human
stringlengths 301
5k
|
---|
In the case considered, this stimulus was the notion of the
physical continuum, drawn from the rough data of the senses.
But this notion leads to a series of contradictions from which it
is necessary successively to free ourselves. So we are forced to
imagine a more and more complicated system of symbols. That
at which we stop is not only exempt from internal contradiction
(it was so already at all the stages we have traversed), but
neither is it in contradiction with various propositions called intuitive,
which are derived from empirical notions more or less
elaborated. |
So far, I have only considered the order in which our terms
are ranged. But for most applications that does not suffice. We
must learn to compare the interval which separates any two
terms. Only on this condition does the continuum become a
measurable magnitude and the operations of arithmetic applicable. |
This definition is arbitrary in a very large measure. It is not
completely so, however. It is subjected to certain conditions
and, for example, to the rules of commutativity and associativity
of addition. But provided the definition chosen satisfies these
rules, the choice is indifferent, and it is useless to particularize it. |
Further, there are infinitesimals which are infinitely small in
relation to those of the first order, and, on the contrary, infinitely
great in relation to those of order 1 + ε, and that however small
ε may be. Here, then, are new terms intercalated in our series,
and if I may be permitted to revert to the phraseology lately employed
which is very convenient though not consecrated by usage,
I shall say that thus has been created a sort of continuum of the
third order. |
It would be easy to go further, but that would be idle; one
would only be imagining symbols without possible application,
and no one will think of doing that. The continuum of the third
order, to which the consideration of the different orders of infinitesimals
leads, is itself not useful enough to have won citizenship,
and geometers regard it only as a mere curiosity. The mind uses
its creative faculty only when experience requires it. |
One must be very wise not to regard it as evident that every
curve has a tangent; and in fact if we picture this curve and a
straight as two narrow bands we can always so dispose them that
they have a part in common without crossing. If we imagine
then the breadth of these two bands to diminish indefinitely, this
common part will always subsist and, at the limit, so to speak, the
two lines will have a point in common without crossing, that is to
say, they will be tangent. |
Consider any two aggregates of sensations. Either we can
discriminate them one from another, or we can not, just as in
Fechner's experiments a weight of 10 grams can be distinguished
from a weight of 12 grams, but not from a weight of 11 grams.
This is all that is required to construct the continuum of several
dimensions. |
But suppose now that these imaginary animals, while remaining
without thickness, have the form of a spherical, and not of a
plane, figure, and are all on the same sphere without power to get
off. What geometry will they construct? First it is clear they
will attribute to space only two dimensions; what will play for
them the rôle of the straight line will be the shortest path from
one point to another on the sphere, that is to say, an arc of a great
circle; in a word, their geometry will be the spherical geometry. |
If we resume the comparison made above and imagine beings
without thickness living on one of these surfaces, they will regard
as possible the motion of a figure all of whose lines remain constant
in length. On the contrary, such a movement would appear
absurd to animals without thickness living on a surface of variable
curvature. |
Nothing remains then of the objection above formulated.
This is not all. Lobachevski's geometry, susceptible of a concrete
interpretation, ceases to be a vain logical exercise and is capable
of applications; I have not the time to speak here of these applications,
nor of the aid that Klein and I have gotten from them
for the integration of linear differential equations. |
Such, for example, is that of the equality of two figures; two
figures are equal when they can be superposed; to superpose
them one must be displaced until it coincides with the other; but
how shall it be displaced? If we should ask this, no doubt we
should be told that it must be done without altering the shape
and as a rigid solid. The vicious circle would then be evident. |
In fact this definition defines nothing; it would have no meaning
for a being living in a world where there were only fluids.
If it seems clear to us, that is because we are used to the properties
of natural solids which do not differ much from those of the
ideal solids, all of whose dimensions are invariable. |
"It may happen that the motion of a rigid figure is such that
all the points of a line belonging to this figure remain motionless
while all the points situated outside of this line move. Such a
line will be called a straight line." We have designedly, in this
enunciation, separated the definition from the axiom it implies. |
That is perfectly true, but most of these definitions are incompatible
with the motion of a rigid figure, which in the theorem
of Lie is supposed possible. These geometries of Riemann, in
many ways so interesting, could never therefore be other than
purely analytic and would not lend themselves to demonstrations
analogous to those of Euclid. |
We have seen above that we constantly reason as if the geometric
figures behaved like solids. What geometry would borrow
from experience would therefore be the properties of these
bodies. The properties of light and its rectilinear propagation
have also given rise to some of the propositions of geometry,
and in particular those of projective geometry, so that from this
point of view one would be tempted to say that metric geometry
is the study of solids, and projective, that of light. |
1º Because it is the simplest; and it is so not only in consequence
of our mental habits, or of I know not what direct intuition
that we may have of Euclidean space; it is the simplest in
itself, just as a polynomial of the first degree is simpler than one
of the second; the formulas of spherical trigonometry are more
complicated than those of plane trigonometry, and they would
still appear so to an analyst ignorant of their geometric signification. |
Beings with minds like ours, and having the same senses as
we, but without previous education, would receive from a suitably
chosen external world impressions such that they would be led
to construct a geometry other than that of Euclid and to localize
the phenomena of that external world in a non-Euclidean space,
or even in a space of four dimensions. |
As for us, whose education has been accomplished by our
actual world, if we were suddenly transported into this new
world, we should have no difficulty in referring its phenomena to
our Euclidean space. Conversely, if these beings were transported
into our environment, they would be led to relate our
phenomena to non-Euclidean space. |
Sight, however, enables us to judge of distances and consequently
to perceive a third dimension. But every one knows
that this perception of the third dimension reduces itself to the
sensation of the effort at accommodation it is necessary to make,
and to that of the convergence which must be given to the two
eyes, to perceive an object distinctly. |
It has, it is true, precisely three dimensions, which means that
the elements of our visual sensations (those at least which combine
to form the notion of extension) will be completely defined
when three of them are known; to use the language of
mathematics, they will be functions of three independent
variables. |
It is only later, and as a consequence of new experiences, that
we learn how to decompose the bodies of variable form into
smaller elements, such that each is displaced almost in accordance
with the same laws as solid bodies. Thus we distinguish
'deformations' from other changes of state; in these deformations,
each element undergoes a mere change of position, which
can be corrected, but the modification undergone by the aggregate
is more profound and is no longer susceptible of correction
by a correlative movement. |
On the other hand, our body, thanks to the number of its
articulations and muscles, may make a multitude of different
movements; but all are not capable of 'correcting' a modification
of external objects; only those will be capable of it in which our
whole body, or at least all those of our sense-organs which come
into play, are displaced as a whole, that is, without their relative
positions varying, or in the fashion of a solid body. |
But this is not the case; geometry is only the résumé of the
laws according to which these images succeed each other. Nothing
then prevents us from imagining a series of representations,
similar in all points to our ordinary representations, but succeeding
one another according to laws different from those to
which we are accustomed. |
If a sentient being happens to be in the neighborhood, his
impressions will be modified by the displacement of the object,
but he can reestablish them by moving in a suitable manner. It
suffices if finally the aggregate of the object and the sentient
being, considered as forming a single body, has undergone one of
those particular displacements I have just called non-Euclidean.
This is possible if it be supposed that the limbs of these beings
dilate according to the same law as the other bodies of the world
they inhabit. |
If therefore negative parallaxes were found, or if it were
demonstrated that all parallaxes are superior to a certain limit,
two courses would be open to us; we might either renounce
Euclidean geometry, or else modify the laws of optics and suppose
that light does not travel rigorously in a straight line. |
This, in fact, is a property which, in Euclidean or non-Euclidean
space, belongs to the straight and belongs only to it. But
how shall we ascertain experimentally whether it belongs to this
or that concrete object? It will be necessary to measure distances,
and how shall one know that any concrete magnitude
which I have measured with my material instrument really represents
the abstract distance? |
I will explain myself: consider any material system; we shall
have to regard, on the one hand, 'the state' of the various bodies
of this system (for instance, their temperature, their electric
potential, etc.), and, on the other hand, their position in space;
and among the data which enable us to define this position we
shall, moreover, distinguish the mutual distances of these bodies,
which define their relative positions, from the conditions which
define the absolute position of the system and its absolute orientation
in space. |
It is easy to see that this is an idle fear; in fact, to apply
the law of relativity in all rigor, it must be applied to the entire
universe. For if only a part of this universe were considered,
and if the absolute position of this part happened to vary, the
distances to the other bodies of the universe would likewise vary,
their influence on the part of the universe considered would consequently
augment or diminish, which might modify the laws
of the phenomena happening there. |
The state of bodies and their mutual distances at any instant,
as well as the velocities with which these distances vary at this
same instant, will depend only on the state of those bodies and
their mutual distances at the initial instant, and the velocities
with which these distances vary at this initial instant, but they
will not depend either upon the absolute initial position of the
system, or upon its absolute orientation, or upon the velocities
with which this absolute position and orientation varied at the
initial instant. |
Suppose a man be transported to a planet whose heavens were
always covered with a thick curtain of clouds, so that he could
never see the other stars; on that planet he would live as if it
were isolated in space. Yet this man could become aware that it
turned, either by measuring its oblateness (done ordinarily by
the aid of astronomic observations, but capable of being done by
purely geodetic means), or by repeating the experiment of Foucault's
pendulum. The absolute rotation of this planet could
therefore be made evident. |
To know the height of the mainmast does not suffice for calculating
the age of the captain. When you have measured every
bit of wood in the ship you will have many equations, but
you will know his age no better. All your measurements bearing
only on your bits of wood can reveal to you nothing except
concerning these bits of wood. Just so your experiments, however
numerous they may be, bearing only on the relations of
bodies to one another, will reveal to us nothing about the mutual
relations of the various parts of space. |
7. Will you say that if the experiments bear on the bodies,
they bear at least upon the geometric properties of the bodies?
But, first, what do you understand by geometric properties of
the bodies? I assume that it is a question of the relations of the
bodies with space; these properties are therefore inaccessible to
experiments which bear only on the relations of the bodies to one
another. This alone would suffice to show that there can be no
question of these properties. |
Still let us begin by coming to an understanding about the
sense of the phrase: geometric properties of bodies. When I
say a body is composed of several parts, I assume that I do not
enunciate therein a geometric property, and this would remain
true even if I agreed to give the improper name of points to the
smallest parts I consider. |
These are determinations we may make without having in
advance any notion about form or about the metric properties of
space. They in no wise bear on the 'geometric properties of
bodies.' And these determinations will not be possible if the
bodies experimented upon move in accordance with a group
having the same structure as the Lobachevskian group (I mean
according to the same laws as solid bodies in Lobachevski's geometry).
They suffice therefore to prove that these bodies move in
accordance with the Euclidean group, or at least that they do
not move according to the Lobachevskian group. |
Therefore these new determinations are not possible if the
bodies move according to the Euclidean group; but they become
so if it be supposed that the bodies move according to the Lobachevskian
group. They would suffice, therefore (if one made
them), to prove that the bodies in question do not move according
to the Euclidean group. |
Thus, without making any hypothesis about form, about the
nature of space, about the relations of bodies to space, and without
attributing to bodies any geometric property, I have made
observations which have enabled me to show in one case that
the bodies experimented upon move according to a group whose
structure is Euclidean, in the other case that they move according
to a group whose structure is Lobachevskian. |
In fact one could imagine (I say imagine) bodies moving so
as to render possible the second series of determinations. And
the proof is that the first mechanician met could construct such
bodies if he cared to take the pains and make the outlay. You
will not conclude from that, however, that space is non-Euclidean. |
And in fact, the object, although moved away, may form its
image at the same point of the retina. Sight responds yes, the
object has remained at the same point and touch answers no,
because my finger which just now touched the object, at present
touches it no longer. If experience had shown us that one finger
may respond no when the other says yes, we should likewise
say that touch acts at a distance. |
To each attitude corresponds thus a point; but it often happens
that the same point corresponds to several different attitudes (in
this case we say our finger has not budged, but the rest of the
body has moved). We distinguish, therefore, among the changes
of attitude those where the finger does not budge. How are we
led thereto? It is because often we notice that in these changes
the object which is in contact with the finger remains in contact
with it. |
In our mind pre-existed the latent idea of a certain number
of groups—those whose theory Lie has developed. Which group
shall we choose, to make of it a sort of standard with which to
compare natural phenomena? And, this group chosen, which of
its sub-groups shall we take to characterize a point of space? Experience
has guided us by showing us which choice best adapts
itself to the properties of our body. But its rôle is limited to that. |
4º Finally, our Euclidean geometry is itself only a sort of
convention of language; mechanical facts might be enunciated
with reference to a non-Euclidean space which would be a guide
less convenient than, but just as legitimate as, our ordinary
space; the enunciation would thus become much more complicated,
but it would remain possible. |
Teachers of mechanics usually pass rapidly over the example
of the ball; but they add that the principle of inertia is verified
indirectly by its consequences. They express themselves badly;
they evidently mean it is possible to verify various consequences
of a more general principle, of which that of inertia is only a
particular case. |
In the first case, we must suppose that the velocity of a body
depends only upon its position and upon that of the neighboring
bodies; in the second case that the change of acceleration of a
body depends only upon the position of this body and of the
neighboring bodies, upon their velocities and upon their accelerations. |
Let us slightly modify our fiction. Suppose a world analogous
to our solar system, but where, by a strange chance, the orbits of
all the planets are without eccentricity and without inclination.
Suppose further that the masses of these planets are too slight
for their mutual perturbations to be sensible. Astronomers inhabiting
one of these planets could not fail to conclude that the
orbit of a star can only be circular and parallel to a certain plane;
the position of a star at a given instant would then suffice to determine
its velocity and its whole path. The law of inertia which
they would adopt would be the first of the two hypothetical laws
I have mentioned. |
Imagine now that this system is some day traversed with great
velocity by a body of vast mass, coming from distant constellations.
All the orbits would be profoundly disturbed. Still our
astronomers would not be too greatly astonished; they would very
well divine that this new star was alone to blame for all the
mischief. "But," they would say, "when it is gone, order will
of itself be reestablished; no doubt the distances of the planets
from the sun will not revert to what they were before the cataclysm,
but when the perturbing star is gone, the orbits will again
become circular." |
For this principle to be only in appearance true, for one to
have cause to dread having some day to replace it by one of the
analogous principles I have just now contrasted with it, would be
necessary our having been misled by some amazing chance, like
that which, in the fiction above developed, led into error our
imaginary astronomers. |
Such a hypothesis is too unlikely to delay over. No one will
believe that such coincidences can happen; no doubt the probability
of two eccentricities being both precisely null, to within
errors of observation, is not less than the probability of one being
precisely equal to 0.1, for instance, and the other to 0.2, to within
errors of observation. The probability of a simple event is not
less than that of a complicated event; and yet, if the first happens,
we shall not consent to attribute it to chance; we should not
believe that nature had acted expressly to deceive us. The hypothesis
of an error of this sort being discarded, it may therefore
be admitted that in so far as astronomy is concerned, our law has
been verified by experiment. |
There it seems we have a means of defining mass; the position
of the center of gravity evidently depends on the values attributed
to the masses; it will be necessary to dispose of these values
in such a way that the motion of the center of gravity may be
rectilinear and uniform; this will always be possible if Newton's
third law is true, and possible in general only in a single way. |
We could reconstruct all mechanics by attributing different
values to all the masses. This new mechanics would not be in
contradiction either with experience or with the general principles
of dynamics (principle of inertia, proportionality of
forces to masses and to accelerations, equality of action and
reaction, rectilinear and uniform motion of the center of gravity,
principle of areas). |
Hertz has raised the question whether the principles of mechanics
are rigorously true. "In the opinion of many physicists,"
he says, "it is inconceivable that the remotest experience
should ever change anything in the immovable principles of
mechanics; and yet, what comes from experience may always
be rectified by experience." After what we have just said, these
fears will appear groundless. |
Whatever does not teach us to measure it is as useless to
mechanics as is, for instance, the subjective notion of warmth
and cold to the physicist who is studying heat. This subjective
notion can not be translated into numbers, therefore it is of no
use; a scientist whose skin was an absolutely bad conductor of
heat and who, consequently, would never have felt either sensations
of cold or sensations of warmth, could read a thermometer
just as well as any one else, and that would suffice him for constructing
the whole theory of heat. |
But, after all, what have we done? We have defined the
force to which the thread is subjected by the deformation undergone
by this thread, which is reasonable enough; we have further
assumed that if a body is attached to this thread, the effort transmitted
to it by the thread is equal to the action this body exercises
on this thread; after all, we have therefore used the principle of
the equality of action and reaction, in considering it, not as an
experimental truth, but as the very definition of force. |
All forces are not transmitted by threads (besides, to be able
to compare them, they would all have to be transmitted by identical
threads). Even if it should be conceded that the earth is
attached to the sun by some invisible thread, at least it would be
admitted that we have no means of measuring its elongation. |
Why then take this détour? You admit a certain definition
of force which has a meaning only in certain particular cases.
In these cases you verify by experiment that it leads to the law
of acceleration. On the strength of this experiment, you then
take the law of acceleration as a definition of force in all the
other cases. |
Would it not be simpler to consider the law of acceleration as
a definition in all cases, and to regard the experiments in question,
not as verifications of this law, but as verifications of the
principle of reaction, or as demonstrating that the deformations
of an elastic body depend only on the forces to which this body is
subjected? |
Andrade's ideas are nevertheless very interesting; if they
do not satisfy our logical craving, they make us understand
better the historic genesis of the fundamental ideas of mechanics.
The reflections they suggest show us how the human mind has
raised itself from a naïve anthropomorphism to the present conceptions
of science. |
Are the law of acceleration, the rule of the composition of
forces then only arbitrary conventions? Conventions, yes; arbitrary,
no; they would be if we lost sight of the experiments which
led the creators of the science to adopt them, and which, imperfect
as they may be, suffice to justify them. It is well that from
time to time our attention is carried back to the experimental
origin of these conventions. |
Assume it then, and consider a body subjected to a force;
the relative motion of this body, in reference to an observer
moving with a uniform velocity equal to the initial velocity of
the body, must be identical to what its absolute motion would be
if it started from rest. We conclude hence that its acceleration
can not depend upon its absolute velocity; the attempt has even
been made to derive from this a demonstration of the law of
acceleration. |
There long were traces of this demonstration in the regulations
for the degree B. ès Sc. It is evident that this attempt is
idle. The obstacle which prevented our demonstrating the law
of acceleration is that we had no definition of force; this obstacle
subsists in its entirety, since the principle invoked has not furnished
us the definition we lacked. |
Thus enunciated, in fact, the principle of relative motion
singularly resembles what I called above the generalized principle
of inertia; it is not altogether the same thing, since it is a question
of the differences of coordinates and not of the coordinates
themselves. The new principle teaches us therefore something
more than the old, but the same discussion is applicable and
would lead to the same conclusions; it is unnecessary to return
to it. |
I will pause longer on the case of relative motions referred to
axes which rotate uniformly. If the heavens were always
covered with clouds, if we had no means of observing the stars,
we nevertheless might conclude that the earth turns round; we
could learn this from its flattening or again by the Foucault pendulum
experiment. |
Many difficulties, however, would soon awaken their attention;
if they succeeded in realizing an isolated system, the center of
gravity of this system would not have an almost rectilinear path.
They would invoke, to explain this fact, the centrifugal forces
which they would regard as real, and which they would attribute
no doubt to the mutual actions of the bodies. Only they would
not see these forces become null at great distances, that is to say
in proportion as the isolation was better realized; far from it;
centrifugal force increases indefinitely with the distance. |
But this is not all. Space is symmetric, and yet the laws of
motion would not show any symmetry; they would have to distinguish
between right and left. It would be seen for instance
that cyclones turn always in the same sense, whereas by reason
of symmetry these winds should turn indifferently in one sense
and in the other. If our scientists by their labor had succeeded
in rendering their universe perfectly symmetric, this symmetry
would not remain, even though there was no apparent reason
why it should be disturbed in one sense rather than in the other. |
They would get themselves out of the difficulty doubtless, they
would invent something which would be no more extraordinary
than the glass spheres of Ptolemy, and so it would go on, complications
accumulating, until the long-expected Copernicus
sweeps them all away at a single stroke, saying: It is much
simpler to assume the earth turns round. |
And just as our Copernicus said to us: It is more convenient
to suppose the earth turns round, since thus the laws of astronomy
are expressible in a much simpler language; this one would
say: It is more convenient to suppose the earth turns round,
since thus the laws of mechanics are expressible in a much
simpler language. |
We have seen that the coordinates of bodies are determined
by differential equations of the second order, and that so are the
differences of these coordinates. This is what we have called
the generalized principle of inertia and the principle of relative
motion. If the distances of these bodies were determined likewise
by equations of the second order, it seems that the mind
ought to be entirely satisfied. In what measure does the mind
get this satisfaction and why is it not content with it? |
But here two different points of view may be taken; we may
distinguish two sorts of constants. To the eyes of the physicist
the world reduces to a series of phenomena, depending, on the
one hand, solely upon the initial phenomena; on the other hand,
upon the laws which bind the consequents to the antecedents.
If then observation teaches us that a certain quantity is a constant,
we shall have the choice between two conceptions. |
For example, in virtue of Newton's laws, the duration of the
revolution of the earth must be constant. But if it is 366
sidereal days and something over, and not 300 or 400, this is in
consequence of I know not what initial chance. This is an
accidental constant. If, on the contrary, the exponent of the
distance which figures in the expression of the attractive force is
equal to −2 and not to −3, this is not by chance, but because
Newton's law requires it. This is an essential constant. |
A word in passing to forestall an objection: the inhabitants
of this imaginary world could neither observe nor define the
area-constant as we do, since the absolute longitudes escape them;
that would not preclude their being quickly led to notice a certain
constant which would introduce itself naturally into their
equations and which would be nothing but what we call the area-constant. |
But then see what would happen. If the area-constant is
regarded as essential, as depending upon a law of nature, to calculate
the distances of the planets at any instant it will suffice
to know the initial values of these distances and those of their
first derivatives. From this new point of view, the distances will
be determined by differential equations of the second order. |
Yet would the mind of these astronomers be completely satisfied?
I do not believe so; first, they would soon perceive that
in differentiating their equations and thus raising their order,
these equations became much simpler. And above all they would
be struck by the difficulty which comes from symmetry. It
would be necessary to assume different laws, according as the
aggregate of the planets presented the figure of a certain polyhedron
or of the symmetric polyhedron, and one would escape from
this consequence only by regarding the area-constant as accidental. |
I have taken a very special example, since I have supposed
astronomers who did not at all consider terrestrial mechanics,
and whose view was limited to the solar system. Our universe is
more extended than theirs, as we have fixed stars, but still it too
is limited, and so we might reason on the totality of our universe
as the astronomers on their solar system. |
If we will not admit that this may be simply one of the second
derivatives, we have only the choice of hypotheses. Either it
may be supposed, as is ordinarily done, that this something else
is the absolute orientation of the universe in space, or the rapidity
with which this orientation varies; and this supposition may be
correct; it is certainly the most convenient solution for geometry;
it is not the most satisfactory for the philosopher, because
this orientation does not exist. |
Or it may be supposed that this something else is the position
or the velocity of some invisible body; this has been done by
certain persons who have even called it the body alpha, although
we are doomed never to know anything of this body but its
name. This is an artifice entirely analogous to that of which I
spoke at the end of the paragraph devoted to my reflections on
the principle of inertia. |
Suppose an isolated system formed of a certain number of
material points; suppose these points subjected to forces depending
only on their relative position and their mutual distances,
and independent of their velocities. In virtue of the principle
of the conservation of energy, a function of forces must exist. |
In this simple case the enunciation of the principle of the
conservation of energy is of extreme simplicity. A certain quantity,
accessible to experiment, must remain constant. This quantity
is the sum of two terms; the first depends only on the position
of the material points and is independent of their velocities;
the second is proportional to the square of these velocities. This
resolution can take place only in a single way. |
This molecule seems to know the point whither it is to go, to
foresee the time it would take to reach it by such and such
a route, and then to choose the most suitable path. The statement
presents the molecule to us, so to speak, as a living and
free being. Clearly it would be better to replace it by an enunciation
less objectionable, and where, as the philosophers would
say, final causes would not seem to be substituted for efficient
causes. |
If the system is not regarded as completely isolated, it is
probable that the rigorously exact expression of its internal
energy will depend on the state of the external bodies. Again,
I have above supposed the sum of the external work was null,
and if we try to free ourselves from this rather artificial restriction,
the enunciation becomes still more difficult. |
But this word reminds me that I am digressing and am on
the point of leaving the domain of mathematics and physics. I
check myself therefore and will stress of all this discussion only
one impression, that Mayer's law is a form flexible enough for
us to put into it almost whatever we wish. By that I do not mean
it corresponds to no objective reality, nor that it reduces itself
to a mere tautology, since, in each particular case, and provided
one does not try to push to the absolute, it has a perfectly clear
meaning. |
Almost everything I have just said applies to the principle
of Clausius. What distinguishes it is that it is expressed by
an inequality. Perhaps it will be said it is the same with all
physical laws, since their precision is always limited by errors
of observation. But they at least claim to be first approximations,
and it is hoped to replace them little by little by laws more
and more precise. If, on the other hand, the principle of Clausius
reduces to an inequality, this is not caused by the imperfection
of our means of observation, but by the very nature of
the question. |
If these postulates possess a generality and a certainty which
are lacking to the experimental verities whence they are drawn,
this is because they reduce in the last analysis to a mere convention
which we have the right to make, because we are certain
beforehand that no experiment can ever contradict it. |
At first blush, the analogy is complete; the rôle of experiment
seems the same. One will therefore be tempted to say:
Either mechanics must be regarded as an experimental science,
and then the same must hold for geometry; or else, on the contrary,
geometry is a deductive science, and then one may say as
much of mechanics. |
On the contrary, the fundamental conventions of mechanics,
and the experiments which prove to us that they are convenient,
bear on exactly the same objects or on analogous objects. The
conventional and general principles are the natural and direct
generalization of the experimental and particular principles. |
Let it not be said that thus I trace artificial frontiers between
the sciences; that if I separate by a barrier geometry properly
so called from the study of solid bodies, I could just as well erect
one between experimental mechanics and the conventional mechanics
of the general principles. In fact, who does not see that
in separating these two sciences I mutilate them both, and that
what will remain of conventional mechanics when it shall be
isolated will be only a very small thing and can in no way be compared
to that superb body of doctrine called geometry? |
Besides, if we study mechanics, it is to apply it; and we can
apply it only if it remains objective. Now, as we have seen, what
the principles gain in generality and certainty they lose in objectivity.
It is, therefore, above all with the objective side of the
principles that we must be familiarized early, and that can be
done only by going from the particular to the general, instead of
the inverse. |
And above all the scientist must foresee. Carlyle has somewhere
said something like this: "Nothing but facts are of importance.
John Lackland passed by here. Here is something
that is admirable. Here is a reality for which I would give all
the theories in the world." Carlyle was a fellow countryman of
Bacon; but Bacon would not have said that. That is the language
of the historian. The physicist would say rather: "John Lackland
passed by here; that makes no difference to me, for he
never will pass this way again." |
For without generalization foreknowledge is impossible. The
circumstances under which one has worked will never reproduce
themselves all at once. The observed action then will never recur;
the only thing that can be affirmed is that under analogous circumstances
an analogous action will be produced. In order to
foresee, then, it is necessary to invoke at least analogy, that is to
say, already then to generalize. |
It is often said experiments must be made without a preconceived
idea. That is impossible. Not only would it make
all experiment barren, but that would be attempted which could
not be done. Every one carries in his mind his own conception
of the world, of which he can not so easily rid himself. We must,
for instance, use language; and our language is made up only of
preconceived ideas and can not be otherwise. Only these are
unconscious preconceived ideas, a thousand times more dangerous
than the others. |
Shall we say that if we introduce others, of which we are
fully conscious, we shall only aggravate the evil? I think not.
I believe rather that they will serve as counterbalances to each
other—I was going to say as antidotes; they will in general accord
ill with one another—they will come into conflict with one another,
and thereby force us to regard things under different
aspects. This is enough to emancipate us. He is no longer a
slave who can choose his master. |
It is clear that any fact can be generalized in an infinity of
ways, and it is a question of choice. The choice can be guided
only by considerations of simplicity. Let us take the most commonplace
case, that of interpolation. We pass a continuous line,
as regular as possible, between the points given by observation.
Why do we avoid points making angles and too abrupt turns?
Why do we not make our curve describe the most capricious zig-zags?
It is because we know beforehand, or believe we know, that
the law to be expressed can not be so complicated as all that. |
We may calculate the mass of Jupiter from either the movements
of its satellites, or the perturbations of the major planets,
or those of the minor planets. If we take the averages of the
determinations obtained by these three methods, we find three
numbers very close together, but different. We might interpret
this result by supposing that the coefficient of gravitation is not
the same in the three cases. The observations would certainly be
much better represented. Why do we reject this interpretation?
Not because it is absurd, but because it is needlessly complicated.
We shall only accept it when we are forced to, and that is not yet. |
This custom is imposed upon physicists by the causes that I
have just explained. But how shall we justify it in the presence
of discoveries that show us every day new details that are richer
and more complex? How shall we even reconcile it with the
belief in the unity of nature? For if everything depends on
everything, relationships where so many diverse factors enter can
no longer be simple. |
Examples of the opposite abound. In the kinetic theory of
gases, one deals with molecules moving with great velocities,
whose paths, altered by incessant collisions, have the most capricious
forms and traverse space in every direction. The observable
result is Mariotte's simple law. Every individual fact was complicated.
The law of great numbers has reestablished simplicity
in the average. Here the simplicity is merely apparent, and only
the coarseness of our senses prevents our perceiving the complexity. |
Many phenomena obey a law of proportionality. But why?
Because in these phenomena there is something very small. The
simple law observed, then, is only a result of the general analytical
rule that the infinitely small increment of a function is
proportional to the increment of the variable. As in reality our
increments are not infinitely small, but very small, the law of
proportionality is only approximate, and the simplicity is only
apparent. What I have just said applies to the rule of the superposition
of small motions, the use of which is so fruitful, and
which is the basis of optics. |
And Newton's law itself? Its simplicity, so long undetected,
is perhaps only apparent. Who knows whether it is not due to
some complicated mechanism, to the impact of some subtile matter
animated by irregular movements, and whether it has not become
simple only through the action of averages and of great numbers?
In any case, it is difficult not to suppose that the true law
contains complementary terms, which would become sensible at
small distances. If in astronomy they are negligible as modifying
Newton's law, and if the law thus regains its simplicity, it
would be only because of the immensity of celestial distances. |
For that purpose, let us see what part is played in our generalizations
by the belief in simplicity. We have verified a simple
law in a good many particular cases; we refuse to admit that this
agreement, so often repeated, is simply the result of chance, and
conclude that the law must be true in the general case. |
What does it matter then whether the simplicity be real, or
whether it covers a complex reality? Whether it is due to the
influence of great numbers, which levels down individual differences,
or to the greatness or smallness of certain quantities, which
allows us to neglect certain terms, in no case is it due to chance.
This simplicity, real or apparent, always has a cause. We can
always follow, then, the same course of reasoning, and if a simple
law has been observed in several particular cases, we can legitimately
suppose that it will still be true in analogous cases. To
refuse to do this would be to attribute to chance an inadmissible
rôle. |
There is, however, a difference. If the simplicity were real
and essential, it would resist the increasing precision of our means
of measure. If then we believe nature to be essentially simple,
we must, from a simplicity that is approximate, infer a simplicity
that is rigorous. This is what was done formerly; and this is
what we no longer have a right to do. |
Well, even this ill humor is not justified. The physicist who
has just renounced one of his hypotheses ought, on the contrary,
to be full of joy; for he has found an unexpected opportunity
for discovery. His hypothesis, I imagine, had not been adopted
without consideration; it took account of all the known factors
that it seemed could enter into the phenomenon. If the test does
not support it, it is because there is something unexpected and
extraordinary; and because there is going to be something found
that is unknown and new. |
Has the discarded hypothesis, then, been barren? Far from
that, it may be said it has rendered more service than a true
hypothesis. Not only has it been the occasion of the decisive
experiment, but, without having made the hypothesis, the experiment
would have been made by chance, so that nothing would
have been derived from it. One would have seen nothing extraordinary;
only one fact the more would have been catalogued
without deducing from it the least consequence. |