G x)" | |
shows "E g" | |
text \<open>Once the atomicity of `greater than' is added as a premise, a call to \<open>sledgehammer\<close> | |
suggests the following two-step proof, which Isabelle verifies easily:\<close> | |
proof - | |
have "C g \<and> (\<forall>i. i = n \<or> \<not> G i g \<or> \<not> C i) \<or> n = g" | |
by (metis (lifting, full_types) g_def lemma_1) | |
then show ?thesis | |
by (metis (lifting) G_atomic g_def negativity_constraint premise_2) | |
qed | |
text \<open>If provided with all premises, \<open>sledgehammer\<close> still suggests a proof using only | |
\<open>premise_2\<close>:\<close> | |
theorem | |
assumes connectivity: "\<^bold>\<forall> x. \<^bold>\<forall> y. G x y \<or> G y x \<or> x \<^bold>= y" | |
and premise_1: "\<^bold>\<exists> x. \<Phi> x" | |
and premise_2: "\<not> E (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<longrightarrow> (\<^bold>\<exists> y. G y (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<and> C y)" | |
and G_atomic: "\<And> x. atomic (G x)" | |
shows "E g" | |
proof - | |
have "\<Phi> g \<or> n = g" | |
by (metis (lifting, full_types) g_def lemma_1) | |
then show ?thesis | |
by (metis (lifting) G_atomic g_def negativity_constraint premise_2) | |
qed | |
text \<open>Note that this version of the argument does employ the \<open>negativity_constraint\<close>, | |
as well as the premise that identity is atomic via \<open>lemma_1\<close>. So although it has less | |
non-logical premises than the original version of the argument, it has more, and more | |
controversial, logical premises.\<close> | |
section \<open>Soundness\<close> | |
text \<open>Since \<open>premise_1\<close> and the connectivity of `is greater than' are both dispensable, and | |
the atomicity of `is greater than' is not especially controversial, the main non-logical premise | |
of the argument turns out to be \<open>premise_2\<close>. Note that \<open>premise_2\<close> is entailed | |
by God's existence:\<close> | |
theorem | |
assumes theism: "E g" | |
shows "\<not> E (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<longrightarrow> (\<^bold>\<exists> y. G y (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<and> C y)" | |
using g_def theism by auto | |
text \<open>So under the supposition that `is greater than' is atomic, \<open>premise_2\<close> | |
is equivalent to God's existence, suggesting an atheist might wish to reject it as question-begging | |
(see @{cite "oppenheimer_computationally-discovered_2011"}, pp. 348-9 and | |
@{cite "garbacz_prover9s_2012"} for more detailed discussion of this point).\<close> | |
text \<open>However, Ted Parent has pointed out that \<open>premise_2\<close> need not stand on its own, | |
but may be further supported by the following argument @{cite "parent_prover9_2015"}, | |
p. 478:\<close> | |
lemma | |
assumes premise_3: "\<^bold>\<forall> y. \<^bold>\<forall> z. ((E y \<and> \<not> E z) \<longrightarrow> ((y \<^bold>= (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<or> z = (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x)) \<longrightarrow> y = (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x)))" and something_exists: "\<^bold>\<exists> x. E x" and god_is_conceivable: "C g" and C_atomic: "atomic C" | |
shows "\<not> E (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x) \<longrightarrow> (\<^bold>\<exists> y. C y \<and> G y (\<^bold>\<tau> x. \<Phi> x))" | |
by (metis (no_types, lifting) C_atomic description_theorem_3 g_def god_is_conceivable premise_3 something_exists) | |
text \<open>But as Parent says, the premise that `exists in the understanding' is atomic is | |
particularly questionable. If `exists in the understanding' is atomic, then it follows from | |
\<open>description_theorem_3\<close> that, for example, if the largest positive integer exists in | |
the understanding, then something is the largest positive integer. But since `the largest positive | |
integer' is a grammatical description, there is a case to be made that the largest positive integer | |
does exist in the understanding, even though nothing is the largest positive integer | |
@{cite "parent_prover9_2015"}, p. 480-1.\<close> | |
section \<open>Conclusion\<close> | |
text \<open>The main difference between Oppenheimer and Zalta's reconstruction of the argument in | |
Prover9 and the reconstruction presented here in Isabelle/HOL is that whereas Prover9 employs | |
first-order logic, Isabelle/HOL employs higher-order logic. That means that the Russellian | |
\<open>description_axiom\<close> schema can be stated directly in Isabelle/HOL, whereas in Prover9 | |
it has to be represented indirectly using first-order quantifiers ranging over predicates and | |
relations @{cite "oppenheimer_computationally-discovered_2011"}, pp. 338-41.\<close> | |
text \<open>Because of the way Oppenheimer and Zalta carry out this embedding, it is presupposed | |
in their presentation that all the non-logical predicates which occur in their argument are | |
atomic. In contrast, in the presentation in Isabelle/HOL, whenever the assumption that a certain | |
predicate is atomic is needed, this has to be made explicit as a premise of the argument. This | |
is not a merely practical matter since, as Parent points out, the question of whether `exists | |
in the understanding' is an atomic predicate turns out to be crucial.\<close> | |
text \<open>Abstracting from the peculiarities of different software, a surprising result is that | |
whereas every version of the argument requires the premise that identity is atomic, and some | |
versions require the additional premises that `is greater than' is atomic and `exists in the | |
understanding' is atomic, no version of the argument requires the premises that `exists in | |
reality', or in other words `exists' simpliciter, is atomic. This is in spite of the fact that | |
the question of whether `exists' is a genuine predicate has historically being one of the most | |
controversial questions raised by Anselm's argument.\<close> | |
end | |
section \<open>Acknowledgements\<close> | |
text \<open>I thank Bob Beddor, Christoph Benzmuller, Dana Goswick, Frank Jackson, Paul Oppenheimer, | |
Michael Pelczar, Abelard Podgorski, Hsueh Qu, Neil Sinhababu, Weng-Hong Tang, Jennifer Wang, | |
Alastair Wilson and an audience at the University of Sydney for comments on this paper. | |
\<close> | |