human
stringlengths 301
5k
|
---|
The progress of science has seemed to imperil the best established
principles, those even which were regarded as fundamental.
Yet nothing shows they will not be saved; and if this comes about
only imperfectly, they will still subsist even though they are
modified. The advance of science is not comparable to the changes
of a city, where old edifices are pitilessly torn down to give place
to new, but to the continuous evolution of zoologic types which
develop ceaselessly and end by becoming unrecognizable to the
common sight, but where an expert eye finds always traces of the
prior work of the centuries past. One must not think then that
the old-fashioned theories have been sterile and vain. |
Does the harmony the human intelligence thinks it discovers
in nature exist outside of this intelligence? No, beyond doubt
a reality completely independent of the mind which conceives it,
sees or feels it, is an impossibility. A world as exterior as that,
even if it existed, would for us be forever inaccessible. But what
we call objective reality is, in the last analysis, what is common
to many thinking beings, and could be common to all; this common
part, we shall see, can only be the harmony expressed by
mathematical laws. It is this harmony then which is the sole
objective reality, the only truth we can attain; and when I add
that the universal harmony of the world is the source of all
beauty, it will be understood what price we should attach to the
slow and difficult progress which little by little enables us to know
it better. |
It is impossible to study the works of the great mathematicians,
or even those of the lesser, without noticing and distinguishing
two opposite tendencies, or rather two entirely different kinds of
minds. The one sort are above all preoccupied with logic; to
read their works, one is tempted to believe they have advanced
only step by step, after the manner of a Vauban who pushes
on his trenches against the place besieged, leaving nothing to
chance. The other sort are guided by intuition and at the first
stroke make quick but sometimes precarious conquests, like bold
cavalrymen of the advance guard. |
M. Méray wants to prove that a binomial equation always has
a root, or, in ordinary words, that an angle may always be subdivided.
If there is any truth that we think we know by direct
intuition, it is this. Who could doubt that an angle may always
be divided into any number of equal parts? M. Méray does not
look at it that way; in his eyes this proposition is not at all evident
and to prove it he needs several pages. |
On the other hand, look at Professor Klein: he is studying one
of the most abstract questions of the theory of functions: to determine
whether on a given Riemann surface there always exists a
function admitting of given singularities. What does the celebrated
German geometer do? He replaces his Riemann surface
by a metallic surface whose electric conductivity varies according
to certain laws. He connects two of its points with the two poles
of a battery. The current, says he, must pass, and the distribution
of this current on the surface will define a function whose
singularities will be precisely those called for by the enunciation. |
Doubtless Professor Klein well knows he has given here only
a sketch; nevertheless he has not hesitated to publish it; and he
would probably believe he finds in it, if not a rigorous demonstration,
at least a kind of moral certainty. A logician would
have rejected with horror such a conception, or rather he would
not have had to reject it, because in his mind it would never have
originated. |
Again, permit me to compare two men, the honor of French
science, who have recently been taken from us, but who both
entered long ago into immortality. I speak of M. Bertrand and
M. Hermite. They were scholars of the same school at the same
time; they had the same education, were under the same influences;
and yet what a difference! Not only does it blaze forth
in their writings; it is in their teaching, in their way of speaking,
in their very look. In the memory of all their pupils these two
faces are stamped in deathless lines; for all who have had the
pleasure of following their teaching, this remembrance is still
fresh; it is easy for us to evoke it. |
Among the German geometers of this century, two names above
all are illustrious, those of the two scientists who founded the
general theory of functions, Weierstrass and Riemann. Weierstrass
leads everything back to the consideration of series and
their analytic transformations; to express it better, he reduces
analysis to a sort of prolongation of arithmetic; you may turn
through all his books without finding a figure. Riemann, on the
contrary, at once calls geometry to his aid; each of his conceptions
is an image that no one can forget, once he has caught its
meaning. |
The two sorts of minds are equally necessary for the progress
of science; both the logicians and the intuitionalists have achieved
great things that others could not have done. Who would venture
to say whether he preferred that Weierstrass had never
written or that there had never been a Riemann? Analysis and
synthesis have then both their legitimate rôles. But it is interesting
to study more closely in the history of science the part
which belongs to each. |
What is the cause of this evolution? It is not hard to find.
Intuition can not give us rigor, nor even certainty; this has been
recognized more and more. Let us cite some examples. We know
there exist continuous functions lacking derivatives. Nothing is
more shocking to intuition than this proposition which is imposed
upon us by logic. Our fathers would not have failed to say: "It
is evident that every continuous function has a derivative, since
every curve has a tangent." |
How can intuition deceive us on this point? It is because when
we seek to imagine a curve we can not represent it to ourselves
without width; just so, when we represent to ourselves a straight
line, we see it under the form of a rectilinear band of a certain
breadth. We well know these lines have no width; we try to
imagine them narrower and narrower and thus to approach the
limit; so we do in a certain measure, but we shall never attain
this limit. And then it is clear we can always picture these two
narrow bands, one straight, one curved, in a position such that
they encroach slightly one upon the other without crossing. We
shall thus be led, unless warned by a rigorous analysis, to conclude
that a curve always has a tangent. |
But it would not be the same had we used concrete images,
had we, for example, considered this function as an electric potential;
it would have been thought legitimate to affirm that electrostatic
equilibrium can be attained. Yet perhaps a physical comparison
would have awakened some vague distrust. But if care
had been taken to translate the reasoning into the language of
geometry, intermediate between that of analysis and that of
physics, doubtless this distrust would not have been produced,
and perhaps one might thus, even to-day, still deceive many
readers not forewarned. |
It was not slow in being noticed that rigor could not be introduced
in the reasoning unless first made to enter into the definitions.
For the most part the objects treated of by mathematicians
were long ill defined; they were supposed to be known
because represented by means of the senses or the imagination;
but one had only a crude image of them and not a precise idea
on which reasoning could take hold. It was there first that the
logicians had to direct their efforts. |
By that means the difficulties arising from passing to the limit,
or from the consideration of infinitesimals, are finally removed.
To-day in analysis only whole numbers are left or systems, finite
or infinite, of whole numbers bound together by a net of equality
or inequality relations. Mathematics, as they say, is arithmetized. |
The philosophers make still another objection: "What you gain
in rigor," they say, "you lose in objectivity. You can rise toward
your logical ideal only by cutting the bonds which attach
you to reality. Your science is infallible, but it can only remain
so by imprisoning itself in an ivory tower and renouncing all relation
with the external world. From this seclusion it must go
out when it would attempt the slightest application." |
For example, I seek to show that some property pertains to
some object whose concept seems to me at first indefinable, because
it is intuitive. At first I fail or must content myself with
approximate proofs; finally I decide to give to my object a precise
definition, and this enables me to establish this property in
an irreproachable manner. |
Well, is it not a great advance to have distinguished what long
was wrongly confused? Does this mean that nothing is left of
this objection of the philosophers? That I do not intend to say;
in becoming rigorous, mathematical science takes a character so
artificial as to strike every one; it forgets its historical origins;
we see how the questions can be answered, we no longer see how
and why they are put. |
I have already had occasion to insist on the place intuition
should hold in the teaching of the mathematical sciences. Without
it young minds could not make a beginning in the understanding
of mathematics; they could not learn to love it and
would see in it only a vain logomachy; above all, without intuition
they would never become capable of applying mathematics.
But now I wish before all to speak of the rôle of intuition in
science itself. If it is useful to the student it is still more so to
the creative scientist. |
We seek reality, but what is reality? The physiologists tell us
that organisms are formed of cells; the chemists add that cells
themselves are formed of atoms. Does this mean that these atoms
or these cells constitute reality, or rather the sole reality? The
way in which these cells are arranged and from which results the
unity of the individual, is not it also a reality much more interesting
than that of the isolated elements, and should a naturalist
who had never studied the elephant except by means of the microscope
think himself sufficiently acquainted with that animal? |
Pure analysis puts at our disposal a multitude of procedures
whose infallibility it guarantees; it opens to us a thousand different
ways on which we can embark in all confidence; we are
assured of meeting there no obstacles; but of all these ways,
which will lead us most promptly to our goal? Who shall tell
us which to choose? We need a faculty which makes us see the
end from afar, and intuition is this faculty. It is necessary to
the explorer for choosing his route; it is not less so to the one
following his trail who wants to know why he chose it. |
If you are present at a game of chess, it will not suffice, for the
understanding of the game, to know the rules for moving the
pieces. That will only enable you to recognize that each move
has been made conformably to these rules, and this knowledge
will truly have very little value. Yet this is what the reader of a
book on mathematics would do if he were a logician only. To
understand the game is wholly another matter; it is to know why
the player moves this piece rather than that other which he could
have moved without breaking the rules of the game. It is to
perceive the inward reason which makes of this series of successive
moves a sort of organized whole. This faculty is still more
necessary for the player himself, that is, for the inventor. |
Perhaps you think I use too many comparisons; yet pardon still
another. You have doubtless seen those delicate assemblages of
silicious needles which form the skeleton of certain sponges.
When the organic matter has disappeared, there remains only a
frail and elegant lace-work. True, nothing is there except silica,
but what is interesting is the form this silica has taken, and we
could not understand it if we did not know the living sponge
which has given it precisely this form. Thus it is that the old
intuitive notions of our fathers, even when we have abandoned
them, still imprint their form upon the logical constructions we
have put in their place. |
But at the moment of formulating this conclusion I am seized
with scruples. At the outset I distinguished two kinds of mathematical
minds, the one sort logicians and analysts, the others
intuitionalists and geometers. Well, the analysts also have been
inventors. The names I have just cited make my insistence on
this unnecessary. |
Besides, do you think they have always marched step by step
with no vision of the goal they wished to attain? They must have
divined the way leading thither, and for that they needed a guide.
This guide is, first, analogy. For example, one of the methods of
demonstration dear to analysts is that founded on the employment
of dominant functions. We know it has already served to
solve a multitude of problems; in what consists then the rôle of
the inventor who wishes to apply it to a new problem? At the
outset he must recognize the analogy of this question with those
which have already been solved by this method; then he must
perceive in what way this new question differs from the others,
and thence deduce the modifications necessary to apply to the
method. |
But how does one perceive these analogies and these differences?
In the example just cited they are almost always evident, but I
could have found others where they would have been much more
deeply hidden; often a very uncommon penetration is necessary
for their discovery. The analysts, not to let these hidden analogies
escape them, that is, in order to be inventors, must, without
the aid of the senses and imagination, have a direct sense of what
constitutes the unity of a piece of reasoning, of what makes, so
to speak, its soul and inmost life. |
No, our distinction corresponds to something real. I have said
above that there are many kinds of intuition. I have said how
much the intuition of pure number, whence comes rigorous
mathematical induction, differs from sensible intuition to which
the imagination, properly so called, is the principal contributor. |
Is the abyss which separates them less profound than it at first
appeared? Could we recognize with a little attention that this
pure intuition itself could not do without the aid of the senses?
This is the affair of the psychologist and the metaphysician and
I shall not discuss the question. But the thing's being doubtful
is enough to justify me in recognizing and affirming an essential
difference between the two kinds of intuition; they have not
the same object and seem to call into play two different faculties
of our soul; one would think of two search-lights directed upon
two worlds strangers to one another. |
Among the analysts there will then be inventors, but they will
be few. The majority of us, if we wished to see afar by pure intuition
alone, would soon feel ourselves seized with vertigo. Our
weakness has need of a staff more solid, and, despite the exceptions
of which we have just spoken, it is none the less true that
sensible intuition is in mathematics the most usual instrument of
invention. |
So long as we do not go outside the domain of consciousness,
the notion of time is relatively clear. Not only do we distinguish
without difficulty present sensation from the remembrance of past
sensations or the anticipation of future sensations, but we know
perfectly well what we mean when we say that of two conscious
phenomena which we remember, one was anterior to the other;
or that, of two foreseen conscious phenomena, one will be anterior
to the other. |
I have only a single observation to add. For an aggregate of
sensations to have become a remembrance capable of classification
in time, it must have ceased to be actual, we must have
lost the sense of its infinite complexity, otherwise it would have
remained present. It must, so to speak, have crystallized around
a center of associations of ideas which will be a sort of label. It
is only when they thus have lost all life that we can classify our
memories in time as a botanist arranges dried flowers in his
herbarium. |
But these labels can only be finite in number. On that score,
psychologic time should be discontinuous. Whence comes the
feeling that between any two instants there are others? We
arrange our recollections in time, but we know that there remain
empty compartments. How could that be, if time were not a
form pre-existent in our minds? How could we know there were
empty compartments, if these compartments were revealed to us
only by their content? |
But that is not all; into this form we wish to put not only the
phenomena of our own consciousness, but those of which other
consciousnesses are the theater. But more, we wish to put there
physical facts, these I know not what with which we people space
and which no consciousness sees directly. This is necessary because
without it science could not exist. In a word, psychologic
time is given to us and must needs create scientific and physical
time. There the difficulty begins, or rather the difficulties, for
there are two. |
The least reflection shows that by itself it has none at all. It
will only have that which I choose to give it, by a definition which
will certainly possess a certain degree of arbitrariness. Psychologists
could have done without this definition; physicists and
astronomers could not; let us see how they have managed. |
In fact, the best chronometers must be corrected from time to
time, and the corrections are made by the aid of astronomic
observations; arrangements are made so that the sidereal clock
marks the same hour when the same star passes the meridian.
In other words, it is the sidereal day, that is, the duration of the
rotation of the earth, which is the constant unit of time. It is
supposed, by a new definition substituted for that based on the
beats of the pendulum, that two complete rotations of the earth
about its axis have the same duration. |
However, the astronomers are still not content with this definition.
Many of them think that the tides act as a check on our
globe, and that the rotation of the earth is becoming slower and
slower. Thus would be explained the apparent acceleration of
the motion of the moon, which would seem to be going more
rapidly than theory permits because our watch, which is the
earth, is going slow. |
If experience made us witness such a sight, our postulate
would be contradicted. For experience would tell us that the
first duration αα´ is equal to the first duration ββ´ and that the
second duration αα´ is less than the second duration ββ´. On the
other hand, our postulate would require that the two durations
αα´ should be equal to each other, as likewise the two durations
ββ´. The equality and the inequality deduced from experience
would be incompatible with the two equalities deduced from the
postulate. |
Now can we affirm that the hypotheses I have just made are
absurd? They are in no wise contrary to the principle of contradiction.
Doubtless they could not happen without the principle
of sufficient reason seeming violated. But to justify a
definition so fundamental I should prefer some other guarantee. |
Physicists seek to make this distinction; but they make it only
approximately, and, however they progress, they never will
make it except approximately. It is approximately true that the
motion of the pendulum is due solely to the earth's attraction;
but in all rigor every attraction, even of Sirius, acts on the pendulum. |
In 1572, Tycho Brahe noticed in the heavens a new star. An
immense conflagration had happened in some far distant heavenly
body; but it had happened long before; at least two hundred
years were necessary for the light from that star to reach our
earth. This conflagration therefore happened before the discovery
of America. Well, when I say that; when, considering this
gigantic phenomenon, which perhaps had no witness, since the
satellites of that star were perhaps uninhabited, I say this phenomenon
is anterior to the formation of the visual image of the
isle of Española in the consciousness of Christopher Columbus,
what do I mean? |
This hypothesis is indeed crude and incomplete, because this
supreme intelligence would be only a demigod; infinite in one
sense, it would be limited in another, since it would have only an
imperfect recollection of the past; and it could have no other,
since otherwise all recollections would be equally present to it
and for it there would be no time. And yet when we speak of
time, for all which happens outside of us, do we not unconsciously
adopt this hypothesis; do we not put ourselves in the
place of this imperfect god; and do not even the atheists put
themselves in the place where god would be if he existed? |
What I have just said shows us, perhaps, why we have tried
to put all physical phenomena into the same frame. But that
can not pass for a definition of simultaneity, since this hypothetical
intelligence, even if it existed, would be for us impenetrable.
It is therefore necessary to seek something else. |
The ordinary definitions which are proper for psychologic time
would suffice us no more. Two simultaneous psychologic facts
are so closely bound together that analysis can not separate without
mutilating them. Is it the same with two physical facts? Is
not my present nearer my past of yesterday than the present of
Sirius? |
It has also been said that two facts should be regarded as
simultaneous when the order of their succession may be inverted
at will. It is evident that this definition would not suit two
physical facts which happen far from one another, and that, in
what concerns them, we no longer even understand what this
reversibility would be; besides, succession itself must first be
defined. |
I write a letter; it is afterward read by the friend to whom I
have addressed it. There are two facts which have had for their
theater two different consciousnesses. In writing this letter I
have had the visual image of it, and my friend has had in his turn
this same visual image in reading the letter. Though these two
facts happen in impenetrable worlds, I do not hesitate to regard
the first as anterior to the second, because I believe it is its cause. |
This rule appears in fact very natural, and yet we are often
led to depart from it. We hear the sound of the thunder only
some seconds after the electric discharge of the cloud. Of two
flashes of lightning, the one distant, the other near, can not the
first be anterior to the second, even though the sound of the
second comes to us before that of the first? |
Another difficulty; have we really the right to speak of the
cause of a phenomenon? If all the parts of the universe are interchained
in a certain measure, any one phenomenon will not be
the effect of a single cause, but the resultant of causes infinitely
numerous; it is, one often says, the consequence of the state of
the universe a moment before. How enunciate rules applicable
to circumstances so complex? And yet it is only thus that these
rules can be general and rigorous. |
Could not the observed facts be just as well explained if we attributed
to the velocity of light a little different value from that
adopted, and supposed Newton's law only approximate? Only
this would lead to replacing Newton's law by another more complicated.
So for the velocity of light a value is adopted, such
that the astronomic laws compatible with this value may be as
simple as possible. When navigators or geographers determine
a longitude, they have to solve just the problem we are discussing;
they must, without being at Paris, calculate Paris time.
How do they accomplish it? They carry a chronometer set for
Paris. The qualitative problem of simultaneity is made to depend
upon the quantitative problem of the measurement of
time. I need not take up the difficulties relative to this latter
problem, since above I have emphasized them at length. |
Or else they observe an astronomic phenomenon, such as an
eclipse of the moon, and they suppose that this phenomenon is
perceived simultaneously from all points of the earth. That is
not altogether true, since the propagation of light is not instantaneous;
if absolute exactitude were desired, there would be a
correction to make according to a complicated rule. |
We therefore choose these rules, not because they are true,
but because they are the most convenient, and we may recapitulate
them as follows: "The simultaneity of two events, or the
order of their succession, the equality of two durations, are to be
so defined that the enunciation of the natural laws may be as
simple as possible. In other words, all these rules, all these
definitions are only the fruit of an unconscious opportunism." |
In the articles I have heretofore devoted to space I have above
all emphasized the problems raised by non-Euclidean geometry,
while leaving almost completely aside other questions more difficult
of approach, such as those which pertain to the number of
dimensions. All the geometries I considered had thus a common
basis, that tridimensional continuum which was the same for all
and which differentiated itself only by the figures one drew in
it or when one aspired to measure it. |
In this continuum, primitively amorphous, we may imagine a
network of lines and surfaces, we may then convene to regard
the meshes of this net as equal to one another, and it is only
after this convention that this continuum, become measurable,
becomes Euclidean or non-Euclidean space. From this amorphous
continuum can therefore arise indifferently one or the
other of the two spaces, just as on a blank sheet of paper may
be traced indifferently a straight or a circle. |
In space we know rectilinear triangles the sum of whose angles
is equal to two right angles; but equally we know curvilinear
triangles the sum of whose angles is less than two right angles.
The existence of the one sort is not more doubtful than that of
the other. To give the name of straights to the sides of the first
is to adopt Euclidean geometry; to give the name of straights to
the sides of the latter is to adopt the non-Euclidean geometry.
So that to ask what geometry it is proper to adopt is to ask, to
what line is it proper to give the name straight? |
And then when we ask: Can one imagine non-Euclidean space?
That means: Can we imagine a world where there would be noteworthy
natural objects affecting almost the form of non-Euclidean
straights, and noteworthy natural bodies frequently undergoing
motions almost similar to the non-Euclidean motions? I
have shown in 'Science and Hypothesis' that to this question we
must answer yes. |
If one of these universes is our Euclidean world, what its inhabitants
will call straight will be our Euclidean straight; but
what the inhabitants of the second world will call straight will
be a curve which will have the same properties in relation to the
world they inhabit and in relation to the motions that they will
call motions without deformation. Their geometry will, therefore,
be Euclidean geometry, but their straight will not be our
Euclidean straight. It will be its transform by the point-transformation
which carries over from our world to theirs. The
straights of these men will not be our straights, but they will
have among themselves the same relations as our straights to one
another. It is in this sense I say their geometry will be ours.
If then we wish after all to proclaim that they deceive themselves,
that their straight is not the true straight, if we still are
unwilling to admit that such an affirmation has no meaning, at
least we must confess that these people have no means whatever
of recognizing their error. |
The theorems of analysis situs have, therefore, this peculiarity,
that they would remain true if the figures were copied by an
inexpert draftsman who should grossly change all the proportions
and replace the straights by lines more or less sinuous. In
mathematical terms, they are not altered by any 'point-transformation'
whatsoever. It has often been said that metric geometry
was quantitative, while projective geometry was purely qualitative.
That is not altogether true. The straight is still distinguished
from other lines by properties which remain quantitative
in some respects. The real qualitative geometry is, therefore,
analysis situs. |
The same questions which came up apropos of the truths of
Euclidean geometry, come up anew apropos of the theorems of
analysis situs. Are they obtainable by deductive reasoning?
Are they disguised conventions? Are they experimental verities?
Are they the characteristics of a form imposed either
upon our sensibility or upon our understanding? |
Note likewise that in analysis situs the empiricists are disembarrassed
of one of the gravest objections that can be leveled
against them, of that which renders absolutely vain in advance
all their efforts to apply their thesis to the verities of Euclidean
geometry. These verities are rigorous and all experimentation
can only be approximate. In analysis situs approximate experiments
may suffice to give a rigorous theorem and, for instance,
if it is seen that space can not have either two or less than two
dimensions, nor four or more than four, we are certain that it has
exactly three, since it could not have two and a half or three
and a half. |
I have explained in 'Science and Hypothesis' whence we
derive the notion of physical continuity and how that of mathematical
continuity has arisen from it. It happens that we are
capable of distinguishing two impressions one from the other,
while each is indistinguishable from a third. Thus we can readily
distinguish a weight of 12 grams from a weight of 10 grams,
while a weight of 11 grams could be distinguished from neither
the one nor the other. Such a statement, translated into symbols,
may be written: |
The physical continuum is, so to speak, a nebula not resolved;
the most perfect instruments could not attain to its resolution.
Doubtless if we measured the weights with a good balance instead
of judging them by the hand, we could distinguish the weight of
11 grams from those of 10 and 12 grams, and our formula would
become: |
First we must introduce the notion of cut, studying first physical
continua. We have seen what characterizes the physical continuum.
Each of the elements of this continuum consists of a
manifold of impressions; and it may happen either that an element
can not be discriminated from another element of the same
continuum, if this new element corresponds to a manifold of
impressions not sufficiently different, or, on the contrary, that
the discrimination is possible; finally it may happen that two
elements indistinguishable from a third may, nevertheless, be
distinguished one from the other. |
To justify this definition it is proper to see whether it is in this
way that geometers introduce the notion of three dimensions at
the beginning of their works. Now, what do we see? Usually
they begin by defining surfaces as the boundaries of solids or
pieces of space, lines as the boundaries of surfaces, points as the
boundaries of lines, and they affirm that the same procedure can
not be pushed further. |
This is just the idea given above: to divide space, cuts that are
called surfaces are necessary; to divide surfaces, cuts that are
called lines are necessary; to divide lines, cuts that are called
points are necessary; we can go no further, the point can not be
divided, so the point is not a continuum. Then lines which can be
divided by cuts which are not continua will be continua of one
dimension; surfaces which can be divided by continuous cuts of
one dimension will be continua of two dimensions; finally, space
which can be divided by continuous cuts of two dimensions will
be a continuum of three dimensions. |
Thus the definition I have just given does not differ essentially
from the usual definitions; I have only endeavored to give it a
form applicable not to the mathematical continuum, but to the
physical continuum, which alone is susceptible of representation,
and yet to retain all its precision. Moreover, we see that this
definition applies not alone to space; that in all which falls under
our senses we find the characteristics of the physical continuum,
which would allow of the same classification; that it would be
easy to find there examples of continua of four, of five, dimensions,
in the sense of the preceding definition; such examples
occur of themselves to the mind. |
It seems now that the question we put to ourselves at the start
is answered. When we say that space has three dimensions, it
will be said, we mean that the manifold of points of space satisfies
the definition we have just given of the physical continuum
of three dimensions. To be content with that would be to suppose
that we know what is the manifold of points of space, or even
one point of space. |
Now that is not as simple as one might think. Every one
believes he knows what a point is, and it is just because we know
it too well that we think there is no need of defining it. Surely
we can not be required to know how to define it, because in going
back from definition to definition a time must come when we must
stop. But at what moment should we stop? |
So, then, we should ask ourselves if it is possible to represent
to ourselves a point of space. Those who answer yes do not reflect
that they represent to themselves in reality a white spot made
with the chalk on a blackboard or a black spot made with a pen
on white paper, and that they can represent to themselves only
an object or rather the impressions that this object made on their
senses. |
When they try to represent to themselves a point, they represent
the impressions that very little objects made them feel. It
is needless to add that two different objects, though both very
little, may produce extremely different impressions, but I
shall not dwell on this difficulty, which would still require some
discussion. |
It is impossible to represent to oneself absolute space; when I
try to represent to myself simultaneously objects and myself in
motion in absolute space, in reality I represent to myself my own
self motionless and seeing move around me different objects and
a man that is exterior to me, but that I convene to call me. |
If we suppose two different objects which successively occupy
the same relative position with regard to ourselves, the impressions
that these two objects make upon us will be very different;
if we localize them at the same point, this is simply because it is
necessary to make the same movements to reach them; apart from
that, one can not just see what they could have in common. |
But, given an object, we can conceive many different series of
movements which equally enable us to reach it. If then we represent
to ourselves a point by representing to ourselves the series
of muscular sensations which accompany the movements which
enable us to reach this point, there will be many ways entirely
different of representing to oneself the same point. If one is not
satisfied with this solution, but wishes, for instance, to bring in
the visual sensations along with the muscular sensations, there
will be one or two more ways of representing to oneself this same
point and the difficulty will only be increased. In any case the
following question comes up: Why do we think that all these
representations so different from one another still represent the
same point? |
Another remark: I have just said that it is to our own body
that we naturally refer exterior objects; that we carry about
everywhere with us a system of axes to which we refer all the
points of space and that this system of axes seems to be invariably
bound to our body. It should be noticed that rigorously we
could not speak of axes invariably bound to the body unless the
different parts of this body were themselves invariably bound to
one another. As this is not the case, we ought, before referring
exterior objects to these fictitious axes, to suppose our body
brought back to the initial attitude. |
The movements that we impress upon our members have as
effect the varying of the impressions produced on our senses by
external objects; other causes may likewise make them vary; but
we are led to distinguish the changes produced by our own
motions and we easily discriminate them for two reasons: (1)
because they are voluntary; (2) because they are accompanied
by muscular sensations. |
We then observe that among the external changes are some
which can be corrected, thanks to an internal change which brings
everything back to the primitive state; others can not be corrected
in this way (it is thus that, when an exterior object is displaced,
we may then by changing our own position replace ourselves
as regards this object in the same relative position as before, so
as to reestablish the original aggregate of impressions; if this
object was not displaced, but changed its state, that is impossible).
Thence comes a new distinction among external changes:
those which may be so corrected we call changes of position;
and the others, changes of state. |
If I could not move my eye, should I have any reason to suppose
that the sensation of red at the center of the retina is to the
sensation of red at the border of the retina as that of blue at the
center is to that of blue at the border? I should only have four
sensations qualitatively different, and if I were asked if they
are connected by the proportion I have just stated, the question
would seem to me ridiculous, just as if I were asked if there is an
analogous proportion between an auditory sensation, a tactile
sensation and an olfactory sensation. |
I should therefore distinguish the simple changes of position
without change of attitude, and the changes of attitude. Both
would appear to me under form of muscular sensations. How
then am I led to distinguish them? It is that the first may serve
to correct an external change, and that the others can not, or at
least can only give an imperfect correction. |
Although motor impressions have had, as I have just explained,
an altogether preponderant influence in the genesis of the notion
of space, which never would have taken birth without them, it
will not be without interest to examine also the rôle of visual
impressions and to investigate how many dimensions 'visual
space' has, and for that purpose to apply to these impressions
the definition of § 3. |
To do away with this difficulty, consider only sensations of the
same nature, red sensations, for instance, differing one from
another only as regards the point of the retina that they affect.
It is clear that I have no reason for making such an arbitrary
choice among all the possible visual sensations, for the purpose
of uniting in the same class all the sensations of the same color,
whatever may be the point of the retina affected. I should never
have dreamt of it, had I not before learned, by the means we
have just seen, to distinguish changes of state from changes of
position, that is, if my eye were immovable. Two sensations of
the same color affecting two different parts of the retina would
have appeared to me as qualitatively distinct, just as two sensations
of different color. |
And yet most often it is said that the eye gives us the sense of
a third dimension, and enables us in a certain measure to recognize
the distance of objects. When we seek to analyze this feeling,
we ascertain that it reduces either to the consciousness of the
convergence of the eyes, or to that of the effort of accommodation
which the ciliary muscle makes to focus the image. |
Two red sensations affecting the same point of the retina will
therefore be regarded as identical only if they are accompanied
by the same sensation of convergence and also by the same sensation
of effort of accommodation or at least by sensations of
convergence and accommodation so slightly different as to be
indistinguishable. |
Will it then be said that it is experience which teaches us that
space has three dimensions, since it is in setting out from an
experimental law that we have come to attribute three to it? But
we have therein performed, so to speak, only an experiment in
physiology; and as also it would suffice to fit over the eyes glasses
of suitable construction to put an end to the accord between the
feelings of convergence and of accommodation, are we to say that
putting on spectacles is enough to make space have four dimensions
and that the optician who constructed them has given one
more dimension to space? Evidently not; all we can say is that
experience has taught us that it is convenient to attribute three
dimensions to space. |
The intermediation of this physical continuum, capable of
representation, is indispensable; because we can not represent
space to ourselves, and that for a multitude of reasons. Space
is a mathematical continuum, it is infinite, and we can represent
to ourselves only physical continua and finite objects. The different
elements of space, which we call points, are all alike, and,
to apply our definition, it is necessary that we know how to distinguish
the elements from one another, at least if they are not
too close. Finally absolute space is nonsense, and it is necessary
for us to begin by referring space to a system of axes invariably
bound to our body (which we must always suppose put back in
the initial attitude). |
That would be easy, I have said, but that would be rather long;
and would it not be a little superficial? This group of displacements,
we have seen, is related to space, and space could be deduced
from it, but it is not equivalent to space, since it has not
the same number of dimensions; and when we shall have shown
how the notion of this continuum can be formed and how that of
space may be deduced from it, it might always be asked why
space of three dimensions is much more familiar to us than this
continuum of six dimensions, and consequently doubted whether
it was by this detour that the notion of space was formed in the
human mind. |
Suppose experience had taught us the contrary, as might well
be; this hypothesis contains nothing absurd. Suppose, therefore,
that we had ascertained experimentally that the condition relative
to touch may be fulfilled without that of sight being fulfilled
and that, on the contrary, that of sight can not be fulfilled without
that of touch being also. It is clear that if this were so we
should conclude that it is touch which may be exercised at a distance,
and that sight does not operate at a distance. |
At the end of the preceding chapter we analyzed visual space;
we saw that to engender this space it is necessary to bring in the
retinal sensations, the sensation of convergence and the sensation
of accommodation; that if these last two were not always
in accord, visual space would have four dimensions in place of
three; we also saw that if we brought in only the retinal sensations,
we should obtain 'simple visual space,' of only two dimensions.
On the other hand, consider tactile space, limiting ourselves
to the sensations of a single finger, that is in sum to the
assemblage of positions this finger can occupy. This tactile
space that we shall analyze in the following section and which
consequently I ask permission not to consider further for the
moment, this tactile space, I say, has three dimensions. Why
has space properly so called as many dimensions as tactile space
and more than simple visual space? It is because touch does not
operate at a distance, while vision does operate at a distance.
These two assertions have the same meaning and we have just
seen what this is. |
We are led to distinguish the series σ, because it often happens
that when we have executed the movements which correspond to
these series σ of muscular sensations, the tactile sensations which
are transmitted to us by the nerve of the finger that we have
called the first finger, persist and are not altered by these movements.
Experience alone tells us that and it alone could tell us. |
It seems that I am about to be led to conclusions in conformity
with empiristic ideas. I have, in fact, sought to put in evidence
the rôle of experience and to analyze the experimental facts
which intervene in the genesis of space of three dimensions. But
whatever may be the importance of these facts, there is one thing
we must not forget and to which besides I have more than once
called attention. These experimental facts are often verified
but not always. That evidently does not mean that space has
often three dimensions, but not always. |
I know well that it is easy to save oneself and that, if the
facts do not verify, it will be easily explained by saying that
the exterior objects have moved. If experience succeeds, we say
that it teaches us about space; if it does not succeed, we hie to
exterior objects which we accuse of having moved; in other
words, if it does not succeed, it is given a fillip. |
I will add that experience brings us into contact only with
representative space, which is a physical continuum, never with
geometric space, which is a mathematical continuum. At the
very most it would appear to tell us that it is convenient to give
to geometric space three dimensions, so that it may have as
many as representative space. |
The empiric question may be put under another form. Is it
impossible to conceive physical phenomena, the mechanical phenomena,
for example, otherwise than in space of three dimensions?
We should thus have an objective experimental proof,
so to speak, independent of our physiology, of our modes of
representation. |
But it is not so; I shall not here discuss the question completely,
I shall confine myself to recalling the striking example
given us by the mechanics of Hertz. You know that the great
physicist did not believe in the existence of forces, properly so
called; he supposed that visible material points are subjected to
certain invisible bonds which join them to other invisible points
and that it is the effect of these invisible bonds that we attribute
to forces. |
Whatever should be thought of this hypothesis, whether we be
allured by its simplicity, or repelled by its artificial character,
the simple fact that Hertz was able to conceive it, and to regard
it as more convenient than our habitual hypotheses, suffices to
prove that our ordinary ideas, and, in particular, the three dimensions
of space, are in no wise imposed upon mechanics with
an invincible force. |
When it is said that our sensations are 'extended' only one
thing can be meant, that is that they are always associated with
the idea of certain muscular sensations, corresponding to the
movements which enable us to reach the object which causes
them, which enable us, in other words, to defend ourselves against
it. And it is just because this association is useful for the defense
of the organism, that it is so old in the history of the species
and that it seems to us indestructible. Nevertheless, it is only
an association and we can conceive that it may be broken; so
that we may not say that sensation can not enter consciousness
without entering in space, but that in fact it does not enter consciousness
without entering in space, which means, without being
entangled in this association. |
I have not hitherto spoken of the rôle of certain organs to
which the physiologists attribute with reason a capital importance,
I mean the semicircular canals. Numerous experiments
have sufficiently shown that these canals are necessary to our
sense of orientation; but the physiologists are not entirely in
accord; two opposing theories have been proposed, that of Mach-Delage
and that of M. de Cyon. |
The three pairs of canals would have as sole function to tell us
that space has three dimensions. Japanese mice have only two
pairs of canals; they believe, it would seem, that space has only
two dimensions, and they manifest this opinion in the strangest
way; they put themselves in a circle, and, so ordered, they spin
rapidly around. The lampreys, having only one pair of canals,
believe that space has only one dimension, but their manifestations
are less turbulent. |
We must, therefore, come back to the theory of Mach-Delage.
What the nerves of the canals can tell us is the difference of pressure
on the two extremities of the same canal, and thereby: (1)
the direction of the vertical with regard to three axes rigidly
bound to the head; (2) the three components of the acceleration
of translation of the center of gravity of the head; (3) the centrifugal
forces developed by the rotation of the head; (4) the
acceleration of the motion of rotation of the head. |
Among those who put this question I should make a distinction;
practical people ask of us only the means of money-making.
These merit no reply; rather would it be proper to ask of them
what is the good of accumulating so much wealth and whether,
to get time to acquire it, we are to neglect art and science, which
alone give us souls capable of enjoying it, 'and for life's sake to
sacrifice all reasons for living.' |
They would doubtless concede that these structures are well
worth the trouble they have cost us. But this is not enough.
Mathematics has a triple aim. It must furnish an instrument
for the study of nature. But that is not all: it has a philosophic
aim and, I dare maintain, an esthetic aim. It must aid the
philosopher to fathom the notions of number, of space, of time.
And above all, its adepts find therein delights analogous to those
given by painting and music. They admire the delicate harmony
of numbers and forms; they marvel when a new discovery opens
to them an unexpected perspective; and has not the joy they thus
feel the esthetic character, even though the senses take no part
therein? Only a privileged few are called to enjoy it fully, it is
true, but is not this the case for all the noblest arts? |
The mathematician should not be for the physicist a mere purveyor
of formulas; there should be between them a more intimate
collaboration. Mathematical physics and pure analysis are not
merely adjacent powers, maintaining good neighborly relations;
they mutually interpenetrate and their spirit is the same. This
will be better understood when I have shown what physics gets
from mathematics and what mathematics, in return, borrows
from physics. |
But this is not all: law springs from experiment, but not immediately.
Experiment is individual, the law deduced from it is
general; experiment is only approximate, the law is precise, or at
least pretends to be. Experiment is made under conditions
always complex, the enunciation of the law eliminates these complications.
This is what is called 'correcting the systematic errors.' |
In a word, to get the law from experiment, it is necessary to
generalize; this is a necessity imposed upon the most circumspect
observer. But how generalize? Every particular truth
may evidently be extended in an infinity of ways. Among these
thousand routes opening before us, it is necessary to make a
choice, at least provisional; in this choice, what shall guide us? |