Datasets:

Modalities:
Text
Languages:
English
Libraries:
Datasets
License:
zhangir-azerbayev
added books
afd65d6
raw
history blame
14.7 kB
\chapter{Breaking the continuum hypothesis}
We now use the technique of forcing to break the
Continuum Hypothesis by choosing a good poset $\Po$.
As I mentioned earlier, one can also build a model
where the Continuum Hypothesis is true;
this is called the \emph{constructible universe},
(this model is often called ``$V=L$'').
However, I think it's more fun when things break\dots
%\section{Forcing $V \neq L$ is really easy}
%As a small aside, to check we're on the right track we show the following result.
%
%\begin{theorem}[$V \ne L$]
% Let $M$ be a countable transitive model of $\ZFC$.
% Let $\Po \in M$ be \emph{any} splitting poset,
% and let $G \subseteq \Po$ be $M$-generic.
% Then $M[G] \vDash (V \neq L)$.
%\end{theorem}
%\begin{proof}
% Since $L$ has a $\Sigma_1$ definition,
% we have \[ L^{M[G]} = L^M \subseteq M \subsetneq M[G] \]
% where the last part follows from $G \notin M[G]$.
%\end{proof}
%
%Thus $M[G] \vDash \ZFC + (V \ne L)$ for any splitting poset $\Po$,
%and we are one step closer to breaking $\CH$.
\section{Adding in reals}
Starting with a \emph{countable} transitive model $M$.
We want to choose $\Po \in M$ such that $(\aleph_2)^M$ many real numbers appear,
and then worry about cardinal collapse later.
Recall the earlier situation where we set $\Po$ to be the infinite complete binary tree; its nodes can be thought of as partial functions $n \to 2$ where $n < \omega$.
Then $G$ itself is a path down this tree; i.e.\ it can be encoded as a total function $G : \omega \to 2$,
and corresponds to a real number.
\begin{center}
\begin{asy}
size(8cm);
pair P = Drawing("\varnothing", (0,4), dir(90), red);
pair P0 = Drawing("0", (-5,2), 1.5*dir(90), red);
pair P1 = Drawing("1", (5,2), 1.5*dir(90));
pair P00 = Drawing("00", (-7,0), 1.4*dir(120));
pair P01 = Drawing("01", (-3,0), 1.4*dir(60), red);
pair P10 = Drawing("10", (3,0), 1.4*dir(120));
pair P11 = Drawing("11", (7,0), 1.4*dir(60));
pair P000 = Drawing("000", (-8,-3));
pair P001 = Drawing("001", (-6,-3));
pair P010 = Drawing("010", (-4,-3), red);
pair P011 = Drawing("011", (-2,-3));
pair P100 = Drawing("100", (2,-3));
pair P101 = Drawing("101", (4,-3));
pair P110 = Drawing("110", (6,-3));
pair P111 = Drawing("111", (8,-3));
draw(P01--P0--P00);
draw(P11--P1--P10);
draw(P0--P--P1);
draw(P000--P00--P001);
draw(P100--P10--P101);
draw(P010--P01--P011);
draw(P110--P11--P111);
draw(P--P0--P01--P010--(P010+2*dir(-90)), red+1.4);
MP("G", P010+2*dir(-90), dir(-90), red);
\end{asy}
\end{center}
We want to do something similar,
but with $\omega_2$ many real numbers instead of just one.
In light of this, consider in $M$ the poset
\[
\Po = \opname{Add} \left( \omega_2, \omega \right)
\defeq \left( \left\{ p : \omega_2 \times \omega \to 2,
\dom(p) \text{ is finite} \right\},
\supseteq \right).
\]
These elements $p$ (conditions) are ``partial functions'':
we take some finite subset of $\omega_2 \times \omega$ and map it into $2=\{0,1\}$.
(Here $\dom(p)$ denotes the domain of $p$,
which is the finite subset of $\omega_2 \times \omega$ mentioned.)
Moreover, we say $p \le q$ if $\dom(p) \supseteq \dom(q)$
and the two functions agree over $\dom(q)$.
\begin{ques}
What is the maximal element $1_\Po$ here?
\end{ques}
\begin{exercise}
Show that a generic $G$ can be encoded as a function $\omega_2 \times \omega \to 2$.
\end{exercise}
%Let $G \subseteq \opname{Add}(\omega_2, \omega)$ be an $M$-generic.
%We claim that, like in the binary case, $G$ can be encoded as a function $\omega_2 \times \omega \to 2$.
%To see this, consider $\alpha \in \omega_2$ and $n \in \omega$; we have the dense set
%\[ D_{\alpha, n}
% = \left\{ p \in \opname{Add}(\omega_2, \omega)
% \mid (\alpha, n) \in \dom(p) \right\}
%\]
%(this is obviously dense, given any $p$ add in $(\alpha, n)$ if it's not in there already).
%So $G$ hits this dense set, meaning that for every $(\alpha, n)$ there's a function in $G$ which defines it.
%Using the fact that $G$ is upwards closed and a filter, we may as before we may interpret $G$ as a function $\omega_2 \times \omega \to 2$.
\begin{lemma}[$G$ encodes distinct real numbers]
For $\alpha \in \omega_2$ define
\[ G_\alpha = \left\{ n \mid G\left( \alpha,n \right) = 0 \right\} \in \PP(\NN). \]
Then $G_\alpha \neq G_\beta$ for any $\alpha \neq \beta$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
We claim that the set
\[ D = \left\{ q \mid \exists n \in \omega :
q\left( \alpha, n \right) \neq q\left( \beta, n \right)
\text{ are both defined}
\right\} \]
is dense.
\begin{ques}
Check this.
(Use the fact that the domains are all finite.)
\end{ques}
% This is pretty easy to see.
% Consider $p \in \opname{Add}(\omega_2, \omega)$.
% Then you can find an $n$ such that
% neither $(\alpha, n)$ nor $(\beta, n)$ is defined,
% just because $\dom(p)$ is finite.
% Then you make $p'$ as $p$ plus $p'( (\alpha, n) ) = 1$
% and $p'( (\beta, n) ) = 0$.
% Hence the set is dense.
Since $G$ is an $M$-generic it hits this dense set $D$.
Hence $G_\alpha \neq G_\beta$.
\end{proof}
Since $G \in M[G]$ and $M[G] \vDash \ZFC$,
it follows that each $G_\alpha$ is in $M[G]$.
So there are at least $\aleph_2^M$ real numbers in $M[G]$.
We are done once we can show there is no cardinal collapse.
\section{The countable chain condition}
It remains to show that with $\Po = \opname{Add}(\omega, \omega_2)$, we have that
\[ \aleph_2^{M[G]} = \aleph_2^M. \]
In that case, since $M[G]$ will have $\aleph_2^M = \aleph_2^{M[G]}$ many reals, we will be done.
To do this, we'll rely on a combinatorial property of $\Po$:
\begin{definition}
We say that $A \subseteq \mathcal P$ is a \vocab{strong antichain}
if for any distinct $p$ and $q$ in $A$, we have $p \perp q$.
\end{definition}
\begin{example}[Example of an antichain]
In the infinite binary tree,
the set $A = \{00, 01, 10, 11\}$ is a strong antichain
(in fact maximal by inclusion).
\end{example}
This is stronger than the notion of ``antichain'' than you might be used to!\footnote{%
In the context of forcing, some authors use ``antichain'' to refer to ``strong antichain''.
I think this is lame.}
We don't merely require that every two elements are incomparable,
but that they are in fact \emph{incompatible}.
\begin{ques}
Draw a finite poset and an antichain of it which is not strong.
\end{ques}
\begin{definition}
A poset $\Po$ has the \vocab{$\kappa$-chain condition}
(where $\kappa$ is a cardinal) if all strong antichains
in $\Po$ have size less than $\kappa$.
The special case $\kappa = \aleph_1$ is called the \vocab{countable chain condition},
because it implies that every strong antichain is countable.
\end{definition}
We are going to show that if the poset has the $\kappa$-chain condition
then it preserves all cardinals greater than $\kappa$.
% or was it > \kappa?
In particular, the countable chain condition will show that $\Po$ preserves all the cardinals.
Then, we'll show that $\opname{Add}(\omega, \omega_2)$ does indeed have this property.
This will complete the proof.
We isolate a useful lemma:
\begin{lemma}[Possible values argument]
Suppose $M$ is a transitive model of $\ZFC$ and $\Po$ is a partial order
such that $\Po$ has the $\kappa$-chain condition in $M$.
Let $X,Y \in M$ and let $f: X \to Y$
be some function in $M[G]$, but $f \notin M$.
Then there exists a function $F \in M$, with $F: X \to \PP(Y)$ and such that
for any $x \in X$,
\[ f(x) \in F(x) \quad\text{and}\quad \left\lvert F(x) \right\rvert^M < \kappa. \]
\end{lemma}
What this is saying is that if $f$ is some new function that's generated,
$M$ is still able to pin down the values of $f$ to at most $\kappa$ many values.
\begin{proof}
The idea behind the proof is easy: any possible value of $f$ gives us some condition in
the poset $\Po$ which forces it.
Since distinct values must have incompatible conditions,
the $\kappa$-chain condition guarantees
there are at most $\kappa$ such values.
Here are the details.
Let $\dot f$, $\check X$, $\check Y$ be names for $f$, $X$, $Y$.
Start with a condition $p$ such that $p$ forces the sentence
\[ \text{``$\dot f$ is a function from $\check X$ to $\check Y$''}. \]
We'll work just below here.
For each $x \in X$, we can consider (using the Axiom of Choice) a maximal strong antichain $A(x)$
of incompatible conditions $q \le p$ which forces $f(x)$ to equal some value $y \in Y$.
Then, we let $F(x)$ collect all the resulting $y$-values.
These are all possible values, and there are less than $\kappa$ of them.
\end{proof}
\section{Preserving cardinals}
As we saw earlier, cardinal collapse can still occur.
For the Continuum Hypothesis we want to avoid this possibility,
so we can add in $\aleph_2^M$ many real numbers and have $\aleph_2^{M[G]} = \aleph_2^M$.
It turns out that to verify this, one can check a weaker result.
\begin{definition}
For $M$ a transitive model of $\ZFC$ and $\Po \in M$ a poset,
we say $\Po$ \vocab{preserves cardinals} if
$\forall G \subseteq \Po$ an $M$-generic,
the model $M$ and $M[G]$ agree on the sentence ``$\kappa$ is a cardinal'' for every $\kappa$.
Similarly we say $\Po$ \vocab{preserves regular cardinals} if $M$ and $M[G]$
agree on the sentence ``$\kappa$ is a regular cardinal'' for every $\kappa$.
\end{definition}
Intuition:
In a model $M$, it's possible that two ordinals which are in bijection in $V$ are no longer in bijection in $M$.
Similarly, it might be the case that some cardinal $\kappa \in M$ is regular,
but stops being regular in $V$ because some function $f : \ol\kappa \to \kappa$ is cofinal but happened to only exist in $V$.
In still other words, ``$\kappa$ is a regular cardinal '' turns out to be a $\Pi_1$ statement too.
Fortunately, each implies the other.
We quote the following without proof.
\begin{proposition}[Preserving cardinals $\iff$ preserving regular cardinals]
Let $M$ be a transitive model of $\ZFC$.
Let $\Po \in M$ be a poset.
Then for any $\lambda$,
$\Po$ preserves cardinalities less than or equal to $\lambda$
if and only if $\Po$ preserves regular cardinals less than or equal to $\lambda$.
Moreover the same holds if we replace ``less than or equal to''
by ``greater than or equal to''.
\end{proposition}
Thus, to show that $\Po$ preserves cardinality and cofinalities
it suffices to show that $\Po$ preserves regularity.
The following theorem lets us do this:
\begin{theorem}[Chain conditions preserve regular cardinals]
Let $M$ be a transitive model of ZFC, and let $\Po \in M$ be a poset.
Suppose $M$ satisfies the sentence ``$\Po$ has the $\kappa$ chain condition and $\kappa$ is regular''.
Then $\Po$ preserves regularity greater than or equal to $\kappa$.
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}
Use the Possible Values Argument.
\Cref{prob:chain}.
\end{proof}
In particular, if $\Po$ has the countable chain condition then $\Po$ preserves \emph{all} the cardinals (and cofinalities).
Therefore, it remains to show that $\opname{Add}(\omega, \omega_2)$ satisfies the countable chain condition.
\section{Infinite combinatorics}
We now prove that $\opname{Add}(\omega, \omega_2)$ satisfies the countable chain condition.
This is purely combinatorial, and so we work briefly.
\begin{definition}
Suppose $C$ is an uncountable collection of finite sets.
$C$ is a \vocab{$\Delta$-system} if there exists a \vocab{root} $R$
with the condition that for any distinct $X$ and $Y$
in $C$, we have $X \cap Y = R$.
\end{definition}
\begin{lemma}
[$\Delta$-System lemma] Suppose $C$ is an uncountable collection of finite sets.
Then $\exists \ol C \subseteq C$ such that $\ol C$ is an uncountable $\Delta$-system.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
There exists an integer $n$ such that $C$ has uncountably many guys of length $n$.
So we can throw away all the other sets, and just assume that all sets in $C$ have size $n$.
We now proceed by induction on $n$.
The base case $n=1$ is trivial, since we can just take $R = \varnothing$.
For the inductive step we consider two cases.
First, assume there exists an $a \in C$ contained in uncountably many $F \in C$.
Throw away all the other guys.
Then we can just delete $a$, and apply the inductive hypothesis.
Now assume that for every $a$, only countably many members of $C$ have $a$ in them.
We claim we can even get a $\ol C$ with $R = \varnothing$.
First, pick $F_0 \in C$.
It's straightforward to construct an $F_1$ such that $F_1 \cap F_0 = \varnothing$.
And we can just construct $F_2, F_3, \dots$
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}
For all $\kappa$, $\opname{Add}(\omega, \kappa)$ satisfies the countable chain condition.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Assume not. Let
\[ \left\{ p_\alpha : \alpha < \omega_1 \right\} \]
be a strong antichain. Let
\[ C = \left\{ \dom(p_\alpha) : \alpha < \omega_1 \right\}. \]
Let $\ol C \subseteq C$ be such that $\ol C$ is uncountable, and $\ol C$ is a $\Delta$-system with root $R$.
Then let
\[ B = \left\{ p_\alpha : \dom(p_\alpha) \in R \right\}. \]
Each $p_\alpha \in B$ is a function $p_\alpha : R \to \{0,1\}$,
so there are two that are the same.
\end{proof}
Thus, we have proven that the Continuum Hypothesis cannot be proven in $\ZFC$.
\section\problemhead
\begin{problem}
\label{prob:chain}
Let $M$ be a transitive model of ZFC, and let $\Po \in M$ be a poset.
Suppose $M$ satisfies the sentence ``$\Po$ has the $\kappa$ chain condition and $\kappa$ is regular''.
Show that $\Po$ preserves regularity greater than or equal to $\kappa$.
\begin{hint}
Assume not, and take $\lambda > \kappa$ regular in $M$;
if $f : \ol \lambda \to \lambda$,
use the Possible Values Argument on $f$ to generate a function in $M$
that breaks cofinality of $\lambda$.
\end{hint}
\begin{sol}
It suffices to show that $\Po$ preserves regularity greater than or equal to $\kappa$.
Consider $\lambda > \kappa$ which is regular in $M$,
and suppose for contradiction that $\lambda$ is not regular in $M[G]$.
That's the same as saying that there is a function $f \in M[G]$,
$f : \ol \lambda \to \lambda$ cofinal, with $\ol \lambda < \lambda$.
Then by the Possible Values Argument,
there exists a function $F \in M$ from $\ol \lambda \to \PP(\lambda)$
such that $f(\alpha) \in F(\alpha)$ and $\left\lvert F(\alpha) \right\rvert^M < \kappa$
for every $\alpha$.
Now we work in $M$ again.
Note for each $\alpha \in \ol\lambda$,
$F(\alpha)$ is bounded in $\lambda$ since $\lambda$ is regular in $M$ and
greater than $\left\lvert F(\alpha) \right\rvert$.
Now look at the function $\ol \lambda \to \lambda$ in $M$ by just
\[ \alpha \mapsto \cup F(\alpha) < \lambda. \]
This is cofinal in $M$, contradiction.
\end{sol}
\end{problem}