human
stringlengths 301
5k
|
---|
Here is how we should go: first, to make known the genus
force, we must show one after the other all the species of this
genus; they are very numerous and very different; there is the
pressure of fluids on the insides of the vases wherein they are
contained; the tension of threads; the elasticity of a spring; the
gravity working on all the molecules of a body; friction; the
normal mutual action and reaction of two solids in contact. |
Is this enough? Not yet. We now know how to compare the
intensity of two forces which have the same direction and same
point of application; we must learn to do it when the directions
are different. For that, imagine a string stretched by a weight
and passing over a pulley; we shall say that the tensor of the
two legs of the string is the same and equal to the tension weight. |
This definition of ours enables us to compare the tensions of
the two pieces of our string, and, using the preceding definitions,
to compare any two forces having the same direction as
these two pieces. It should be justified by showing that the
tension of the last piece of the string remains the same for the
same tensor weight, whatever be the number and the disposition
of the reflecting pulleys. It has still to be completed by showing
this is only true if the pulleys are frictionless. |
It is after having passed through all these meanders that one
may represent forces by arrows, and I should even wish that in
the development of the reasonings return were made from time
to time from the symbol to the reality. For instance it would
not be difficult to illustrate the parallelogram of forces by aid
of an apparatus formed of three strings, passing over pulleys,
stretched by weights and in equilibrium while pulling on the
same point. |
Knowing force, it is easy to define mass; this time the definition
should be borrowed from dynamics; there is no way of doing
otherwise, since the end to be attained is to give understanding
of the distinction between mass and weight. Here again, the
definition should be led up to by experiments; there is in fact a
machine which seems made expressly to show what mass is,
Atwood's machine; recall also the laws of the fall of bodies, that
the acceleration of gravity is the same for heavy as for light
bodies, and that it varies with the latitude, etc. |
Can mathematics be reduced to logic without having to appeal
to principles peculiar to mathematics? There is a whole school,
abounding in ardor and full of faith, striving to prove it. They
have their own special language, which is without words, using
only signs. This language is understood only by the initiates,
so that commoners are disposed to bow to the trenchant affirmations
of the adepts. It is perhaps not unprofitable to examine
these affirmations somewhat closely, to see if they justify the
peremptory tone with which they are presented. |
Many mathematicians followed his lead and set a series of
questions of the sort. They so familiarized themselves with
transfinite numbers that they have come to make the theory of
finite numbers depend upon that of Cantor's cardinal numbers.
In their eyes, to teach arithmetic in a way truly logical, one
should begin by establishing the general properties of transfinite
cardinal numbers, then distinguish among them a very
small class, that of the ordinary whole numbers. Thanks to this
détour, one might succeed in proving all the propositions relative
to this little class (that is to say all our arithmetic and our
algebra) without using any principle foreign to logic. This
method is evidently contrary to all sane psychology; it is certainly
not in this way that the human mind proceeded in constructing
mathematics; so its authors do not dream, I think, of
introducing it into secondary teaching. But is it at least logic,
or, better, is it correct? It may be doubted. |
The geometers who have employed it are however very numerous.
They have accumulated formulas and they have thought
to free themselves from what was not pure logic by writing
memoirs where the formulas no longer alternate with explanatory
discourse as in the books of ordinary mathematics, but where
this discourse has completely disappeared. |
For M. Couturat, the new works, and in particular those of
Russell and Peano, have finally settled the controversy, so long
pending between Leibnitz and Kant. They have shown that
there are no synthetic judgments a priori (Kant's phrase to
designate judgments which can neither be demonstrated analytically,
nor reduced to identities, nor established experimentally),
they have shown that mathematics is entirely reducible to logic
and that intuition here plays no rôle. |
I do not make this formal character of his geometry a reproach
to Hilbert. This is the way he should go, given the problem he
set himself. He wished to reduce to a minimum the number of
the fundamental assumptions of geometry and completely enumerate
them; now, in reasonings where our mind remains active,
in those where intuition still plays a part, in living reasonings,
so to speak, it is difficult not to introduce an assumption or a
postulate which passes unperceived. It is therefore only after
having carried back all the geometric reasonings to a form purely
mechanical that he could be sure of having accomplished his
design and finished his work. |
Even admitting it were established that all the theorems could
be deduced by procedures purely analytic, by simple logical
combinations of a finite number of assumptions, and that these
assumptions are only conventions; the philosopher would still
have the right to investigate the origins of these conventions,
to see why they have been judged preferable to the contrary
conventions. |
To seek the origin of this instinct, to study the laws of this
deep geometry, felt, not stated, would also be a fine employment
for the philosophers who do not want logic to be all. But it is
not at this point of view I wish to put myself, it is not thus I
wish to consider the question. The instinct mentioned is necessary
for the inventor, but it would seem at first we might do
without it in studying the science once created. Well, what I
wish to investigate is if it be true that, the principles of logic
once admitted, one can, I do not say discover, but demonstrate,
all the mathematical verities without making a new appeal to
intuition. |
If previously have been defined all these notions but one, then
this last will be by definition the thing which verifies these postulates.
Thus certain indemonstrable assumptions of mathematics
would be only disguised definitions. This point of view
is often legitimate; and I have myself admitted it in regard for
instance to Euclid's postulate. |
Under this form, his opinion is inadmissible. Mathematics is
independent of the existence of material objects; in mathematics
the word exist can have only one meaning, it means free from
contradiction. Thus rectified, Stuart Mill's thought becomes
exact; in defining a thing, we affirm that the definition implies no
contradiction. |
If therefore we have a system of postulates, and if we can
demonstrate that these postulates imply no contradiction, we
shall have the right to consider them as representing the definition
of one of the notions entering therein. If we can not demonstrate
that, it must be admitted without proof, and that then
will be an assumption; so that, seeking the definition under the
postulate, we should find the assumption under the definition. |
We therefore shall find in the sequel of the exposition the
word defined; have we the right to affirm, of the thing represented
by this word, the postulate which has served for definition?
Yes, evidently, if the word has retained its meaning, if we do
not attribute to it implicitly a different meaning. Now this is
what sometimes happens and it is usually difficult to perceive it;
it is needful to see how this word comes into our discourse, and
if the gate by which it has entered does not imply in reality a
definition other than that stated. |
This difficulty presents itself in all the applications of mathematics.
The mathematical notion has been given a definition
very refined and very rigorous; and for the pure mathematician
all doubt has disappeared; but if one wishes to apply it to the
physical sciences for instance, it is no longer a question of this
pure notion, but of a concrete object which is often only a rough
image of it. To say that this object satisfies, at least approximately,
the definition, is to state a new truth, which experience
alone can put beyond doubt, and which no longer has the character
of a conventional postulate. |
The definitions of number are very numerous and very different;
I forego the enumeration even of the names of their authors.
We should not be astonished that there are so many. If one
among them was satisfactory, no new one would be given. If
each new philosopher occupying himself with this question has
thought he must invent another one, this was because he was not
satisfied with those of his predecessors, and he was not satisfied
with them because he thought he saw a petitio principii. |
This is because it is impossible to give a definition without
using a sentence, and difficult to make a sentence without using
a number word, or at least the word several, or at least a word
in the plural. And then the declivity is slippery and at each
instant there is risk of a fall into petitio principii. |
To justify its pretensions, logic had to change. We have seen
new logics arise of which the most interesting is that of Russell.
It seems he has nothing new to write about formal logic, as if
Aristotle there had touched bottom. But the domain Russell
attributes to logic is infinitely more extended than that of the
classic logic, and he has put forth on the subject views which are
original and at times well warranted. |
A great number of new notions have been introduced, and
these are not simply combinations of the old. Russell knows
this, and not only at the beginning of the first chapter, 'The
Logic of Propositions,' but at the beginning of the second and
third, 'The Logic of Classes' and 'The Logic of Relations,' he
introduces new words that he declares indefinable. |
If I take the series 0, 1, 2, I see it fulfils the assumptions 1,
2, 4 and 5; but to satisfy assumption 3 it still is necessary that
3 be an integer, and consequently that the series 0, 1, 2, 3, fulfil
the assumptions; we might prove that it satisfies assumptions
1, 2, 4, 5, but assumption 3 requires besides that 4 be an integer
and that the series 0, 1, 2, 3, 4 fulfil the assumptions, and so on. |
"Let us take as the basis of our consideration first of all a
thought-thing 1 (one)" (p. 341). Notice that in so doing we in
no wise imply the notion of number, because it is understood that
1 is here only a symbol and that we do not at all seek to know
its meaning. "The taking of this thing together with itself
respectively two, three or more times...." Ah! this time it is
no longer the same; if we introduce the words 'two,' 'three,' and
above all 'more,' 'several,' we introduce the notion of number;
and then the definition of finite whole number which we shall
presently find, will come too late. Our author was too circumspect
not to perceive this begging of the question. So at the end
of his work he tries to proceed to a truly patching-up process. |
Afterwards he separates these combinations into two classes,
the class of the existent and the class of the non-existent, and
till further orders this separation is entirely arbitrary. Every
affirmative statement tells us that a certain combination belongs
to the class of the existent; every negative statement tells us that
a certain combination belongs to the class of the non-existent. |
Russell is faithful to his point of view, which is that of comprehension.
He starts from the general idea of being, and
enriches it more and more while restricting it, by adding new
qualities. Hilbert on the contrary recognizes as possible beings
only combinations of objects already known; so that (looking at
only one side of his thought) we might say he takes the view-point
of extension. |
Let us continue with the exposition of Hilbert's ideas. He
introduces two assumptions which he states in his symbolic
language but which signify, in the language of the uninitiated,
that every quality is equal to itself and that every operation performed
upon two identical quantities gives identical results. |
So stated, they are evident, but thus to present them would
be to misrepresent Hilbert's thought. For him mathematics
has to combine only pure symbols, and a true mathematician
should reason upon them without preconceptions as to their
meaning. So his assumptions are not for him what they are for
the common people. |
He considers them as representing the definition by postulates
of the symbol (=) heretofore void of all signification. But to
justify this definition we must show that these two assumptions
lead to no contradiction. For this Hilbert used the reasoning of
our number III, without appearing to perceive that he is using
complete induction. |
As to the third, evidently it implies no contradiction. Does
this mean that the definition guarantees, as it should, the existence
of the object defined? We are here no longer in the mathematical
sciences, but in the physical, and the word existence has
no longer the same meaning. It no longer signifies absence of
contradiction; it means objective existence. |
And since I am on this subject, still another word. Of the
phosphorus example I said: "This proposition is a real verifiable
physical law, because it means that all bodies having all the other
properties of phosphorus, save its point of fusion, melt like it at
44°." And it was answered: "No, this law is not verifiable,
because if it were shown that two bodies resembling phosphorus
melt one at 44° and the other at 50°, it might always be said
that doubtless, besides the point of fusion, there is some other
unknown property by which they differ." |
And the better to make evident the difference between the case
of the straight and that of phosphorus, one more remark. The
straight has in nature many images more or less imperfect, of
which the chief are the light rays and the rotation axis of the
solid. Suppose we find the ray of light does not satisfy Euclid's
postulate (for example by showing that a star has a negative
parallax), what shall we do? Shall we conclude that the straight
being by definition the trajectory of light does not satisfy the
postulate, or, on the other hand, that the straight by definition
satisfying the postulate, the ray of light is not straight? |
Suppose now we find that phosphorus does not melt at 44°,
but at 43.9°. Shall we conclude that phosphorus being by definition
that which melts at 44°, this body that we did call phosphorus
is not true phosphorus, or, on the other hand, that phosphorous
melts at 43.9°? Here again we are free to adopt the one
or the other definition and consequently the one or the other
conclusion; but to adopt the first would be stupid because we
can not be changing the name of a substance every time we
determine a new decimal of its fusion-point. |
To sum up, Russell and Hilbert have each made a vigorous
effort; they have each written a work full of original views,
profound and often well warranted. These two works give us
much to think about and we have much to learn from them.
Among their results, some, many even, are solid and destined to
live. |
The logicians have attempted to answer the preceding considerations.
For that, a transformation of logistic was necessary,
and Russell in particular has modified on certain points his
original views. Without entering into the details of the debate,
I should like to return to the two questions to my mind most important:
Have the rules of logistic demonstrated their fruitfulness
and infallibility? Is it true they afford means of proving
the principle of complete induction without any appeal to
intuition? |
Russell seeks to reconcile these contradictions, which can only
be done, according to him, "by restricting or even sacrificing the
notion of class." And M. Couturat, discovering the success of
his attempt, adds: "If the logicians succeed where others have
failed, M. Poincaré will remember this phrase, and give the honor
of the solution to logistic." |
To demonstrate that a system of postulates implies no contradiction,
it is necessary to apply the principle of complete induction;
this mode of reasoning not only has nothing 'bizarre' about
it, but it is the only correct one. It is not 'unlikely' that it has
ever been employed; and it is not hard to find 'examples and
precedents' of it. I have cited two such instances borrowed from
Hilbert's article. He is not the only one to have used it, and
those who have not done so have been wrong. What I have
blamed Hilbert for is not his having recourse to it (a born
mathematician such as he could not fail to see a demonstration
was necessary and this the only one possible), but his having
recourse without recognizing the reasoning by recurrence. |
I pointed out a second error of logistic in Hilbert's article.
To-day Hilbert is excommunicated and M. Couturat no longer
regards him as of the logistic cult; so he asks if I have found
the same fault among the orthodox. No, I have not seen it in the
pages I have read; I know not whether I should find it in the
three hundred pages they have written which I have no desire to
read. |
Only, they must commit it the day they wish to make any
application of mathematics. This science has not as sole object
the eternal contemplation of its own navel; it has to do with
nature and some day it will touch it. Then it will be necessary
to shake off purely verbal definitions and to stop paying oneself
with words. |
To go back to the example of Hilbert: always the point at
issue is reasoning by recurrence and the question of knowing
whether a system of postulates is not contradictory. M. Couturat
will doubtless say that then this does not touch him, but it perhaps
will interest those who do not claim, as he does, the liberty
of contradiction. |
Now to examine Russell's new memoir. This memoir was
written with the view to conquer the difficulties raised by those
Cantor antinomies to which frequent allusion has already been
made. Cantor thought he could construct a science of the
infinite; others went on in the way he opened, but they soon ran
foul of strange contradictions. These antinomies are already
numerous, but the most celebrated are: |
This number exists; and in fact the numbers capable of being
defined by a like phrase are evidently finite in number since the
words of the English language are not infinite in number. Therefore
among them will be one less than all the others. And, on the
other hand, this number does not exist, because its definition
implies contradiction. This number, in fact, is defined by the
phrase in italics which is composed of less than a hundred English
words; and by definition this number should not be capable
of definition by a like phrase. |
According to the zigzag theory "definitions (propositional
functions) determine a class when they are very simple and cease
to do so only when they are complicated and obscure." Who,
now, is to decide whether a definition may be regarded as simple
enough to be acceptable? To this question there is no answer, if
it be not the loyal avowal of a complete inability: "The rules
which enable us to recognize whether these definitions are predicative
would be extremely complicated and can not commend themselves
by any plausible reason. This is a fault which might be
remedied by greater ingenuity or by using distinctions not yet
pointed out. But hitherto in seeking these rules, I have not
been able to find any other directing principle than the absence
of contradiction." |
It is toward the no-classes theory that Russell finally inclines.
Be that as it may, logistic is to be remade and it is not clear
how much of it can be saved. Needless to add that Cantorism
and logistic are alone under consideration; real mathematics,
that which is good for something, may continue to develop in
accordance with its own principles without bothering about the
storms which rage outside it, and go on step by step with its usual
conquests which are final and which it never has to abandon. |
The first postulate is not more evident than the principle to be
proved. The second not only is not evident, but it is false, as
Whitehead has shown; as moreover any recruit would see at the
first glance, if the axiom had been stated in intelligible language,
since it means that the number of combinations which can be
formed with several objects is less than the number of these
objects. |
A demonstration truly founded upon the principles of analytic
logic will be composed of a series of propositions. Some, serving
as premises, will be identities or definitions; the others will be
deduced from the premises step by step. But though the bond
between each proposition and the following is immediately evident,
it will not at first sight appear how we get from the first
to the last, which we may be tempted to regard as a new truth.
But if we replace successively the different expressions therein by
their definition and if this operation be carried as far as possible,
there will finally remain only identities, so that all will
reduce to an immense tautology. Logic therefore remains sterile
unless made fruitful by intuition. |
But that is ancient history. Russell has perceived the peril
and takes counsel. He is about to change everything, and, what
is easily understood, he is preparing not only to introduce new
principles which shall allow of operations formerly forbidden,
but he is preparing to forbid operations he formerly thought
legitimate. Not content to adore what he burned, he is about
to burn what he adored, which is more serious. He does not add
a new wing to the building, he saps its foundation. |
The general principles of Dynamics, which have, since Newton,
served as foundation for physical science, and which appeared
immovable, are they on the point of being abandoned or
at least profoundly modified? This is what many people have
been asking themselves for some years. According to them, the
discovery of radium has overturned the scientific dogmas we believed
the most solid: on the one hand, the impossibility of the
transmutation of metals; on the other hand, the fundamental
postulates of mechanics. |
Perhaps one is too hasty in considering these novelties as
finally established, and breaking our idols of yesterday; perhaps
it would be proper, before taking sides, to await experiments
more numerous and more convincing. None the less is it necessary,
from to-day, to know the new doctrines and the arguments,
already very weighty, upon which they rest. |
Astronomic observations and the most ordinary physical phenomena
seem to have given of these principles a confirmation complete,
constant and very precise. This is true, it is now said,
but it is because we have never operated with any but very
small velocities; Mercury, for example, the fastest of the planets,
goes scarcely 100 kilometers a second. Would this planet act
the same if it went a thousand times faster? We see there is yet
no need to worry; whatever may be the progress of automobilism,
it will be long before we must give up applying to our machines
the classic principles of dynamics. |
After the discovery of the cathode rays two theories appeared.
Crookes attributed the phenomena to a veritable molecular bombardment;
Hertz, to special undulations of the ether. This was
a renewal of the debate which divided physicists a century ago
about light; Crookes took up the emission theory, abandoned
for light; Hertz held to the undulatory theory. The facts seem
to decide in favor of Crookes. |
It has been recognized, in the first place, that the cathode
rays carry with them a negative electric charge; they are deviated
by a magnetic field and by an electric field; and these deviations
are precisely such as these same fields would produce upon projectiles
animated by a very high velocity and strongly charged
with electricity. These two deviations depend upon two quantities:
one the velocity, the other the relation of the electric charge
of the projectile to its mass; we cannot know the absolute value
of this mass, nor that of the charge, but only their relation; in
fact, it is clear that if we double at the same time the charge and
the mass, without changing the velocity, we shall double the
force which tends to deviate the projectile, but, as its mass is also
doubled, the acceleration and deviation observable will not be
changed. The observation of the two deviations will give us
therefore two equations to determine these two unknowns. We
find a velocity of from 10,000 to 30,000 kilometers a second; as
to the ratio of the charge to the mass, it is very great. We may
compare it to the corresponding ratio in regard to the hydrogen
ion in electrolysis; we then find that a cathodic projectile carries
about a thousand times more electricity than an equal mass of
hydrogen would carry in an electrolyte. |
The same calculations made with reference to the β rays of
radium have given velocities still greater: 100,000 or 200,000
kilometers or more yet. These velocities greatly surpass all those
we know. It is true that light has long been known to go 300,000
kilometers a second; but it is not a carrying of matter, while, if
we adopt the emission theory for the cathode rays, there would
be material molecules really impelled at the velocities in question,
and it is proper to investigate whether the ordinary laws of mechanics
are still applicable to them. |
If the velocity of a cathode corpuscle varies, the intensity of the
corresponding current will likewise vary; and there will develop
effects of self-induction which will tend to oppose this variation.
These corpuscles should therefore possess a double inertia: first
their own proper inertia, and then the apparent inertia, due to
self-induction, which produces the same effects. They will therefore
have a total apparent mass, composed of their real mass and
of a fictitious mass of electromagnetic origin. Calculation shows
that this fictitious mass varies with the velocity, and that the
force of inertia of self-induction is not the same when the velocity
of the projectile accelerates or slackens, or when it is deviated;
therefore so it is with the force of the total apparent inertia. |
But the electrons do not merely show us their existence in
these rays where they are endowed with enormous velocities.
We shall see them in very different rôles, and it is they that
account for the principal phenomena of optics and electricity.
The brilliant synthesis about to be noticed is due to Lorentz. |
In certain bodies, the metals for example, we should have
fixed electrons, between which would circulate moving electrons
enjoying perfect liberty, save that of going out from the metallic
body and breaking the surface which separates it from the exterior
void or from the air, or from any other non-metallic body. |
In other bodies, the dielectrics and the transparent bodies, the
movable electrons enjoy much less freedom. They remain as if
attached to fixed electrons which attract them. The farther they
go away from them the greater becomes this attraction and
tends to pull them back. They therefore can make only small
excursions; they can no longer circulate, but only oscillate about
their mean position. This is why these bodies would not be conductors;
moreover they would most often be transparent, and
they would be refractive, since the luminous vibrations would be
communicated to the movable electrons, susceptible of oscillation,
and thence a perturbation would result. |
1º The positive electrons have a real mass, much greater than
their fictitious electromagnetic mass; the negative electrons alone
lack real mass. We might even suppose that apart from electrons
of the two signs, there are neutral atoms which have only their
real mass. In this case, mechanics is not affected; there is no
need of touching its laws; the real mass is constant; simply, motions
are deranged by the effects of self-induction, as has always
been known; moreover, these perturbations are almost negligible,
except for the negative electrons which, not having real mass, are
not true matter. |
How shall we decide between these two hypotheses? By operating
upon the canal rays as Kaufmann did upon the β rays?
This is impossible; the velocity of these rays is much too slight.
Should each therefore decide according to his temperament, the
conservatives going to one side and the lovers of the new to the
other? Perhaps, but, to fully understand the arguments of the
innovators, other considerations must come in. |
But wait! This result is not exact, it is only approximate; let
us push the approximation a little farther. The dimensions of
the ellipse will depend then upon the absolute velocity of the
earth. Let us compare the major axes of the ellipse for the
different stars: we shall have, theoretically at least, the means of
determining this absolute velocity. |
Besides, this method is purely theoretical. In fact, the aberration
is very small; the possible variations of the ellipse of aberration
are much smaller yet, and, if we consider the aberration
as of the first order, they should therefore be regarded as of the
second order: about a millionth of a second; they are absolutely
inappreciable for our instruments. We shall finally see, further
on, why the preceding theory should be rejected, and why we
could not determine this absolute velocity even if our instruments
were ten thousand times more precise! |
One might imagine some other means, and in fact, so one has.
The velocity of light is not the same in water as in air; could
we not compare the two apparent positions of a star seen through
a telescope first full of air, then full of water? The results have
been negative; the apparent laws of reflection and refraction
are not altered by the motion of the earth. This phenomenon
is capable of two explanations: |
It is true that, if the energy sent out from the discharger or
from the lamp meets a material object, this object receives a
mechanical push as if it had been hit by a real projectile, and
this push will be equal to the recoil of the discharger and of
the lamp, if no energy has been lost on the way and if the object
absorbs the whole of the energy. Therefore one is tempted to
say that there still is compensation between the action and the
reaction. But this compensation, even should it be complete,
is always belated. It never happens if the light, after leaving
its source, wanders through interstellar spaces without ever meeting
a material body; it is incomplete, if the body it strikes is not
perfectly absorbent. |
The same effects of the Maxwell-Bartholi pressure are forecast
likewise by the theory of Hertz of which we have before
spoken, and by that of Lorentz. But there is a difference. Suppose
that the energy, under the form of light, for example, proceeds
from a luminous source to any body through a transparent
medium. The Maxwell-Bartholi pressure will act, not alone
upon the source at the departure, and on the body lit up at the
arrival, but upon the matter of the transparent medium which it
traverses. At the moment when the luminous wave reaches a
new region of this medium, this pressure will push forward the
matter there distributed and will put it back when the wave
leaves this region. So that the recoil of the source has for
counterpart the forward movement of the transparent matter
which is in contact with this source; a little later, the recoil of
this same matter has for counterpart the forward movement of
the transparent matter which lies a little further on, and so on. |
Only, is the compensation perfect? Is the action of the Maxwell-Bartholi
pressure upon the matter of the transparent
medium equal to its reaction upon the source, and that whatever
be this matter? Or is this action by so much the less as the
medium is less refractive and more rarefied, becoming null in
the void? |
There would then be perfect compensation, as required by the
principle of the equality of action and reaction, even in the least
refractive media, even in the air, even in the interplanetary
void, where it would suffice to suppose a residue of matter, however
subtile. If on the contrary we admit the theory of Lorentz,
the compensation, always imperfect, is insensible in the air and
becomes null in the void. |
First, it obliges us to generalize the hypothesis of Lorentz and
Fitzgerald on the contraction of all bodies in the sense of the
translation. In particular, we must extend this hypothesis to
the electrons themselves. Abraham considered these electrons as
spherical and indeformable; it will be necessary for us to admit
that these electrons, spherical when in repose, undergo the
Lorentz contraction when in motion and take then the form of
flattened ellipsoids. |
This deformation of the electrons will influence their mechanical
properties. In fact I have said that the displacement of
these charged electrons is a veritable current of convection and
that their apparent inertia is due to the self-induction of this
current: exclusively as concerns the negative electrons; exclusively
or not, we do not yet know, for the positive electrons.
Well, the deformation of the electrons, a deformation which
depends upon their velocity, will modify the distribution of the
electricity upon their surface, consequently the intensity of the
convection current they produce, consequently the laws according
to which the self-induction of this current will vary as a
function of the velocity. |
It still is Lorentz who has made this remarkable synthesis;
stop a moment and see what follows therefrom. First, there is
no more matter, since the positive electrons no longer have real
mass, or at least no constant real mass. The present principles
of our mechanics, founded upon the constancy of mass, must
therefore be modified. Again, an electromagnetic explanation
must be sought of all the known forces, in particular of gravitation,
or at least the law of gravitation must be so modified that
this force is altered by velocity in the same way as the electromagnetic
forces. We shall return to this point. |
We have before us, then, two theories: one where the electrons
are indeformable, this is that of Abraham; the other where they
undergo the Lorentz deformation. In both cases, their mass
increases with the velocity, becoming infinite when this velocity
becomes equal to that of light; but the law of the variation is
not the same. The method employed by Kaufmann to bring to
light the law of variation of the mass seems therefore to give us
an experimental means of deciding between the two theories. |
There is one point however to which I wish to draw attention:
that is to the measurement of the electrostatic field, a measurement
upon which all depends. This field was produced between
the two armatures of a condenser; and, between these armatures,
there was to be made an extremely perfect vacuum, in order to
obtain a complete isolation. Then the difference of potential of
the two armatures was measured, and the field obtained by dividing
this difference by the distance apart of the armatures. That
supposes the field uniform; is this certain? Might there not be
an abrupt fall of potential in the neighborhood of one of the
armatures, of the negative armature, for example? There may
be a difference of potential at the meeting of the metal and the
vacuum, and it may be that this difference is not the same on the
positive side and on the negative side; what would lead me to
think so is the electric valve effects between mercury and vacuum.
However slight the probability that it is so, it seems that it
should be considered. |
We know that a body submerged in a fluid experiences, when
in motion, considerable resistance, but this is because our fluids
are viscous; in an ideal fluid, perfectly free from viscosity, the
body would stir up behind it a liquid hill, a sort of wake; upon
departure, a great effort would be necessary to put it in motion,
since it would be necessary to move not only the body itself, but
the liquid of its wake. But, the motion once acquired, it would
perpetuate itself without resistance, since the body, in advancing,
would simply carry with it the perturbation of the liquid,
without the total vis viva of the liquid augmenting. Everything
would happen therefore as if its inertia was augmented. An
electron advancing in the ether would behave in the same way:
around it, the ether would be stirred up, but this perturbation
would accompany the body in its motion; so that, for an observer
carried along with the electron, the electric and magnetic fields
accompanying this electron would appear invariable, and would
change only if the velocity of the electron varied. An effort
would therefore be necessary to put the electron in motion, since
it would be necessary to create the energy of these fields; on the
contrary, once the movement acquired, no effort would be necessary
to maintain it, since the created energy would only have to
go along behind the electron as a wake. This energy, therefore,
could only augment the inertia of the electron, as the agitation of
the liquid augments that of the body submerged in a perfect
fluid. And anyhow, the negative electrons at least have no other
inertia except that. |
A question then suggests itself: let us admit the principle of
relativity; an observer in motion would not have any means of
perceiving his own motion. If therefore no body in its absolute
motion can exceed the velocity of light, but may approach it as
nearly as you choose, it should be the same concerning its relative
motion with reference to our observer. And then we might be
tempted to reason as follows: The observer may attain a velocity
of 200,000 kilometers; the body in its relative motion with reference
to the observer may attain the same velocity; its absolute
velocity will then be 400,000 kilometers, which is impossible,
since this is beyond the velocity of light. This is only a seeming,
which vanishes when account is taken of how Lorentz evaluates
local time. |
1º In incandescent gases certain electrons take an oscillatory
motion of very high frequency; the displacements are very small,
the velocities are finite, and the accelerations very great; energy
is then communicated to the ether, and this is why these gases
radiate light of the same period as the oscillations of the electron; |
4º In an incandescent metal, the electrons enclosed in this
metal are impelled with great velocity; upon reaching the surface
of the metal, which they can not get through, they are reflected
and thus undergo a considerable acceleration. This is why the
metal emits light. The details of the laws of the emission of
light by dark bodies are perfectly explained by this hypothesis; |
2º By the attraction the body exercises upon an exterior body,
in virtue of Newton's law. We should therefore distinguish the
mass coefficient of inertia and the mass coefficient of attraction.
According to Newton's law, there is rigorous proportionality
between these two coefficients. But that is demonstrated only
for velocities to which the general principles of dynamics are
applicable. Now, we have seen that the mass coefficient of inertia
increases with the velocity; should we conclude that the mass
coefficient of attraction increases likewise with the velocity and
remains proportional to the coefficient of inertia, or, on the contrary,
that this coefficient of attraction remains constant? This
is a question we have no means of deciding. |
But experiment shows us that these molecules attract each
other in consequence of Newtonian gravitation; and then we may
make two hypotheses: we may suppose gravitation has no relation
to the electrostatic attractions, that it is due to a cause
entirely different, and is simply something additional; or else
we may suppose the attractions are not proportional to the
charges and that the attraction exercised by a charge +1 upon
a charge −1 is greater than the mutual repulsion of two +1
charges, or two −1 charges. |
In other words, the electric field produced by the positive
electrons and that which the negative electrons produce might
be superposed and yet remain distinct. The positive electrons
would be more sensitive to the field produced by the negative
electrons than to the field produced by the positive electrons;
the contrary would be the case for the negative electrons. It is
clear that this hypothesis somewhat complicates electrostatics,
but that it brings back into it gravitation. This was, in sum,
Franklin's hypothesis. |
Such is the hypothesis of Lorentz, which reduces to Franklin's
hypothesis for slight velocities; it will therefore explain, for
these small velocities, Newton's law. Moreover, as gravitation
goes back to forces of electrodynamic origin, the general theory
of Lorentz will apply, and consequently the principle of relativity
will not be violated. |
Let us recur to the hypotheses A, B and C, and study first
the motion of a planet attracted by a fixed center. The hypotheses
B and C are no longer distinguished, since, if the attracting point
is fixed, the field it produces is a purely electrostatic field, where
the attraction varies inversely as the square of the distance, in
conformity with Coulomb's electrostatic law, identical with that
of Newton. |
We should not be led to results less fantastic if, contrary to
Darwin's views, we endowed the corpuscles of Lesage with an
elasticity imperfect without being null. In truth, the vis viva of
these corpuscles would not be entirely converted into heat, but
the attraction produced would likewise be less, so that it would be
only the part of this vis viva converted into heat, which would
contribute to produce the attraction and that would come to the
same thing; a judicious employment of the theorem of the viriel
would enable us to account for this. |
The theory of Lesage may be transformed; suppress the corpuscles
and imagine the ether overrun in all senses by luminous
waves coming from all points of space. When a material object
receives a luminous wave, this wave exercises upon it a mechanical
action due to the Maxwell-Bartholi pressure, just as if it
had received the impact of a material projectile. The waves in
question could therefore play the rôle of the corpuscles of Lesage.
This is what is supposed, for example, by M. Tommasina. |
On the other hand, attraction is not absorbed by the body it
traverses, or hardly at all; it is not so with the light we know.
Light which would produce the Newtonian attraction would have
to be considerably different from ordinary light and be, for
example, of very short wave length. This does not count that,
if our eyes were sensible of this light, the whole heavens should
appear to us much more brilliant than the sun, so that the sun
would seem to us to stand out in black, otherwise the sun would
repel us instead of attracting us. For all these reasons, light
which would permit of the explanation of attraction would be
much more like Röntgen rays than like ordinary light. |
And besides, the X-rays would not suffice; however penetrating
they may seem to us, they could not pass through the whole
earth; it would be necessary therefore to imagine X´-rays much
more penetrating than the ordinary X-rays. Moreover a part of
the energy of these X´-rays would have to be destroyed, otherwise
there would be no attraction. If you do not wish it transformed
into heat, which would lead to an enormous heat production,
you must suppose it radiated in every direction under the
form of secondary rays, which might be called X´´ and which
would have to be much more penetrating still than the X´-rays,
otherwise they would in their turn derange the phenomena of
attraction. |
I have striven to give in few words an idea as complete as
possible of these new doctrines; I have sought to explain how
they took birth; otherwise the reader would have had ground
to be frightened by their boldness. The new theories are not
yet demonstrated; far from it; only they rest upon an aggregate
of probabilities sufficiently weighty for us not to have the right
to treat them with disregard. |
Novelties are so attractive, and it is so hard not to seem
highly advanced! At least there will be the wish to open vistas
to the pupils and, before teaching them the ordinary mechanics,
to let them know it has had its day and was at best good enough
for that old dolt Laplace. And then they will not form the habit
of the ordinary mechanics. |
It is with the ordinary mechanics that they must live; this
alone will they ever have to apply. Whatever be the progress of
automobilism, our vehicles will never attain speeds where it is
not true. The other is only a luxury, and we should think of
the luxury only when there is no longer any risk of harming
the necessary. |
Consider now the milky way; there also we see an innumerable
dust; only the grains of this dust are not atoms, they are stars;
these grains move also with high velocities; they act at a distance
one upon another, but this action is so slight at great distance
that their trajectories are straight; and yet, from time to time,
two of them may approach near enough to be deviated from their
path, like a comet which has passed too near Jupiter. In a word,
to the eyes of a giant for whom our suns would be as for us our
atoms, the milky way would seem only a bubble of gas. |
Such was Lord Kelvin's leading idea. What may be drawn
from this comparison? In how far is it exact? This is what we
are to investigate together; but before reaching a definite conclusion,
and without wishing to prejudge it, we foresee that the
kinetic theory of gases will be for the astronomer a model he
should not follow blindly, but from which he may advantageously
draw inspiration. Up to the present, celestial mechanics has
attacked only the solar system or certain systems of double stars.
Before the assemblage presented by the milky way, or the agglomeration
of stars, or the resolvable nebulae it recoils, because it
sees therein only chaos. But the milky way is not more complicated
than a gas; the statistical methods founded upon the calculus
of probabilities applicable to a gas are also applicable to it.
Before all, it is important to grasp the resemblance of the two
cases, and their difference. |
The new theory comes to offer us other resources. In fact, we
know the motions of the stars nearest us, and we can form an
idea of the rapidity and direction of their velocities. If the ideas
above set forth are exact, these velocities should follow Maxwell's
law, and their mean value will tell us, so to speak, that
which corresponds to the temperature of our fictitious gas. But
this temperature depends itself upon the dimensions of our gas
bubble. In fact, how will a gaseous mass let loose in the void
act, if its elements attract one another according to Newton's
law? It will take a spherical form; moreover, because of gravitation,
the density will be greater at the center, the pressure also
will increase from the surface to the center because of the weight
of the outer parts drawn toward the center; finally, the temperature
will increase toward the center: the temperature and the
pressure being connected by the law called adiabatic, as happens
in the successive layers of our atmosphere. At the surface itself,
the pressure will be null, and it will be the same with the absolute
temperature, that is to say with the velocity of the molecules. |
However that may be, the pressure, and consequently the
temperature, at the center of the gaseous sphere would be by so
much the greater as the sphere was larger since the pressure
increases by the weight of all the superposed layers. We may
suppose that we are nearly at the center of the milky way, and
by observing the mean proper velocity of the stars, we shall
know that which corresponds to the central temperature of our
gaseous sphere and we shall determine its radius. |
But you will say these hypothesis differ greatly from the
reality; first, the milky way is not spherical and we shall soon
return to this point, and again the kinetic theory of gases is not
compatible with the hypothesis of a homogeneous sphere. But
in making the exact calculation according to this theory, we
should find a different result, doubtless, but of the same order
of magnitude; now in such a problem the data are so uncertain
that the order of magnitude is the sole end to be aimed at. |
But there is another difficulty: the milky way is not spherical,
and we have reasoned hitherto as if it were, since this is the form
of equilibrium a gas isolated in space would take. To make
amends, agglomerations of stars exist whose form is globular and
to which would better apply what we have hitherto said. Herschel
has already endeavored to explain their remarkable appearances.
He supposed the stars of the aggregates uniformly
distributed, so that an assemblage is a homogeneous sphere; each
star would then describe an ellipse and all these orbits would be
passed over in the same time, so that at the end of a period the
aggregate would take again its primitive configuration and this
configuration would be stable. Unluckily, the aggregates do not
appear to be homogeneous; we see a condensation at the center,
we should observe it even were the sphere homogeneous, since
it is thicker at the center; but it would not be so accentuated.
We may therefore rather compare an aggregate to a gas in adiabatic
equilibrium, which takes the spherical form because this is
the figure of equilibrium of a gaseous mass. |
But to return to the milky way; it is not spherical and would
rather be represented as a flattened disc. It is clear then that a
mass starting without velocity from the surface will reach the
center with different velocities, according as it starts from the
surface in the neighborhood of the middle of the disc or just on
the border of the disc; the velocity would be notably greater in
the latter case. Now, up to the present, we have supposed that
the proper velocities of the stars, those we observe, must be comparable
to those which like masses would attain; this involves a
certain difficulty. We have given above a value for the dimensions
of the milky way, and we have deduced it from the observed
proper velocities which are of the same order of magnitude as
that of the earth in its orbit; but which is the dimension we have
thus measured? Is it the thickness? Is it the radius of the disc?
It is doubtless something intermediate; but what can we say then
of the thickness itself, or of the radius of the disc? Data are
lacking to make the calculation; I shall confine myself to giving
a glimpse of the possibility of basing an evaluation at least approximate
upon a deeper discussion of the proper motions. |
They will tell us nothing about the rotation itself, since we belong
to the turning system. If the spiral nebulæ are other
milky ways, foreign to ours, they are not borne along in this
rotation, and we might study their proper motions. It is true
they are very far away; if a nebula has the dimensions of the
milky way and if its apparent radius is for example 20´´, its
distance is 10,000 times the radius of the milky way. |
I shall not further discuss the relative value of these two hypotheses
since there is a third which is perhaps more probable.
We know that among the irresolvable nebulæ, several kinds may
be distinguished: the irregular nebulæ like that of Orion, the
planetary and annular nebulæ, the spiral nebulæ. The spectra
of the first two families have been determined, they are discontinuous;
these nebulæ are therefore not formed of stars; besides,
their distribution on the heavens seems to depend upon the milky
way; whether they have a tendency to go away from it, or on
the contrary to approach it, they make therefore a part of the
system. On the other hand, the spiral nebulæ are generally
considered as independent of the milky way; it is supposed that
they, like it, are formed of a multitude of stars, that they are,
in a word, other milky ways very far away from ours. The
recent investigations of Stratonoff tend to make us regard the
milky way itself as a spiral nebula, and this is the third hypothesis
of which I wish to speak. |
From this point of view, there would not be a real permanent
motion, the central nucleus would constantly lose matter which
would go out of it never to return, and would drain away progressively.
But we may modify the hypothesis. In proportion
as it goes away, the star loses its velocity and ends by stopping;
at this moment attraction regains possession of it and leads it
back toward the nucleus; so there will be centripetal currents.
We must suppose the centripetal currents are the first rank and
the centrifugal currents the second rank, if we adopt the comparison
with a troop in battle executing a change of front; and,
in fact, it is necessary that the composite centrifugal force be
compensated by the attraction exercised by the central layers of
the swarm upon the extreme layers. |
Besides, at the end of a certain time a permanent régime establishes
itself; the swarm being curved, the attraction exercised
upon the pivot by the moving wing tends to slow up the pivot
and that of the pivot upon the moving wing tends to accelerate
the advance of this wing which no longer augments its lag, so that
finally all the radii end by turning with a uniform velocity. We
may still suppose that the rotation of the nucleus is quicker than
that of the radii. |
A question remains; why do these centripetal and centrifugal
swarms tend to concentrate themselves in radii instead of disseminating
themselves a little everywhere? Why do these rays distribute
themselves regularly? If the swarms concentrate themselves,
it is because of the attraction exercised by the already
existing swarms upon the stars which go out from the nucleus
in their neighborhood. After an inequality is produced, it tends
to accentuate itself in this way. |
But, in conclusion, I wish to call your attention to a question,
that of the age of the milky way or the nebulæ. If what we
think we see is confirmed, we can get an idea of it. That sort of
statistical equilibrium of which gases give us the model is established
only in consequence of a great number of impacts. If
these impacts are rare, it can come about only after a very long
time; if really the milky way (or at least the agglomerations
which are contained in it), if the nebulæ have attained this equilibrium,
this means they are very old, and we shall have an inferior
limit of their age. Likewise we should have of it a superior
limit; this equilibrium is not final and can not last always.
Our spiral nebulæ would be comparable to gases impelled by
permanent motions; but gases in motion are viscous and their
velocities end by wearing out. What here corresponds to the
viscosity (and which depends upon the chances of impact of the
molecules) is excessively slight, so that the present régime may
persist during an extremely long time, yet not forever, so that our
milky ways can not live eternally nor become infinitely old. |
Well, it is certain that if we compute in this manner the age
of the milky way, we shall get enormous figures. But here a
difficulty presents itself. Certain physicists, relying upon other
considerations, reckon that suns can have only an ephemeral existence,
about fifty million years; our minimum would be much
greater than that. Must we believe that the evolution of the
milky way began when the matter was still dark? But how have
the stars composing it reached all at the same time adult age,
an age so briefly to endure? Or must they reach there all successively,
and are those we see only a feeble minority compared with
those extinguished or which shall one day light up? But how
reconcile that with what we have said above on the absence of a
noteworthy proportion of dark matter? Should we abandon one
of the two hypotheses, and which? I confine myself to pointing
out the difficulty without pretending to solve it; I shall end therefore
with a big interrogation point. |