text
stringlengths 313
1.33M
|
---|
# Communication Systems/Time-Division Multiplexing
Consider a situation where there are multiple signals which would all
like to use the same wire (or medium). For instance, a telephone company
wants multiple signals on the same wire at the same time. It certainly
would save a great deal of space and money by doing this, not to mention
time by not having to install new wires. How would they be able to do
this? One simple answer is known as **Time-Division Multiplexing**.
## Time Division Multiplexing
**Time-Division Multiplexing** (TDM) is a convenient method for
combining various digital signals onto a single transmission media such
as wires, fiber optics or even radio. These signals may be interleaved
at the bit, byte, or some other level. The resulting pattern may be
transmitted directly, as in digital carrier systems, or passed through a
modem to allow the data to pass over an analog network. Digital data is
generally organized into frames for transmission and individual users
assigned a time slot, during which frames may be sent. If a user
requires a higher data rate than that provided by a single channel,
multiple time slots can be assigned.
Digital transmission schemes in North America and Europe have developed
along two slightly different paths, leading to considerable
incompatibility between the networks found on the two continents.
BRA (basic rate access) is a single digitized voice channel, the basic
unit of digital multiplexing.
:
: ![](BRA_comparison.gif "fig:BRA_comparison.gif")
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: ![](digital_transmission_systems.gif "fig:digital_transmission_systems.gif")
### North American TDM
The various transmission rates are not integral numbers of the basic
rate. This is because additional framing and synchronization bits are
required at every multiplexing level.
:
: ![](north_american_TDM.gif "fig:north_american_TDM.gif")
In North America, the basic digital channel format is known as DS-0.
These are grouped into frames of 24 channels each. A concatenation of 24
channels and a start bit is called a frame. Groups of 12 frames are
called multiframes or superframes. These vary the start bit to aid in
synchronizing the link and add signaling bits to pass control messages.
:
: ![](DS_framing.gif "fig:DS_framing.gif")
#### S Bit Synchronization
The S bit is used to identify the start of a DS-1 frame. There are 8
thousand S bits per second. They have an encoded pattern, to aid in
locating channel position within the frame.
:
: ![](s_bits.gif "fig:s_bits.gif")
This forms a regular pattern of 1 0 1 0 1 0 for the odd frames and 0 0 1
1 1 0 for the even frames. Additional synchronization information is
encoded in the DS-1 frame when it is used for digital data applications,
so lock is more readily acquired and maintained.
For data customers, channel 24 is reserved as a special sync byte, and
bit 8 of the other channels is used to indicate if the remaining 7 bits
are user data or system control information. Under such conditions, the
customer has an effective channel capacity of 56 Kbps.
To meet the needs of low speed customers, an additional bit is robbed to
support sub-rate multiplexer synchronization, leaving 6 x 8 Kbps = 48
Kbps available. Each DS-0 can be utilized as:
:
: • 5 x 9.6 Kbps channels or
: • 10 x 4.8 Kbps channels or
: • 20 x 2.48 Kbps channels.
In the DS-2 format, 4 DS-1 links are interleaved, 12 bits at a time. An
additional 136 Kbps is added for framing and control functions resulting
in a total bit rate of 6.312 Mbps.
#### Signaling
Signaling provides control and routing information. Two bits, called the
A and B bits, are taken from each channel in frames 6 and 12 in the
multiframe. The A bit is the least significant bit in each channel in
frame 6, and the B bit is the least significant bit in each channel in
frame 12. This provides a signaling rate of 666 2/3 bps per channel.
The quality of voice transmission is not noticeably affected when 2% of
the signal is robbed for signaling. For data, it may be a different
story. If the data is encoded in an analog format such as FSK or PSK,
then robbing bits is of no consequence, but if the data is already in
digital form, then robbing bits results in unacceptable error rates. It
is for this reason that in North America, a 64 Kbps clear channel cannot
readily be switched through the PSTN. This means that data customers are
limited to 56 Kbps clear channels. This simple condition has a profound
effect on the development of new services such as ISDN. In most
facilities, the A and B bits represent the status of the telephone hook
switch, and correspond to the M lead on the E&M interface of the calling
party.
#### ESF
CCITT has modified the North American digital hierarchy for the
deployment of ISDN, by means of recommendation G.704. ESF consists of 24
DS-0 channels in a frame, but groups them into a 24-frame multiframe
instead of the usual 12-frame multiframe.
The S bit is renamed the F bit, but only 1/4 of them are used for
synchronization. This is possible because of improvements in frame
search techniques and allows more signaling states to be defined.
Bit robbing is still used for signaling over an ESF link, but with the
advent of ISDN, it will not be permitted. Instead, channel 24 is used to
support a D channel.
:
: ![](ESF.gif "fig:ESF.gif")
#### Typical T1 CPE Application
The large telecom carriers are not the only ones who deploy high-speed
TDM facilities. In many cases, heavy users of voice or data services can
reduce their transmission costs by concentrating their numerous low
speed lines on to a high speed facility.
There are many types of T1 multiplexers available today. Some are
relatively simple devices, while others allow for channel concatenation,
thus supporting a wide range of data rates. The ability to support
multiple DS-0s allows for easy facilitation of such protocols as the
video teleconferencing standard, Px64.
:
: ![](T1_mux.gif "fig:T1_mux.gif")
#### Multiplexers
Multiplexing units are often designated by the generic term M~*ab*~
where*a* is input DS level and *b* is the output DS level. Thus, an M13
multiplexer combines 28 DS--1s into a single DS--3 and an M23
multiplexer combines 7 DS--2s into a single DS--3.
:
: ![](M13_mux.gif "fig:M13_mux.gif")
#### ZBTSI
ZBTSI (zero byte time slot interchange) is used on DS--4 links. Four
DS-1 frames are loaded into a register, and renumbered 1--96. If there
are any empty slots \[all zeros\], the first framing bit is inverted and
all blank slots are relocated to the front of the frame. Channel 1 is
then loaded with a 7-bit number corresponding to the original position
of the first empty slot. Bit 8 used to indicate whether the following
channel contains user information or another address for an empty slot.
If there is a second vacancy, bit 8 in the previous channel is set, and
the empty slot address is placed in channel 2. This process continues
until all empty positions are filled.
The decoding process at the receiver is done in reverse. Borrowing 1 in
4 framing bits for this system is not enough to cause loss of
synchronization and provides a 64 Kbps clear channel to the end-user.
### European TDM Carriers
European systems were developed along slightly different principles. The
64 Kbps channel is still the basic unit, but signaling is not included
in each channel. Instead, common channel signaling is used. In a level 1
carrier, channels 0 and 16 are reserved for signaling and control. This
subtle difference means that European systems did not experience the
toll fraud and 56 k bottlenecks common to North American systems, and
they experience a much larger penetration of ISDN services.
:
: ![](European_TDM.gif "fig:European_TDM.gif")
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: ![](E1_frame.gif "fig:E1_frame.gif")
## Zero Substitutions
In order to prevent transmission systems from loosing lock on the data
stream, it is necessary to avoid long strings of zeros. One of the most
effective ways of doing this is to replace the zeros with a
predetermined code. This substitution must be done in such a way that
the receiver can identify it and strip it off before passing the data
stream to the client.
AMI provides a simple means of detecting substitutions. In the normal
course of events, alternate marks are inverted. Therefor, deliberately
inducing a bipolarvariation at the transmitter can alert the receiver of
a substitution. However, a single violation is indistinguishable from a
transmission error. Consequently, some additional condition must also
occur.
There are two common methods to create a second condition:
: · Create a second bipolar violation in the opposite direction,
within a specified time. This has the effect of keeping the average
signal level at zero.
: · Count the number of marks from the last substitution to predict
the next type of violation
### B6ZS
B6ZS (binary six zero substitution) is used on T2 AMI transmission
links.
Synchronization can be maintained by replacing strings of zeros with
bipolar violations. Since alternate marks have alternate polarity, two
consecutive pulses of the same polarity constitute a violation.
Therefore, violations can be substituted for strings of zeros, and the
receiver can determine where substitutions were made.
Since the last mark may have been either positive (+) or negative (-),
there are two types of substitutions:
:
: ![](B6ZS_substitutions.gif "fig:B6ZS_substitutions.gif")
These substitutions force two consecutive violations. A single bit error
does not create this condition.
:
: ![](B6ZS_example.gif "fig:B6ZS_example.gif")
### B8ZS
This scheme uses the same substitution as B6ZS.
:
: ![](B8ZS_substitutions.gif "fig:B8ZS_substitutions.gif")
### B3ZS
B3ZS is more involved than B6ZS, and is used on DS--3 carrier systems.
The substitution is not only dependent on the polarity of the last mark,
but also on the number of marks since the last substitution.
:
: ![](B3ZS_substitutions.gif "fig:B3ZS_substitutions.gif")
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: ![](B3ZS_example.gif "fig:B3ZS_example.gif")
### HDB3
HDB3 (high density binary 3) introduces bipolar violations when four
consecutive zeros occur. It can therefore also be called B4ZS. The
second and thirds zeros are left unchanged, but the fourth zero is given
the same polarity as the last mark. The first zero may be modified to a
one to make sure that successive violations are of alternate polarity.
:
: ![](HDB3_substitutions.gif "fig:HDB3_substitutions.gif")
HDB3 is used in Europe. Violation, or V pulses are injected after three
consecutive zeros. The fourth zero is given the same polarity as the
last mark. In the event of long strings of zeros occurring, a succession
of single polarity pulses would occur, and a dc offset would build-up.
To prevent this, the first zero in a group of 4, may be modified to a 1.
This B or balancing pulse assures that successive violations are of
alternate polarity.
:
: ![](HDB3_waveform.gif "fig:HDB3_waveform.gif")
### Block Code Substitution
These schemes operate on bytes rather than a bit at a time. Some
transmit the signal as binary levels, but most use multi-level pulses.
Some authors categorize these as line codes.
A binary block code has the designation *n*B*m*B, where *n* input bits
are encoded into *m* output bits. The most common of these is the 3B4B
code.
:
: ![](3B4B_coding.gif "fig:3B4B_coding.gif")
In Europe 4B3T, which encodes 4 binary bits into 3 ternary levels, has
been selected as the BRA for ISDN. In North America, 2B1Q which encodes
2 binary bits into 1 quaternary level has been selected for BRA.
:
: ![](2B1Q_coding.gif "fig:2B1Q_coding.gif")
Some block codes do not generate multilevel pulses. For example, 24B1P
or 24B25B simply adds a P or parity bit to a 24 bit block.
## Benefits of TDM
TDM is all about cost: fewer wires and simpler receivers are used to
transmit data from multiple sources to multiple destinations. TDM also
uses less bandwidth than Frequency-Division Multiplexing (FDM) signals,
unless the bitrate is increased, which will subsequently increase the
necessary bandwidth of the transmission.
## Synchronous TDM
Synchronous TDM is a system where the transmitter and the receiver both
know exactly which signal is being sent. Consider the following diagram:
`Signal A ---> |---| |A|B|C|A|B|C| |------| ---> Signal A`\
`Signal B ---> |TDM| --------------> |De-TDM| ---> Signal B`\
`Signal C ---> |---| |------| ---> Signal C`
In this system, starting at time-slice 0, every third time-slice is
reserved for Signal A; starting at time-slice 1, every third time-slice
is reserved for Signal B; and starting at time-slice 2, every third
time-slice is reserved for Signal C. In this situation, the receiver
(De-TDM) needs only to switch after the signal on each time-slice is
received.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
The data flow of each input connection is divided into units where each
input occupies one input time slot. Each input connection has a time
slot alloted in the output irrespective of the fact whether it is
sending data or not.
` A -----|A3|A2|A1|---> |---| .............|C3|B3|A3|C2|B2|A2|C1|B1|A1| |------| ---> A`\
` | | | | | | |`\
` B -----|B3|B2|B1|---> |MUX| -------------|--------|--------|----------> |De-MUX| ---> B`\
` | | | | | | |`\
` C -----|C3|C2|C1|---> |---| | | | |------| ---> C`\
` <--> <-------->`\
` Bit Interval Frame (x seconds)`
Sync TDM is inefficient when one or more input lines have no data to
send. Thus, it is used with lines with high data traffic.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
Sampling rate is same for all signals. Maximum sampling rate = twice the
maximum frequency all the signals.
## Statistical TDM
Synchronous TDM is beneficial because the receiver and transmitter can
both cost very little. However, consider the most well-known network:
the Internet. In the Internet, a given computer might have a data rate
of 1kbps when hardly anything is happening, but might have a data rate
of 100kbps when downloading a large file from a fast server. How are the
time-slices divided in this instance? If every time slice is made big
enough to hold 100Kbps, when the computer isn\'t downloading any data,
all of that time and electricity will be wasted. If every time-slice is
only big enough for the minimum case, the time required to download
bigger files will be greatly increased.
The solution to this problem is called **Statistical TDM**, and is the
solution that the Internet currently uses. In Statistical TDM, each data
item, known as the payload (we used time-slices to describe these
earlier), is appended with a certain amount of information about who
sent it, and who is supposed to receive it (the header). The combination
of a payload and a header is called a **packet**. Packets are like
envelopes in the traditional \"snail mail\" system: Each packet contains
a destination address and a return address as well as some enclosed
data. Because of this, we know where each packet was sent from and where
it is going.
The downside to statistical TDM is that the sender needs to be smart
enough to write a header, and the receiver needs to be smart enough to
read the header and (if the packet is to be forwarded,) send the packet
toward its destination.
### Link Utilization
Statistical multiplexing attempts to maximize the use of a communication
path. The study of this is often called *queuing theory*. A queue is
simply a line of customers or packets waiting to be served. Under most
circumstances, the arrival rate is unpredictable and therefor follows a
random or Poisson distribution pattern, whereas the service time is
constant.
The utilization or fraction of time actually used by a packet
multiplexing system to process packets is given by:
:
: ![](Utilization.gif "fig:Utilization.gif")
The queue length or average number of items waiting to be served is
given by:
$$q = \frac{{\rho ^2 }}{{2\left( {1 - \rho } \right)}} + \rho$$
:
: ![](Queue_length.gif "fig:Queue_length.gif")
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: **Example**
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: A T1 link has been divided into a number of 9.6 Kbps channels
and has a combined user data rate of 1.152 Mbps. Access to this
channel is offered to 100 customers, each requiring 9.6 Kbps
data 20% of the time. If the user arrival time is strictly
random find the T1 link utilization.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: **Solution**
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: The utilization or fraction of time used by the system to
process packets is given by:
$$\rho = \frac{{\alpha NR}}{M} = \frac{{0.2 \times 100 \times 9.6 \times 10^3 }}{{1.152 \times 10^6 }} = 0.167$$
:
: A 24 channel system dedicated to DATA, can place five 9.6 Kbps
customers in each of 23 channels, for a total of 115 customers.
In the above statistical link, 100 customers created an
*average* utilization of 0.167 and were easily fitted, with room
to spare if they transmit on the average 20% of the time. If
however, the customer usage were not randomly distributed, then
the above analysis would have to be modified.
This example shows the potential for statistical multiplexing. If
channels were assigned on a demand basis (only when the customer had
something to send), a single T1 may be able to support hundreds of low
volume users.
A utilization above 0.8 is undesirable in a statistical system, since
the slightest variation in customer requests for service would lead to
buffer overflow. Service providers carefully monitor delay and
utilization and assign customers to maximize utilization and minimize
cost.
## Packets
Packets will be discussed in greater detail once we start talking about
digital networks (specifically the Internet). Packet headers not only
contain address information, but may also include a number of different
fields that will display information about the packet. Many headers
contain error-checking information (checksum, Cyclic Redundancy Check)
that enables the receiver to check if the packet has had any errors due
to interference, such as electrical noise.
## Duty Cycles
Duty cycle is defined as \" the time that is effectively used to send or
receive the data, expressed as a percentage of total period of time.\"
The more the duty cycle , the more effective transmission or reception.
We can define the pulse width, τ, as being the time that a bit occupies
from within its total alloted bit-time *T~b~*. If we have a duty cycle
of *D*, we can define the pulse width as:
$$\tau = DT_b$$
Where:
$$0 < \tau \le T_b$$
The pulse width is equal to the bit time if we are using a 100% duty
cycle.
|
# Communication Systems/Frequency-Division Multiplexing
## Introduction
It turns out that many wires have a much higher bandwidth than is needed
for the signals that they are currently carrying. Analog Telephone
transmissions, for instance, require only 3 000 Hz of bandwidth to
transmit human voice signals. Over short distances, however,
twisted-pair telephone wire has an available bandwidth of nearly
100000 Hz!
There are several terrestrial radio based communications systems
deployed today. They include:
- Cellular radio
- Mobile radio
- Digital microwave radio
Mobile radio service was first introduced in the St. Louis in 1946. This
system was essentially a radio dispatching system with an operator who
was able to patch the caller to the PSTN via a switchboard. Later, an
improved mobile telephone system, IMTS, allowed customers to dial their
own calls without the need for an operator. This in turn developed into
the cellular radio networks we see today.
The long haul PSTNs and packet data networks use a wide variety of
transmission media including
- Terrestrial microwave
- Satellite microwave
- Fiber optics
- Coaxial cable
In this section, we will be concerned with terrestrial microwave
systems. Originally, microwave links used FDM exclusively as the access
technique, but recent developments are changing analog systems to
digital where TDM is more appropriate.
### Fixed Access Assignment
Three basic methods can be used to combine customers on to fixed channel
radio links:
- FDMA - (Frequency division multiple access) analog or digital
- TDMA - (Time division multiple access) three conversation paths are
time division multiplexed in 6.7 mSec time slots on a single
carrier.
- CDMA - (Code division multiple access) this uses spread spectrum
techniques to increase the subscriber density. The transmitter hops
through a pseudo-random sequence of frequencies. The receiver is
given the sequence list and is able to follow the transmitter. As
more customers are added to the system, the signal to noise will
gradually degrade. This is in contrast to AMPS where customers are
denied access once all of the frequencies are assigned code division
multiple access \[digital only\]
:
: ![](Fixed_assgnment_access.gif "fig:Fixed_assgnment_access.gif")
## What is FDM?
**Frequency Division Multiplexing** (FDM) allows engineers to utilize
the extra space in each wire to carry more than one signal. By
frequency-shifting some signals by a certain amount, engineers can shift
the spectrum of that signal up into the unused band on that wire. In
this way, multiple signals can be carried on the same wire, without
having to divy up time-slices as in Time-Division Multiplexing
schemes.In analog transmission, signals are commonly multiplexed using
frequency-division multiplexing (FDM), in which the carrier bandwidth is
divided into subchannels of different frequency widths, each carrying a
signal at the same time in parallel
Traditional terrestrial microwave and satellite links employ FDM.
Although FDM in telecommunications is being reduced, several systems
will continue to use this technique, namely: broadcast & cable TV, and
commercial & cellular radio.
### Analog Carrier Systems
The standard telephony voice band \[300 -- 3400 Hz\] is heterodyned and
stacked on high frequency carriers by single sideband amplitude
modulation. This is the most bandwidth efficient scheme possible.
:
: ![](Single_voice_channel.gif "fig:Single_voice_channel.gif")
The analog voice channels are pre-grouped into threes and heterodyned on
carriers at 12, 16, and 20 kHz. The resulting upper sidebands of four
such pregroups are then heterodyned on carriers at 84, 96, 108, and
120 kHz to form a 12-channel group.
Since the lower sideband is selected in the second mixing stage, the
channel sequence is reversed and a frequency inversion occurs within
each channel.
:
: ![](12_channel_group.gif "fig:12_channel_group.gif")
This process can continue until the available bandwidth on the coaxial
cable or microwave link is exhausted.
:
: ![](Analog_carrier_systems.gif "fig:Analog_carrier_systems.gif")
In the North American system, there are:
- 12 channels per group
- 5 groups per supergroup
- 10 super groups per mastergroup
- 6 master groups per jumbogroup
In the European CCITT system, there are:
- 12 channels per group
- 5 groups per supergroup
- 5 super groups per mastergroup
- 3 master groups per supermastergroup
There are other FDM schemes including:
- L600 - 600 voice channels 60--2788 kHz
- U600 - 600 voice channels 564--3084 kHz
- L3 - 1860 voice channels 312--8284 kHz, comprised of 3 mastergroups
and a supergroup
- L4 - 3600 voice channels, comprised of six U600s
## Benefits of FDM
FDM allows engineers to transmit multiple data streams simultaneously
over the same channel, at the expense of bandwidth. To that extent, FDM
provides a trade-off: faster data for less bandwidth. Also, to
demultiplex an FDM signal requires a series of bandpass filters to
isolate each individual signal. Bandpass filters are relatively
complicated and expensive, therefore the receivers in an FDM system are
generally expensive.
## Examples of FDM
As an example of an FDM system, Commercial broadcast radio (AM and FM
radio) simultaneously transmits multiple signals or \"stations\" over
the airwaves. These stations each get their own frequency band to use,
and a radio can be tuned to receive each different station. Another good
example is cable television, which simultaneously transmits every
channel, and the TV \"tunes in\" to which channel it wants to watch.
## Orthogonal FDM
Orthogonal Frequency Division Multiplexing (OFDM) is a more modern
variant of FDM that uses orthogonal sub-carriers to transmit data that
does not overlap in the frequency spectrum and is able to be separated
out using frequency methods. OFDM has a similar data rate to traditional
FDM systems, but has a higher resilience to disruptive channel
conditions such as noise and channel fading.
|
# Communication Systems/What is Modulation?
Modulation is a term that is going to be used very frequently in this
book. So much in fact, that we could almost have renamed this book
\"Principles of Modulation\", without having to delete too many
chapters. So, the logical question arises: What exactly is modulation?
## Definition
**Modulation** is a process of mixing a signal with a sinusoid to
produce a new signal. This new signal, conceivably, will have certain
benefits over an un-modulated signal. Mixing of low frequency signal
with high frequency carrier signal is called modulation.
$$f(t) = A \sin(\omega t + \phi)$$
we can see that this sinusoid has 3 parameters that can be altered, to
affect the shape of the graph. The first term, A, is called the
magnitude, or amplitude of the sinusoid. The next term, $\omega$ is
known as the frequency, and the last term, $\phi$ is known as the phase
angle. All 3 parameters can be altered to transmit data.
The sinusoidal signal that is used in the modulation is known as the
**carrier signal**, or simply \"the carrier\". The signal that is used
in modulating the carrier signal(or sinusoidal signal) is known as the
\"data signal\" or the \"message signal\". It is important to notice
that a simple sinusoidal carrier contains no information of its own.
In other words we can say that modulation is used because some data
signals are not always suitable for direct transmission, but the
modulated signal may be more suitable.
## Types of Modulation
There are 3 basic types of modulation: Amplitude modulation, Frequency
modulation, and Phase modulation.
amplitude modulation
: a type of modulation where the amplitude of the carrier signal is
modulated (changed) in proportion to the message signal while the
frequency and phase are kept constant.
frequency modulation
: a type of modulation where the frequency of the carrier signal is
modulated (changed) in proportion to the message signal while the
amplitude and phase are kept constant.
phase modulation
: a type of modulation where the phase of the carrier signal is varied
accordance to the low frequency of the message signal is known as
phase modulation.
## Why Use Modulation?
Why use modulation at all? To answer this question, let\'s consider a
channel that essentially acts like a bandpass filter: both the lowest
frequency components and the highest frequency components are attenuated
or unusable in some way, with transmission only being practical over
some intermediate frequency range. If we can\'t send low-frequency
signals, then we need to shift our signal up the frequency ladder.
Modulation allows us to send a signal over a bandpass frequency range.
If every signal gets its own frequency range, then we can transmit
multiple signals *simultaneously* over a single channel, all using
different frequency ranges.
Another reason to modulate a signal is to allow the use of a smaller
antenna. A baseband (low frequency) signal would need a huge antenna
because in order to be efficient, the antenna needs to be about 1/10th
the length of the wavelength. Modulation shifts the baseband signal up
to a much higher frequency, which has much smaller wavelengths and
allows the use of a much smaller antenna.
## Examples
Think about your car radio. There are more than a dozen (or so) channels
on the radio at any time, each with a given frequency: 100.1 MHz,
102.5 MHz etc\... Each channel gets a certain range (usually about
0.22 MHz), and the entire bayot gets transmitted over that range.
Modulation makes it all possible, because it allows us to send voice and
music (which are essential baseband signals) over a bandpass (or
\"Broadband\") channel.
## Non-sinusoidal modulation
A sine wave at one frequency can be separated from a sine wave at
another frequency (or a cosine wave at the same frequency) because the
two signals are \"orthogonal\".
There are other sets of signals, such that every signal in the set is
orthogonal to every other signal in the set.
A simple orthogonal set is time multiplexed division (TDM) \-- only one
transmitter is active at any one time.
Other more complicated sets of orthogonal waveforms---Walsh codes and
various pseudo-noise codes such as Gold codes and maximum length
sequences---are also used in some communication systems.
The process of combining these waveforms with data signals is sometimes
called \"modulation\", because it is so very similar to the way
modulation combines sine waves with data signals.
## Further reading
- Data Coding Theory/Spectrum
Spreading
- Wikipedia:Walsh code
- Wikipedia:Gold code
- Wikipedia:pseudonoise code
- Wikipedia:maximum length
sequence
|
# Communication Systems/Analog vs. Digital
There is lots of talk nowadays about buzzwords such as \"Analog\" and
\"Digital\". Certainly, engineers who are interested in creating a new
communication system should understand the difference. Which is better,
analog or digital? What is the difference? What are the pros and cons of
each? This chapter will look at the answers to some of these questions.
## What are They?
What exactly is an analog signal, and what is a digital signal?
Analog : Analog signals are continuous in both time and value. Analog signals are used in many systems, although the use of analog signals has declined with the advent of cheap digital signals. All natural signals are Analog in nature or analog signal is that signal which amplitude on Y axis change with time on X axis\...
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
Digital : Digital signals are discrete in time and value. Digital signals are signals that are represented by binary numbers, \"1\" or \"0\". The 1 and 0 values can correspond to different discrete voltage values, and any signal that *doesn\'t quite fit* into the scheme just gets rounded off.
or digital signal is that signal which have certain or fixed value on Y
axis change with time on X axis\...
Digital signals are sampled, quantized & encoded version of continuous
time signals which they represent. In addition, some techniques also
make the signal undergo encryption to make the system more tolerant to
the channel.
## What are the Pros and Cons?
Each paradigm has its own benefits and problems
Analog : Analog systems are less tolerant to noise, make good use of bandwidth, and are easy to manipulate mathematically. However, analog signals require hardware receivers and transmitters that are designed to perfectly fit the particular transmission.\
Digital : Digital signals are more tolerant to noise, but digital signals can be completely corrupted in the presence of excess noise. In digital signals, noise could cause a 1 to be interpreted as a 0 and vice versa, which makes the received data different than the original data. Imagine if the army transmitted a position coordinate to a missile digitally, and a single bit was received in error. This single bit error could cause a missile to miss its target by miles. Luckily, there are systems in place to prevent this sort of scenario, such as checksums and CRCs, which tell the receiver when a bit has been corrupted and ask the transmitter to resend the data. The primary benefit of digital signals is that they can be handled by simple, standardized receivers and transmitters, and the signal can be then dealt with in software (which is comparatively cheap to change).
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
Discrete Digital and Analogue:
Discrete data has a fixed set of possible values.\
Digital data is a type of Discrete data where the fixed value can either
be 1 or 0.\
Analogue data can take on any real value.
## Sampling and Reconstruction
The process of converting from analog data to digital data is called
\"sampling\". The process of recreating an analog signal from a digital
one is called \"reconstruction\". This book will not talk about either
of these subjects in much depth beyond this, although other books on the
topic of EE might, such as A-level Physics (Advancing
Physics)/Digitisation/Digitisation "wikilink").
## Further reading
- Electronics/Digital to Analog & Analog to Digital
Converters
|
# Communication Systems/Communication Mediums
Signals need a channel to follow, so that they can move from place to
place. These **Communication Mediums**, or \"channels\" are things like
wires and antennae that transmit the signal from one location to
another. Some of the most common channels are listed below:
## Twisted Pair Wire
**Twisted Pair** is a transmission medium that uses two conductors that
are twisted together to form a pair. The concept for the twist of the
conductors is to prevent interference. Ideally, each conductor of the
pair basically receives the same amount of interference, positive and
negative, effectively cancelling the effect of the interference.
Typically, most inside cabling has four pairs with each pair having a
different twist rate. The different twist rates help to further reduce
the chance of crosstalk by making the pairs appear electrically
different in reference to each other. If the pairs all had the same
twist rate, they would be electrically identical in reference to each
other causing crosstalk, which is also referred to as capacitive
coupling. Twisted pair wire is commonly used in telephone and data
cables with variations of categories and twist rates.
Other variants of Twisted Pair are the **Shielded Twisted Pair** cables.
The shielded types operate very similar to the non-shielded variety,
except that Shielded Twisted Pair also has a layer of metal foil or mesh
shielding around all the pairs or each individual pair to further shield
the pairs from electromagnetic interference. Shielded twisted pair is
typically deployed in situations where the cabling is subjected to
higher than normal levels of interference.
## Coaxial Cable
Another common type of wire is **Coaxial Cable**. Coaxial cable (or
simply, \"coax\") is a type of cable with a single data line, surrounded
by various layers of padding and shielding. The most common coax cable,
common television cable, has a layer of wire mesh surrounding the padded
core, that absorbs a large amount of EM interference, and helps to
ensure a relatively clean signal is transmitted and received. Coax cable
has a much higher bandwidth than a twisted pair, but coax is also
significantly more expensive than an equal length of twisted pair wire.
Coax cable frequently has an available bandwidth in excess of hundreds
of megahertz (in comparison with the hundreds of kilohertz available on
twisted pair wires).
Originally, Coax cable was used as the backbone of the telephone network
because a single coaxial cable could hold hundreds of simultaneous phone
calls by a method known as \"Frequency Division Multiplexing\"
(discussed in a later chapter). Recently however, Fiber Optic cables
have replaced Coaxial Cable as the backbone of the telephone network
because Fiber Optic channels can hold many more simultaneous phone
conversations (thousands at a time), and are less susceptible to
interference, crosstalk, and noise then Coaxial Cable.
## Fiber Optics
**Fiber Optic** cables are thin strands of glass that carry pulses of
light (frequently infrared light) across long distances. Fiber Optic
channels are usually immune to common RF interference, and can transmit
incredibly high amounts of data very quickly. There are 2 general types
of fiber optic cable: single frequency cable, and multi-frequency cable.
single frequency cable carries only a single frequency of laser light,
and because of this there is no self-interference on the line.
Single-frequency fiber optic cables can attain incredible bandwidths of
many gigahertz. Multi-Frequency fiber optics cables allow a
Frequency-Division Multiplexed series of signals to each inhabit a given
frequency range. However, interference between the different signals can
decrease the range over which reliable data can be transmitted.
## Wireless Transmission
In **wireless transmission systems**, signals are propagated as
Electro-Magnetic waves through free space. Wireless signals are
transmitted by a transmitter, and received by a receiver. Wireless
systems are inexpensive because no wires need to be installed to
transmit the signal, but wireless transmissions are susceptible not only
to EM interference, but also to physical interference. A large building
in a city, for instance can interfere with cell-phone reception, and a
large mountain could block AM radio transmissions. Also, WiFi internet
users may have noticed that their wireless internet signals don\'t
travel through walls very well.
There are 2 types of antennas that are used in wireless communications,
**isotropic**, and **directional**.
### Isotropic
People should be familiar with isotropic antennas because they are
everywhere: in your car, on your radio, etc\... Isotropic antennas are
omni-directional in the sense that they transmit data out equally (or
nearly equally) in all directions. These antennas are excellent for
systems (such as FM radio transmission) that need to transmit data to
multiple receivers in multiple directions. Also, Isotropic antennas are
good for systems in which the direction of the receiver, relative to the
transmitter is not known (such as cellular phone systems).
### Directional
Directional antennas focus their transmission power in a single narrow
direction range. Some examples of directional antennas are satellite
dishes, and wave-guides. The downfall of the directional antennas is
that they need to be pointed directly at the receiver all the time to
maintain transmission power. This is useful when the receiver and the
transmitter are not moving (such as in communicating with a
geo-synchronous satellite).
|
# Communication Systems/Coherent Receivers
## Receiver Design
It turns out that if we know what kind of signal to expect, we can
better receive those signals. This should be intuitive, because it is
hard to find something if we don\'t know what precisely we are looking
for. How is a receiver supposed to know what is data and what is noise,
if it doesnt know what data looks like?
Coherent transmissions are transmissions where the receiver knows what
type of data is being sent. Coherency implies a strict timing mechanism,
because even a data signal may look like noise if you look at the wrong
part of it. In contrast, noncoherent receivers don\'t know exactly what
they are looking for, and therefore noncoherent communication systems
need to be far more complex (both in terms of hardware and mathematical
models) to operate properly.
This section will talk about coherent receivers, first discussing the
\"Simple Receiver\" case, and then going into theory about what the
optimal case is. Once we know mathematically what an optimal receiver
should be, we then discuss two actual implementations of the optimal
receiver.
It should be noted that the remainder of this book will discuss optimal
receivers. After all, why would a communication\'s engineer use anything
that is less than the best?
## The Simple Receiver
A simple receiver is just that: simple. A general simple receiver will
consist of a low-pass filter (to remove excess high-frequency noise),
and then a sampler, that will select values at certain points in the
wave, and interpolate those values to form a smooth output curve. In
place of a sampler (for purely analog systems), a general envelope
filter can also be used, especially in AM systems. In other systems,
different tricks can be used to demodulate an input signal, and acquire
the data. However simple receivers, while cheap, are not the best choice
for a receiver. Occasionally they are employed because of their price,
but where performance is an issue, a better alternative receiver should
be used.
## The Optimal Receiver
Engineers are able to mathematically predict the structure of the
optimal receiver. Read that sentence again: Engineers are able to
design, analyze, and build the best possible receiver, for any given
signal. This is an important development for several reasons. First, it
means that no more research should go into finding a better receiver.
The best receiver has already been found, after all. Second, it means
any communications system will not be hampered (much) by the receiver.
### Derivation
here we will attempt to show how the coherent receiver is derived.
### Matched Receiver
The matched receiver is the logical conclusion of the optimal receiver
calculation. The matched receiver convolves the signal with itself, and
then tests the output. Here is a diagram:
`s(t)----->(Convolve with r(t))----->`
This looks simple enough, except that convolution modules are often
expensive. An alternative to this approach is to use a correlation
receiver.
### Correlation Receiver
The correlation receiver is similar to the matched receiver, instead
with a simple switch: The multiplication happens first, and the
integration happens second.
Here is a general diagram:
` r(t)`\
` |`\
` v`\
`s(t) ----->(X)----->(Integrator)--->`
In a digital system, the integrator would then be followed by a
threshold detector, while in an analog receiver, it might be followed by
another detector, like an envelope detector.
## Conclusion
To do the best job of receiving a signal we need to know the form of the
signal that we are sending. After all we can\'t design a receiver until
after we\'ve decided how the signal will be sent. This method poses some
problems in that the receiver must be able to line up the received
signal with the given reference signal to work the magic: if the
received signal and the reference signal are out of sync with each
other, either as a function of an error in phase or an error in
frequency, then the optimal receiver will not work.
## Further reading
|
# Communication Systems/Analog Modulation Introduction
## Analog Modulation Overview
Let\'s take a look at a generalized sinewave:
$$x\left( t \right) = A\sin \left( {\omega t + \theta } \right)$$ It
consists of three components namely; amplitude, frequency and phase.
Each of which can be decomposed to provide finer detail:
$$x(t) = A s(t) \sin ( 2 \pi [f_c + kf_m(t)] t + \alpha \phi(t) )$$
## Types of Analog Modulation
We can see 3 parameters that can be changed in this sine wave to send
information:
- $A s(t)$. This term is called the \"Amplitude\", and changing it is
called \"Amplitude Modulation\" (AM)
- $kf_m(t)$ This term is called the \"Frequency Shift\", and changing
it is called \"Frequency Modulation\"
- $\alpha \phi (t)$. this term is called the \"Phase angle\", and
changing it is called \"Phase Modulation\".
- The terms frequency and phase modulation are often combined into a
more general group called \"Angle Modulation\".
## The Breakdown
Each term consists of a coefficient (called a \"scaling factor\"), and a
function of time that corresponds to the information that we want to
send. The scaling factor out front, A, is also used as the transmission
power coefficient. When a radio station wants their signal to be
stronger (regardless of whether it is AM, FM, or PM), they \"crank-up\"
the power of A, and send more power out onto the airwaves.
## How we Will Cover the Material
We are going to go into separate chapters for each different type of
modulation. This book will attempt to discuss some of the mathematical
models and techniques used with different modulation techniques. It will
also discuss some practical information about how to construct a
transmitter/receiver, and how to use each modulation technique
effectively.
|
# Communication Systems/FM and PM Generalization
## Concept
We can see from our initial overviews that FM and PM modulation schemes
have a lot in common. Both of them are altering the angle of the carrier
sinusoid according to some function. It turns out that we can go so far
as to generalize the two together into a single modulation scheme known
as **angle modulation**. Note that we will never abbreviate \"angle
modulation\" with the letters \"AM\", because Amplitude modulation is
completely different from angle modulation.
## Instantaneous Phase
Let us now look at some things that FM and PM have of common:
$$s_{FM} = A\cos (2 \pi [f_c + ks(t)]t + \phi)$$
$$s_{PM} = A\cos (2 \pi f_c t + \alpha s(t))$$
What we want to analyze is the *argument of the sinusoid*, and we will
call it Psi. Let us show the Psi for the bare carrier, the FM case, and
the PM case:
$$\Psi_{carrier}(t) = 2 \pi f_c t + \phi$$
$$\Psi_{FM}(t) = 2 \pi[f_c + ks(t)] t + \phi$$
$$\Psi_{PM}(t) = 2 \pi f_c t + \alpha s(t)$$
$$s(t) = A\cos(\Psi(t))$$
This Psi value is called the *Instantaneous phase* of the sinusoid.
## Instantaneous Frequency
Using the Instantaneous phase value, we can find the *Instantaneous
frequency* of the wave with the following formula:
$$f(t) = \frac{d\Psi(t)}{dt}$$
We can also express the instantaneous phase in terms of the
instantaneous frequency:
$$\Psi(t) = \int_{-\infty}^t f(\lambda)d\lambda$$
Where the Greek letter \"lambda\" is simply a dummy variable used for
integration. Using these relationships, we can begin to study FM and PM
signals further.
## Determining FM or PM
If we are given the equation for the instantaneous phase of a particular
angle modulated transmission, is it possible to determine if the
transmission is using FM or PM? it turns out that it is possible to
determine which is which, by following 2 simple rules:
1. In PM, instantaneous phase is a linear function.
2. In FM, instantaneous frequency minus carrier frequency is a linear
function.
For a refresher course on Linearity, there is a chapter on the subject
in the Signals and Systems
book
worth re-reading.
## Bandwidth
In a PM system, we know that the value $\alpha s(t)$ can never go
outside the bounds of $(-\pi, \pi]$. Since sinusoidal functions
oscillate between \[-1, 1\], we can use them as a general PM generating
function. Now, we can combine FM and PM signals into a general equation,
called *angle modulation*:
$$v(t) = A \sin ( 2 \pi f_c t + \beta \sin (2 \pi f_m t))$$
If we want to analyze the spectral components of this equation, we will
need to take the Fourier transform of this. But, we can\'t integrate a
sinusoid of a sinusoid, much less find the transform of it. So, what do
we do?
It turns out (and the derivation will be omitted here, for now) that we
can express this equation as an infinite sum, as such:
$$v(t) = A \sum_{n = -\infty}^{\infty}J_n(\beta) \sin [2 \pi(nf_m + f_c)t]$$
But, what is the term $J_n(\beta)$? J is the *Bessel function*, which is
a function that exists only as an open integral (it is impossible to
write it in closed form). Fortunately for us, there are extensive tables
tabulating Bessle function values.
## The Bessel Function
The definition of the Bessel function is the following equation:
$$J_n(\beta) = \frac{1}{2\pi} \int_{-\pi}^\pi e^{j[\beta sin\theta - n\theta]} d\theta$$
The bessel function is a function of 2 variables, N and $\beta$.
Bessel Functions have the following properties:
- If n is even:
$$J_{-n}(\beta) = J_n(\beta)$$
- If n is odd:
$$J_{-n}(\beta) = -J_n(\beta)$$
- $J_{n-1} + J_{n+1} = \frac{2n}{\beta}J_n(\beta)$.
The bessel function is a relatively advanced mathematical tool, and we
will not analyze it further in this book.
## Carson\'s Rule
If we have our generalized function:
$$v(t) = A\sin ( 2 \pi f_c t + \beta \sin (2 \pi f_m t))$$
We can find the bandwidth BW of the signal using the following formula:
$$BW=2(\beta + 1)f_m = 2(\Delta f + f_m)$$
where $\Delta f$ is the maximum frequency deviation, of the transmitted
signal, from the carrier frequency. It is important to note that
Carson\'s rule is only an approximation (albeit one that is used in
industry frequently).
## Demodulation: First Step
Now, it is important to note that FM and PM signals both do the same
first 2 steps during demodulation:
1. Pass the signal through a **limiter**, to remove amplitude peaks
2. Pass the signal through a bandpass filter to remove low and high
frequency noise (as much as possible, without filtering out the
signal).
Once we perform these two steps, we no longer have white noise, because
we\'ve passed the noise through a filter. Now, we say the noise is
**colored**.
here is a basic diagram of our demodulator, so far:
` channel`\
`s(t) ---------> r(t) --->|Limiter|--->|Bandpass Filter|---->z(t)`
Where z(t) is the output of the bandpass filter.
## Filtered Noise
To denote the new, filtered noise, and new filtered signal, we have the
following equation:
$$z(t) = \gamma A \cos (\Psi(t)) + n_0(t)$$
Where we call the additive noise $n_0(t)$ because it has been filtered,
and is not white noise anymore. $n_0(t)$ is known as **narrow band
noise**, and can be denoted as such:
$$n_0(t) = \mathbf{W}(t) \cos(2 \pi f_c t) + \mathbf{Z}(t) \sin(2 \pi f_c t)$$
Now, once we have it in this form, we can use a trigonometric identity
to make this equation more simple:
$$n_0(t) = \mathbf{R}(t) \cos(2 \pi f_c t + \mathbf{\Theta}(t))$$
Where
$$\mathbf{R}(t) = \sqrt{\mathbf{W}(t)^2 + \mathbf{Z}(t)^2}$$
$$\mathbf{\Theta}(t) = tan^{-1} (\mathbf{Z}(t)/\mathbf{W(t)})$$
Here, the new noise parameter R(t) is a **rayleigh** random variable,
and is discussed in the next chapter.
## Noise Analysis
R(t) is a noise function that affects the amplitude of our received
signal. However, our receiver passes the signal through a limiter, which
will remove amplitude fluctuations from our signal. For this reason,
R(t) doesnt affect our signal, and can be safely ignored for now. This
means that the only random variable that is affecting our signal is the
variable $\mathbf{\Theta}(t)$, \"Theta\". Theta is a uniform random
variable, with values between pi and -pi. Values outside this range
\"Wrap around\" because phase is circular.
|
# Communication Systems/AM Receivers
## AM Receivers
The most common receivers in use today are the super heterodyne type.
They consist of:
::\*Antenna
::\*RF amplifier
::\*Local Oscillator and Mixer
::\*IF Section
::\*Detector and Amplifier
The need for these subsystems can be seen when one considers the much
simpler and inadequate TRF or tuned radio frequency amplifier.
### TRF Amplifier
It is possible to design an RF amplifier to accept only a narrow range
of frequencies, such as one radio station on the AM band.
:
: ![](TRF_amplifier.gif "fig:TRF_amplifier.gif")
By adjusting the center frequency of the tuned circuit, all other input
signals can be excluded.
:
: ![](Channel_selection.gif "fig:Channel_selection.gif")
The AM band ranges from about 500 kHz to 1600 kHz. Each station requires
10 kHz of this spectrum, although the baseband signal is only 5 kHz.
Recall that for a tuned circuit: $Q = \frac{{f_c }}{B}$. The center or
resonant frequency in an RLC network is most often adjusted by varying
the capacitor value. However, the Q remains approximately constant as
the center frequency is adjusted. This suggests that as the bandwidth
varies as the circuit is tuned.
:
: For example, the Q required at the lower end of the AM band to
select only one radio station would be approximately:
$$Q = \frac{{f_c }}{B} = \frac{{500\;kHz}}{{10\;kHz}} = 50$$
:
: As the tuned circuit is adjusted to the higher end of the AM
band, the resulting bandwidth is:
$$B = \frac{{f_c }}{Q} = \frac{{1600\;kHz}}{{50}} = 30\;kHz$$
A bandwidth this high could conceivably pass three adjacent stations,
thus making meaningful reception impossible.
To prevent this, the incoming RF signal is heterodyned to a fixed IF or
intermediate frequency and passed through a constant bandwidth circuit.
### Superheterodyne Receiver
:
: ![](Heterodyne.gif "fig:Heterodyne.gif")
The RF amplifier boosts the RF signal into the mixer. It has broad
tuning and amplifies not just one RF station, but many of them
simultaneously. It also amplifies any input noise and even contributes
some of its own.
The other mixer input is a high frequency sine wave created by a local
oscillator. In AM receivers, it is always 455 kHz above the desired
station carrier frequency. An ideal mixer will combine the incoming
carrier with the local oscillator to create sum and difference
frequencies. .
A real mixer combines two signals and creates a host of new frequencies:
:
: • A dc level
: • The original two frequencies
: • The sum and difference of the two input frequencies
: • Harmonics of the two input frequencies
: • Sums and differences of all of the harmonics
Since the RF amplifier passes several radio stations at once, the mixer
output can be very complex. However, the only signal of real interest is
the difference between the desired station carrier frequency and the
local oscillator frequency. This difference frequency, also called the
IF (intermediate frequency) will alway be 455 kHz. By passing this
through a 10 kHz BPF (band pass filter) centered at 455 kHz, the bulk of
the unwanted signals can be eliminated.
#### Local Oscillator Frequency
Since the mixer generates sum and difference frequencies, it is possible
to generate the 455 kHz IF signal if the local oscillator is either
above or below the IF. The inevitable question is which is preferable.
:
: **Case I The local Oscillator is above the IF.** This would
require that the oscillator tune from (500 + 455) kHz to
(1600 + 455) kHz or approximately 1 to 2 MHz. It is normally the
capacitor in a tuned RLC circuit, which is varied to adjust the
center frequency while the inductor is left fixed.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: Since $f_c = \frac{1}{{2\pi \sqrt {LC} }}$
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: solving for *C* we obtain
$C = \frac{1}{{L\left( {2\pi f_c } \right)^2 }}$
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: When the tuning frequency is a maximum, the tuning capacitor is
a minimum and vice versa. Since we know the range of frequencies
to be created, we can deduce the range of capacitance required.
$$\frac{{C_{\max } }}{{C_{\min } }} = \frac{{L\left( {2\pi f_{\max } } \right)^2 }}{{L\left( {2\pi f_{\min } } \right)^2 }} = \left( {\frac{{2\;MHz}}{{1\;MHz}}} \right)^2 = 4$$
Making a capacitor with a 4:1 value change is well within the realm of
possibility.
:
: **Case II The local Oscillator is below the IF**. This would
require that the oscillator tune from (500 - 455) kHz to
(1600 - 455) kHz or approximately 45 kHz to 1145 kHz, in which
case:
$$\frac{{C_{\max } }}{{C_{\min } }} = \left( {\frac{{1145\;kHz}}{{45\;kHz}}} \right)^2 \approx 648$$
It is not practical to make a tunable capacitor with this type of range.
Therefore the local oscillator in a standard AM receiver is above the
radio band.
#### Image Frequency
Just as there are two oscillator frequencies, which can create the same
IF, two different station frequencies can create the IF. The undesired
station frequency is known as the image frequency.
;;;![](Image_frequency.gif "Image_frequency.gif")
If any circuit in the radio front end exhibits non-linearities, there is
a possibility that other combinations may create the intermediate
frequency. Once the image frequency is in the mixer, there is no way to
remove it since it is now heterodyned into the same IF band as the
desired station.
### AM Detection
There are two basic types of AM detection, coherent and non-coherent. Of
these two, the non-coherent is the simpler method.
::\*Non-coherent detection does not rely on regenerating the carrier
signal. The information or modulation envelope can be removed or
detected by a diode followed by an audio filter.
::\*Coherent detection relies on regenerating the carrier and mixing it
with the AM signal. This creates sum and difference frequencies. The
difference frequency corresponds to the original modulation signal.
Both of these detection techniques have certain drawbacks. Consequently,
most radio receivers use a combination of both.
#### Envelope Detector
:
: ![](Envelope_detector.gif "fig:Envelope_detector.gif")
An envelope detector is simply a half wave rectifier followed by a low
pass filter. In the case of commercial AM radio receivers, the detector
is placed after the IF section. The carrier at this point is 455 kHz
while the maximum envelope frequency is only 5 kHz. Since the ripple
component is nearly 100 times the frequency of the highest baseband
signal and does not pass through any subsequent audio amplifiers.
:
: An AM signal where the carrier frequency is only 10 times the
envelope frequency would have considerable ripple:
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: ![](Exagerated_am_ripple.gif "fig:Exagerated_am_ripple.gif"){width="300"}
#### Synchronous Detector
In a synchronous or coherent detector, the incoming AM signal is mixed
with the original carrier frequency.
:
: ![](Synchronous_detector.gif "fig:Synchronous_detector.gif")
If you think this looks suspiciously like a mixer, you are absolutely
right! A synchronous detector is one where the difference frequency
between the two inputs is zero Hz. Of in other words, the two input
frequencies are the same. Let\'s check the math.
Recall that the AM input is mathematically defined by:
$$e_{am} = \underbrace {\sin \omega _c t}_{{\rm{Carrier}}} + \underbrace {\frac{m}{2}\sin \left( {\omega _c - \omega _m } \right)t}_{{\rm{Lower}}\;{\rm{Sideband}}} - \underbrace {\frac{m}{2}\sin \left( {\omega _c + \omega _m } \right)t}_{{\rm{Upper}}\;{\rm{Sideband}}}$$
:
: At the multiplier output, we obtain:
$${\rm{mixer}}\;{\rm{out = }}e_{am} \times \sin \omega _c t = \underbrace { - \frac{m}{2}\sin \omega _m t}_{{\rm{Original}}\;{\rm{Modulation}}\;{\rm{Signal}}}\underbrace { - \frac{1}{2}\sin 2\omega _c t - \frac{m}{4}\sin \left( {2\omega _c - \omega _m } \right)t + \frac{m}{4}\sin \left( {2\omega _c + \omega _m } \right)t}_{{\rm{AM}}\;{\rm{signal}}\;{\rm{centered}}\;{\rm{at}}\;{\rm{2}}\;{\rm{times}}\;{\rm{the}}\;{\rm{carrier}}\;{\rm{frequency}}}$$
:
: The high frequency component can be filtered off leaving only
the original modulation signal.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: This technique has one serious drawback. The problem is how to
create the exact carrier frequency. If the frequency is not
exact, the entire baseband signal will be shifted by the
difference. A shift of only 50 Hz will make the human voice
unrecognizable. It is possible to use a PLL (phase locked loop),
but making one tunable for the entire AM band is not trivial.
As a result, most radio receivers use an oscillator to create a fixed
intermediate frequency. This is then followed by an envelope detector or
a fixed frequency PLL.
#### Squaring Detector
The squaring detector is also a synchronous or coherent detector. It
avoids the problem of having to recreate the carrier by simply squaring
the input signal. It essentially uses the AM signal itself as a sort of
wideband carrier.
:
: ![](Squaring_detector.gif "fig:Squaring_detector.gif")
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: The output of the multiplier is the square of the input AM
signal:
$$\left( {e_{am} } \right)^2 = \left( {\sin \omega _c t + \frac{m}{2}\sin \left( {\omega _c - \omega _m } \right)t - \frac{m}{2}\sin \left( {\omega _c + \omega _m } \right)t} \right)^2$$
Since the input is being multiplied by the ${\sin \omega _c t}$
component, one of the resulting difference terms is the original
modulation signal. The principle difficulty with this approach is trying
to create a linear, high frequency multiplier.
|
# Communication Systems/Binary Modulation Schemes
This page discusses the binary modulation schemes and \"keying\".
## What is \"Keying?\"
Square waves, sinc waves, and raised-cosine rolloff waves are all well
and good, but all of them have drawbacks. If we use an optimal, matched
filter, we can eliminate the effect of jitter, so frankly, why would we
consider square waves at all? Without jitter as a concern, it makes no
sense to correct for jitter, or even take it into consideration.
However, since the matched filter needs to look at individual symbols,
the transmitted signal can\'t suffer from any intersymbol interference
either. Therefore, we aren\'t using the sinc pulse.
Since the raised-cosine roll-off wave suffers from both these problems
(in smaller amounts, however), we don\'t want to use that pulse either.
So the question is, what other types of pulses can we send?
It turns out that if we use some of the techniques we have developed
using analog signal modulation, and implement a sinusoidal carrier wave,
we can create a signal with no inter-symbol interference, very low
bandwidth, and no worries about jitter. Just like analog modulation,
there are 3 aspects of the carrier wave that we can change: the
amplitude, the frequency, and the phase angle. Instead of
\"modulation\", we call these techniques **keying** techniques, because
they are operating on a binary-number basis.
There is one important point to note before continuing with this
discussion: Binary signals **are not** periodic signals. Therefore, we
cannot expect that a binary signal is going to have a discrete spectra
like a periodic squarewave will have. For this reason, the spectral
components of binary data are continuous spectra.
## Amplitude Shift Keying
In an ASK system, we are changing the amplitude of the sine wave to
transmit digitial data. We have the following cases:
- Binary 1: $A_1 \sin(f_c t)$
- Binary 0: $A_0 \sin(f_c t)$
The simplest modulation scheme sets A0 = 0V (turning the transmitter
off), and setting A1 = +5V (any random non-zero number turns the
transmitter on). This special case of ASK is called OOK (On-Off keying).
Morse code uses OOK.
Another common special case of ASK sets A1 to some positive number, and
A0 to the corresponding negative number A0 = -A1. We will mention this
case again later.
In ASK, we have the following equation:
$$a(t) \sin(\omega t)$$
by the principal of duality, multiplication in the time domain becomes
convolution in the frequency domain, and vice-versa. Therefore, our
frequency spectrum will have the following equation:
$$A(j\omega) * \delta(t - \omega)$$
where the impulse function is the fourier-transform of the sinusoid,
centered at the frequency of the wave. the value for A is going to be a
sinc wave, with a width dependent on the bitrate. We remember from the
Signals and Systems book that
convolution of a signal with an impulse is that signal centered where
the impulse was centered. Therefore, we know now that the frequency
domain shape of this curve is a sinc wave centered at the carrier
frequency.
## Frequency Shift Keying
In **Frequency Shift Keying** (FSK), we can logically assume that the
parameter that we will be changing is the frequency of the sine wave.
FSK is unique among the different keying methods in that data is never
transmitted *at* the carrier frequency, but is instead transmitted at a
certain offset from the carrier frequency. If we have a carrier
frequency of $f_c$, and a frequency offset of $\Delta f$, we can
transmit binary values as such:
- Binary 1: $A \sin ((f_c + \Delta f)t)$
- Binary 0: $A \sin ((f_c - \Delta f)t)$
Similar to ASK, we have FSK, which uses 2 different frequencies to
transmit data. For now we will call them $\omega1, \omega2$. Using the
same logic that we used above, the fourier representations of these
waves will be (respectively):
$$A_1(j\omega) * \delta(t - \omega1)$$
$$A_0(j\omega) * \delta(t - \omega2)$$
With one sinc wave centered at the first frequency, and one sinc wave
centered at the second frequency. Notice that A1 and A0 are the
half-square waves associated with the 1s and the 0s, respectively. These
will be described later.
### Error Rate
The BER of coherent QPSK in the presence of gaussian and Rayleigh noise
is as follows:
: {\| border=1
\|- \| Gaussian Noise \|\| Rayleigh Fading \|- \|
$\frac{1}{2}\operatorname{erfc} \left( \sqrt{\frac{E_b}{N_0}} \right)$
\| $\frac{1}{2}\left( 1 - \sqrt{\frac{\gamma_0}{2 + \gamma_0}} \right)$
\|}
## Phase Shift Keying
PSK systems are slightly different then ASK and FSK systems, and because
of this difference, we can exploit an interesting little trick of
trigonometry. PSK is when we vary the phase angle of the wave to
transmit different bits. For instance:
- Binary 1: $A \sin(f_c t + \phi_1)$
- Binary 0: $A \sin(f_c t + \phi_0)$
If we evenly space them out around the unit-circle, we can give
ourselves the following nice values:
- Binary 1: $A \sin(f_c t + 0)$
- Binary 0: $A \sin(f_c t + \pi)$
Now, according to trigonometry, we have the following identity:
$\sin(f_c t + \pi) = -\sin(f_c t)$
So in general, our equations for each signal (s) is given by:
- $s_1(t) = A\sin(f_c t)$
- $s_0(t) = -A\sin(f_c t)$
Which looks awfully like an ASK signal. Therefore, we can show that the
spectrum of a PSK signal is the same as the spectrum of an ASK signal.
There are two
commonally
used forms of Phase Shift keying Modulation:
Binary Phase Shift Keying (BPSK)
Quadrature Phase Shift Keying (QPSK)
Binary Phase Shift keying is set out above.
### QPSK
Quadrature Phase Shift Keying utilises the fact that a cosine wave is in
quadrature to a sine wave, allowing 2 bits to be simultaneously
represented.
- Binary 11: $A \sin(f_c t + 0) + \cos(f_c+\pi/2)$
- Binary 10: $A \sin(f_c t + 0) + \cos(f_c -\pi/2)$
- Binary 01: $A \sin(f_c t + \pi) + + \cos(f_c+\pi/2)$
- Binary 00: $A \sin(f_c t + \pi) + + \cos(f_c - \pi/2)$
QPSK has the advantage over BPSK of requiring half the transmission band
width for the same data rate, and error probability.
### Error Rate
The BER of coherent BPSK in the presence of gaussian and Rayleigh noise
is as follows:
: {\| border=1
\|- \| Gaussian Noise \|\| Rayleigh Fading \|- \|
$\frac{1}{2}\operatorname{erfc} \left( \sqrt{\frac{E_b}{N_0}} \right)$
\| $\frac{1}{2}\left( 1 - \sqrt{\frac{\gamma_0}{1 + \gamma_0}} \right)$
\|}
## Binary Transmitters
## Binary Receivers
|
# Communication Systems/M-ary Modulation Schemes
Now what if try to cram more information into a single bittime? If we
take 2 bits at a time, and arrange them together, we can assign each set
of 2 bits to a different symbol, and then we can transmit the different
symbols.
## Pronunciation
`"M-ary" is pronounced like "em airy".`
## Example: Q-ASK
Let us use the following scheme:
- \"00\" = +5V
- \"01\" = +1.66V
- \"10\" = -1.66V
- \"11\" = -5V
we can see now that we can transmit data *twice as fast* using this
scheme, although we need to have a more complicated receiver, that can
decide between 4 different pulses (instead of 2 different pulses, like
we have been using).
## Bits Per Symbol
All popular communication systems transmit an integer number of bits per
symbol. We can relate the number of bits (\"k\") and the number of
different symbols (\"m\") with the following equation:
$$m = 2^k$$
This causes the number of symbols to be a power of two.
With M-ary modulation techniques, the \"symbols per second\" rate can be
much slower than the \"bits per second\" data rate.
## QPSK
Quadrature phase shift keying (aka 4-PSK) is PSK modulation that has
four points in the constellation. !QPSK
Modulator !QPSK
Demodulator There are several
variations on this technique:
- simple QPSK
- DQPSK (differential QPSK)
- OQPSK (offset QPSK)
- SOPSK (shaped offset QPSK)
- π/4 QPSK (shifted constellation QPSK)
## CPFSK (MSK)
\[MSK\]minimum shift keying
## DPSK
## For further reading
- Wikipedia:Constellation
diagram
- Wikipedia:Quadrature amplitude
modulation
|
# Communication Systems/Wave Propagation
This page will discuss some of the fundamental basics of EM wave
propagation.
## Electromagnetic Spectrum
:
: ![](cont_emspec2.jpg "fig:cont_emspec2.jpg")
## Radio Waves
Maxwell first predicted the existence of electromagnetic waves in the
19th century. He came to this conclusion by careful examination of the
equations describing electric and magnetic phenomenon. It was left up to
Hertz to create these waves, and Marconi to exploit them.
In spite of one hundred years of study, exactly what radio waves are and
why they exist, remain somewhat of a mystery.
Electromagnetic waves in free space, or TEM waves, consist of electric
and magnetic fields, each at right angles to each other and the
direction of propagation.
:
: ![](tem_wave.gif "fig:tem_wave.gif")
The relationship between wavelength and frequency is given by:
$$c = \lambda f$$
:
: where c is the speed of light (approximately 300,000 m/s in
vacuum), f is the frequency of the wave, and λ is the wavelength
of the wave.
Radio waves can be reflected and refracted in a manner similar to light.
They are affected by the ground terrain, atmosphere and other objects.
Maxwell's equations state that a time varying magnetic field produces an
electric field and a time varying electric field produces a magnetic
field. This is kind of a chicken and egg situation.
Radio waves propagate outward from an antenna, at the speed of light.
The exact nature of these waves is determined by the transmission
medium. In free space, they travel in straight lines, whereas in the
atmosphere, they generally travel in a curved path. In a confined or
guided medium, radio waves do not propagate in the TEM mode, but rather
in a TE or TM mode.
Radio waves interact with objects in three principle ways:
:
: Reflection -- A radio wave bounces off an object larger than its
wavelength.
: Diffraction -- Waves bend around objects.
: Scattering -- A radiowave bounces off an object smaller than its
wavelength.
Because of these complex interactions, radio wave propagation is often
examined in three distinct regions in order to simplify the analysis:
:
: Surface (or ground) waves are located very near the earth's
surface.
: Space waves occur in the lower atmosphere (troposphere).
: Sky waves occur in the upper atmosphere (ionosphere).
The boundaries between these regions are somewhat fuzzy. In many cases,
it is not possible to examine surface waves without considering space
waves.
:
: ![](electron_density_altitude.gif "fig:electron_density_altitude.gif")
### Common RF Band Designations
Frequency band name Frequency Wavelength
----------------------------------- ----------------- --------------------
ELF - Extremely Low Frequency 3 -- 30 Hz 100000 -- 10000 km
SLF - Super Low Frequency 30 -- 300 Hz 10000 -- 1000 km
ULF - Ultra Low Frequency 300 -- 3000 Hz 1000 -- 100 km
VLF - Very Low Frequency 3 -- 30 kHz 100 -- 10 km
LF - Low Frequency 30 -- 300 kHz 10 -- 1 km
MF - Medium Frequency 300 -- 3000 kHz 1000 -- 100 m
HF - High Frequency 3 -- 30 MHz 100 -- 10 m
VHF - Very High Frequency 30 -- 300 MHz 10 -- 1 m
UHF - Ultra High Frequency 300 -- 3000 MHz 1000 -- 100 mm
SHF - Super High Frequency 3 -- 30 GHz 100 -- 10 mm
EHF - Extremely High Frequency 30 -- 300 GHz 10 -- 1 mm
THF - Tremendously High Frequency 300 -- 3000 GHz 1 -- 0.1 mm
### Surface Waves
These are the principle waves used in AM, FM and TV broadcast. Objects
such as buildings, hills, ground conductivity, etc. have a significant
impact on their strength. Surface waves are usually vertically polarized
with the electric field lines in contact with the earth.
:
: ![](surface_wave.gif "fig:surface_wave.gif")
#### Refraction
Because of refraction, the radio horizon is larger than the optical
horizon by about 4/3. The typical maximum direct wave transmission
distance (in km) is dependent on the height of the transmitting and
receiving antennas (in meters):
$$d_{\max } \approx \sqrt {17h_t } + \sqrt {17h_r } \quad {\rm{km}}$$
However, the atmospheric conditions can have a dramatic effect on the
amount of refraction.
:
: ![](refraction_distance.gif "fig:refraction_distance.gif")
##### Super Refraction
In super refraction, the rays bend more than normal thus shortening the
radio horizon. This phenomenon occurs when temperature increases but
moisture decreases with height. Paradoxically, in some cases, the radio
wave can travel over enormous distances. It can be reflected by the
earth, rebroadcast and super refracted again.
##### Sub refraction
In sub refraction, the rays bend less than normal. This phenomenon
occurs when temperature decreases but moisture increases with height. In
extreme cases, the radio signal may be refracted out into space.
### Space Waves
These waves occur within the lower 20 km of the atmosphere, and are
comprised of a direct and reflected wave. The radio waves having high
frequencies are basically called as space waves. These waves have the
ability to propagate through atmosphere, from transmitter antenna to
receiver antenna. These waves can travel directly or can travel after
reflecting from earth's surface to the troposphere surface of earth. So,
it is also called as Tropospherical Propagation. In the diagram of
medium wave propagation, c shows the space wave propagation. Basically
the technique of space wave propagation is used in bands having very
high frequencies. E.g. V.H.F. band, U.H.F band etc. At such higher
frequencies the other wave propagation techniques like sky wave
propagation, ground wave propagation can't work. Only space wave
propagation is left which can handle frequency waves of higher
frequencies. The other name of space wave propagation is line of sight
propagation. There are some limitations of space wave propagation.
1. These waves are limited to the curvature of the earth.
2. These waves have line of sight propagation, means their propagation
is along the line of sight distance.
The line of sight distance is that exact distance at which both the
sender and receiver antenna are in sight of each other. So, from the
above line it is clear that if we want to increase the transmission
distance then this can be done by simply extending the heights of both
the sender as well as the receiver antenna. This type of propagation is
used basically in radar and television communication.
The frequency range for television signals is nearly 80 to 200 MHz.
These waves are not reflected by the ionosphere of the earth. The
property of following the earth's curvature is also missing in these
waves. So, for the propagation of television signal, geostationary
satellites are used. The satellites complete the task of reflecting
television signals towards earth. If we need greater transmission then
we have to build extremely tall antennas.
#### Direct Wave
This is generally a line of sight transmission, however, because of
atmospheric refraction the range extends slightly beyond the horizon.
#### Ground Reflected Wave
Radio waves may strike the earth, and bounce off. The strength of the
reflection depends on local conditions. The received radio signal can
cancel out if the direct and reflected waves arrive with the same
relative strength and 180^o^ out of phase with each other.
Horizontally polarized waves are reflected with almost the same
intensity but with a 180^o^ phase reversal.
Vertically polarized waves generally reflect less than half of the
incident energy. If the angle of incidence is greater than 10^o^ there
is very little change in phase angle.
### Sky Waves
These waves head out to space but are reflected or refracted back by the
ionosphere. The height of the ionosphere ranges from 50 to 1,000 km.[^1]
Radio waves are refracted by the ionized gas created by solar radiation.
The amount of ionization depends on the time of day, season and the
position in the 11-year sun spot cycle. The specific radio frequency
refracted is a function of electron density and launch angle.
A communication channel thousands of kilometers long can be established
by successive reflections at the earth's surface and in the upper
atmosphere. This ionospheric propagation takes place mainly in the HF
band.
The ionosphere is composed of several layers, which vary according to
the time of day. Each layer has different propagation characteristics:
:
: D layer -- This layer occurs only during the day at altitudes of
60 to 90 km. High absorption takes place at frequencies up to 7
MHz.
: E layer -- This layer occurs at altitudes of 100 to 125 km. In
the summer, dense ionization clouds can form for short periods.
These clouds called *sporadic E* can refract radio signals in
the VHF spectrum. This phenomenon allows amateur radio operators
to communicate over enormous distances.
: F layer - This single nighttime layer splits into two layers (F1
and F2) during the day. The F1 layer forms at about 200 km and
F2 at about 400 km. The F2 layer propagates most HF short-wave
transmissions.
Because radio signals can take many paths to the receiver, multipath
fading can occur. If the signals arrive in phase, the result is a
stronger signal. If they arrive out of phase with each other, they tend
to cancel.
Deep fading, lasting from minutes to hours over a wide frequency range,
can occur when solar flares increase the ionization in the D layer.
The useful transmission band ranges between the LUF (lowest usable
frequency) and MUF (maximum usable frequency). Frequencies above the MUF
are refracted into space. Below the LUF, radio frequencies suffer severe
absorption. If a signal is near either of these two extremes, it may be
subject to fading.
Meteors create ionization trails that reflect radio waves. Although
these trails exist for only a few seconds, they have been successfully
used in communications systems spanning 1500 km.
The Aurora Borealis or Northern Lights cause random reflection in the
3 - 5 MHz region. Aurora causes signal flutter at 100 Hz to 2000 Hz thus
making voice transmission impossible.
## Fading and Interference
Radio signals may vary in intensity for many reasons.
### Flat Earth Reflections (Horizontal Polarization)
There are at least two possible paths for radio waves to travel when the
antennas are near the earth: direct path and reflected path. These two
signals interact in a very complex manner. However, ignoring
polarization and assuming a flat earth can produce some interesting
mathematical descriptions.
:
: ![](direct_relected_wave.gif "fig:direct_relected_wave.gif")
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: *p~1~* = direct wave path length
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: *p~2~* = reflected wave path length
$$\Delta$$*p* = *p~2~ - p~1~* difference in path lengths
:
: *d* = distance
From the geometry we can observe:
$$p_1^2 = \left( {h_r - h_t } \right)^2 + d^2$$
$$p_2^2 = \left( {h_r + h_t } \right)^2 + d^2$$
$$p_2^2 - p_1^2 = \left( {h_r - h_t } \right)^2 + d^2 - \left( {h_r + h_t } \right)^2 - d^2 = 4h_r h_t$$
$$\left( {p_2 - p_1 } \right)\left( {p_2 + p_1 } \right) = 4h_r h_t$$
But$\Delta p = \left( {p_2 - p_1 } \right)$ and
$d \approx p_1 \approx p_2$
$$\Delta p2d \approx 4h_r h_t$$ therefore
$\Delta p \approx \frac{{2h_r h_t }}{d}$
If the difference in the two paths $\Delta$*p*, is 1/2 $\lambda$ long,
the two signals tend to cancel. If $\Delta$*p* is equal to $\lambda$,
the two signals tend to reinforce. The path difference $\Delta$*p*
therefore corresponds to a phase angle change of:
$$\varphi _p = \frac{{2\pi }}{\lambda }\Delta p = \frac{{4\pi h_r h_t }}{{\lambda d}}$$
The resultant received signal is the sum of the two components. The
situation is unfortunately made more complex by the fact that the phase
integrity of the reflected wave is not maintained at the point of
reflection.
If we limit the examination of reflected waves to the horizontally
polarized situation, we obtain the following geometry:
:
: ![](vector_sum.gif "fig:vector_sum.gif")
Applying the cosine rule to this diagram, we obtain a resultant signal
of:
$$E_r = E_1 \sqrt {2\left( {1 - \cos \varphi _p } \right)} = 2E_1 \sin \left( {\frac{{\varphi _p }}{2}} \right)$$
The signal strength of the direct wave is the unit distance value
divided by the distance: $E_r = \frac{{E_0 }}{d}$ Therefore, the
received signal can be written as:
$$E_r = \frac{{2E_0 }}{d}\sin \left( {\frac{{2\pi h_r h_t }}{{\lambda d}}} \right)$$
For small angles this can be approximated by:
$$E_r \approx \frac{{2E_0 }}{d}\frac{{2\pi h_r h_t }}{{\lambda d}} = E_0 \frac{{4\pi h_r h_t }}{{\lambda d^2 }}$$
### Multipath Fading
The received signal is generally a combination of many signals, each
coming over a different path. The phase and amplitude of each component
are related to the nature of the path. These signals combine in a very
complex manner. Some multipath fading effects are characterized by delay
spread, Rayleigh and Ricean fading, doppler shifting, etc. Fading is the
most significant phenomenon causing signal degradation. There are
several different categories of fading:
::\* Flat fading: the entire pass band of interest is affected equally
(also known as narrow or amplitude varying channels).
::\*Frequency selective fading: certain frequency components are
affected more than others (also known as wideband channels). This
phenomenon tends to introduce inter-symbol interference.
::\*Slow fading: the channel characteristics vary at less than the baud
rate.
::\*Fast fading: the channel characteristics vary faster than the baud
rate.
#### Time Dispersion
Time dispersion occurs when signals arrive at different times. Signals
traveling at the speed of light move about 1 foot in 1 nanosecond. This
spreading tends to limit the bit rate over RF links.
#### Rayleigh Fading
The Rayleigh distribution can be used to describe the statistical
variations of a flat fading channel. Generally, the strength of the
received signal falls off as the inverse square of the distance between
the transmitter and receiver. However, in cellular systems, the antennas
are pointed slightly down and the signal falls of more quickly.
:
: ![](Rayleigh_fading_doppler_10Hz.gif "fig:Rayleigh_fading_doppler_10Hz.gif"){width="300"}
#### Ricean Fading
The Ricean distribution is used to describe the statistical variations
of signals with a strong direct or line-of-sight component and numerous
weaker reflected ones. This can happen in any multipath environment such
as inside buildings or in an urban center.
A received signal is generally comprised of several signals, each taking
a slightly different path. Since some may add constructively in-phase
and others out of phase, the overall signal strength may vary by 40 dB
or more if the receiver is moved even a very short distance.
#### Doppler Shift
A frequency shift is caused by the relative motion of the transmitter
and receiver, or any object that reflects/refracts signal. This movement
creates random frequency modulation. Doppler frequency shift is either
positive or negative depending on whether the transmitter is moving
towards or away from the receiver.
This Doppler frequency shift is given by:
$$f_d = \frac{{v_m }}{c}f_c$$
*v~m~* is the relative motion of the transmitter with respect to the
receiver, *c* is the speed of light and *f~c~* is the transmitted
frequency. In the multipath environment, the relative movement of each
path is generally different. Thus, the signal is spread over a band of
frequencies. This is known as the Doppler spread.
### Atmospheric Diffraction
Radio waves cannot penetrate very far into most objects. Consequently,
there is often a shadow zone behind objects such as buildings,hills,
etc.
The radio shadow zone does not have a very sharp cutoff due to spherical
spreading, also called Huygens' principle. Each point on a wavefront
acts as it were a point source radiating along the propagation path. The
overall wavefront is the vector sum of all the point sources or
wavelets. The wavelet magnitude is proportional to $1 + \cos \theta$
where $\theta$ is measured from the direction of propagation. The
amplitude is maximum in the direction of propagation and zero in the
reverse direction.
## Reflection
Reflection normally occurs due to the surface of earth or building &
hills which have large dimension relative to the wavelength of the
propagation waves. The reflected wave changes the incident angle.
There is similarity b/w the reflection of light by a conducting medium.
In both cases, angle of reflection is equal to angle of incidence. The
equality of the angles of reflection & incidence follows the second law
of reflection for light.
## Diffraction
Diffraction occurs in beams of light or waves when they become spread
out as a result of passing through a narrow slit. Maximum diffraction
occurs when the slit through which the wave passes through is equal to
the wavelength of the wave. Diffraction will result in constructive and
destructive interference.
## Path Loss
## References
[^1]: <http://www.hq.nasa.gov/iwgsdi/Ionosphere.html>
|
# Communication Systems/Antennas
## Antennas
The purpose of an antenna is to collect and convert electromagnetic
waves to electronic signals. Transmission lines then guide these to the
receiver front end.
The relevant electric fields associated with an antenna are extremely
complex and have the general form:
$$E = j30\beta ^2 Idz\left( {\frac{j}{{\beta r}} + \frac{1}{{\left( {\beta r} \right)^2 }} + \frac{1}{{\left( {\beta r} \right)^3 }}} \right)\sin \theta e^{ - j\beta r}$$
where *Idz* = moment of differential current element in rms amp meters
$$\beta = \frac{{2\pi }}{\lambda }$$
:
: *r* = distance in meters
The near field or Fresnel region consists of three fields.
The electrostatic (*1/r^3^*) and inductive (*1/r^2^*) fields fall off in
intensity quite quickly. The far field or Fraunhoffer region consists
entirely of the (*j/r*) radiated field. This article will only consider
this radiated field.
Although most antennas are simply a piece of bent wire, their
interaction with electromagnetic fields is quite complex, and a whole
array of terms is needed to characterize them:
::\**Beamwidth*: the angle defines by the radiation pattern where the
signal strength drops 3 dB of its maximum value in a given plane.
::\**Polarization*: the plane of electric field polarization with
respect to the earth.
::\**Gain*: a figure of merit used to quantify the signal capturing
ability of the antenna. It is closely related to directivity and
beamwidth.
::\**Effective area*: a measure of the antenna's ability to collect
energy. It is related to gain by the expression:
$A = \frac{{G\lambda ^2 }}{{4\pi }}$.
::\**Input impedance*: The impedance, which is necessary in the receiver
for maximum power transfer to occur.
::\**Radiation resistance*: the ratio of the power driving the antenna
to the square of the current driving its terminals.
::\**Bandwidth*: the usable frequency band associated with the antenna.
Before any antenna can be selected, the center frequency and operating
bandwidth must be known. In general, the higher the operating frequency,
the smaller the antenna. Antenna gain is always measured against a known
reference such as an isotropic source (*dBi*) or a half wave dipole
(*dBd*).
Antenna Type Typical Gain \[*dBd*\]
------------------ ------------------------
Dipole 0
Omni 0
Gain Omni 3 --- 12
Mobile Whip -0.6 to +5.5
Corner Reflector 4 --- 10
Log Periodic 3 --- 8
Horn 5 --- 12
Helix 5 --- 12
Microstrip Patch 3 --- 15
Yagi 3 --- 20
Panel 5 --- 20
Increasing antenna gain by 3 dB generally requires increasing the size
by a factor of 2-3 or by reducing the beamwidth. Vertical omni
directional antennas and collinear arrays are used for line-of-sight
communications with ground-based mobile units. Sectoring can be
accomplished by panel antennas. Fixed point-to-point links generally use
a yagi or parabolic dish.
Antennas exhibit reciprocity, which means they have the same gain
whether used for transmitting or receiving.
### Isotropic Radiators
An isotropic source radiates energy equally well in all directions.
Stars are isotropic radiators. Our sun is an extremely powerful
radiator, broadcasting 64 Megawatts per square meter of surface.
Although it is not possible to construct isotropic radio antennas, the
concept provides useful analytical tools.
The power density as a function of distance from an isotropic source is
easily calculated. It is simply the total energy broadcast, divided by
the area it passes through, in this case, a sphere.
$$P_{DI} = \frac{{P_t }}{{4\pi r^2 }}$$ watts/m^2^
Isotropic gain is also called absolute gain. Antennas gains with respect
to isotropic gain are specified in units of dBi. Antenna gains can also
be specified with respect to a half wave dipole or a short vertical
antenna. The gain of a half-wave dipole is 1.64 dBi, and that of a
dipole is 2.15 dBi.
### Non Isotropic Radiators
Virtually all types of antennas are non-isotropic sources. That is that
they tend to radiate more energy in a particular direction.
:
: ![](non_isotropic_radiator.gif "fig:non_isotropic_radiator.gif")
Because of this non-uniform energy distribution, the antenna appears to
have a gain (*G~t~*) (if broadcasting the same power) relative to an
isotropic radiator along its principal axis and a loss in other most
directions. The power density along the antenna axis is given by:
$$P_D = \frac{{P_t G_t }}{{4\pi r^2 }}$$ watts/m^2^
The receiving antenna attempts to collect this radiated energy through
an effective area (*A~eff~*). The received power is therefore:
$$P_r = \frac{{P_t G_t }}{{4\pi r^2 }}A_{eff}$$ watts
It would seem reasonable to conclude that the effective area is simply
the physical size of the antenna. Fortunately, this is not the case, and
very small antennas are possible.
It has been determined that there is a relationship between effective
area, transmitted wavelength and antenna gain:
$$\frac{{A_{eff} }}{{G_r }} = \frac{{\lambda ^2 }}{{4\pi }}$$
Therefore, the received power can be expressed as:
:
: $P_r = P_t G_t G_r \left( {\frac{\lambda }{{4\pi r}}} \right)^2$
watts
Recall that: $\lambda = \frac{c}{f}$
If *f* is expressed in MHz, *c* in meters per second, and *r* in km,
then the received power in dB can be expressed as:
$$P_r = P_t + G_t + G_r - \left( {32.45 + 20\log r + 20\log f} \right)$$
dB
### Electric Field Strength
If the power density of an electromagnetic wave is known, the field
strength can be obtained from:
$$E = \sqrt {Z_0 P_D }$$
where:
$$Z_0 = \sqrt {\frac{\mu }{\varepsilon }} = \sqrt {\frac{{4\pi \times 10^{ - 7} }}{{8.854 \times 10^{ - 12} }}} = 120\pi$$
(for free space)
Therefore the field strength at one meter is:
$$E_o = \sqrt {120\pi \frac{{P_t G_t }}{{4\pi r^2 }}} = \sqrt {30P_t G_t }$$
volts/m
## Antenna Types
Antennas come in a bewildering array of shapes and sizes however, they
can be divided into two broad categories : Marconi and Hertzian.
Marconi antennas are electrically unbalanced and a require a ground
plane. Hertzian antennas are electrically balanced and do not require a
ground plane. Depending on one\'s point of view, it is possible to
consider one type the subset of the other. This will become clearer
later on.
## Marconi Antenna
Marconi antennas are usually 1/4 wavelength long and require a path to
ground. The ground plane itself acts as a reflector of energy, and
combines with the directly radiated wave to create the overall radiation
pattern. If the ground is dry or otherwise a poor conductor, a copper
grid is generally laid out on the ground. The impedance of a 1/4
$\lambda$ Marconi antenna is 36.6 $\Omega$.
:
: ![](1_4_wave_marconi_antenna.gif "1_4_wave_marconi_antenna.gif")
!100 px
Notice that a Marconi antenna could be considered as a dipole antenna
with one of the poles buried in the ground. The ground acts as a
reflector to create the appearance of an buried antenna in the same way
that a mirror creates the appearance of someone behind the glass.
Increasing the antenna length has a significant impact on the radiation
pattern:
:
: ![](Marconi_antennas.gif "fig:Marconi_antennas.gif")
### Helical Antenna
Most Marconi antennas operate in the broadside mode, which means that
the bulk of the signal radiates off the side of the wire. However it is
possible to modify the antenna to operate in the end fire mode:
:
: ![](Helical_antenna_principle.png "fig:Helical_antenna_principle.png")
## Hertzian Antenna
Hertzian antennas do not require a path to either ground or a ground
plane. The simplest antenna of this type is the elementary doublet. It
is a hypothetical antenna where the instantaneous current magnitude is
constant along its length.
:
: ![](elementary_doublet.gif "fig:elementary_doublet.gif")
The radiation pattern for this antenna is donut shaped, with the antenna
rod running through the hole. The bulk of the energy is radiated at
right angles to the rod and nothing off the ends.
:
: ![](doublet_radiation_pattern.gif "fig:doublet_radiation_pattern.gif")
This antenna is often used as a reference instead of an isotropic
radiator, since close approximations of it can be constructed. Other
antennas can be considered as being composed of a series of doublets.
The field strength at any distance and angle can be calculated from:
$$E = \frac{{60\pi LI}}{{\lambda r}}$$
Where
:
: *L* = doublet length in meters
: $\lambda$= wavelength in meters
: *I* = current in amps (rms)
: *r* = distance in meters
### Dipole Antenna
A dipole is sometimes referred to as a Hertzian dipole. Since it has a
relatively simple construction and its radiation characteristics are
well defined, it is often used as the standard to which all other
antennas are compared.
The dipole radiation pattern is shaped like a slightly flattened donut.
:
: ![](dipole_pattern.gif "fig:dipole_pattern.gif")
The simplest antenna is the dipole. The relationship between antenna
current and electric field is given by:
$$E_\theta = j\eta \frac{{e^{ - j\beta r} }}{{2\pi r}}I\frac{{\cos \left( {\frac{{\beta L\cos \theta }}{2}} \right) - \cos \left( {\frac{{\beta L}}{2}} \right)}}{{\sin \theta }}$$
where:
:
: *E* = electric field strength
: $\theta$ = angle from antenna axis (in radians)
: *I* = antenna current (rms)
: $\eta$ = intrinsic impedance (377 $\Omega$)
: *L* = antenna length
: *r* = distance
A ½ $\lambda$ dipole has an impedance of about 70 $\Omega$. To increase
this impedance and more closely match the characteristics of a twin lead
cable, the dipole may be folded. A ½ $\lambda$ folded dipole has an
input impedance of about 280 $\Omega$, and is used as the driving
element in many other types of antennas.
Most TV receivers are equipped with two indoor antennas, one to cover
the VHF band and the other the UHF band. The most common VHF antennas
are the extendible monopole and vee dipole colloquially known as the
rabbit ears. These are available with either a 75 $\Omega$ or 300
$\Omega$ impedance and have a typical gain of -4 dB with respect to a ½
$\lambda$ dipole. The vee dipole has a lower input impedance than a
straight dipole of the same length, but under some conditions, it can
exhibit a higher directivity due to the reduction of sidelobes.
The common UHF antennas are the circular loop and triangular dipole.
They typically have a 300 $\Omega$ impedance. The dipole version
sometimes has a reflecting screen to improve the gain and directivity.
### Halfwave Dipole
The radiation pattern of the half wave dipole is very much like a donut.
:
: ![](half_wave_dipole_pattern.gif "fig:half_wave_dipole_pattern.gif")
The distribution of voltage, current, and impedance resemble:
:
: ![](half_wave_dipole_current.gif "fig:half_wave_dipole_current.gif")
By increasing the length of the dipole, the donut tends to flatten out
and then explodes into complex multi lobed shapes.
### Folded Dipole
:
: ![](Antenna-folded-dipole-diagram.png "fig:Antenna-folded-dipole-diagram.png")
folded dipole antenna has high input impedance as compared to ordinary
dipole.
### Loop Antenna
The entire UHF band can be received on a single 20.3 cm diameter loop.
The circumference varies from one wavelength at 470 MHz to 1.7
wavelengths at 806 MHz. The directivity is about 3.5 dB. The mid band
gain is 3 dB higher than a ½ $\lambda$ dipole, but falls off to about
1 dB at either end.
:
: ![](loop_antenna.gif "fig:loop_antenna.gif")
Loop antennas that are much smaller than wavelength they are attempting
to catch, exhibit a null in the direction of the loop axis. This makes
it suitable for radio direction finding equipment. If the loop size is
increased, it begins to generate a lobe across the axis and in line with
the feed.
### Triangular Dipole (Bowtie)
:
: ![](bow_tie_antenna.gif "fig:bow_tie_antenna.gif")
The bowtie antenna is formed of two triangular sheets connected to a
transmission line and provides a 3 dB gain over a simple dipole. It can
also be constructed of a wire mesh if the spacing is less than 1/10
wavelength. The input impedance is a function of length and flare angle.
For television applications, the flare angle a is between 60^o^ and
80^o^. If the antenna is mounted ¼ $\lambda$ in front of a reflecting
surface, the gain increases to approximately 9 dB. Stacking two of them
vertically one wavelength apart, increases the overall gain to about
12 dB.
If the receiver is located at a great distance from the broadcast tower,
it is often necessary to use an outdoor antenna. These often have a gain
of 15 dB. Placing the antenna on a tall mast also increases the received
signal strength by as much as an additional 14 dB. A further improvement
occurs because these antennas have a greater immunity to interference,
due to their complex structure.
Most outdoor antennas are a combination of two antennas \[UHF and VHF\]
in a single structure. The VHF antenna is generally a log-periodic
dipole array. The UHF antenna may be an LPDA, Yagi-Uda, corner
reflector, parabolic reflector, or triangular dipole array with
reflecting screen.
### Log Periodic Dipole Array \[LPDA\]
This antenna is called a log periodic array because the impedance
variations across the usable band are periodic functions of frequency.
The high impedance version is mounted on an insulated boom and feed by a
balanced cable. The average domestic antenna of this type has a gain of
about 4.5 dB in the low VHF band, rising to 7 dB in the high VHF band.
:
: ![](log_periodic_antenna.gif "fig:log_periodic_antenna.gif")
$$\tau = \frac{{X_n }}{{X_{n + 1} }} = \frac{{L_n }}{{L_{n + 1} }} = \frac{{s_n }}{{s_{_{n + 1} } }} = \frac{{d_n }}{{d_{n + 1} }}$$
\-- Typically $0.7 \le \tau \le 0.95$
$$\alpha = \tan ^{ - 1} \left( {\frac{{1 - \tau }}{{4\sigma }}} \right)$$
\-- Typically $10^0 \le \alpha \le 45^0$
$$\sigma = \frac{{d_n }}{{2L_n }}$$
:
: Bandwidth:
$B = \frac{{f_{high} }}{{f_{low} }}\left( {1 + 7.7\left( {1 - \tau } \right)^2 \cot \alpha } \right)$
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: Number of dipoles:
$N = 1 + \frac{{\ln B}}{{\ln \frac{1}{\tau }}}$
Most CATV applications use a 75 $\Omega$ unbalanced configuration,
because it is more compatible with their cable feeds and equipment.
:
: ![](unbalanced_coax_feed.gif "fig:unbalanced_coax_feed.gif")
Two parallel conducting booms form a low impedance transmission line.
Phase reversal between dipoles is obtained by alternate attachment to
the booms.
An UHF LPDA can be constructed from V-shaped dipoles. The dipoles are
used in their ½ $\lambda$ and 3/2 $\lambda$ modes and eliminate the need
for higher frequency dipoles.
### Yagi Uda Antenna
:
: ![](yagi.gif "fig:yagi.gif")
The dipole is typically 0.40 to 0.50 wavelengths long. The reflector is
normally 0.55 wavelengths long and placed anywhere from 0.1 to 0.25
wavelengths behind the dipole. The reflector spacing has no effect on
the forward gain, but does influence the front to back ratio and input
impedance.
The directors are normally 0.4 to 0.45 wavelengths long and are spaced
at 0.3 to 0.4 wavelengths in front of the dipole. An antenna will
usually have 6 to 12 directors.
### Parabolic Reflector
:
:
## Antenna Arrays
By combining several radiating elements together, the overall radiation
pattern can be modified to suit a particular application. In some cases
the antennas must be manually steered, but in other cases they can be
electronically steered using phase shifting between elements.
:
: !200 px
![](PAVE_PAWS_Radar_Clear_AFS_Alaska.jpg "PAVE_PAWS_Radar_Clear_AFS_Alaska.jpg"){width="200"}
The array factor is the increase in field strength in an array when
compared to a single element radiating the same power:
:
: ![](Array_side_view.gif "fig:Array_side_view.gif")
$$AF = \left| {\frac{{\sin \left( {\frac{{n\varphi }}{2}} \right)}}{{\sqrt n \sin \left( {\frac{\varphi }{2}} \right)}}} \right| \vdots \quad \quad \quad AF_{\max } = \sqrt n$$
:
: Where:
$$\varphi = \frac{{2\pi }}{\lambda }s\cos \left( \theta \right) + \alpha$$
:
: = phase difference between radiated fields from adjacent
elements
:
: *n* = number of radiating elements
: *s* = element spacing in wavelengths
: $\alpha$ = current phase shift between elements
: $\theta$ = angle from array axis
### Broadside Array
If all of the elements are fed in-phase, there will always be a
broadside radiation pattern. However, depending on the relative spacing,
an end fire pattern can also be created.
:
: ![](Broadside_wavefront.gif "fig:Broadside_wavefront.gif")
The radiating elements in the above illustration can be placed such that
they reinforce one another along the array axis, or not. An end fire
pattern is recreated when they reinforce.
By varying the space or phase shift between the elements, the size and
direction of the side lobes can be adjusted between these two extremes.
Increasing the number of radiating elements increases the overall array
gain.
:
: ![](Array_factor_1.gif "fig:Array_factor_1.gif")
Determining the array factor is sometimes relatively straightforward. By
definition, the signal strength for a broadside array is a maximum when
$\theta$ = 90^o^ and a minimum when $\theta$ = 0^o^
Since the array factor is a maximum when $\varphi$ = 0^o^ we can
determine the current phase shift $\alpha$, required to create a
broadside radiation pattern for a given frequency or element spacing:
$$\varphi = \frac{{2\pi }}{\lambda }s\cos \left( \theta \right) + \alpha$$
$$0 = \frac{{2\pi }}{\lambda }s\cos \left( \theta \right) + \alpha$$
$$\alpha = 0$$
:
: Therefore the array factor for a broadside array is:
$$AF = \left| {\frac{{\sin \left( {\frac{{n\varphi }}{2}} \right)}}{{\sqrt n \sin \left( {\frac{\varphi }{2}} \right)}}} \right|\quad {\rm{where}}\quad \varphi = \frac{{2\pi }}{\lambda }s\cos \left( \theta \right)$$
$${\rm{generally}}\quad s = \frac{\lambda }{2}\quad \quad \quad {\rm{therefore}}\quad \quad \quad \varphi = 2cos\left( \theta \right)$$
Each element may have its own feed or there may be a single feed:
:
: ![](Broadside_feed.gif "fig:Broadside_feed.gif")
This form of antenna is often deployed in vertical stacks, with a
reflector spaced 1/4 wavelength behind the curtain. This broadband
dipole curtain array is the standard antenna for 100 to 500 kW
short-wave broadcasting stations.
:
: ![](Broadside_array.gif "fig:Broadside_array.gif")
CBC Radio International operates eight curtain arrays at Sackville NB.
Three have an output power of 100 kW and five have an output of 250 kW.
They are tunable over the range of 4.9 to 21.7 MHz. Signals are beamed
to Africa, Europe, Latin America, The Caribbean, the USA, and Mexico.
### Endfire Array
If all of the elements are positioned in such a way that the combined
wave fronts reinforce along the array axis.
:
: ![](Endfire.gif "fig:Endfire.gif")
Calculate the array factor is relatively straightforward. The signal
strength is a maximum when $\theta$ = 0^o^ and a minimum when $\theta$ =
90^o^
Since the array factor is a maximum when $\varphi$ = 0^o^ we can
determine the value of $\alpha$:
$$\varphi = \frac{{2\pi }}{\lambda }s\cos \left( \theta \right) + \alpha$$
$$0 = \frac{{2\pi }}{\lambda }s\cos \left( 0 \right) + \alpha$$
$$\alpha = - \frac{{2\pi }}{\lambda }s$$
:
: The array factor for an end fire array is:
$$AF = \left| {\frac{{\sin \left( {\frac{{n\varphi }}{2}} \right)}}{{\sqrt n \sin \left( {\frac{\varphi }{2}} \right)}}} \right|\quad {\rm{where}}\quad \varphi = \frac{{2\pi }}{\lambda }s\left( {\cos \left( \theta \right) - 1} \right)$$
$${\rm{generally}}\quad s = \frac{\lambda }{4}\quad \quad \quad {\rm{therefore}}\quad \quad \quad \varphi = \frac{\pi }{2}\left( {cos\left( \theta \right) - 1} \right)$$
Varying the spacing for a 6-element array produced the following
patterns:
:
: ![](Broadside_patterns.gif "fig:Broadside_patterns.gif")
### Phased Array
By varying the phase shift between elements, a beam or multiple beams
can be pointed towards a given direction. This forms the basis of the
large electronically steered radar system currently being deployed.
Collectively theses systems are known as phased arrays.
:
: !300 px
The PAVE PAWS early warning radar for example has 1792 active crossed
dipole antennas on a 102-foot face. Each face can scan 120^o^ in azimuth
and 80^o^ in elevation. The array has a range of 300 miles and can
produce multiple beams, which can be redirected in milliseconds.
## Further reading
- Wifi/Building an antenna
|
# Communication Systems/Noise Figure
This page is going to talk about the effect of noise on transmission
systems.
## Types of Noise
Most man made electro-magnetic noise occurs at frequencies below
500 MHz. The most significant of these include:
:
: • Hydro lines
: • Ignition systems
: • Fluorescent lights
: • Electric motors
Therefore deep space networks are placed out in the desert, far from
these sources of interference.
There are also a wide range of natural noise sources which cannot be so
easily avoided, namely:
:
: •*Atmospheric noise* - lighting \< 20 MHz
: •*Solar noise* - sun - 11 year sunspot cycle
: •*Cosmic noise* - 8 MHz to 1.5 GHz
: •*Thermal or Johnson noise*. Due to free electrons striking
vibrating ions.
: •*White noise* - white noise has a constant spectral density
over a specified range of frequencies. Johnson noise is an
example of white noise.
: •*Gaussian noise* - Gaussian noise is completely random in
nature however, the probability of any particular amplitude
value follows the normal distribution curve. Johnson noise is
Gaussian in nature.
: •*Shot noise* - bipolar transistors
$$i_n = \sqrt {2qI_{dc} \Delta f}$$
:
: where *q* = electron charge 1.6 x 10^-19^ coulombs
: •*Excess noise, flicker, 1/f, and pink noise* \< 1 KHz are
Inversely proportional to frequency and directly proportional to
temperature and dc current
: •*Transit time noise* - occurs when the electron transit time
across a junction is the same period as the signal.
Of these, only Johnson noise can be readily analysed and compensated
for. The noise power is given by:
$$P_n = kTB$$
Where:
:
: *k* = Boltzmann\'s constant (1.38 x 10^-23^ J/K)
: T = temperature in degrees Kelvin
: B = bandwidth in Hz
This equation applies to copper wire wound resistors, but is close
enough to be used for all resistors. Maximum power transfer occurs when
the source and load impedance are equal.
### Combining Noise Voltages
The instantaneous value of two noise voltages is simply the sum of their
individual values at the same instant.
$$v_{total\;inst} = v_{1\;inst} + v_{2\;inst}$$
This result is readily observable on an oscilloscope. However, it is not
particularly helpful, since it does not result in a single stable
numerical value such as one measured by a voltmeter.
If the two voltages are coherent \[K = 1\], then the total rms voltage
value is the sum of the individual rms voltage values.
$$v_{total\;rms} = v_{1\;rms} + v_{2\;rms}$$
If the two signals are completely random with respect to each other \[K
= 0\], such as Johnson noise sources, the total power is the sum of all
of the individual powers:
$$P_{total\;random\;noise} = P_{n1\;random} + P_{n2\;random}$$
A Johnson noise of power *P = kTB*, can be thought of as a noise voltage
applied through a resistor, Thevenin equivalent.
:
: ![](noise_source.gif "fig:noise_source.gif")
An example of such a noise source may be a cable or transmission line.
The amount of noise power transferred from the source to a load, such as
an amplifier input, is a function of the source and load impedances.
:
: ![](noise_circuit.gif "fig:noise_circuit.gif")
If the load impedance is 0 $\Omega$, no power is transferred to it since
the voltage is zero. If the load has infinite input impedance, again no
power is transferred to it since there is no current. Maximum power
transfer occurs when the source and load impedances are equal.
$$P_{L\;\max } = \frac{{e_s^2 }}{{4R_s }}$$
The rms noise voltage at maximum power transfer is:
$$e_n = \sqrt {4RP} = \sqrt {4RkTB}$$
:
: ![](matched_thermal_noise.gif "fig:matched_thermal_noise.gif")
Observe what happens if the noise resistance is resolved into two
components:
$$e_n^2 = 4RkTB = 4\left( {R_1 + R_2 } \right)kTB = e_{n1}^2 + e_{n2}^2$$
From this we observe that random noise resistance can be added directly,
but random noise voltages add vectorially:
:
: ![](vector_addition.gif "fig:vector_addition.gif")
If the noise sources are not quite random, and there is some correlation
between them \[0 \< K \< 1\], the combined result is not so easy to
calculate:
$$P_{Total\;\left( {{\rm{not }}\;{\rm{quite}}\;{\rm{ random}}} \right)} = \frac{{E_1^2 + E_2^2 + 2KE_1 E_2 }}{{R_0 }} = P_1 + P_2 = 2K\sqrt {P_1 + P_2 }$$
:
: where
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: *K* = correlation \[0 _\<_ *K*
_\<_ 1\]
: *R~0~* = reference impedance
## Noise Temperature
The amount of noise in a given transmission medium can be equated to
thermal noise. Thermal noise is well-studied, so it makes good sense to
reuse the same equations when possible. To this end, we can say that any
amount of radiated noise can be approximated by thermal noise with a
given **effective temperature**. Effective temperature is measured in
Kelvin. Effective temperature is frequently compared to the **standard
temperature**, $T_o$, which is 290 Kelvin.
In microwave applications, it is difficult to speak in terms of currents
and voltages since the signals are more aptly described by field
equations. Therefore, temperature is used to characterize noise. The
total noise temperature is equal to the sum of all the individual noise
temperatures.
## Noise Figure
The terms used to quantify noise can be somewhat confusing but the key
definitions are:
:
: **Signal to noise ratio**: It is either unitless or specified in
dB. The S/N ratio may be specified anywhere within a system.
$$\frac{S}{N} = \frac{{{\rm{signal}}\;{\rm{power}}}}{{{\rm{noise}}\;{\rm{power}}}} = \frac{{P_s }}{{P_n }}$$
$$\left( {\frac{S}{N}} \right)_{dB} = 10\log \frac{{P_s }}{{P_n }}$$
:
: **Noise Factor (or Noise Ratio)**:
$F = \frac{{\left( {\frac{S}{N}} \right)_{in} }}{{\left( {\frac{S}{N}} \right)_{out} }}$
(unit less)
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: **Noise Figure**: $NF = 10\log F = SNR_{in} - SNR_{out}$ dB
This parameter is specified in all high performance amplifiers and is
measure of how much noise the amplifier itself contributes to the total
noise. In a perfect amplifier or system, *NF* = 0 dB. This discussion
does not take into account any noise reduction techniques such as
filtering or dynamic emphasis.
:
: ![](g.gif "fig:g.gif")
### Friiss\' Formula & Amplifier Cascades
It is interesting to examine an amplifier cascade to see how noise
builds up in a large communication system.
$$F = \frac{{\left( {\frac{S}{N}} \right)_{in} }}{{\left( {\frac{S}{N}} \right)_{out} }} = \frac{{S_{in} }}{{N_{in} }} \times \frac{{N_{out} }}{{S_{out} }}$$
Amplifier gain can be defined as: $G = \frac{{S_{out} }}{{S_{in} }}$
:
: ![](g2.gif "fig:g2.gif")
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: Therefore the output signal power is: $S_{out} = GS_{in}$
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: and the noise factor (ratio) can be rewritten as:
$F = \frac{{S_{in} }}{{N_{in} }} \times \frac{{N_{out} }}{{GS_{in} }} = \frac{{N_{out} }}{{GN_{in} }}$
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: The output noise power can now be written: $N_{out} = FGN_{in}$
From this we observe that the input noise is increased by the noise
ratio and amplifier gain as it passes through the amplifier. A noiseless
amplifier would have a noise ratio (factor) of 1 or noise figure of
0 dB. In this case, the input noise would only be amplified by the gain
since the amplifier would not contribute noise.
:
: The minimum noise that can enter any system is the Johnson
Noise:
$$N_{in\left( {{\rm{minimum}}} \right)} = kTB$$
:
: Therefore the minimum noise that can appear at the output of any
amplifier is:
$$N_{out\left( {{\rm{minimum}}} \right)} = FGkTB$$
:
: The output noise of a perfect amplifier would be (*F* = 1):
$$N_{out\left( {{\rm{perfect}}} \right)} = GkTB$$
:
: The difference between these two values is the noised created
(added) by the amplifier itself:
$$N_{out\left( {{\rm{added}}} \right)} = N_{out\left( {{\rm{minimum}}} \right)} - N_{out\left( {{\rm{perfect}}} \right)} = FGkTB - GkTB = \left( {F - 1} \right)GkTB$$
:
: This is the additional (created) noise, appearing at the output.
**The total noise out of the amplifier is then given by:**
$$N_{total} = N_{out\left( {{\rm{perfect}}} \right)} + N_{out\left( {{\rm{added}}} \right)} = GkTB + \left( {F - 1} \right)GkTB$$
If a second amplifier were added in series, the total output noise would
consist the first stage noise amplified by the second stage gain, plus
the additional noise of the second amplifier:
$$N_{total} = G_1 G_2 kTB + \left( {F_1 - 1} \right)G_1 G_2 kTB + \left( {F_2 - 1} \right)G_2 kTB$$
:
: If we divide both sides of this expression by the common term:
$G_1 G_2 kTB$
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: we obtain:
$$\frac{{N_{total} }}{{G_1 G_2 kTB}} = \frac{{G_1 G_2 kTB + \left( {F_1 - 1} \right)G_1 G_2 kTB + \left( {F_2 - 1} \right)G_2 kTB}}{{G_1 G_2 kTB}}$$
:
: Recall:
$F = \frac{{N_{out} }}{{GN_{in} }} = \frac{{N_{total} }}{{G_1 G_2 kTB}}$
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: Then: $F_{overall} = F_1 + \frac{{F_2 - 1}}{{G_1 }}$
This process can be extended to include more amplifiers in cascade to
arrive at:
: **Friiss\' Formula**
$$F = F_1 + \frac{{F_2 - 1}}{{G_1 }} + \frac{{F_3 - 1}}{{G_1 G_2 }} +$$
This equation shows that the overall system noise figure is largely
determined by the noise figure of the first stage in a cascade since the
noise contribution of any stage is divided by the gains of the preceding
stages. This is why the 1st stage in any communication system should be
an LNA (low noise amplifier).
## Receiver Sensitivity
In a given bandwidth, W, we can show that the noise power N equals:
$$N = F(kT_0)W$$
From N, we can show that the sensitivity of the receiver is equal to
$$SNR \times N$$
## Cascaded Systems
|
# Communication Systems/Wired Transmission
This page will discuss the topic of signal propagation through physical
mediums, such as wires.
## Transmission Line Equation
Many kinds of communication systems require signals at some point to be
conveyed over copper wires.
The following analysis requires two assumptions:
:
: • A transmission line can be decomposed into small, distributed
passive electrical elements
: • These elements are independent of frequency (i.e. although
*reactance* is a function of frequency, resistance, capacitance
and inductance are not)
These two assumptions limit the following analysis to frequencies up to
the low MHz region. The second assumption is particularly difficult to
defend since it is well known that the resistance of a wire increases
with frequency because the conduction cross-section decreases. This
phenomenon is known as the skin effect and is not easy to evaluate.
:
: ![](transmission_line.gif "fig:transmission_line.gif")
The purpose behind the following mathematical manipulation is to obtain
an expression that defines the voltage (or current) at any time (*t*)
along any portion (*x*) of the transmission line. Later, this analysis
will be extended to include the frequency domain.
Recall the characteristic equations for inductors and capacitors:
$$v = L\frac{{\partial i}}{{\partial t}}$$ and
$i = C\frac{{\partial v}}{{\partial t}}$
### Kirchoff\'s Voltage Law
Kirchoff\'s voltage law (KVL) simply states that the sum of all voltage
potentials around a closed loop equal zero. Or in other words, if you
walked up a hill and back down, the net altitude change would be zero.
:
: Applying KVL in the above circuit, we obtain:
$$v\left( {x,t} \right) = R\Delta xi\left( {x,t} \right) + L\Delta x\frac{{\partial i}}{{\partial t}}\left( {x,t} \right) + v\left( {x + \Delta x,t} \right)$$
:
: Rearranging:
$$v\left( {x,t} \right) - v\left( {x + \Delta x,t} \right) = R\Delta xi\left( {x,t} \right) + L\Delta x\frac{{\partial i}}{{\partial t}}\left( {x,t} \right)$$
:
: But the LHS (left hand side) of the above equation, represents
the voltage drop across the cable element $\Delta v$, therefor:
$$\Delta v = R\Delta xi\left( {x,t} \right) + L\Delta x\frac{{\partial i}}{{\partial t}}\left( {x,t} \right)$$
:
: Dividing through by $\Delta x$, we obtain:
$$\frac{{\Delta v}}{{\Delta x}} = Ri\left( {x,t} \right) + L\frac{{\partial i}}{{\partial t}}\left( {x,t} \right)$$
:
: The LHS is easily recognized as a derivative. Simplifying the
notation:
$$\frac{{\partial v}}{{\partial x}} = Ri + L\frac{{\partial i}}{{\partial t}}$$
This expression has both current and voltage in it. It would be
convenient to write the equation in terms of current or voltage as a
function of distance or time.
### Simplifying the Equation (trust me)
The first step in separating voltage and current is to take the
derivative with respect to the position *x* (**Equation 1**):
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 v}}{{\partial x^2 }} = R\frac{{\partial i}}{{\partial x}} + L\frac{{\partial ^2 i}}{{\partial x\partial t}}$$
:
: The next step is to eliminate the current terms, leaving an
expression with voltage only. The change in current along the
line is equal to the current being shunted across the line
through the capacitance *C* and conductance *G*. By applying KCL
in the circuit, we obtain the necessary information (**Equation
2**):
$$\frac{{\partial i}}{{\partial x}} = Gv + C\frac{{\partial v}}{{\partial t}}$$
:
: Taking the derivative with respect to time, we obtain
(**Equation 3**):
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 i}}{{\partial x\partial t}} = G\frac{{\partial v}}{{\partial t}} + C\frac{{\partial ^2 v}}{{\partial t^2 }}$$
:
: Substituting (**Equation 2**) and (**Equation 3**) into
(**Equation 1**), we obtain the desired simplification:
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 v}}{{\partial x^2 }} = R\left[ {Gv + C\frac{{\partial v}}{{\partial t}}} \right] + L\left[ {G\frac{{\partial v}}{{\partial t}} + C\frac{{\partial ^2 v}}{{\partial t^2 }}} \right]$$
:
: Collecting the terms, we obtain:
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: **The Transmission Line Equation for Voltage**
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 v}}{{\partial x^2 }} = RGv + \left( {RC + LG} \right)\frac{{\partial v}}{{\partial t}} + LC\frac{{\partial ^2 v}}{{\partial t^2 }}$$
This equation is known as the transmission line equation. Note that it
has voltage at any particular location *x* as a function of time *t*.
:
: Similarly for current, we obtain:
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: **The Transmission Line Equation for Current**
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 i}}{{\partial x^2 }} = RGi + \left( {RC + LG} \right)\frac{{\partial i}}{{\partial t}} + LC\frac{{\partial ^2 i}}{{\partial t^2 }}$$
But we\'re not quite done yet.
### Solving the Transmission Line Equation
Historically, a mathematician would solve the transmission line equation
for *v* by assuming a solution for *v*, substituting it into the
equation, and observing whether the result made any sense. An engineer
would follow a similar procedure by making an "educated guess" based on
some laboratory experiments, as to what the solution might be. Today
there are more sophisticated techniques used to find solutions. In this
respect, the engineer may lag behind the mathematician by several
centuries in finding applications for mathematical tools.
To solve the transmission line equation, we shall guess that the
solution for the voltage function is of the form:
$$v\left( t \right) = e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \gamma x}$$
The first term represents a unity vector rotating at an angular velocity
of $\omega$ radians per second, in other words, a sine wave of some
frequency. The second term denotes the sinusoid being modified by the
transmission line, namely its amplitude decaying exponentially with
distance. If we let $\gamma$ be a complex quantity, we can also include
any phase changes which occur as the signal travels down the line.
: The sine wave is used as a signal source because it is easy to
generate, and manipulate mathematically. Euler's Identity shows the
relationship between exponential notation and trigonometric
functions:
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: **Euler\'s Identity**
$$e^{j\omega t} = \cos \left( {\omega t} \right) + j\sin \left( {\omega t} \right)$$
:
: Going back to our educated guess, we will let
$\gamma = \alpha + j\beta$, therefore:
$$v\left( t \right) = e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} = e^{ - \alpha x} e^{\left( {\omega t - \beta x} \right)j}$$
:
: The term $e^{ - \alpha x}$ represents the exponential amplitude
decay as this signal travels down the line. $\alpha$ is known as
the attenuation coefficient and is expressed in Nepers per
meter.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: The term $e^{\left( {\omega t - \beta x} \right)j}$ represents
the frequency of the signal at any point along the line. $\beta$
component is known as the phase shift coefficient, and is
expressed in radians per meter.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: Substituting our *educated guess*
$$v\left( t \right) = e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x}$$
:
: into the transmission line equation for voltage, we obtain:
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 }}{{\partial x^2 }}\left[ {e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right] = RG\left[ {e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right] + \left( {RC + LG} \right)\frac{\partial }{{\partial t}}\left[ {e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right] + LC\frac{{\partial ^2 }}{{\partial t^2 }}\left[ {e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right]$$
This looks pretty intimidating, but if you can do basic differentials
and algebra, you can do this!
#### Simplifying the Equation (trust me)
The idea now is to work through the math to see if we come up with a
reasonable solution. If we arrive at a contradiction or an unreasonable
result, it means that our educated guess was wrong and we have to do
more experimenting and come up with a better guess as to how voltage and
current travel down a transmission line.
Let\'s look at this equation one term at a time:
:
: LHS = RHS Term 1 + RHS Term 2 + RHS Term 3
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: Starting with the left hand side (LHS) we get the following
simplification:
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 }}{{\partial x^2 }}\left[ {e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right] = \frac{\partial }{{\partial x}}\left[ { - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right] = \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)^2 e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x}$$
:
: Believe it or not, the RHS Term 1 does not need simplifying.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: Simplifying the RHS Term 2, we obtain:
$$\left( {RC + LG} \right)\frac{\partial }{{\partial t}}\left[ {e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right] = \left( {RC + LG} \right)j\omega \left( {e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right)$$
:
: Simplifying the RHS Term 3, we obtain:
$$LC\frac{{\partial ^2 }}{{\partial t^2 }}\left[ {e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right] = LC\frac{\partial }{{\partial t}}\left[ {j\omega e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right] = - LC\omega ^2 e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x}$$
:
: Let\'s put it all back together:
$$\left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)^2 e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} = RG\left( {e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right) + \left( {RC + LG} \right)j\omega \left( {e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right) - LC\omega ^2 \left( {e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} } \right)$$
:
: Note that each of the four terms contain the expression
$e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x}$.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: Therefore we end up with:
$$\left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)^2 = RG + \left( {RC + LG} \right)j\omega - LC\omega ^2$$
:
: And this can be further simplified to:
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: **Attenuation and Phase Shift Coefficients**
$$\alpha + j\beta = \gamma = \sqrt {\left( {R + j\omega L} \right)\left( {G + j\omega C} \right)}$$
This result is not self contradictory or unreasonable. Therefore we
conclude that our educated guess was right and we have successfully
found an expression for attenuation and phase shift on a transmission
line as a function of its distributed electrical components and
frequency.
### Lossless Transmission Line
Signal loss occurs by two basic mechanisms: signal power can be
dissipated in a resistor \[or conductance\] or signal currents may be
shunted to an AC ground via a reactance. In transmission line theory, a
lossless transmission line does not dissipate power. Signals, will still
gradually diminish however, as shunt reactances return the current to
the source via the ground path. For the power loss to equal zero, R = G
= 0. This condition occurs when the transmission line is very short. An
oscilloscope probe is an example of a very short transmission line. The
transmission line equation reduces to the voltage equation:
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 v}}{{\partial x^2 }} = LC\frac{{\partial ^2 v}}{{\partial t^2 }}$$
:
: and the current equation:
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 i}}{{\partial x^2 }} = LC\frac{{\partial ^2 i}}{{\partial t^2 }}$$
To determine how sinusoidal signals are affected by this type of line,
we simply substitute a sinusoidal voltage or current into the above
expressions and solve as before, or we could take a much simpler
approach. We could start with the solution for the general case:
$$\alpha + j\beta = \gamma = \sqrt {\left( {R + j\omega L} \right)\left( {G + j\omega C} \right)}$$
:
: Let *R* = *G* = 0, and simplify:
$$\alpha + j\beta = \sqrt {\left( {j\omega L} \right)\left( {j\omega C} \right)} = \omega \left( {LC} \right)^2 j$$
:
: Equating the real and imaginary parts:
$$\alpha = 0$$
$$\beta = \omega \sqrt {LC}$$
This expression tells us that **a signal travelling down a lossless
transmission line, experiences a phase shift directly proportional to
its frequency.**
#### Phase Velocity
A new parameter, known as phase velocity, can be extracted from these
variables:
$$V_p = \frac{1}{{\sqrt {LC} }} = \frac{\omega }{\beta }$$ meters per
second
Phase velocity is the speed at which a fixed point on a wavefront,
appears to move. In the case of wire transmission lines, it is also the
velocity of propagation., typically: 0.24c \< Vp \< 0.9c .
The distance between two identical points on a wavefront is its
wavelength ($\lambda$) and since one cycle is defined as 2$\pi$ radians:
$$\lambda = \frac{{2\pi }}{\beta }$$ and $\omega = 2\pi f$
:
: therefore:
$$V_p = \lambda f$$
In free space, the phase velocity is 3 x 10^8^ meters/sec, the speed of
light. In a cable, the phase velocity is somewhat lower because the
signal is carried by electrons. In a waveguide transmission line, the
phase velocity exceeds the speed of light.
### Distortionless Transmission Line
A distortionless line does not distort the signal phase, but does
introduce a signal loss. Since common transmission lines are not super
conductors, the signal will decrease in amplitude but retain the same
shape as the input. This characteristic is essential for long cable
systems.
Phase distortion does not occur if the phase velocity *V~p~* is constant
at all frequencies.
By definition, a phase shift of 2$\pi$ radians occurs over one
wavelength $\lambda$.
:
: Since
$$V_p = \lambda f\quad \quad \lambda = \frac{{2\pi }}{\beta }\quad \quad f = \frac{\omega }{{2\pi }}$$
:
: Then:
$$V_p = \frac{{2\pi }}{\beta } \times \frac{\omega }{{2\pi }} = \frac{\omega }{\beta }$$
This tells us that in order for phase velocity *V~p~* to be constant,
the phase shift coefficient $\beta$, must vary directly with frequency
$\omega$.
:
: Recall
$$\gamma = \sqrt {\left( {R + j\omega L} \right)\left( {G + j\omega C} \right)} = \alpha + j\beta$$
The problem now is to find $\beta$. This can be done as follows:
$$\gamma = \sqrt {\left( {\frac{{R + j\omega L}}{{j\omega L}}} \right)\left( {j\omega L} \right)\left( {\frac{{G + j\omega C}}{{j\omega C}}} \right)\left( {j\omega C} \right)} = j\omega \sqrt {LC} \sqrt {1 + \frac{R}{{j\omega L}}} \sqrt {1 + \frac{G}{{j\omega C}}}$$
It may seem that we have lost $\beta$, but do not give up. The 2nd and
3rd roots can be expanded by means of the Binomial Expansion.
:
: Recall:
$$\left( {1 + x} \right)^n = 1 + nx + \frac{{n\left( {n - 1} \right)}}{{2!}}x^2 + \frac{{n\left( {n - 1} \right)\left( {n - 2} \right)}}{{3!}}x^3 + \cdots$$
:
: In this instance *n* = 1/2. Since the contribution of successive
terms diminishes rapidly, $\gamma$ is expanded to only 3 terms:
$$\gamma \approx j\omega \sqrt {LC} \left( {1 + \frac{1}{2}\frac{R}{{j\omega L}} - \frac{1}{8}\left( {\frac{R}{{j\omega L}}} \right)^2 } \right)\left( {1 + \frac{1}{2}\frac{G}{{j\omega C}} - \frac{1}{8}\left( {\frac{G}{{j\omega C}}} \right)^2 } \right)$$
This may seem complex, but remember it is only algebra and it will
reduce down to simple elegance. Expanding the terms we obtain:
$$\gamma \approx j\omega \sqrt {LC} \left\{ \begin{array}{l}
1 + \frac{1}{2}\frac{G}{{j\omega C}} - \frac{1}{8}\left( {\frac{G}{{j\omega C}}} \right)^2 + \frac{1}{2}\frac{R}{{j\omega L}} - \frac{1}{4}\frac{{RG}}{{\omega ^2 LC}} \\
- \frac{1}{{16}}\frac{R}{{j\omega L}}\left( {\frac{G}{{j\omega C}}} \right)^2 - \frac{1}{8}\left( {\frac{R}{{j\omega L}}} \right)^2 \\
- \frac{1}{{16}}\left( {\frac{R}{{j\omega L}}} \right)^2 \frac{G}{{j\omega C}} + \frac{1}{{64}}\left( {\frac{R}{{j\omega L}}} \right)^2 \left( {\frac{G}{{j\omega C}}} \right)^2 \\
\end{array} \right\}$$
:
: Since $\gamma = \alpha + j\beta$, we merely have to equate the
real and imaginary terms to find $\beta$.
$$\beta \approx \omega \sqrt {LC} \left\{ {1 + \underbrace {\frac{1}{8}\left( {\frac{G}{{\omega C}}} \right)^2 - \frac{1}{4}\frac{{RG}}{{\omega ^2 LC}} + \frac{1}{8}\left( {\frac{R}{{\omega L}}} \right)^2 }_{{\rm{Difference}}\;{\rm{of}}\;{\rm{squares}}} + \underbrace {\frac{1}{{64}}\left( {\frac{R}{{\omega L}}} \right)^2 \left( {\frac{G}{{\omega C}}} \right)^2 }_{{\rm{Very}}\;{\rm{small}}}} \right\}$$
:
: Or
$$\beta \approx \omega \sqrt {LC} \left\{ {1 + \frac{1}{8}\left( {\frac{R}{{\omega L}} - \frac{G}{{\omega C}}} \right)^2 } \right\}$$
:
: Note that if $\frac{R}{{\omega L}} = \frac{G}{{\omega C}}$ then
$\beta \approx \omega \sqrt {LC}$
From this we observe that $\beta$ is directly proportional to $\omega$.
:
: Therefore the **requirement for distortionless transmission
is:**
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: *RC = LG*
:
: This is one of the essential design characteristics for a
broadband coax cable network.
If we equate the real terms, we obtain:
$$\alpha \approx \sqrt {RG}$$
So there is a reason to study algebra after all!
## The Frequency Domain
Signal analysis is often performed in the frequency domain. This tells
us how the transmission line affects the spectral content of the signals
they are carrying.
To determine this, it is necessary to find the Fourier Transform of the
transmission line equation. Recall:
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 v}}{{\partial x^2 }} = RGv + \left( {RC + LG} \right)\frac{{\partial v}}{{\partial t}} + LC\frac{{\partial ^2 v}}{{\partial t^2 }}$$
and recall (hopefully) the Fourier Transform (which converts the time
domain to the frequency domain):
$$\mathbb{F}\left\{ {f\left( t \right)} \right\} = F\left( \omega \right) = \int\limits_{ - \infty }^\infty {e^{ - j\omega t} f\left( t \right)dt}$$
To prevent this analysis from 'blowing up', we must put a stipulation on
the voltage function namely, that it vanishes to zero at an infinite
distance down the line. This comprises a basic boundary condition.
$${\text{let}}\quad v \to 0\quad {\text{as}}\quad x \to \infty$$
This stipulation is in agreement with actual laboratory experiments. It
is well known that the signal magnitude diminishes as the path
lengthens.
Likewise, a time boundary condition, that the signal was zero at some
time in the distant past and will be zero at some time in the distant
future, must be imposed.
$${\text{let}}\quad v \to 0\quad {\text{as}}\quad t \to \infty$$
Although engineers have no difficulty imposing these restrictions,
mathematical purists, are somewhat offended. For this and other reasons,
other less restrictive transforms have been developed. The most notable
in this context, is the Laplace transform, which does not have the same
boundary conditions.
Having made the necessary concessions in order to continue our analysis,
we must find the Fourier Transform corresponding to the following terms:
$$\mathbb{F}\left\{ v \right\}\quad \quad \quad \mathbb{F}\left\{ {\frac{{\partial v}}
{{\partial t}}} \right\}\quad \quad \quad \mathbb{F}\left\{ {\frac{{\partial ^2 v}}
{{\partial t^2 }}} \right\}$$
$${\text{Let:}}\quad \quad \quad \mathbb{F}\left\{ v \right\} = V$$
:
: Then applying the transform on the derivative, we obtain:
$$\mathbb{F}\left\{ {\frac{{\partial v}}
{{\partial t}}} \right\} = \int\limits_{ - \infty }^\infty {e^{ - j\omega t} \frac{{\partial v}}
{{\partial t}}dt}$$
This equation can be solved by using integration by parts:
$$\int {u\,dv} = uv - \int {v\,du}$$
$${\text{let}}\quad u = e^{ - j\omega t} \quad \quad \quad \therefore du = - j\omega e^{ - j\omega t}$$
$${\text{and}}\quad dv = \frac{{\partial v}}{{\partial t}}\quad \quad \quad \therefore v = v$$
$$\therefore \mathbb{F}\left\{ {\frac{{\partial v}}
{{\partial t}}} \right\} = e^{ - j\omega t} \left. v \right|_{ - \infty }^\infty - \int\limits_{ - \infty }^\infty {v\left( { - j\omega e^{ - j\omega t} } \right)dt}$$
Applying the boundary conditions when t goes to infinity makes the 1st
term disappear.
$$\therefore \mathbb{F}\left\{ {\frac{{\partial v}}
{{\partial t}}} \right\} = j\omega \int\limits_{ - \infty }^\infty {e^{ - j\omega t} v\,dt}$$
Note that the resulting integral is simply the Fourier Transform. In
other words:
$$\mathbb{F}\left\{ {\frac{{\partial v}}
{{\partial t}}} \right\} = j\omega \mathbb{F}\left\{ v \right\} = j\omega V$$
:
: similarly:
$$\mathbb{F}\left\{ {\frac{{\partial ^2 v}}
{{\partial t^2 }}} \right\} = \left( {j\omega } \right)^2 \mathbb{F}\left\{ v \right\} = \left( {j\omega } \right)^2 V$$
We can now write the transmission line equation in the frequency domain:
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 V}}
{{\partial x^2 }} = RGV + \left( {RC + LG} \right)j\omega V + LC\left( {j\omega } \right)^2 V$$
:
: where:
$$V = V\left( \omega \right) = \mathbb{F}\left\{ {v\left( t \right)} \right\}$$
:
: Rearranging the terms, we obtain:
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 V}}
{{\partial x^2 }} = \left[ {RG + \left( {RC + LG} \right)j\omega + \left( {j\omega L} \right)\left( {j\omega C} \right)} \right]V$$
:
: or
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 V}}
{{\partial x^2 }} = \left[ {\left( {R + j\omega L} \right)\left( {G + j\omega C} \right)} \right]V$$
:
: since:
$$\sqrt {\left( {R + j\omega L} \right)\left( {G + j\omega C} \right)} = \alpha + j\beta = \gamma$$
:
: then
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 V}}{{\partial x^2 }} = \gamma ^2 V$$
:
: or
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 V}}{{\partial x^2 }} - \gamma ^2 V = 0$$
This represents the most general form of the transmission line equation
in the frequency domain. This equation must now be solved for V to
observe how voltage (or current) varies with distance and frequency.
This can be done by assuming a solution of the form:
$$V = \underbrace {Ae^{ - \gamma x} }_{{\text{forward}}\;{\text{wave}}} + \underbrace {Be^{\gamma x} }_{{\text{reverse}}\;{\text{wave}}}$$
These terms represent an exponential decay as the signal travels down
the transmission line. If we ignore any reflections, assuming that the
cable is infinitely long or properly terminated, this simplifies to:
$$V = V_0 e^{ - \gamma x}$$
To verify whether this assumption is correct, substitute it into the
equation, and see if a contradiction occurs. If there is no
contradiction, then our assumption constitutes a valid solution.
$$\frac{{\partial ^2 }}{{\partial x^2 }}V_0 e^{ - \gamma x} - \gamma ^2 V_0 e^{ - \gamma x} = 0$$
$$\frac{\partial }{{\partial x}}\left( { - \gamma ^2 V_0 e^{ - \gamma x} } \right) - \gamma ^2 V_0 e^{ - \gamma x} = 0$$
$$\gamma ^2 V_0 e^{ - \gamma x} - \gamma ^2 V_0 e^{ - \gamma x} = 0$$
$$0 = 0$$
Thus we validate the assumed solution. This tells us that in the
frequency domain, the voltage or current on a transmission line decays
exponentially:
$$V = V_0 e^{ - \gamma x}$$
:
: where:
$$\gamma = \sqrt {\left( {R + j\omega } \right)\left( {G + j\omega } \right)} = \left| \gamma \right|\angle \varphi = \alpha + j\beta$$
$$\gamma = {\text{ propagation}}\;{\text{constant}}$$
$$\alpha = {\text{ attenuation}}\;{\text{coeficient}}$$
$$\beta = {\text{phase}}\;{\text{coefficient}}$$
In exponential notation, a sinusoid may be represented by a rotating
unity vector, of some frequency:
$$e^{j\omega t} = \cos \omega t + j\sin \omega t$$
Note that the magnitude of this function is 1, but the phase angle is
changing as a function of *t*.
:
: If we let: $V_0 = e^{j\omega t}$
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: Then:
$V_0 = e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \gamma x} = e^{j\omega t} e^{ - \left( {\alpha + j\beta } \right)x} = \underbrace {e^{ - \alpha x} }_{{\text{attenuation}}\;vs.\;x}\overbrace {e^{j\left( {\omega t - \beta x} \right)} }^{{\text{phase}}\;vs{\text{.}}\;t\;{\text{and}}\;x}$
This result is quite interesting because it is the same solution for the
transmission line equation in the time domain. The term
${e^{ - \alpha x} }$ represents an exponential decay. The signal is
attenuated as length *x* increases. The amount of attenuation is defined
as:
:
: Attenuation in Nepers:
$N = \left| {\ln e^{ - \alpha x} } \right| = \alpha x$
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
:
: Attenuation in dB:
$= 20\log e^{ - \alpha x} \approx 8.68589\alpha x$
This allows us to determine the attenuation at any frequency at any
point in a transmission line, if we are given the basic line parameters
of*R, L, G, & C*.
The term ${e^{j\left( {\omega t - \beta x} \right)} }$ represents a
rotating unity vector since:
$$e^{j\left( {\omega t - \beta x} \right)} = \cos \left( {\omega t - \beta x} \right) + j\sin \left( {\omega t - \beta x} \right)$$
The phase angle of this vector is ${\beta x}$ radians.
## Characteristic Impedance
The characteristic impedance of a transmission line is also known as its
surge impedance, and should not be confused with its resistance. If a
line is infinitely long, electrical signals will still propagate down
it, even though the resistance approaches infinity. The characteristic
impedance is determined from its AC attributes, not its DC ones.
Recall from our earlier analysis:
|
# Communication Systems/Wireless Transmission
This page will discuss Wireless EM wave propagation, and some basics
about antennas.
## Isotropic Antennas
An isotropic antenna radiates it\'s transmitted power equally in all
directions. This is an ideal model; all real antennas have at least some
directionality associated with them. However, it is mathematically
convenient, and good enough for most purposes.
### Power Flux Density
If the transmitted power is spread evenly across a sphere of radius R
from the antenna, we can find the power per unit area of that sphere,
called the **Power Flux Density** using the Greek letter Φ (capital phi)
and the following formula:
$$\Phi = \frac{P_T}{4 \pi R^2}$$
Where $P_T$ is the total transmitted power of the signal.
### Effective Area
The **effective area** of an antenna is the equivalent amount of area of
transmission power, from a non-ideal isotropic antenna that appears to
be the area from an ideal antenna. For instance, if our antenna is
non-ideal, and 1 meter squared of area can effectively be modeled as .5
meters squared from an ideal antenna, then we can use the ideal number
in our antenna. We can relate the actual area and the effective area of
our antenna using the *antenna efficiency* number, as follows:
$$\eta = \frac{A_e}{A}$$
The area of an ideal isotropic antenna can be calculated using the
wavelength of the transmitted signal as follows:
$$A = \frac{\lambda^2}{4 \pi}$$
### Received Power
The amount of power that is actually received by a receiver placed at
distance R from the isotropic antenna is denoted $P_R$, and can be found
with the following equation:
$$P_R = \Phi_R A_e$$
Where $\Phi_R$ is the power flux density at the distance R. If we plug
in the formula for the effective area of an ideal isotropic antenna into
this equation, we get the following result:
$$P_R = \frac{P_T}{(4 \pi R / \lambda)^2} = \frac{P_T}{L_P}$$
Where $L_P$ is the path-loss, and is defined as:
$$L_P = \left( \frac{4 \pi R}{\lambda} \right)^2$$
The amount of power lost across freespace between two isotropic antenna
(a transmitter and a receiver) depends on the wavelength of the
transmitted signal.
## Directional Antennas
A directional antenna, such as a parabolic antenna, attempts to radiate
most of its power in the direction of a known receiver.
Here are some definitions that we need to know before we proceed:
Azimuth Angle:The Azimuth angle, often denoted with a θ (Greek lower-case Theta), is the angle that the direct transmission makes with respect to a given reference angle (often the angle of the target receiver) when looking down on the antenna from above.\
Elevation Angle:The elevation angle is the angle that the transmission direction makes with the ground. Elevation angle is denoted with a φ (Greek lower-case phi)
### Directivity
Given the above definitions, we can define the transmission gain of a
directional antenna as a function of θ and φ, assuming the same
transmission power:
$$G_T(\theta, \phi) = \frac{\Phi_{\theta,\ \phi}}{\Phi_{isotropic}}$$
### Effective Area
The effective area of a parabolic antenna is given as such:
$$A_e = \eta \frac{\pi D^2}{4}$$
### Transmit Gain
$$G_{max} = \frac{4 \pi A_e}{\lambda^2}$$
If we are at the transmit antenna, and looking at the receiver, the
angle that the transmission differs from the direction that we are
looking is known as Ψ (Greek upper-case Psi), and we can find the
transmission gain as a function of this angle as follows:
$$G(\Psi) = \left( \frac{2J_1((\pi D / \lambda) sin(\Psi))}{sin(\Psi)} \right)^2 \left( \frac{\lambda}{\pi D} \right)^2$$
Where $J_1(\ )$ denotes the first-order bessel function.
### Friis Equation
The **Friis Equation** is used to relate several values together when
using directional antennas:
$$P_R = \frac{P_T G_T G_R}{L_P}$$
The Friis Equation is the fundamental basis for **link-budget
analysis**.
## Link-Budget Analysis
If we express all quantities from the Friis Equation in decibels, and
divide both sides by the noise-density of the transmission medium, N0,
we get the following equation:
$$C/N_0 = EIRP - L_P + (G_R/T_e) - k$$
Where C/N0 is the received carrier-to-noise ratio, and we can decompose
N0 as follows:
$$N_0 = kTe$$
k is Boltzmann\'s constant, (-228.6dBW) and Te is the effective
temperature of the noise signal (in degrees Kelvin). EIRP is the
\"Equivalent Isotropic Radiated Power\", and is defined as:
$$EIRP = G_T P_T$$
To perform a link-budget analysis, we add all the transmission gain
terms from the transmitter, we add the receive gain divided by the
effective temperature, and we subtract Boltzmann\'s constant and all the
path losses of the transmission.
## Further reading
- Jean-Claude Wippler. \"What if you're out of wireless
range?\".
2013.
|
# Communication Systems/Space-Division Multiplexing
This page is all about **Space-Division Multiplexing** (SDM).
- What is SDM: When we want to transmit multiple messages, the goal is
maximum reuse of the given resources: time and frequency.
Time-Division Multiplexing (TDM), operates by dividing the time up
into time slices, so that the available time can be reused.
Frequency-Division Multiplexing (FDM), operates by dividing up the
frequency into transmission bands, so that the frequency spectrum
can be reused. However, if we remember our work with directional
antennas, we can actually reuse both time and frequency, by
transmitting our information along parallel channels. This is known
as **Space-Division Multiplexing**.
## Technical categorisations
### Spatial Coding
## Multipathing
## Application systems
### MIMO Systems
### Smart antenna
|
# Communication Systems/Fading Channels
Over large distances, signal quality degrades even without the presence
of large quantities of AWGN. This degradation is known as **fading**,
and channels that exhibit these properties are known as **fading
channels**.
## What Causes Fading
Fading can be caused due to natural weather disturbances, such as
rainfall, snow, fog, hail and extremely cold air over a warm earth.
Fading can also be created by man made disturbances, such as irrigation,
or from multiple transmission paths, irregular earth surfaces, and
varying terrains.
## Fading Channel Models
### Rician fading
### Rayleigh Fading
### nakagami fading
## Scales of Fading
### *Large-Scale Fading*
Fading generally is a signal loss either in amplitude or phase due to
sudden changes in Channel response. Large scale fading \" Shadowing\"
concerns about large distances effect so, its affect appears clearly in
case of the a moving vehicle where the signal is influenced by Multipath
phenomena where the transmitted signal is received from more than one
path.
### Small-Scale Fading
Small scale fading is concerned about very small changes in the position
of Transmitter or receiver in order of the wavelength as this affect
greatly the received frequency due to doppler effect so as the speed of
the vehicle increases as the frequency is more rapidly changing and it
can be described as fast or slow fading AND flat or slow fading.
## Small-Scale Fading Types
### Frequency-Selective Fading
### Flat Fading
In flat fading, the coherence bandwidth of the channel is larger than
the bandwidth of the signal. Therefore, all frequency components of the
signal will experience the same magnitude of fading. a signal undergoes
flat fading if:
` Bs << Bc`
### Fast Fading
Fast fading occurs when coherant time of the channel is small relative
to the delay constraint of the channel. Amplitude and phase changes
imposed by the channel varies considerably over period of use.
|
# Bourne Shell Scripting/Appendix D: Cookbook
------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
!Wikimedia Commons logo{width="20"} **\[`{{localurl:{{NAMESPACE}}:{{PAGENAME}}|action=edit§ion=new}}`{=mediawiki} Post a new Cookbook entry\]**
If you use the title box, then you do not need to put a title in the body.
------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
## Branch on extensions
When writing a bash script which should do different things based on the
extension of a file, the following pattern is helpful.
``` shell
#filepath should be set to the name(with optional path) of the file in question
ext=${filepath##*.}
if [[ "$ext" == txt ]] ; then
#do something with text files
fi
```
(Source: slike.com Bash
FAQ).
## Rename several files
This recipe shows how to rename several files following a pattern.
In this example, the user has huge collection of screenshots. This user
wants to rename the files using a Bourne-compatible shell. Here is an
\"ls\" at the shell prompt to show you the filenames. The goal is to
rename images like \"snapshot1.png\" to
\"nethack-kernigh-22oct2005-01.png\".
``` console
$ ls
snapshot1.png snapshot25.png snapshot40.png snapshot56.png snapshot71.png
snapshot10.png snapshot26.png snapshot41.png snapshot57.png snapshot72.png
snapshot11.png snapshot27.png snapshot42.png snapshot58.png snapshot73.png
snapshot12.png snapshot28.png snapshot43.png snapshot59.png snapshot74.png
snapshot13.png snapshot29.png snapshot44.png snapshot6.png snapshot75.png
snapshot14.png snapshot3.png snapshot45.png snapshot60.png snapshot76.png
snapshot15.png snapshot30.png snapshot46.png snapshot61.png snapshot77.png
snapshot16.png snapshot31.png snapshot47.png snapshot62.png snapshot78.png
snapshot17.png snapshot32.png snapshot48.png snapshot63.png snapshot79.png
snapshot18.png snapshot33.png snapshot49.png snapshot64.png snapshot8.png
snapshot19.png snapshot34.png snapshot5.png snapshot65.png snapshot80.png
snapshot2.png snapshot35.png snapshot50.png snapshot66.png snapshot81.png
snapshot20.png snapshot36.png snapshot51.png snapshot67.png snapshot82.png
snapshot21.png snapshot37.png snapshot52.png snapshot68.png snapshot83.png
snapshot22.png snapshot38.png snapshot53.png snapshot69.png snapshot9.png
snapshot23.png snapshot39.png snapshot54.png snapshot7.png
snapshot24.png snapshot4.png snapshot55.png snapshot70.png
```
First, to add a \"0\" (zero) before snapshots 1 through 9, write a for
loop (in effect, a short shell script).
- Use `?` which is a filename pattern for a single character. Using
it, I can match snapshots 1 through 9 but miss 10 through 83 by
saying `snapshot?.png`.
- Use `${`*parameter*`#`*pattern*`}` to substitute the value of
*parameter* with the *pattern* removed from the beginning. This is
to get rid of \"snapshot\" so I can put in \"snapshot0\".
- Before actually running the loop, insert an \"echo\" to test that
the commands will be correct.
``` console
$ for i in snapshot?.png; do echo mv "$i" "snapshot0${i#snapshot}"; done
mv snapshot1.png snapshot01.png
mv snapshot2.png snapshot02.png
mv snapshot3.png snapshot03.png
mv snapshot4.png snapshot04.png
mv snapshot5.png snapshot05.png
mv snapshot6.png snapshot06.png
mv snapshot7.png snapshot07.png
mv snapshot8.png snapshot08.png
mv snapshot9.png snapshot09.png
```
That seems good, so run it by removing the \"echo\".
``` console
$ for i in snapshot?.png; do mv "$i" "snapshot0${i#snapshot}"; done
```
An ls confirms that this was effective.
Now change prefix \"snapshot\" to \"nethack-kernigh-22oct2005-\". Run a
loop similar to the previous one:
``` console
$ for i in snapshot*.png; do \
> mv "$i" "nethack-kernigh-22oct2005-${i#snapshot}" \
> done
```
This saves the user from typing 83 \"mv\" commands.
## Long command line options
The builtin `getopts` does not support long options so the external
`getopt` is required. (On some systems, `getopt` *also* does not support
long options, so the next example will not work.)
``` shell
eval set -- $(getopt -l install-opts: "" "$@")
while true; do
case "$1" in
--install-opts)
INSTALL_OPTS=$2
shift 2
;;
--)
shift
break
;;
esac
done
echo $INSTALL_OPTS
```
The call to `getopt` quotes and reorders the command line arguments
found in `$@`. `set` then makes replaces `$@` with the output from
`getopt`
Another example of getopt use can also be found in the Advanced Bash
Script Guide
## Process certain files through xargs
In this recipe, we want to process a large list of files, but we must
run one command for each file. In this example, we want to convert the
sampling rates of some sound files to 44100 hertz. The command is
**`sox file.ogg -r 44100 conv/file.ogg`**, which converts `file.ogg` to
a new file `conv/file.ogg`. We also want to skip files that are already
44100 hertz.
First, we need the sampling rates of our files. One way is to use the
**`file`** command:
``` console
$ file *.ogg
audio_on.ogg: Ogg data, Vorbis audio, mono, 44100 Hz, ~80000 bps
beep_1.ogg: Ogg data, Vorbis audio, stereo, 44100 Hz, ~193603 bps
cannon_1.ogg: Ogg data, Vorbis audio, mono, 48000 Hz, ~96000 bps
...
```
(The files in this example are from Secret Maryo
Chronicles.) We can use **`grep -v`** to
filter out all lines that contain \'44100 Hz\':
``` console
$ file *.ogg | grep -v '44100 Hz'
cannon_1.ogg: Ogg data, Vorbis audio, mono, 48000 Hz, ~96000 bps
...
jump_small.ogg: Ogg data, Vorbis audio, mono, 8000 Hz, ~22400 bps
live_up.ogg: Ogg data, Vorbis audio, mono, 22050 Hz, ~40222 bps
...
```
We finished with \"grep\" and \"file\", so now we want to remove the
other info and leave only the filenames to pass to \"sox\". We use the
text utility **`cut`**. The option **`-d:`** divides each line into
fields at the colon; **`-f1`** selects the first field.
``` console
$ file *.ogg | grep -v '44100 Hz' | cut -d: -f1
cannon_1.ogg
...
jump_small.ogg
live_up.ogg
...
```
We can use another pipe to supply the filenames on the standard input,
but \"sox\" expects them as arguments. We use **`xargs`**, which will
run a command repeatedly using arguments from the standard input. The
**`-n1`** option specifies one argument per command. For example, we can
run **`echo sox`** repeatedly:
``` console
$ file *.ogg | grep -v '44100 Hz' | cut -d: -f1 | xargs -n1 echo sox
sox cannon_1.ogg
...
sox itembox_set.ogg
sox jump_small.ogg
...
```
However, these commands are wrong. The full command for cannon_1.ogg,
for example, is **`sox cannon_1.ogg -r 44100 conv/cannon_1.ogg`**.
\"xargs\" will insert incoming data into placeholders indicated by
\"{}\". We use this strategy in our pipeline. If we have doubt, then
first we can build a test pipeline with \"echo\":
``` console
$ file *.ogg | grep -v '44100 Hz' | cut -d: -f1 | \
> xargs -i 'echo sox {} -r 44100 conv/{}'
sox cannon_1.ogg -r 44100 conv/cannon_1.ogg
...
sox itembox_set.ogg -r 44100 conv/itembox_set.ogg
sox jump_small.ogg -r 44100 conv/jump_small.ogg
...
```
It worked, so let us remove the \"echo\" and run the \"sox\" commands:
``` console
$ mkdir conv
$ file *.ogg | grep -v '44100 Hz' | cut -d: -f1 | \
> xargs -i 'sox {} -r 44100 conv/{}'
```
After a wait, the converted files appear in the `conv` subdirectory. The
above three lines alone did the entire conversion.
## Simple playlist frontend for GStreamer
If you have GStreamer, the command
`gst-launch filesrc location=`*`filename`*` ! decodebin ! audioconvert ! esdsink`
will play a sound or music file of any format for which you have a
GStreamer plugin. This script will play through a list of files,
optionally looping through them. (Replace \"esdsink\" with your favorite
sink.)
``` {.shell .numberLines}
#!/bin/sh
loop=false
if test x"$1" == x-l; then
loop=true
shift
fi
while true; do
for i in "$@"; do
if test -f "$i"; then
echo "${0##*/}: playing $i" > /dev/stderr
gst-launch filesrc location="$i" ! decodebin ! audioconvert ! esdsink
else
echo "${0##*/}: not a file: $i" > /dev/stderr
fi
done
if $loop; then true; else break; fi
done
```
This script demonstrates some common Bourne shell tactics:
- \"loop\" is a boolean variable. It works because its values \"true\"
and \"false\" are both Unix commands (and sometimes shell builtins),
thus you can use them as conditions in `if` and `while` statements.
- The shell builtin \"shift\" removes \$1 from the argument list, thus
shifting \$2 to \$1, \$3 to \$2, and so forward. This script uses it
to process an \"-l\" option.
- The substitution `${0##*/}` gives everything in \$0 after the last
slash, thus \"playlist\", not \"/home/musicfan/bin/playlist\".
|
# Introduction to Numerical Methods/Introduction
Mathematical models are a central piece of science and engineering. Some
models have closed-form solutions, therefore they can be solved
analytically. Many models can not be solved analytically or the analytic
solution is too costly to be practical. All models can be solved
computationally and the result may not be the exact answer but it can be
useful. George E. P. Box was right by saying All models are wrong, but
some are useful. Since
errors are inevitable a more practical question we ought to ask is how
close the answer needs to be for it to be useful. In lots of engineering
situations the only way to get the \"right answer\" is to use the
following formula:
right answer = wrong answer + corrections
Missile Knows Where It Is
is an audio click explaining how a missile guidance system can possibly
work by repeatedly correcting it errors.
Before we discuss how to manage errors lets explore the sources of
errors.
|
# Introduction to Numerical Methods/Rounding Off Errors
# Rounding Off Errors
Learning objectives:
- recognize the sources of overflow and underflow errors
- convert between decimal representation and floating point
representation
- understand the IEEE 754 standard of a floating point representation
on computers
- calculate the machine epsilon of a representation.
## Integer Overflow (Error)
How are integers represented on a computer?
Most computers use the 2\'s
complement
representation. Assume we have 4 bits to store and operate on an integer
we may end up with the following situation:
` 0111 (7)`\
`+0001 (1)`\
`-----`\
` 1000 (-8)`
The numbers in parentheses are the decimal value represented by the 2\'s
complement binary integers. The result is obviously wrong because adding
positive numbers should never result in a negative number. The reason
for the error is that result exceeds the range of values the 4-bit can
store with the 2\'s complement notation.
The following example gives the wrong answer for the same reason. The
leading 1 can not be stored.
` 1000 (-8)`\
`+1111 (-1)`\
`-----`\
`10111 (7)`
## Floating-point Underflow (Error)
In math numbers have infinite precision, but numerals (representations
of number) have finite precision. One third (1/3) can not be represented
precisely in decimal or it would require a infinite number of digits,
which is impossible. Similarly 0.2 can not be represented precisely in
binary, which means its binary representation is not precise (an
approximation).
When numbers are computed/calculated on a computer, the representations
of the numbers are being manipulated and the result will very likely be
imprecise. This is an important limitation of computing. Essentially the
computer must be considered a part of our model when we solve problems
computationally. We must factor the computer in because it is a binary
computer approximating base ten numbers.
An floating-point underflow or
underflow happens
when the result of a calculation is too small to be stored. A underflow
can be caused by the (negative) overflow of the exponent.
: What is the binary representation of $11.1875_{10}$?
### Fixed-point Representation
Any real number can be represented in binary as a fixed-point number. To
convert the number from its decimal (base 10) representation to its
binary representation we need to convert the integer part and the
fractional part to binary separately, because different methods are
required. Please check out the following resource on how to do that
1.
With a fixed number of digits and a fixed decimal point the range of
representable values is fixed. Given five digits as follows
$nnn.nn_{10}$, we can represent positive values from $0.01_{10}$ to
$999.99_{10}$. Using the following scientific notation
$nnn \times 10^{nn}$ we can represent positive values ranging from
$0.01_{10}$ to $99900_{10}$, which is much larger than that of the
fixed-point representation.
### Floating-point Representation
Given a fixed number of digits we can represent a larger range of values
using the floating-point
format. The IEEE 754 format is a international standard on
floating-point representation of numbers in computers. A 32-bit floating
point number (single precision) is represented using three parts as
shown in the figure: : a sign bit, a (biased) exponent, and a fraction.
!The number 0.15625 represented as a single-precision IEEE 754-1985
floating-point number. See text for
explanation.
The value represented by an IEEE 754 single precision floating point
number can be calculated using the following formula:
$$(-1)^{sign} \times 1.fraction \times 2^{exponent - 127}$$
For example to store in IEEE single precision floating point format
$0.15625_{10}=0.00101_{2}=1.01_2 \times 2^{-3}$, we need to store a sign
bit of $0$ (0 means positive and 1 means negative), a fraction of $.01$,
and a biased exponent of $-3_{10}+127_{10}=124_{10}=1111100_2$. Because
all numbers, except 0, will have a leading one in the binary
\"scientific\" representation that one is not stored in IEEE 754 format
to save one bit. We will say how the value 0 is represented in a moment.
The biased exponent is just a clever way to use the available bits to
represent more values and make number comparison faster. We will use
8-bit exponent as an example. In the figure above, we have 8-bit which
can represent $2^8=256_{10}$ different things. The bit patterns have no
intrinsic meaning, so we can use them to represent anything we want. The
green part shows the values those bit patterns represent when they are
treated as binary representations of unsigned integers. The problem is
that we want to represent negative values as well. One easy solution is
to treat the left most bit as the sign bit: 0 means positive and 1 means
negative, which result in two zeros $+0$ and $-0$. The blue part shows
what happens when we use the 2\'s complement scheme to represent both
positive and negative values using the same set of bit patterns. Recall
that the 2\'s complement scheme is often used to simply hardware design
so that we can use addition to do subtraction: a - b is the same as a +
(the 2\'s complement of -b). To get the 2\'s complement of a positive
integer is to invert all the bits and add 1 to it. Now any subtraction
can be done with a inversion and two additions. The problem with 2\'s
complement representation is that a \"larger\" looking pattern does not
necessarily represent a larger value. !This figure shows how the biased
exponent for IEEE 754
works.
The red part shows the biased exponent represented by the same set of
bit patterns. As you can see a \"larger\" looking pattern always
represent a larger value except for the all one patterns, which is used
to represent a special value. The advantage of the biased exponent
representation is that each value is represented by a unique pattern (no
two zeros) and comparing floating point numbers is easier. The exponent
is put before the fraction in IEEE 754 standard so that floating point
numbers can be compared by treating their bit patterns as unsigned
integers (much faster).
The following table shows some special values represented by special bit
patterns.
biased expoent fraction numbers
---------------- ---------- --------------------
00\...00 0 0
00\...00 nonzero denormalized
11\...11 0 +/- infinity
11\...11 nonzero NaN (Not a Number)
Because the implicit/hidden 1 is always added to the fraction to get the
represented value a special pattern is needed to represent the zero
value. Now the result of a division by zero can be represented as +/-
infinity (division by zero in integer operation will crash your
program). $\sqrt{-4}$, $$ and $0/0$ can be represented as NaN, which
helps debugging your programs.
: What is the IEEE 754 floating-point representation of this number:
$-2.340625 \times 10^1$
: What is the decimal equivalent of this IEEE 754 floating-point
number: 1100 0000 1111 0000 0000 0000 0000 0000?
: What is the largest IEEE 754 single precision floating-point number?
What are the downsides of floating-point or scientific representation?
With five digits we can represent $999.99_{10}$ precisely using fixed
point notation. However, when we use the following
scientific/floating-point notation $n.nn \times 10^{nn}$ the closest
value we can represent is $9.99 \times 10^{02}$ and the error is
$999.99-999=0.99$ - a loss of precision.
### Real v.s. Floating-point Number Lines
This figure illustrates
the different the number line for real numbers and that for floating
point numbers. The following observations can be made:
- The real number line is continuous, dense, and infinite.
- The floating-point number (representation) line is discrete, sparse,
and finite.
- A group of real numbers are represented by the same floating-point
number (an approximation).
- The sizes of groups get larger and larger as the floating-point
numbers get larger.
Lets study a concrete example. With four decimal digits and a fixed
point representation ($nnn.n$) we can represent 0, 0.1, 0.2, 0.3, \...,
999.8, 999.9 with equal distance between the consecutive numbers. With a
floating-point representation ($+n.nn \times 10^{\pm n}$) , the smallest
value we can represent is $1.00 \times 10^{-9}=0.\underbrace{0...0}_8 1$
and the largest representable value is $1.11 \times 10^{+9}=1110000000$.
Now lets look at representable values by this floating-point number
format around some points on the number line:
- Next to 0:
$1.00 \times 10^{-9}=0.\underbrace{0...0}_8 1, 1.01 \times 10^{-9}=0.\underbrace{0...0}_8 101, 1.02 \times 10^{-9}=0.\underbrace{0...0}_8 102, ...$
(the distance between consecutive numbers is 0.00000000001)
- Next to 1:
$1.00 \times 10^{0}=1, 1.01 \times 10^{0}=1.01, 1.02 \times 10^{0}=1.02, ...$
(the distance between consecutive numbers is 0.01)
- Next to 10:
$1.00 \times 10^{1}=10, 1.01 \times 10^{1}=10.1, 1.02 \times 10^{1}=10.2, ...$
(the distance between consecutive numbers is 0.1)
- Next to 100:
$1.00 \times 10^{2}=100, 1.01 \times 10^{2}=101, 1.02 \times 10^{2}=102, ...$
(the distance between consecutive numbers is 1)
- Next to 1000:
$1.00 \times 10^{3}=1000, 1.01 \times 10^{3}=1010, 1.02 \times 10^{3}=1020, ...$
(the distance between consecutive numbers is 10)
As you can see not every real number can be represented using the
floating-point format. The distribution of the representable values is
not uniform: it is denser around smaller values and more sparse (spread
out) around larger values, which means the larger a value we want to
represent the less precise we can do it.
What is the smallest IEEE 754 single precision number greater than 1?
### Machine Epsilon
Machine epsilon is defined to be
the smallest positive number which, when added to 1, gives a number
different from 1. The machine epsilon for floating-point format is
$b^{-(p-1)}$, where $b$ is the base (radix) and $p$ (precision) is the
number of digits for the fraction plus one.
What is the machine epsilon of IEEE 754 floating-point numbers?
|
# Introduction to Numerical Methods/Measuring Errors
# Measuring Errors
In this lesson we will learn how to quantify errors.
Learning objectives
- identify true and relative true errors
- identify approximate and relative approximate errors
- explain the relationship between the absolute relative approximate
error and the number of significant digits
- identify significant digits
Reference
: Chapter 1 of Holistic Numerical
Methods
## True and Relative True Errors
A true error ($E_t$) is defined as the difference between the true
(exact) value and an approximate value. This type of error is only
measurable when the true value is available. You might wonder why we
would use an approximate value instead of the true value. One example
would be when the true value cannot be represented precisely due to the
notational system or the limit of the physical storage we use.
`true error (`$E_t$`) = true value - approximate value`
A true error doesn\'t signify how important an error is. For instance, a
0.1 pound error is a very small error when measuring a person\'s weight,
but the same error can be disastrous when measuring the dosage of a
medicine. Relative true error ($\epsilon_t$) is defined as the ratio
between the true error and the true value.
`relative true error (`$\epsilon_t$`) = true error / true value`
## Approximate and Relative Approximate Errors
Oftentimes the true value is unknown to us, especially in numerical
computing. In this case we will have to quantify errors using
approximate values only. When an iterative method is used, we get an
approximate value at the end of each iteration. The approximate error
($E_a$) is defined as the difference between the present approximate
value and the previous approximation (i.e. the change between the
iterations).
`approximate error (`$E_a$`) = present approximation – previous approximation`
Similarly we can calculate the relative approximate error ($\epsilon_a$)
by dividing the approximate error by the present approximate value.
`relative approximate error (`$\epsilon_a$`) = approximate error / present approximation`
## Relative Approximate Error and Significant Digits
Assume our iterative method yield a better approximation as the
iteration goes on. Oftentimes we can set an acceptable tolerance to stop
the iteration at when the relative approximate error is small enough. We
often set the tolerance in terms of the number of significant
digits - the number
of digits that carry meaning contributing to its precision. It
corresponds to the number of digits in the scientific notation to
represent a number\'s significand or
mantissa.
An approximate rule for minimizing the error is as follows: if the
absolute relative approximate error is less than or equal to a
predefined tolerance (usually in terms of the number of significant
digits), then the acceptable error has been reached and no more
iterations would be required. Given the absolute relative approximate
error, we can derive the least number of digits that are significant
using the same equation.
$|\epsilon_a| \le 0.5 \times 10^{2-m}%$
|
# Introduction to Numerical Methods/Python Programming
# Python Programming
Objectives:
- familiarize with the Python programming language and command-line
interface
- use correct control structures
- write simple Python programs with correct syntax
- import and use libraries
Resources:
- Introduction to Python for Computational Science and Engineering (A
beginner's
guide)
- Google\'s Python class for
developers
- The Beginner\'s Python Tutorial
- The Official Python Tutorial
- The Official Python for
Beginners
- Introduction to Python
- IPython
Python is a scripting language. You can use the interactive Python
console to write and execute code. After you log into a Unix/Linux
system you can type the type the word \"python\" (with the quotes) to
start the console and hit \^D (ctrl+D) will exit the console. This kind
of interactivity makes it ideal for exploratory discovery - finding a
solution by exploring and experimentation.
## REPL
The Python console executes a Read-Eval-Print Loop (REPL), which means
it prompts you for a expression/command and once you hit enter it will
read your expression, evaluate it, print the value of the expression,
and prompt you for the next expression. This makes it very easy to test
a Python statement. You can use it as a calculator:
``` Python
>>>1+2
3
>>>2**3
8
>>> # this is a comment
...
>>> 2**0.5
1.4142135623730951
```
## Import Libraries
Many useful functions have been implemented in libraries. To use the
functions you need to import them so that their names are recognized.
The dir() function prints a directory of objects (functions) available
in a module:
``` python
>>>import math
>>>dir(math)
['__doc__', '__name__', '__package__', 'acos', 'acosh', 'asin', 'asinh', 'atan', 'atan2', 'atanh', 'ceil',
'copysign', 'cos', 'cosh', 'degrees', 'e', 'erf', 'erfc', 'exp', 'expm1', 'fabs', 'factorial', 'floor', 'fmod',
'frexp', 'fsum', 'gamma', 'hypot', 'isinf', 'isnan', 'ldexp', 'lgamma', 'log', 'log10', 'log1p', 'modf',
'pi', 'pow', 'radians', 'sin', 'sinh', 'sqrt', 'tan', 'tanh', 'trunc']
>>> help(math.exp)
Help on built-in function exp in module math:
exp(...)
exp(x)
Return e raised to the power of x.
>>> # this is similar to 2 ** 0.5
>>> math.sqrt(2)
1.4142135623730951
```
The help() function can be used to find the meaning and the usage of an
object from a library as shown in the previous code example. Note that
you need to hit the letter Q to quit the help session to return to the
Python console.
## Data Types
Python is not a strongly typed language, which means you do not need to
declare a specific data type for a variable. But data items associated
with variables have types, which are implied - derived from the
expression or the operation on the data items. Therefore the data type
of a variable can change over time. The type() function will tell you
the type of data stored in a variable.
``` Python
>>> type(a)
<type 'int'>
>>> type(1)
<type 'int'>
>>> a = 1.0
>>> type(a)
<type 'float'>
>>> a = "one"
>>> type(a)
<type 'str'>
>>> a = False
>>> print a False
>>> type(a)
<type ’bool’>
>>> a = 1 + 2j
>>> type(a)
<type 'complex'>
>>> a = [1, 2, 3]
>>> type(a)
<type 'list'>
```
There are functions that convert between data types, e.g. int(),
float(), str(), and list().
``` Python
>>> a = int("123")
>>> a
123
>>> type(a)
<type 'int'>
>>> a = float("123.4")
>>> a
123.4
>>> type(a)
<type 'float'>
>>> a = str(123.4)
>>> a
'123.4'
>>> type(a)
<type 'str'>
>>> a = list("one two three")
>>> a
['o', 'n', 'e', ' ', 't', 'w', 'o', ' ', 't', 'h', 'r', 'e', 'e']
>>> type(a)
<type 'list'>
```
Data types get promoted automatically as necessary.
``` Python
>>> import sys
>>> sys.maxint
9223372036854775807
>>> type(sys.maxint)
<type 'int'>
>>> type(sys.maxint+1)
<type 'long'>
```
In Python strings, lists and tuples are sequences. They can be indexed
and sliced in the same way. A list in Python can contain data items of
different type.
``` Python
>>> range(10)
[0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9]
>>> for i in range(10):
... print i ** 2
...
0
1
4
9
16
25
36
49
64
81
```
## Source Files
In addition to write and running Python code directly in the console you
can save your commands/statements in a file and run the whole file as a
script using the Python interpreter. For example, in a shell
command-line you can type the following to run your program/script
called hello.py:
``` bash
python hello.py
```
Indentation matters in Python because it is used for defining scopes,
which eliminates the use of braces {}. Please make sure the code at the
same level are indented the same amount represented by tab or space
characters.
## Formatted Printing
You can print numbers using a format string similar to the printf
function in C.
``` Python
>>>a = 0.1
>>> a
0.1
>>>print "%20.19f" % a
0.1000000000000000056
```
This example show the limit of the floating point number representation.
1/10 can not be represented precisely because it is not a power of two.
Even though the console prints a as 0.1 the underlying representation is
almost 0.1.
## Numerical Computation
``` Python
>>> import math
>>> a = math.sqrt(2)
>>> a
1.4142135623730951
>>> a ** 2
2.0000000000000004
```
The following example will run forever till the result overflows the
registers because x will never become exactly 1.0 because the
representation of 0.1 is an approximation (with an error).
``` Python
>>> x = 0.0
>>> while not x == 1.0:
... x = x + 0.1
... print("x=%19.17g" % (x))
...
x=0.10000000000000001
x=0.20000000000000001
x=0.30000000000000004
x=0.40000000000000002
x= 0.5
x=0.59999999999999998
x=0.69999999999999996
```
The moral of the lesson is: do not compare floating point numbers for
strict equality. Alternatively we can calculate the distance between the
two numbers and stop when the distance is short enough (less than a
threshold).
``` Python
>>> x = 0.0
>>> while abs(x - 1.0) > 1e-8:
... x = x + 0.1
... print("x=%19.17g" % (x))
...
x=0.10000000000000001
x=0.20000000000000001
x=0.30000000000000004
x=0.40000000000000002
x= 0.5
x=0.59999999999999998
x=0.69999999999999996
x=0.79999999999999993
x=0.89999999999999991
x=0.99999999999999989
```
If we know exactly how many iterations to perform we can use a for loop
as shown below. Note that range(1, 11) =\> \[1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9,
10\].
``` Python
>>> for i in range(1, 11):
... x = i * 0.1
... print("x=%19.17g" % (x))
...
x=0.10000000000000001
x=0.20000000000000001
x=0.30000000000000004
x=0.40000000000000002
x= 0.5
x=0.60000000000000009
x=0.70000000000000007
x=0.80000000000000004
x=0.90000000000000002
x= 1
```
What does the following piece of code compute? Will the loop ever
finish? Why?
``` Python
>>> eps = 1.0
>>> while 1.0 + eps > 1.0:
... eps = eps / 2.0
...
>>> print eps
1.11022302463e-16
```
The value eps has will always be a power of 2, therefore there will not
be any rounding off errors. However, as the while loop continues eps
gets smaller and smaller. Eventually eps become so small it becomes
nothing comparing to 1.0, which means adding it to 1.0 will result in
1.0. Recall that the machine epsilon is the smallest value when added to
1.0 will result in value different than 1.0. If a number is less than
the machine epsilon and it will cause no effect when it is added to 1.0.
`sys.float_info` tells us that the machine epsilon is
2.220446049250313e-16, which is slightly less than
2x1.11022302463e-16=2.22044604926e-16. This is why when the loop ends
eps equals 1.11022302463e-16.
## Symbolic Computation
The SymPy library for Python allows us
to manipulate variables symbolically (as symbols). The following code
snippets demonstrates some basic functionality of SymPy.
``` python
>>> from sympy import Symbol
>>> x = Symbol('x');
>>> x+2*x+3*x
6*x
>>> y=x+2*x+3*x
>>> y
6*x
>>> y.subs(x, 2)
12
>>> from sympy import diff
>>> diff(y, x)
6
>>> from sympy import sin, cos
>>> diff(sin(x), x)
cos(x)
>>> diff(cos(x), x)
-sin(x)
>>> y = 4 - 1/x
>>> y.diff()
x**(-2)
>>> y.diff().subs(x, 0.5)
4.00000000000000
>>> from sympy import series
>>> sin(x).series(x, 0)
x - x**3/6 + x**5/120 + O(x**6)
>>> sin(x).series(x, 0, 10)
x - x**3/6 + x**5/120 - x**7/5040 + x**9/362880 + O(x**10)
```
## Numpy Array and Linear Algebra
Sources:
- Numpy
Tutorial
- Scipy
Tutorial
A array in numpy is multidimensional table of elements of the same type.
The elements are indexed by a tuple of positive integers. The name of
the class for numpy arrays is ndarray, a.k.a array. Each array object
has a number of attributes:
- mdim: number of dimensions
- shape: a tuple of integers indicating the size of the array in each
dimension. A matrix with m rows and n columns will have (m, n) as
its shape.
- size: the total number elements in an array.
- dtype: the type of elements in an array.
You can install numpy and scipy on Ubuntu as follows:
``` shell
sudo apt-get install python-numpy python-scipy python-matplotlib python-sympy
```
The elements in an array can be referenced using different syntax as
shown in the examples below.
``` python
>>> from numpy import *
>>> a = arange(15).reshape(3, 5)
>>> a
array([[ 0, 1, 2, 3, 4],
[ 5, 6, 7, 8, 9],
[10, 11, 12, 13, 14]])
>>> type(a)
<type 'numpy.ndarray'>
>>> a.shape
(3, 5)
>>> (rows, cols) = a.shape
>>> rows
3
>>> cols
5
>>> a.ndim
2
>>> a.size
15
>>> a[2, 3]
13
>>> a[2][3]
13
>>> a[-1]
array([10, 11, 12, 13, 14])
>>> a[-2]
array([5, 6, 7, 8, 9])
>>> a[-2:]
array([[ 5, 6, 7, 8, 9],
[10, 11, 12, 13, 14]])
>>> a[2:]
array([[10, 11, 12, 13, 14]])
>>> a[:-3]
array([], shape=(0, 5), dtype=int64)
>>> a[:]
array([[ 0, 1, 2, 3, 4],
[ 5, 6, 7, 8, 9],
[10, 11, 12, 13, 14]])
>>> a[1, ...]
array([5, 6, 7, 8, 9])
>>> a[:, 0]
array([ 0, 5, 10])
```
A numpy array can be created from a regular Python list or tuple using
the array function. The type of the array elements depends on that of
the elements in the sequences.
``` python
>>> a = array([[1, 2], [2, 3]])
>>> a
array([[1, 2],
[2, 3]])
>>> a = array(((4, 5), (6, 7)))
>>> a
array([[4, 5],
[6, 7]])
>>> a.dtype
dtype('int64')
>>>>>> b = array([(1.2, 1.3), (1.4, 1.5)])
>>> b
array([[ 1.2, 1.3],
[ 1.4, 1.5]])
>>> b.dtype
dtype('float64')
```
Numpy includes functions that create arrays with default values. The
eye() function creates a identity matrix and the identity() performs a
similar function. The copy function clones an array object includes the
data it contains.
``` python
>>> zeros((2, 3))
array([[ 0., 0., 0.],
[ 0., 0., 0.]])
>>> ones((3, 4))
array([[ 1., 1., 1., 1.],
[ 1., 1., 1., 1.],
[ 1., 1., 1., 1.]])
>>> empty((2, 3))
array([[ 2.68156159e+154, 2.68156159e+154, 2.68156242e+154],
[ 2.68156159e+154, 2.68156159e+154, 2.68156159e+154]])
>>> eye(3, 3)
array([[ 1., 0., 0.],
[ 0., 1., 0.],
[ 0., 0., 1.]])
>>> identity(3, float)
array([[ 1., 0., 0.],
[ 0., 1., 0.],
[ 0., 0., 1.]])
```
Arithmetic operations on numpy arrays are element-wise operations. The
product \* operator does a element-wise multiplication. The dot function
performs matrix multiplications.
``` python
>>> a
array([[1, 2],
[3, 4]])
>>> b = a.copy()
>>> b
array([[1, 2],
[3, 4]])
>>> a*b
array([[ 1, 4],
[ 9, 16]])
>>> dot(a, b)
array([[ 7, 10],
[15, 22]])
```
Numpy also includes a number of basic linear algebra functions.
``` python
>>> from numpy.linalg import *
>>> a = array([[1.0, 2.0], [3.0, 4.0]])
>>> a
array([[ 1., 2.],
[ 3., 4.]])
>>> a.transpose()
array([[ 1., 3.],
[ 2., 4.]])
>>> inv(a)
array([[-2. , 1. ],
[ 1.5, -0.5]])
>>> y = array([[5.], [7.]])
>>> solve(a, y)
array([[-3.],
[ 4.]])
```
## IPython Notebook
The IPython Notebook is an interactive environment that allows coding,
executing, documentation of your Python commands.
Resources:
- How to share an IPython
notebook
- A gallery of IPython
notebooks
- A matplotlib
tutorial
- Exploratory computing with
Python
|
# Introduction to Numerical Methods/Numerical Differentiation
# Numerical Differentiation
Objectives:
- explain the definitions of forward, backward, and center divided
methods for numerical differentiation
- find approximate values of the first derivative of continuous
functions
- reason about the accuracy of the numbers
- find approximate values of the first derivative of discrete
functions (given at discrete data points)
Resources
- numpy
- Numerical
Differentiation
## Forward Divided Difference Method
$f^{'}(x) = \frac{f(x+h)-f(x)}{h} + O(h)$
The following code implements this method:
``` python
from math import exp
def forward_diff(f, x, h=0.0001):
df = (f(x+h) - f(x))/h
return df
x = 0.5
df = forward_diff(exp, x)
print 'first derivative = ', df
print 'exp(', x, ') = ', exp(x)
```
## Backward Divided Difference Method
$f^{'}(x) = \frac{f(x)-f(x-h)}{h} + O(h)$
The following code implements this method:
``` python
from math import exp
def backward_diff(f, x, h=0.0001):
df = (f(x) - f(x-h))/h
return df
x = 0.5
df = backward_diff(exp, x)
print 'first derivative = ', df
print 'exp(', x, ') = ', exp(x)
```
## Center Divided Difference Method
$f^{'}(x) = \frac{f(x+h)-f(x-h)}{2h} + O(h^{2})$
The following code implements this method:
``` python
from math import exp
def center_diff(f, x, h=0.0002):
df = (f(x+h) - f(x-h))/(2.0*h)
return df
x = 0.5
df = center_diff(exp, x)
print 'first derivative = ', df
print 'exp(', x, ') = ', exp(x)
```
## Second Derivative
$f^{''}(x) = \frac{f(x+h) - 2 f(x) + f(x-h)}{h^2} + O(h^2)$
## Taylor Series
Taylor series allows us
to taylor expand a function into an infinite series. If the function is
infinitely differentiable at number h, we can use the Taylor series to
approximate the function. We can derive the backward, the forward, and
the center divided difference methods using Taylor series, which also
give the quantitative estimate of the error in the approximation.
$f(x+h) = f(x) + f^{'}(x)h + \frac{f^{(2)}(x)}{2!}h^{2}+\frac{f^{(3)}(x)}{3!}h^{3}+ \cdots \quad$
For instance the $sin(x)$ function can be approximated by the truncated
Taylor series:
$\sin\left( x \right) \approx x - \frac{x^3}{3!} + \frac{x^5}{5!} - \frac{x^7}{7!}\!$
!The sine function (blue) is closely approximated by its Taylor
polynomial of degree 7 (pink) for a full period centered at the
origin. is closely approximated by its Taylor polynomial of degree 7 (pink) for a full period centered at the origin."){width="400"}
## Effect of Step Size
The following is a program that calculates the first derivative of $e^x$
at x=0.5 from the center divided difference formula using different
values of h. The result shows that the approximation becomes more
accurate (more significant digits) as step size becomes smaller but the
when the step size becomes too small the rounding off error become
significant.
``` python
from math import exp
def center_diff(f, x, h=0.0001):
df = (f(x+h) - f(x-h))/(2.0*h)
return df
x = 0.5
df = center_diff(exp, x)
print 'first derivative = ', df
print 'exp(', x, ') = ', exp(x)
h=0.125
for i in range(50):
df = center_diff(exp, x, h)
print "h=", h, "df=", df
h = h/2.0
```
|
# Introduction to Numerical Methods/Roots of Equations
# Root Finding
Objectives:
- find solutions of quadratic and cubic equations
- derive the formula and follow the algorithms for the solutions of
non-linear equations using the following methods:
- Bisection
- Newton-Raphson
- Secant
- False-Position
Resources
- book chapters on various
methods
- Root Finding
Algorithms
- Bisection Method
- Newton\'s Method
- Secant Method
- False-Position
Method
Roots (or Zeros) of a function
f(x) are values of x
that produces an output of 0. Roots can be real or complex numbers.
Finding the root of $f(x)-g(x)$ is the same as solving the equation
$f(x) = g(x)$. Solving an
equation is finding the
values that satisfy the condition specified by the equation.
Lower degree (quadratic, cubic, and quartic) polynomials have
closed-form solutions, but numerical methods may be easier to use. To
solve a quadratic equation we can use the quadratic formula:
$$ax^2+bx+c=0$$
$$x=\frac{-b\pm\sqrt{b^2-4ac\ }}{2a}$$
There are many root-find
algorithms for
solving equations numerically.
## Bisection Method
The bisection method starts with two guesses and uses a binary search
algorithm to improve the answers. If a function is continuous between
the two initial guesses, the bisection method is guaranteed to converge.
Here is a picture that illustrates the idea:
![A few steps of the bisection method applied over the starting range
\[a1;b1\]. The bigger red dot is the root of the
function.](Bisection_method.svg "A few steps of the bisection method applied over the starting range [a1;b1]. The bigger red dot is the root of the function."){width="400"}
The advantages of bisection method include guaranteed convergence on
continuous functions and the error is bounded.
The disadvantages of bisection method include relatively slow
convergence and non convergence on certain functions.
## Newton-Raphson Method
Newton\'s Method
(a.k.a Newton-Raphson Method) is an open method for solving non-linear
equations. Contrary to a bracketing-method (e.g. bisection method)
Newton\'s method needs one initial guess but it doesn\'t guarantee to
converge.
The basic idea of Newton\'s method is as follows:
: Given a function *f* of \"x\" and a initial guess $x_{0}$ for the
root of this function, a better guess $x_{1}$ is
: $x_{1} = x_0 - \frac{f(x_0)}{f'(x_0)}$
: This is the Newton-Raphson formula.
The following animation illustrates the method:
!The function ƒ is shown in blue and the tangent line is in red. We see
that xn+1 is a better approximation than xn for the root x of the
function
f.{width="400"}
Lets solve the following equations using Newton\'s method:
$$f(x)=x^{2}+2$$
$$f(x)=sin(x)=0$$
$$f(x)=a-\frac{1}{x}=0$$
``` python
from sympy import Symbol, diff, sin
x = Symbol('x')
y = sin(x)
derivative = diff(y, x)
'''
Solve f with initial guess g using Newton's method.
Stop when the absolute relative approximate error is
smaller than the tolerance or the max # iterations
is reached.
'''
def newton(f, derivative, g, tolerance, max_iteration):
x_previous = g
for i in range(max_iteration):
x_current = x_previous - \
y.subs(x, x_previous).evalf()/derivative.subs(x, x_previous).evalf()
error = abs((x_current-x_previous)/x_current)
print "current x:", x_current, " error:", error
x_previous = x_current
if error < tolerance:
break;
newton(y, derivative, 5, 0.005, 15)
```
``` bash
$ python newton.py
current x: 8.38051500624659 error: 0.403377955140806
current x: 10.1008867567293 error: 0.170318883075941
current x: 9.29864101772707 error: 0.0862755898924158
current x: 9.42545121429349 error: 0.0134540186653470
current x: 9.42477796066766 error: 7.14344283379346e-5
```
### Limitations of Newton\'s Method
#### Division by Zero
Because a division is involved in Newton\'s formula when the denominator
becomes zero the method won\'t continue correctly. The following program
demonstrates this issue.
``` python
from sympy import Symbol, diff
x = Symbol('x')
y = 4 - 1.0/x
derivative = diff(y, x)
'''
Solve f with initial guess g using Newton's method.
Stop when the absolute relative approximate error is
smaller than the tolerance or the max # iterations
is reached.
'''
def newton(f, derivative, g, tolerance, max_iteration):
x_previous = g
for i in range(max_iteration):
x_current = x_previous - \
y.subs(x, x_previous)/derivative.subs(x, x_previous)
error = abs((x_current-x_previous)/x_current)
print "current x:", x_current, " error:", error
x_previous = x_current
if error < tolerance:
break;
newton(y, derivative, 0.5, 0.005, 15)
```
Output:
``` bash
$ python newton.py
current x: 0 error: oo
current x: nan error: nan
current x: nan error: nan
current x: nan error: nan
current x: nan error: nan
current x: nan error: nan
...
```
#### Divergence at Inflection Points
When the initial guess is near a inflection
point the method may
diverge from the desired root.
The following code using the same implementation of Newton\'s method
(assume the newton function is imported) demonstrates divergence at an
inflection point (x=0).
``` bash
from sympy import Symbol, diff
x = Symbol('x')
y = (x-1)**3 + 0.5
derivative = diff(y, x)
newton(y, derivative, 5, 0.005, 15)
```
``` bash
$ python newton.py
current x: 3.65625000000000 error: 0.367521367521368
current x: 2.74721164936563 error: 0.330894909696631
current x: 2.11021215705302 error: 0.301865141940137
current x: 1.60492272680972 error: 0.314837232847788
current x: 0.947823175470885 error: 0.693272298403532
current x: -60.2548036313237 error: 1.01573025084058
current x: -39.8365801731819 error: 0.512549605648313
current x: -26.2244867245776 error: 0.519060433539279
current x: -17.1498826852607 error: 0.529135050417335
current x: -11.1004277326071 error: 0.544974941360464
current x: -7.06809009701998 error: 0.570498901434099
current x: -4.38128712811798 error: 0.613245124168828
current x: -2.59328016409484 error: 0.689476975445585
current x: -1.40842833626215 error: 0.841258157995587
current x: -0.634351912031382 error: 1.22026340513730
```
## Secant Method
Secant method is similar
to Newton\'s method in that it is an open method and use a intersection
to get the improved estimate of the root. Secant method avoids
calculating the first derivatives by estimating the derivative values
using the slope of a secant line.
The following figure illustrates the secant method with two initial
guesses and two successive improved estimates: !The first two
iterations of the secant method. The red curve shows the function f and
the blue lines are the secants. For this particular case, the secant
method will not
converge.{width="400"}
The formula for secant method is as follows:
$$x_{i+1}
=x_{i}-\frac{f(x_{i})(x_{i}-x_{i-1})}{f(x_{i})-f(x_{i-1})}$$
## False-Position Method
The false-position method is similar to the bisection method in that it
requires two initial guesses (bracketing method). Instead of using the
midpoint as the improved guess, the false-position method use the root
of secant line that passes both end points. The following figure
illustrates the idea. !The first two iterations of the false position
method. The red curve shows the function f and the blue lines are the
secants.{width="400"}
The formula for false-position method is as follows:
$$x_{r}=\frac{x_uf(x_l) - x_lf(x_u)}{f(x_l) - f(x_u)}$$
|
# Introduction to Numerical Methods/System of Linear Equations
Objectives
- define vector and matrix
- add, subtract, and multiply matrices
- find the transpose of a square matrix
- define the inverse of a matrix
- setup simultaneous linear equations in matrix form
Resources
- book chapter
- Python
programming
# Vectors and Matrices
A matrix) is a
rectangular array of things, such as numbers, symbols, or expressions.
Matrices are commonly used to express linear
transformations and system
of linear
equations.
A triangular matrix
is a special type of square matrices. If all entries of A below the main
diagonal are zero, A is called an upper triangular
matrix#Diagonal_and_triangular_matrices).
: $a_{ij}=0$ for all $i>j$
Similarly if all entries of A above the main diagonal are zero, A is
called a lower triangular matrix.
: $a_{ij}=0$ for all $i<j$
If all entries outside the main diagonal are zero, A is called a
diagonal matrix.
: $a_{ij}=0$ for all $i \ne j$
This matrix
$$\begin{bmatrix}
1 & 4 & 2 \\
0 & 3 & 4 \\
0 & 0 & 1 \\
\end{bmatrix}$$ is upper triangular and this matrix
$$\begin{bmatrix}
1 & 0 & 0 \\
2 & 8 & 0 \\
4 & 9 & 7 \\
\end{bmatrix}$$ is lower triangular.
The identity
matrix#Identity_matrix)
of size n is the n-by-n matrix in which all the elements on the main
diagonal are equal to 1 and all other elements are equal to 0.
## Matrix Multiplication
![](Matrix_multiplication_diagram_2.svg "Matrix_multiplication_diagram_2.svg")
Matrix
multiplication
takes two matrices and produces another matrix. The rule for the
operation is illustrated as follows:
$$\overset{4\times 2 \text{ matrix}}{\begin{bmatrix}
{\color{Brown}{a_{11}}} & {\color{Brown}{a_{12}}} \\
\cdot & \cdot \\
{\color{Orange}{a_{31}}} & {\color{Orange}{a_{32}}} \\
\cdot & \cdot \\
\end{bmatrix}}
\overset{2\times 3\text{ matrix}}{\begin{bmatrix}
\cdot & {\color{Plum}{b_{12}}} & {\color{Violet}{b_{13}}} \\
\cdot & {\color{Plum}{b_{22}}} & {\color{Violet}{b_{23}}} \\
\end{bmatrix}}
= \overset{4\times 3\text{ matrix}}{\begin{bmatrix}
\cdot & x_{12} & x_{13} \\
\cdot & \cdot & \cdot \\
\cdot & x_{32} & x_{33} \\
\cdot & \cdot & \cdot \\
\end{bmatrix}}$$
The values at the intersections marked with circles are:
$$\begin{align}
x_{12} & = {\color{Brown}{a_{11}}}{\color{Plum}{b_{12}}} + {\color{Brown}{a_{12}}}{\color{Plum}{b_{22}}} \\
x_{13} & = {\color{Brown}{a_{11}}}{\color{Violet}{b_{13}}} + {\color{Brown}{a_{12}}}{\color{Violet}{b_{23}}} \\
x_{32} & = {\color{Orange}{a_{31}}}{\color{Plum}{b_{12}}} + {\color{Orange}{a_{32}}}{\color{Plum}{b_{22}}} \\
x_{33} & = {\color{Orange}{a_{31}}}{\color{Violet}{b_{13}}} + {\color{Orange}{a_{32}}}{\color{Violet}{b_{23}}}
\end{align}$$
## Transpose of a Matrix
The transpose of a matrix is
defined as follows: The **transpose** of a matrix **A** is another
matrix **A**^T^ created by any one of the following equivalent actions:
- reflect **A** over its main diagonal (which runs from top-left to
bottom-right) to obtain **A**^T^
- write the rows of **A** as the columns of **A**^T^
- write the columns of **A** as the rows of **A**^T^:
The following figure illustrates the idea:
!The transpose AT of a matrix A can be obtained by reflecting the
elements along its main diagonal. Repeating the process on the
transposed matrix returns the elements to their original
position.{width="200"}
## Inverse of a Matrix
An *n*-by-*n* square matrix **A** is called **invertible** if there
exists an *n*-by-*n* square matrix **B** such that
$$\mathbf{AB} = \mathbf{BA} = \mathbf{I}_n \$$
where **I**~*n*~ denotes the *n*-by-*n* identity matrix and the
multiplication used is ordinary matrix
multiplication. **B** is called the
**\'\'inverse**\'\' of **A**, denoted by **A**^−1^.
## Represent System of Linear Equations in Matrix Form
$$\begin{alignat}{7}
2x &&\; + \;&& y &&\; - \;&& z &&\; = \;&& 8 & \qquad (L_1) \\
-3x &&\; - \;&& y &&\; + \;&& 2z &&\; = \;&& -11 & \qquad (L_2) \\
-2x &&\; + \;&& y &&\; +\;&& 2z &&\; = \;&& -3 & \qquad (L_3)
\end{alignat}$$ We can represent this system of linear equations in
matrix form as shown below:
$$\begin{bmatrix}
2x & + & y & - & z \\
-3x & - & y & + & 2z \\
-2x & + & y & + & 2z
\end{bmatrix} =
\begin{bmatrix}
8 \\
-11 \\
-3
\end{bmatrix}$$ Then we can use matrix multiplication to separate the
variables.
$$\begin{bmatrix}
2 & 1 & -1 \\
-3 & -1 & 2 \\
-2 & 1 & 2
\end{bmatrix}
\begin{bmatrix}
x \\
y \\
z
\end{bmatrix} =
\begin{bmatrix}
8 \\
-11 \\
-3
\end{bmatrix}$$
$$\begin{bmatrix}
25 & 5 & 1 \\
64 & 8 & 1 \\
144 & 12 & 1
\end{bmatrix}
\begin{bmatrix}
a_1 \\
a_2 \\
a_3
\end{bmatrix} =
\begin{bmatrix}
106.8 \\
177.2 \\
279.2
\end{bmatrix}$$
The general matrix form for system of linear equations is as follows:
$$A_{n \times n}X_{n \times 1} = C_{n \times 1}$$ Matrix A is the
coefficient matrix. X is the solution vector (matrix) and C is the right
hand side vector. If we multiply the inverse of A on bother sides we can
see the solution is closely related to the inverse of A.
$$\begin{alignat}{3}
A^{-1}AX &&\; = \;&& A^{-1}C \\
IX &&\; = \;&& A^{-1}C \\
X &&\; = \;&& A^{-1}C
\end{alignat}$$
# Gaussian Elimination
Sources:
- book
chapter
-
Gaussian
elimination is an
algorithm for solving a system of linear equations, which is similar to
finding the inverse of an invertible square matrix. The algorithm
consists of a sequence of row reduction operations performed on the
associated matrix of coefficients. There are three types of elementary
row operations:
- swapping two rows
- multiplying a row by a non-zero constant
- adding a multiple of one row to another row.
For example, the first linear equation (L~1~, pivot equation) can be
used to eliminate $x$ from the next two equations: :
$$\begin{alignat}{7}
2x &&\; + \;&& y &&\; - \;&& z &&\; = \;&& 8 & \qquad (L_1) \\
-3x &&\; - \;&& y &&\; + \;&& 2z &&\; = \;&& -11 & \qquad (L_2) \\
-2x &&\; + \;&& y &&\; +\;&& 2z &&\; = \;&& -3 & \qquad (L_3)
\end{alignat}$$ Then L~2~ (pivot equation) can be used to eliminate $y$
from L~3~. This process is called forward elimination. Now L~3~ can be
solved with one unknown $z$, which can be used to substitute the $z$ in
L~2~ to solve $y$. This process is called backward substitution.
The algorithm for the Gaussian Elimination method can be implemented as
follows:
``` python
'''
x = gauss_elimin(a, b)
Solves [a][x] = [b] by Gauss elimination.
'''
from numpy import dot, array
def gauss_elimin(a, b):
(rows, cols) = a.shape
# elimination phase
for row in range(0, rows-1): # pivot equation/row
for i in range(row+1, rows):
if a[i, row] != 0.0:
factor = a[i, row]/a[row, row]
a[i, row+1:rows] = a[i, row+1:rows] - factor*a[row, row+1:rows]
b[i] = b[i] - factor*b[row]
# back substitution
for k in range(rows-1,-1,-1):
b[k] = (b[k] - dot(a[k, k+1:rows],b[k+1:rows]))/a[k, k]
return b
a = array([[3, 2.0], [-6, 6]])
b = array([7, 6])
print gauss_elimin(a, b)
```
# Gaussian Elimination with Partial Pivoting
Gaussian elimination method is prone to round-off errors especially when
a large number equations allows the error to accumulate. Another problem
is the division by zero error. For example, the following matrix will
break the method because the second pivot element is zero and the method
requires the pivot elements to be non-zero.
$$\left[ \begin{array}{ccc|c}
1 & -1 & 2 & 8 \\
0 & 0 & -1 & -11 \\
0 & 2 & -1 & -3
\end{array} \right]$$ Gaussian elimination with partial pivoting is
similar to the Gaussian elimination except that in the $i$th forward
elimination step the maximum of
$|a_{i,i}|, |a_{i+1, i}|, ..., |a_{n, i}|$ is found and the row that
contains the maximum will be swapped with the pivot row. The previous
coefficient matrix would look as follows after the swaps.
$$\left[ \begin{array}{ccc|c}
1 & -1 & 2 & 8 \\
0 & 2 & -1 & -3 \\
0 & 0 & -1 & -11
\end{array} \right]$$
# Gauss-Seidel Method
Gaussian elimination is a direct (straightforward) method that
transforms the original equations to equivalent ones that are easier to
solve. Some systems of equations have no solution because for example
the number of equations is less than the number of unknowns or one
equation contradicts another equation.
Gauss-Seidel
method is an
iterative (or indirect) method that starts with a guess at the solution
and repeatedly refine the guess till it converges (the convergence
criterion is met). This method is advantageous because it is more
computationally efficient when the coefficient matrix is large and
sparse and the round-off errors can be control by adjusting the error
tolerance.
The algorithm consists the following steps:
1. rewrite each equation for the corresponding unknowns, for example,
the first equation is written with $x_1$ on the left-hand side and
the second equation with $x_2$ on the left-hand side:
$$x_i = \frac{c_{i}-\sum_{j=1, j \ne i}^{n}a_{ij}x_{j}}{a_{ii}}, i=1,2,3, ..., n.$$
1. find initial guess for the $x_i$\'s.
2. use the rewritten equations to calculate the new estimates - always
using the most recent estimates.
3. repeat the previous step till the largest absolute relative
approximate error among all $x_i$\'s is less than the specified
tolerance.
The drawback of most iterative method is that it may not converge when
the system of equations has a coefficient matrix that is not diagonally
dominant. A
system of equations where the coefficient matrix is diagonally dominant
does always converge. The matrix A is diagonally dominant if
$$|a_{ii}| \geq \sum_{j\neq i} |a_{ij}| \quad\text{for all } i,$$ and
$$|a_{ii}| > \sum_{j\neq i} |a_{ij}| \quad\text{for at least one } i.$$
An implementation in Python using
numpy
simply iterates to produce the solution vector.
# LU Decomposition
LU decomposition
factors the coefficient matrix A to the product of a lower triangular
matrix and an upper triangular matrix: A = LU. The process of deriving L
and U from A is called LU decomposition or LU factorization, which is
similar to Gaussian elimination
method.
Once LU decomposition is done, we can use the system of linear equations
represented by A using forward and back substitutions:
$$\begin{alignat}{3}
AX &&\; = \;&& C \\
LUX &&\; = \;&& C \\
L^{-1}LUX &&\; = \;&& L^{-1}C \\
UX &&\; = \;&& L^{-1}C\\
\end{alignat}$$
Let $L^{-1}C=Z$, which means $LZ=C$ and $Z$ can be solved by forward
elimination. From $UX=Z$ we can solve X using backward elimination.
One method of LU decomposition is similar to Gaussian elimination. For a
$3 \times 3$:
$$A=
\begin{bmatrix}
a_{11} & a_{12} & a_{13} \\
a_{21} & a_{22} & a_{23} \\
a_{31} & a_{32} & a_{33} \\
\end{bmatrix} =
\begin{bmatrix}
1 & 0 & 0 \\
l_{21} & 1 & 0 \\
l_{31} & l_{32} & 1 \\
\end{bmatrix}
\begin{bmatrix}
u_{11} & u_{12} & u_{13} \\
0 & u_{22} & u_{23} \\
0 & 0 & u_{33} \\
\end{bmatrix}.$$
$$A=
\begin{bmatrix}
u_{11} & u_{12} & u_{13} \\
u_{11}l_{21} & u_{12}l_{21}+u_{22} & u_{13}l_{21}+u_{23} \\
u_{11}l_{31} & u_{12}l_{31}+u_{22}l_{32} & u_{13}l_{31}+u_{23}l_{32}+u_{33} \\
\end{bmatrix}$$ From the last matrix we can see to eliminate
$a_{21}$ we need to multiple the first row of A by $l_{21}$ and
similarly to eliminate $a_{31}$ by multiplying the first row by
$l_{31}$. To calculate L we can simply record the multipliers used in
the forward elimination steps and the matrix U is the same as the
resultant upper triangular matrix from forward elimination.
Sample code in
Python
## Find the Inverse of a Matrix
Finding the inverse of a matrix is a process related to solving the
system of linear equations. If the inverse of a coefficient matrix is
found then the system of equations represented by the coefficient matrix
is solved.
$$\begin{alignat}{3}
AX &&\; = \;&& C \\
A^{-1}AX &&\; = \;&& A^{-1}C \\
X &&\; = \;&& A^{-1}C \\
\end{alignat}$$
One way to find the inverse of a matrix is to find each column of the
inverse matrix separately by solving a system of linear equations. If
$AB=I$ and
$$A =
\begin{bmatrix}
a_{11} & a_{12} & a_{13} \\
a_{21} & a_{22} & a_{23} \\
a_{31} & a_{32} & a_{33}
\end{bmatrix} \ B=
\begin{bmatrix}
b_{11} & b_{12} & b_{13} \\
b_{21} & b_{22} & b_{23} \\
b_{31} & b_{32} & b_{33}
\end{bmatrix}$$ then
$$A
\begin{bmatrix}
b_{11} \\
b_{21} \\
b_{31}
\end{bmatrix} = LU
\begin{bmatrix}
b_{11} \\
b_{21} \\
b_{31}
\end{bmatrix} =
\begin{bmatrix}
1 \\
0 \\
0
\end{bmatrix}$$. We can calculate the first column of $B$ by
solving a system of equations using the LU decomposition method. The
rest of the columns can be calculated in a similar fashion. As you can
see the LU decomposition method is advantageous the LU decomposition is
performed once and the result is used many times, which lowers the
computational complexity of the whole solution.
|
# Introduction to Numerical Methods/Interpolation
Objectives
- understand interpolation
- derive Newton's divided difference method of interpolation
- derive Lagrangian method of interpolation
- apply the interpolation methods to solve problems
- find derivatives and integrals of discrete functions using
interpolation
Resources
- Direct method
chapter
- Newton\'s method
chapter
- Lagrange method
chapter
- Spline method
chapter
- A Chronology of
Interpolation
- NIST Digital Library of Mathematical
Functions
# Interpolation
Interpolation is the
process of deriving a simple function from a set of discrete data points
so that the function passes through all the given data points (i.e.
reproduces the data points exactly) and can be used to estimate data
points in-between the given ones. It is necessary because in science and
engineering we often need to deal with discrete experimental data.
Interpolation is also used to simplify complicated functions by sampling
data points and interpolating them using a simpler function. Polynomials
are commonly used for interpolation because they are easier to evaluate,
differentiate, and integrate - known as polynomial
interpolation.
It can be proven that given n+1 data points it is always possible to
find a polynomial of order/degree n to pass through/reproduce the n+1
points.
# Direct Method
Given n+1 data points the direct method assumes the following
polynomial:
$$y=f(x)=a_0+a_{1}x+a_{2}x^{2} + ... + a_{n}x^{n}$$
With n+1 values for $x$ and the n+1 corresponding values for $y$ we can
solve for $a_{0}, a_{1}, ..., a_{n}$ by solving the n+1 simultaneous
linear equations, which is known as the direct method.
For example, given two data points $(x_{0}, y_{0})$ and $(x_{1}, y_{1})$
we can use a linear function $y=f(x)=a_{0}+a_{1}x$ to pass through the
two data points:
$$y_{0}=a_{0}+a_{1}x_{0}$$
$$y_{1}=a_{0}+a_{1}x_{1}$$ Once we solve for $a_{0}$and $a_{1}$ (the
coefficients of $f(x)$) we can use the function as the basis for
interpolation - estimating the missing data points in-between.
# Newton\'s Method
In Newton\'s method the interpolating function is written in Newton
polynomial(a.k.a
Newton form). For example, given one data point $(x_{0}, y_{0})$ we can
only derive a polynomial of order zero: $y=f(x)=a_{0}$. Because
$f(x_{0})=y_{0}$ the newton polynomial of order zero is $y=f(x)=y_{0}$.
Given two data points we can write Newton\'s polynomial in the form of
$y=f(x)=a_{0}+a_{1}(x-x_{0})$. Plugging in the two data points gives us
$$a_{0}=y_{0}$$
$$a_{1}=\frac{y_{1}-y_{0}}{x_{1}-x_{0}}$$ Obviously this function passes
through both data points (i.e. accurately reproduces the two data
points). The first derivative of the function at $x=x_{0}$ is
$f'(x_{0})=a_{1}=\frac{y_{1}-y_{0}}{x_{1}-x_{0}}$, which matches the
result from the forward divided difference method.
Given three data points we can write Newton\'s polynomial in the form of
$$y=f(x)=a_{0}+a_{1}(x-x_{0})+a_{2}(x-x_{1})(x-x_{0})$$
Plugging in the three data points gives us
: As $y_{0}=a_{0}$ we get $a_{0}=y_{0}$
: As $y_{1}=a_{0}+a_{1}(x_{1}-x_{0})$ we get
$a_{1}=\frac{y_{1}-y_{0}}{x_{1}-x_{0}}$
: As $y_{2}=a_{0}+a_{1}(x_{2}-x_{0})+a_{2}(x_{2}-x_{1})(x_{2}-x_{0})$
: we get
: `<math>`{=html}
\\begin{align}
a\_{2}&=\\frac{y\_{2}-a\_{0}-a\_{1}(x\_{2}-x\_{0})}{(x\_{2}-x\_{1})(x\_{2}-x\_{0})}\\\\
` &=\frac{y_{2}-y_{0}-\frac{y_{1}-y_{0}}{x_{1}-x_{0}}(x_{2}-x_{0})}{(x_{2}-x_{1})(x_{2}-x_{0})}\\`\
` &=\frac{y_{2}-y_{0}-\frac{y_{1}-y_{0}}{x_{1}-x_{0}}((x_{2}-x_{1})+(x_{1}-x_{0}))}{(x_{2}-x_{1})(x_{2}-x_{0})}\\`\
` &=\frac{y_{2}-y_{0}-\frac{y_{1}-y_{0}}{x_{1}-x_{0}}(x_{2}-x_{1}) - (y_{1}-y_{0})}{(x_{2}-x_{1})(x_{2}-x_{0})}\\`\
` &=\frac{y_{2}-y_{1}-\frac{y_{1}-y_{0}}{x_{1}-x_{0}}(x_{2}-x_{1})}{(x_{2}-x_{1})(x_{2}-x_{0})}\\`\
` &=\frac{\frac{y_{2}-y_{1}}{x_{2}-x_{1}}-\frac{y_{1}-y_{0}}{x_{1}-x_{0}}}{x_{2}-x_{0}}\\`
\\end{align} `</math>`{=html} This third degree polynomial function
passes all three data points (the second derivative and the third
derivative at $x_{0}$ and $x_{1}$match that from the divided difference
method).
From the two examples we can see the coefficients of a Newton polynomial
follow a pattern known as divided
difference. For
example$a_{1}=\frac{y_{1}-y_{0}}{x_{1}-x_{0}}$ is called divided
difference of order 1 (denoted as $f[x_{0}, x_{1}]$) because it depends
on $x_{0}$ and $x_{1}$. The divided difference notation can be used to
write the general order (form) Newton polynomial:
$$f(x)=f[x_{0}]+fx_{0}, x_{1}+fx_{0}, x_{1}, x_{2}(x-x_{1})+...$$
$$+fx_{0}, x_{1}, x_{2}, ...,x_{n}(x-x_{1})(x-x_{2})...(x-x_{n-1})$$
Where
$$a_{0}=f[x_{0}]=y_{0}$$ because $f[x_{i}]=y_{i}$ by definition
$$a_{1}=f[x_{0}, x_{1}]=\frac{f[x_{1}]-f[x_{0}]}{x_{1}-x_{0}}$$
$$a_{2}=f[x_{0}, x_{1}, x_{2}]=\frac{f[x_{1}, x_{2}]-f[x_{0}, x_{1}]}{x_{2}-x_{0}}$$
$$\dots$$
$$a_{k}=f[x_{0}, x_{1}, x_{2}, \dots, x_{k-1}, x_{k}]=\frac{f[x_{1}, x_{2}, \dots, x_{k-1}, x_{k}]-f[x_{0}, x_{1}, x_{2}, \dots, x_{k-1}]}{x_{k}-x_{0}}$$
We can calculate the coefficients of Newton polynomial using the
following table
$$\begin{matrix}
x_0 & y_0 = f[x_0] & & & \\
& & f[x_0,x_1] & & \\
x_1 & y_1 = f[x_1] & & f[x_0,x_1,x_2] & \\
& & f[x_1,x_2] & & f[x_0,x_1,x_2,x_3]\\
x_2 & y_2 = f[x_2] & & f[x_1,x_2,x_3] & \\
& & f[x_2,x_3] & & \\
x_3 & y_3 = f[x_3] & & & \\
\end{matrix}$$ because
$$f[x_{i}]=y_{i}$$
$$f[x_{i}, x_{i+1}]=\frac{f[x_{i+1}]-f[x_{i}]}{x_{i+1}-x_{i}}$$ The
following figures shows the dependency between the divided differences:
!A table for solving the coefficients of a Newton\'s
polynomial.{width="800"}
For example, given data points $(1, 6)$, $(2, 11)$, $(3, 18)$, and
$(4, 27)$ we can draw the following table:
$$\begin{array}{|c||c|c|c|c|c|} i & x_{i} & y_{i} & f[x_i,x_{i+1}] & f[x_i, x_{i+1}, x_{i+2}] & f[x_i, x_{i+1}, x_{i+2}, x_{i+3}]\\
\hline
0 & x_{0}=1 & \begin{align}y_0&=f[x_0]\\
&=6\end{align} & \begin{align}f[x_{0}, x_{1}] &=\frac{f[x_{1}]-f[x_{0}]}{x_{1}-x_{0}}\\
&=\frac{11-6}{2-1}\\
&=5 \end{align}& \begin{align} f[x_{0},x_{1}, x_{2}]&=\frac{f[x_{1}, x_{2}]-f[x_{0},x_{1}]}{x_{2}-x_{0}}\\
&=\frac{7-5}{3-1} \\
&=1 \end{align}& \begin{align}&f[x_{0},x_{1},x_{2},x_{3}]\\
&=\frac{f[x_{1},x_{2},x_{3}]-f[x_{0},x_{1},x_{2}]}{x_{3}-x_{0}}\\
&=\frac{1-1}{4-1}\\
&=0\end{align}\\
\hline
1 & x_{1}=2 & \begin{align}y_1&=f[x_1]\\
&=11\end{align} & \begin{align}f[x_{1}, x_{2}] &=\frac{f[x_{2}]-f[x_1]}{x_{2}-x_{1}}\\
&=\frac{18-11}{3-2}\\
&=7 \end{align} & \begin{align} f[x_{1},x_{2}, x_{3}]&=\frac{f[x_{2}, x_{3}]-f[x_{1},x_{2}]}{x_{3}-x_{1}}\\
&=\frac{9-7}{4-2} \\
&=1 \end{align}& \\
\hline
2 & x_{2}=3 & \begin{align}y_2&=f[x_2]\\
&=18\end{align} & \begin{align}f[x_{2}, x_{3}] &=\frac{f[x_{3}]-f[x_2]}{x_{3}-x_{2}}\\
&=\frac{27-18}{4-3}\\
&=9 \end{align} & & \\
\hline
3 & x_{3}=4 & \begin{align}y_3&=f[x_3]\\
&=27\end{align} & & & \\
\end{array}$$ The four data points lie on a polynomial of order 2, which
is why the coefficient $a_{3}$($f[x_{0},x_{1},x_{2},x_{3}]$) is zero.
Given $[a_{0}, a_{1}, a_{2}] = [6, 5, 1]$ the result polynomial is:
$$\begin{align}y&=a_{0}+a_{1}(x-x_{0})+a_{2}(x-x_{1})(x-x_{0})\\
&=6+5\times(x-1)+1\times(x-2)(x-1)\\
&=x^{2}+2x+3\end{align}$$
Once the coefficients of a Newton\'s polynomial are solved, we can
evaluate the polynomial function for any $x$. A Newton polynomial is
often rewritten in a nested form:
$$f(x)=a_{0}+(x-x_{0})(a_{1}+(x-x_{1})(a_{2}+(x-x_{2})(a_{3}+...+a_{n}(x-x_{n-1}))...)$$,
because this nested form of interpolating polynomial is easier to
evaluate because x only appears in the function n times.
For example, the nested form of a third order interpolating polynomial
is:
$$f(x)=a_{0}+(x-x_{0})(a_{1}+(x-x_{1})(a_{2} +(x-x_{2})a_{3}))$$ The
algorithm of Newton\'s method and its implementation can be found in
this Jupyter
notebook.
# Lagrange Form
Lagrange polynomial
is another form used for polynomial interpolation. It is called a form
because with a given set of distinct points the interpolating polynomial
is unique. We can arrive at the same polynomial through different
methods.
The Lagrange form specifies the interpolation polynomial as:
$$f_{n}(x) := \sum_{i=0}^{n}L_i(x)f(x_{i})$$
$$L_i(x) := \prod_{\begin{smallmatrix}0\le m\le n\\ m\neq i\end{smallmatrix}} \frac{x-x_m}{x_i-x_m} = \frac{(x-x_0)}{(x_i-x_0)} \cdots \frac{(x-x_{i-1})}{(x_i-x_{i-1})} \frac{(x-x_{i+1})}{(x_i-x_{i+1})} \cdots \frac{(x-x_n)}{(x_i-x_n)},$$
where $n$ is the order of the polynomial.
For example, given two data points we get $n=1$ and
$$\begin{align}
f(x)&=L_{0}f(x_{0})+L_{1}f(x_{1})\\
&=\frac{x-x_{1}}{x_{0}-x_{1}}f(x_{0})+\frac{x-x_{0}}{x_{1}-x_{0}}f(x_{1})\\
\end{align}$$ Obviously the function curve passes both data points. The
first derivative also matches that of the divided difference method:
$$\begin{align}
f'(x)&=\frac{f(x_{0})}{x_{0}-x_{1}}+\frac{f(x_{1})}{x_{1}-x_{0}}\\
&=\frac{f(x_{1})-f(x_{0})}{x_{1}-x_{0}}\\
\end{align}$$
# Spline Interpolation
Spline
interpolation uses
a number of polynomial functions to interpolate a set of data points
with each polynomial for two adjacent data points. The Spline method is
necessary because often times when the order of the polynomial become
large polynomial interpolation shows oscillatory behavior (instability
known as Runge\'s
phenomenon). The
following iPython notebook shows an example that suffers this issue:
1
Spline method is not another method for finding polynomial interpolation
of a discrete function, but instead it results in a piecewise polynomial
(splines) in order to avoid the oscillatory behavior. The most common
spline interpolations are linear, quadratic, and cubic splines. Linear
interpolation
uses lines to connect each pair of consecutive data points resulting in
a piecewise interpolation.
!Interpolation example
linear{width="400"}
A quadratic
spline#Examples)
uses a quadratic polynomial to connect consecutive data points.
!Quadratic spline six
segments{width="400"}
A function f(x) is a quadratic spline if the following conditions are
true:
1. The domain of $f(x)$ is an interval \[a, b\].
2. $f(x)$ and $f'(x)$ are continuous on \[a, b\].
3. The data points $x_{i}$ such that $a=x_{0} <x_{1} <\dots<x_{n} =b$
and $f(x)$ is a polynomial of order at most 2 on each subinterval
$[x_{i} , x_{i +1}]$.
|
# Introduction to Numerical Methods/Regression
Objectives
- define linear and non-linear regression models.
- reason about goodness of fit criteria.
- derive coefficients of linear regression models.
- derive coefficients of non-linear regression models
Resources
- textbook chapter on linear
regression
- non-linear
regression
\_\_TOC\_\_
Regression is different from interpolation in that it allows us to
approximate overdetermined
system, which has
more equations than unknowns. This is useful when the exact solution is
too expensive or unnecessary due to errors in the data, such as
measurement errors or random noise.
# Linear Regression
Linear regression finds a linear function that most nearly passes
through the given data points - the regression (function) line best fits
the data. We must define our metric for measuring the goodness of fit.
If all data points lie on the function it is a perfect fit, otherwise
there are errors in the function representation of the data. We can
measure the deviations of the data points from the function. As shown in
the following example
(source)
neither the sum of errors nor the sum of the absolute errors is a good
metric. The data include four points (2, 4), (3, 6), (2, 6), and (3, 8).
We use a straight line to fit the data. Two possible solutions are shown
in iPython
notebook
(Example 1).
## Straight Line (one variable)
Lets look at the example of fitting a straight line to data, i.e. find a
linear regression model with one variable that represents the data. The
function is $f(x)=a_{0}+a_{1}x$ and the (cost) sum of squares of errors
function to be minimized is
$$S(a_0,a_1)=\sum_{i=1}^{n}{(y_i-f(x_i))}^2=\sum_{i=1}^{n}{[y_i-a_{0}-a_{1}x_{i}]}^2$$
We can minimize the $S(a,b)$ function by setting the
gradient to zero. Because the
function has two parameters (variables) there are two gradient
equations:
$$\frac{\partial S}{\partial a_{0}}=2\sum_{i=1}^{n}(y_{i}-a_{0}-a_{1}x_{i})(-1)=0$$
$$\frac{\partial S}{\partial a_{1}}=2\sum_{i=1}^{n}(y_{i}-a_{0}-a_{1}x_{i})(-x_{i})=0$$
The partial derivative represents the rate of change of the function
value with respect to an independent variable while all other variables
being held fixed. When a partial derivative becomes zero it means the
change has stopped. This implies that we have reach a minimum or a
maximum, which can be determined by checking the sign of the 2nd
derivative.
Let\'s consider:
$$\begin{align}
-\sum_{i=1}^{n}y_{i}+\sum_{i=1}^{n}a_{0}+\sum_{i=1}^{n}a_{1}x_{i}&=0\\
-\sum_{i=1}^{n}y_{i}+na_0+\sum_{i=1}^{n}a_{1}x_{i}&=0\\
\end{align}$$
and
$$\begin{align}
-\sum_{i=1}^{n}y_{i}x_{i}+\sum_{i=1}^{n}a_{0}x_{i}+\sum_{i=1}^{n}a_{1}x_{i}^{2}&=0\\
\end{align}$$, we can derive
$$\begin{align}
na_{0}+a_{1}\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}&=\sum_{i=1}^{n}y_{i}\\
a_{0}\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}+a_{1}\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}^2&=\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}y_{i}
\end{align}$$.
Therefore, we can calculate $a_{0}$ and $a_{1}$ as follows:
$$a_{1}=\frac{n\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}y_{i}-\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}\sum_{i=1}^{n}y_{i}}{n\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}^{2} - (\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i})^{2}}$$
$$a_{0}=\frac{\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}^{2}\sum_{i=1}^{n}y_{i}-\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}y_{i}}{n\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}^2-(\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i})^2}$$.
Given the following definitions:
$$\begin{align}
\bar{x}&=\frac{\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}}{n}\\
\bar{y}&=\frac{\sum_{i=1}^{n}y_{i}}{n}\\
S_{1}&=\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}y_{i}-n\bar{x}\bar{y}\\
S_{2}&=\sum_{i=1}^{n}x_{i}^{2}-n\bar{x}^2
\end{align}$$ we get
$$a_{1}=\frac{S1}{S2}$$
$$a_{0}=\bar{y}-a_{1}\bar{x}$$.
# Multi-linear Regression
A linear regression line models the relationship between independent
variables (predictors) and a response variable. Once the model is built
it can be used for prediction. In almost all real-world regression
models multiple predictors (independent variables) are involved to model
multiple factors that affect the response (dependent variable) from the
system. Such models are known as multi-linear models.
## Normal Equation
Another way to find the parameters of a regression model that minimize
the sum of squares of errors is to solve the corresponding normal
equation. Given a
matrix equation $Ax=b$, the normal equation is that which minimizes the
sum of the square differences between the left and right sides:
$$A^{T}Ax=A^{T}b$$.
Given a hypothesized regression model and a dataset we can construct the
left side to express the values our model would predict using the data.
A should be a $m \times n$ matrix where each row represents one of the
$m$ data points (samples) and each column of each row represents a
multiplier for each of the $n$ parameters. $x$ is a $1 \times n$ column
vector for the unknown parameters. The right side $b$ should be a
$1 \times m$ column vector that stores the corresponding $y$ values for
the data points.
Recall the example that fits a straight line (model) $y=a_{0}+a_{1}x$ to
the following data points.
--- ---
x y
2 4
2 6
3 6
3 8
--- ---
: data points
We can construct the left side of the matrix equation $Ax=b$ as:
$$Ax=\underbrace{
\begin{bmatrix}
1 & 2 \\
1 & 2 \\
1 & 3 \\
1 & 3
\end{bmatrix}}_{A}
\underbrace{
\begin{bmatrix}
a_{0} \\
a_{1}
\end{bmatrix}}_{x}$$, which should result in a column vector of the
values our model would predict:
$$\begin{bmatrix}
a_{0}+2a_{1}\\
a_{0}+2a_{1}\\
a_{0}+3a_{1}\\
a_{0}+3a_{1}
\end{bmatrix}$$.
The right side should be a vector of corresponding values from the data
points:
: `<math>`{=html}
b= \\begin{bmatrix} 4 \\\\ 6 \\\\ 6 \\\\ 8 \\end{bmatrix}.
`</math>`{=html} To minimize the sum of square differences between the
left and the right sides is equivalent to solving the following normal
equation:
$$A^{T}Ax=A^{T}b$$. The normal equation for our example is:
$$\underbrace{
\begin{bmatrix}
1 & 1 & 1 & 1 \\
2 & 2 & 3 & 3
\end{bmatrix}}_{A^{T}}
\underbrace{
\begin{bmatrix}
1 & 2 \\
1 & 2 \\
1 & 3 \\
1 & 3
\end{bmatrix}}_{A}
\underbrace{
\begin{bmatrix}
a_{0} \\
a_{1}
\end{bmatrix}}_{x}
=
\underbrace{
\begin{bmatrix}
1 & 1 & 1 & 1 \\
2 & 2 & 3 & 3
\end{bmatrix}}_{A^T}
\underbrace{
\begin{bmatrix}
4 \\
6 \\
6 \\
8
\end{bmatrix}}_{b}$$ If $A^{T}A$ is invertible, the solution vector
should be unique and give us the values for the parameters $a_{0}$ and
$a_{1}$ that minimizes the difference between the model and the data,
i.e. the model best fits the data.
When we determine a regression line of the form $y=a_{0}+a_{1}x$ that
fits four data points, we have four equations that can be written as
$Ax=y$ or
$$\begin{bmatrix}
1 & x^{(1)} \\
1 & x^{(2)} \\
1 & x^{(3)} \\
1 & x^{(4)}
\end{bmatrix}
\begin{bmatrix}
a_{0} \\
a_{1}
\end{bmatrix}
=
\begin{bmatrix}
y^{(0)} \\
y^{(1)} \\
y^{(2)} \\
y^{(3)}
\end{bmatrix}$$
To solve the model we are effectively minimizing $||Ax-b||$.
$y=a_{0}+a_{1}x+a_{2}x^2$
$y=a_{0}+a_{1}sin(x)$
$y=a_{0}e^{-a_{1}x}$
The method introduced in the previous section boils down to solving a
system of linear equations with two unknowns in the following form:
$$\begin{bmatrix}
p & q \\
r & s
\end{bmatrix}
\begin{bmatrix}
a_{0} \\
a_{1}
\end{bmatrix}
=
\begin{bmatrix}
u \\
v
\end{bmatrix}$$
It is not hard to imagine that with $n$ independent variables and $m$
data points we can derive a similar system of linear equations with $n$
unknowns. Then numerical methods, such as Gaussian elimination can be
used to solve for the parameters. We could also use normal equations and
matrix operations to solve for the parameters.
## Gradient Descent
Gradient descent is a
method for finding local minimum of a function. The method is based on
the concept of Gradient, which
is a generalization of the derivative of a function in one dimension
(slope or tangent) to a function in multiple dimensions. For a function
with $n$ variables the gradient at a particular point is a vector whose
components are the $n$ partial derivatives of the function. The
following figure shows the gradient of a function.
!The gradient of the function
−(cos^2^*x* +
cos^2^*y*)^2^}} depicted as a projected vector field on the bottom
plane.2}} depicted as a projected vector field on the bottom plane."){width="400"}
Because the gradient points in the direction of the greatest rate of
increase of the function and its magnitude is the slope of the graph in
that direction, we can start at a random point and take steps
proportional to the negative of the gradient of the current point to
find the local minimum - gradient decent or steepest descent.
Recall that gradients in multiple dimensions are partial derivatives of
the cost function with respect to the parameters for the dimensions:
$$S(a_0,a_1, \cdots, a_n)=\sum_{i=1}^{n}{(y^{(i)}-f(x_1^{(i)},x_2^{(i)},\cdots, x_n^{(i)}))}^2=\sum_{i=1}^{n}{(y^{(i)}-a_{0}-a_{1}x_{1}^{(i)}-\cdots-a_{n}x_{n}^{(i)})}^2$$
$$\frac{\partial S}{\partial a_{0}}=2\sum_{i=1}^{n}(y^{(i)}-a_{0}-a_{1}x_{1}^{(i)}-a_{2}x_{2}^{(i)}-\dots-a_{n}x_{n}^{(i)})(-1)$$
$$\frac{\partial S}{\partial a_{1}}=2\sum_{i=1}^{n}(y^{(i)}-a_{0}-a_{1}x_{1}^{(i)}-a_{2}x_{2}^{(i)}-\dots-a_{n}x_{n}^{(i)})(-x_{1}^{(i)})$$
$$\cdots$$
$$\frac{\partial S}{\partial a_{n}}=2\sum_{i=1}^{n}(y^{(i)}-a_{0}-a_{1}x_{1}^{(i)}-a_{2}x_{2}^{(i)}-\dots-a_{n}x_{n}^{(i)})(-x_{n}^{(i)})$$
Gradient descent can be used to solve non-linear regression models.
# Non-linear Regression
Non-linear
regression models
the relationship in observational data by a function which is a
nonlinear combination of the model parameters and depends on one or more
independent variables. Some nonlinear regression problems can be
transformed to a linear domain. For example, solving
$y=a_{0}+a_{1}x+a_{2}x^{2}$ is equivalent to solving
$y=a_{0}+a_{1}x+a_{2}z$ where $z=x^{2}$.
Here is an
example
of a gradient descent solution to a non-linear regression model.
|
# Introduction to Numerical Methods/Integration
Resources:
- notes on Trapezoidal
Rule
- notes on Simpson's 1/3
Rule
- notes on Romberg
Rule
- notes on integrating discrete
functions
\_\_TOC\_\_
The fundamental theorem of
calculus
states that differentiation and integration are inverse operations: when
a continuous function is first integrated and then differentiated or
vice versa, the original function will be obtained. However the
integrand $f(x)$ may be known only at certain points, such as data
measured from an experiment or from sampling, which is common in
computer applications. Sometimes even though the formula for an
integrand is known, it is difficult or impossible to find the
antiderivative in an elementary function form, e.g the antiderivative of
$f(x)=exp(-x^2)$, cannot be written in elementary form. Computing a
numerical integration (approximation) can be easier than solving the
integral symbolically.
<http://mathworld.wolfram.com/NumericalIntegration.html>
# Trapezoidal Rule
The trapezoidal rule
approximates the area under the curve of the function $f(x)$ as a
trapezoid:
$$\int_{a}^{b} f(x)\, dx \approx (b-a) \left[\frac{f(a) + f(b)}{2} \right].$$
Effectively we are estimating the average function value using two
samples.
The trapezoidal rule belongs to a class of formulas called Newton--Cotes
formulas (evaluating the integrand at equally spaced points). Another
way to look at it is that trapezoidal rule approximates the integrand by
a first order polynomial and then integrating the polynomial over
interval of integration as illustrated in the figure.
!The function *f*(*x*) (in blue) is approximated by a linear function
(in
red). (in blue) is approximated by a linear function (in red).")
The multiple segment Trapezoidal Rule can be used to improve the
accuracy of the approximation by using a sequence of samples:
!Illustration of trapezoidal rule used on a sequence of samples (in
this case, a non-uniform
grid)..")
Lets look at an
example that
approximate the area of a swimming pool.
# Simpson\'s 1/3 Rule
Simpson\'s rule is a
numerical integration method that uses the following approximation
formula:
$$\int_{a}^{b} f(x) \, dx \approx \tfrac{b-a}{6}\left[f(a) + 4f\left(\tfrac{a+b}{2}\right)+f(b)\right].$$
The Simpson\'s rule can be derived by approximating the integrand as a
second order polynomial (quadratic) function as shown in the figure:
!Simpson\'s rule can be derived by approximating the integrand *f*(*x*)
(in blue) by the quadratic interpolant *P*(*x*) (in
red). (in blue) by the quadratic interpolant P(x) (in red).")
$$P(x) = f(a) \tfrac{(x-m)(x-b)}{(a-m)(a-b)} + f(m) \tfrac{(x-a)(x-b)}{(m-a)(m-b)} + f(b) \tfrac{(x-a)(x-x2-x3....-m)}{(b-a)(b-m)}.$$
Another way to look at it is that Simpson's rule is an extension of
Trapezoidal rule where the integrand is approximated by a second order
polynomial.
A sample implementation of Simpson\'s
rule
is available.
# Romberg\'s Rule
The true errors result from the trapezoidal rule is negatively
proportional to the number of segments cubed. Richardson
extrapolation
is a sequence acceleration method for getting a better estimate by
refining such errors. A practical application of Richardson
extrapolation is Romberg integration.
A geometric
example
is available.
<http://www.oscer.ou.edu/AreaUnderCurveExample.pdf>
# Integration of Discrete Functions
The trapezoidal rule with unequal segments can be used to integrate
discrete functions, which are defined by a set of data points.
Interpolation methods, such as polynomial interpolation and spline
interpolation, can be applied to find the function profile, which can be
integrated as a continuous function. In addition linear regression can
also be used for the same purpose.
# Multi-dimensional Integration
Monte Carlo method
is class of computational methods that uses repeated random sampling to
obtain numerical results. To estimate multi-dimensional integrals Monte
Carlo method may yield greater accuracy for the same number of function
evaluations than repeated integrations using one-dimensional methods.
For example we can estimate the value of $\pi$ as shown in the
example.
!Monte Carlo method applied to approximating the value of
. After placing 30000 random points, the estimate
for is within 0.07% of the actual value. This
happens with an approximate probability of
20%.
The path tracing algorithm
in computer graphics applies the Monte Carlo method to render 3D scenes.
It uses repeated random sampling to achieve more accurate estimation
making it one of the most physically accurate 3D graphics rendering
methods in existence
source.
|
# Introduction to Numerical Methods/Ordinary Differential Equations
Resources:
- notes on Ordinary Differential
Equations
- notes on Euler\'s
Method
- notes on Runge-Kutta 2nd Order
Method
- notes on Runge-Kutta 4th Order
Method
\_\_TOC\_\_
A differential
equation is a
equation that relates some function with its derivatives. Such
relationship is commonly found in dynamic system modeling where the rate
of change of a quantity is affect by another quantity, which can be a
function of other quantities. Therefore differential equations are often
used to mathematically represent such relations in many disciplines
including engineering, physics, economics, and biology. We will focus on
ordinary differential equations, which involves no partial derivative.
The solution to a differential equation is the function or a set of
functions that satisfies the equation. Some simple differential
equations with explicit formulas are solvable analytically, but we can
always use numerical methods to estimate the answer using computers to a
certain degree of accuracy.
<http://martinfowler.com/bliki/TwoHardThings.html> \"Two hard things in
computer science: cache invalidation, naming things, and off-by-one
errors.\"
# Initial Value Problem
The general form of first order differential equation: $y'=f(x, y)$ or
$y'=f(x, y(x))$. The solution contains an arbitrary constant (the
constant of integration) because $z(x)=y(x)+c$ satisfies all
differential equations $y(x)$ satisfies. With an auxiliary condition,
e.g. y(a)=b, we can solve y\'=F(x, y). This is known as the initial
value problem.
An indefinite integral of a function $f(x)$ is a class of functions
$F(x)$ so that $F'(x)=f(x)$. The indefinite integral is also known as
the antiderivative. The definite integral of a function over a fixed
interval is a number.
# Connection with Integration
To calculate the integral $F(x)=\int_{a}^{x}f(t)dt$ is to find a $F(x)$
that satisfies the condition $\frac{dF(x)}{dx}=f(x)$, $F(a)=0$. In other
words, integration can be used to solve differential equations with a
initial condition.
# Euler\'s Method
!Illustration of the Euler method. The unknown curve is in blue, and
its polygonal approximation is in
red.
Euler\'s method uses a
step-wise approach to solve ordinary differential equations with an
initial condition.
Given $\frac{dy}{dx} = f(x,y)$ and $y(x_{0})=y_{0}$ ($x$ is an
independent variable and $y$ is a dependent variable) Euler\'s methods
solves for $y_{i}$ for $x=x_i$.
Euler\'s method can be derived in a number of ways. Lets look at a
geographical description.
Given that $\frac{dy}{dx} = f(x,y)$ at a particular point
$(x_{i}, y_{i})$ we can approximate $f(x_{i}, y_{i})$ with
$\frac{y_{i+1}-y_{i}}{x_{i+1}-x_{i}}$. The derivative represents the
instantaneous (happening continuously) change in $y$ at $x$:
$$\lim_{\Delta x \to 0}\frac{\Delta y}{\Delta x}=\frac{dy}{dx}=y'(x)$$
The average change in $y$ over $x$ is
: $\frac{y_{i+1}-y_{i}}{x_{i+1}-x_{i}}=\frac{\Delta y}{\Delta x}$,
which represents a discrete version of the change (changes over
\"steps\" of time). If the change in $x$ is small enough, either of the
two can be used to approximate the other.
Assume that we know the derivative function of an unknown curve and
wants to find the shape of the curve (a function that satisfies a
differential equation). We can start from a known point, use the
differential equation as as a formula to get the slope of the tangent
line to the curve at any point on the curve, and take a small step along
that tangent line up to the next point. If the step is small enough, we
can expect the next point to be close to the curve. If we pretend that
point is still on the curve, the same process can be used to find the
next point and so on. Graphically we are using a polynomial to
approximate the unknown curve. The gap between the two curves represents
the error of the approximation, which can be reduced by shortening the
step sizes.
We just derived the formula for Euler\'s method:
$$y_{i+1} = y_{i} + f(x_{i},y_{i})(x_{i+1}-x_{i})$$
## Example
Given $\frac{dy}{dx} = y$, and $y(0)=1$, solve it for $x$ at 1, i.e.
y(1).
The Euler\'s method formula is a recursively defined function, which can
be calculated iteratively. $(x_{i+1}-x_{i})$ is called the step size. If
we pick a step size of 1 the solution is as follows: !Illustration of
numerical integration for the equation $y'=y, y(0)=1.$ Blue is the Euler
method; green, the midpoint method; red,
the exact solution, $y=e^t.$ The step size is
*h* = 1.0.=1. Blue is the Euler method; green, the midpoint method; red, the exact solution, y=e^t. The step size is h = 1.0."){width="200"}
: {\| class=\"wikitable\"
\|- ! $i$ !! $x_{i}$ !! $y_i$ !!$dy/dx$ \|- \| 0 \|\| 0 \|\| 1 \|\| 1
\|- \| 1 \|\| 1 \|\| 2 \|\| 2 \|- \| 2 \|\| 2 \|\| 4 \|\| 4 \|- \| 3
\|\| 3 \|\| 8 \|\| 8 \|}
Another way to derive Euler\'s method is to use taylor expansion around
$x_{i}$:
$$y(x_0 + h) = y(x_0) + h y'(x_0) + \frac{1}{2}h^2 y''(x_0) + O(h^3).$$
If we ignore higher order derivative terms we get the Euler\'s method
formula:
$$y(x_0 + h) = y(x_0) + h y'(x_0)$$
# Runge-Kutta 2nd Order Method
One of the Runge-Kutta 2nd order method is the midpoint
method, which is a
modified Euler\'s method (one-step method) for numerically solving
ordinary differential equations:
$$y'(x) = f(x, y(x)), \quad y(x_0) = y_0$$. The midpoint method is given
by the formula
$$y_{i+1} = y_i + hf\left(x_i+\frac{h}{2},y_i+\frac{h}{2}f(x_i, y_i)\right)$$.
Note that $y_{i}$ is the approximation of $y(x_{i})$ using this method.
!Illustration of the midpoint method assuming that $y_n$ equals the
exact value $y(t_n).$ The midpoint method computes $y_{n+1}$ so that the
red chord is approximately parallel to the tangent line at the midpoint
(the green
line).. The midpoint method computes y_{n+1} so that the red chord is approximately parallel to the tangent line at the midpoint (the green line).")
# Runga-Kutta 4th Order Method
The Runga-Kutta 4th order
method is
often called \"RK4\", \"classical Runge--Kutta method\" or simply as
\"the Runge--Kutta method\".
$$\begin{align}
y_{i+1} &= y_i + \tfrac{h}{6}\left(k_1 + 2k_2 + 2k_3 + k_4 \right)\\
x_{i+1} &= x_i + h \\
\end{align}$$
for *i* = 0, 1, 2, 3, . . . , using
$$\begin{align}
k_1 &= f(x_i, y_i),
\\
k_2 &= f(x_i + \tfrac{h}{2}, y_i + \tfrac{1}{2} k_1 h),
\\
k_3 &= f(x_i + \tfrac{h}{2}, y_i + \tfrac{1}{2} k_2 h),
\\
k_4 &= f(x_i + h, y_i + k_3 h).
\end{align}$$ This method calculate $y_{i+1}$ by adding to $y_i$) a
weighted average of four increments, each of which is the step size $h$
multiplied by an estimated slope:
- $k_1$ is the increment based on the estimated slope at the beginning
of the interval (Euler\'s method) ;
- $k_2$ is the increment based on the slope at the midpoint of the
interval;
- $k_3$ is again the increment based on the slope at the midpoint, but
now using $k_2$;
- $k_4$ is the increment based on the slope at the end of the
interval, using $k_3$.
In averaging the four increments, greater weight is given to the
increments at the midpoint. The weights are chosen such that if $f$ is
independent of $y$, so that the differential equation is equivalent to a
simple integral.
# Case Study
source
solution in a iPython
notebook
|
# Consciousness Studies/Introduction
Everyone has their own view of the nature of consciousness based on
their education and background. The intention of this book is to expand
this view by providing an insight into the various ideas and beliefs on
the subject as well as a review of current work in neuroscience. The
neuroscientist should find the philosophical discussion interesting
because this provides first-person insights into the nature of
consciousness and also provides some subtle arguments about why
consciousness is not a simple problem. The student of philosophy will
find a useful introduction to the subject and information about
neuroscience and physics that is difficult to acquire elsewhere.
It is often said that consciousness cannot be defined. This is not true;
philosophers have indeed defined it in its own terms. It can be
described in terms of two principal components: firstly **phenomenal
consciousness** which consists of our experience with things laid out in
space and time, sensations, emotions, thoughts, etc., and secondly
**access consciousness** which is the processes that act on the things
in experience. Phenomenal consciousness is much like the "perceptual
space" of psychological and physiological research. It is the many
simultaneous events that become the space of experience in general and
it is now a legitimate target of scientific research.
As will be seen in the following pages, the issue for the scientist and
philosopher is to determine the location and form of the things in
phenomenal consciousness and even to consider whether such a thing could
exist. Is phenomenal consciousness directly things in the world beyond
the body, is it brain activity based on things in the world and internal
processes --- a sort of virtual reality --- or is it some spiritual or
other phenomenon?
## A note on Naive Realism
The study of consciousness may seem to be esoteric or outside of the
main stream but it includes some very real problems in science and
philosophy. The most obvious problem is how we can see anything at all.
Many people with a smattering of geometry tend to believe that they have
a \'point eye\' that sees the world, and this idea is known as
perceptual \"Naive Realism\". Physical considerations show that this
idea is highly contentious; we have two eyes with different images in
each, normally the only images in the world are created by optical
instruments such as the eye, and the photons that carry light to the
observer cannot and do not all converge at a single point. Some of the
discrepancies between the physical reality and our experience are shown
in the illustrations.
![](Constudnaive1.png "Constudnaive1.png")
![](constudnaive2.GIF "constudnaive2.GIF")
The naive realist idea of perception involves a point eye looking at a
geometrical form. But the physics is different; there are two eyes with
sometimes very different images in each. Light is refracted over the
entire area of the cornea and directed over the entire area of the
retina - there is no \'point eye\'.
The cloud of photons that compose light must get in the way of the view
but naive realism neglects this, regarding the photons as somehow
transparent yet gathering as an impossible group of millions of photons
in a viewing point.
Light rays go everywhere, it is only after light has passed through an
optical instrument such as the eye that an image is formed. Hold up a
sheet of paper - there are no images on it.
![](Constudnaive4.png "Constudnaive4.png")The illustrations show the
nature of one of the most difficult problems studied by neuroscience:
how can the images on the two retinas become experience? How can we
imagine things or experience dreams and hallucinations? Studies on the
neural basis of binocular rivalry and MRI studies of imagination are
leading the way in our comprehension of these problems but there is
still **no physical theory that is congruent with sensory experience**.
The problem of *binding* also takes us further from Naive Realism; we
experience speech at the mouth of the speaker even though we might be
listening through headphones, how is sound, touch etc. bound to vision?
The objective of the scientific study of consciousness is to discover
how we convert data from the world into our experience.
A degree of Naive Realism is a sensible idea for coping with the
everyday problems of working and living. Most physical scientists and
people in general are, to some extent, Naive Realists until they study
the biology of sensation and the problems of perception and
consciousness. There is often a suspicion, or even fear, amongst Naive
Realists that any analysis of conscious experience is a suggestion that
the world does not exist or everything is imaginary. These fears are
unfounded: Neuroscience is a study of the part of the physical world
represented by brain activity and is part of medicine.
## Intended audience and how to read this book
This book is intended as a complementary text for neuroscience and
philosophy degree courses. The book is divided into four parts. If you
are not interested in some part, skip to the next. The first part is a
detailed historical review of the philosophy of phenomenal
consciousness. The second part is a discussion of philosophical
theories, it is intended to be challenging and even irritating.
Philosophy undergraduates are encouraged to criticise and react to this
part. The third part is a review of the neuroscience of consciousness
and is suitable for undergraduate studies in the field. The end of the
book is a discussion of theories of consciousness.
Being freely available to all students the book can serve as a source
for seminars even if you disagree with the content i.e.: "Why is (a
given section) an oversimplification/biased/out of date etc.?"
The text covers a difficult area that straddles the humanities and
science faculties. It is probably more oriented towards the scientist
who needs a scientific insight into philosophical theory rather than
vice versa. It is suitable as a **supplementary text** for the following
**undergraduate** modules, units and courses:
- Neurophysiology/Neurobiology modules (physiology of perception,
physiology of consciousness, neuronal basis of consciousness)
- Neuropsychology modules
- Neuroanatomy modules
- Cognitive psychology/Cognitive science
- Psychology of consciousness
- Psychology - behaviourism vs cognitivism debate
- Philosophy of mind and metaphysics
- Computing - Artificial intelligence and consciousness
- Consciousness studies courses
This is a "Wikibook" and, in this edition, has more breadth than depth.
In some areas, particularly in the huge field of the philosophy of
consciousness, topics are introduced and the obvious flaws or successes
pointed out but a fully referenced, in-depth treatment is sometimes
absent at this stage. We need your help and contributions from scholars
in the field are invited. Please contribute but please, at the very
least, scan the book first to ensure that your prospective contribution
has not been included already! In particular contributors who wish to
write "all self respecting scientists think that the brain is a digital
computer" should read the section on information theory and add their
contribution to the section on the possibility of conscious digital
computers.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Introduction#A note on Naive Realism
Everyone has their own view of the nature of consciousness based on
their education and background. The intention of this book is to expand
this view by providing an insight into the various ideas and beliefs on
the subject as well as a review of current work in neuroscience. The
neuroscientist should find the philosophical discussion interesting
because this provides first-person insights into the nature of
consciousness and also provides some subtle arguments about why
consciousness is not a simple problem. The student of philosophy will
find a useful introduction to the subject and information about
neuroscience and physics that is difficult to acquire elsewhere.
It is often said that consciousness cannot be defined. This is not true;
philosophers have indeed defined it in its own terms. It can be
described in terms of two principal components: firstly **phenomenal
consciousness** which consists of our experience with things laid out in
space and time, sensations, emotions, thoughts, etc., and secondly
**access consciousness** which is the processes that act on the things
in experience. Phenomenal consciousness is much like the "perceptual
space" of psychological and physiological research. It is the many
simultaneous events that become the space of experience in general and
it is now a legitimate target of scientific research.
As will be seen in the following pages, the issue for the scientist and
philosopher is to determine the location and form of the things in
phenomenal consciousness and even to consider whether such a thing could
exist. Is phenomenal consciousness directly things in the world beyond
the body, is it brain activity based on things in the world and internal
processes --- a sort of virtual reality --- or is it some spiritual or
other phenomenon?
## A note on Naive Realism
The study of consciousness may seem to be esoteric or outside of the
main stream but it includes some very real problems in science and
philosophy. The most obvious problem is how we can see anything at all.
Many people with a smattering of geometry tend to believe that they have
a \'point eye\' that sees the world, and this idea is known as
perceptual \"Naive Realism\". Physical considerations show that this
idea is highly contentious; we have two eyes with different images in
each, normally the only images in the world are created by optical
instruments such as the eye, and the photons that carry light to the
observer cannot and do not all converge at a single point. Some of the
discrepancies between the physical reality and our experience are shown
in the illustrations.
![](Constudnaive1.png "Constudnaive1.png")
![](constudnaive2.GIF "constudnaive2.GIF")
The naive realist idea of perception involves a point eye looking at a
geometrical form. But the physics is different; there are two eyes with
sometimes very different images in each. Light is refracted over the
entire area of the cornea and directed over the entire area of the
retina - there is no \'point eye\'.
The cloud of photons that compose light must get in the way of the view
but naive realism neglects this, regarding the photons as somehow
transparent yet gathering as an impossible group of millions of photons
in a viewing point.
Light rays go everywhere, it is only after light has passed through an
optical instrument such as the eye that an image is formed. Hold up a
sheet of paper - there are no images on it.
![](Constudnaive4.png "Constudnaive4.png")The illustrations show the
nature of one of the most difficult problems studied by neuroscience:
how can the images on the two retinas become experience? How can we
imagine things or experience dreams and hallucinations? Studies on the
neural basis of binocular rivalry and MRI studies of imagination are
leading the way in our comprehension of these problems but there is
still **no physical theory that is congruent with sensory experience**.
The problem of *binding* also takes us further from Naive Realism; we
experience speech at the mouth of the speaker even though we might be
listening through headphones, how is sound, touch etc. bound to vision?
The objective of the scientific study of consciousness is to discover
how we convert data from the world into our experience.
A degree of Naive Realism is a sensible idea for coping with the
everyday problems of working and living. Most physical scientists and
people in general are, to some extent, Naive Realists until they study
the biology of sensation and the problems of perception and
consciousness. There is often a suspicion, or even fear, amongst Naive
Realists that any analysis of conscious experience is a suggestion that
the world does not exist or everything is imaginary. These fears are
unfounded: Neuroscience is a study of the part of the physical world
represented by brain activity and is part of medicine.
## Intended audience and how to read this book
This book is intended as a complementary text for neuroscience and
philosophy degree courses. The book is divided into four parts. If you
are not interested in some part, skip to the next. The first part is a
detailed historical review of the philosophy of phenomenal
consciousness. The second part is a discussion of philosophical
theories, it is intended to be challenging and even irritating.
Philosophy undergraduates are encouraged to criticise and react to this
part. The third part is a review of the neuroscience of consciousness
and is suitable for undergraduate studies in the field. The end of the
book is a discussion of theories of consciousness.
Being freely available to all students the book can serve as a source
for seminars even if you disagree with the content i.e.: "Why is (a
given section) an oversimplification/biased/out of date etc.?"
The text covers a difficult area that straddles the humanities and
science faculties. It is probably more oriented towards the scientist
who needs a scientific insight into philosophical theory rather than
vice versa. It is suitable as a **supplementary text** for the following
**undergraduate** modules, units and courses:
- Neurophysiology/Neurobiology modules (physiology of perception,
physiology of consciousness, neuronal basis of consciousness)
- Neuropsychology modules
- Neuroanatomy modules
- Cognitive psychology/Cognitive science
- Psychology of consciousness
- Psychology - behaviourism vs cognitivism debate
- Philosophy of mind and metaphysics
- Computing - Artificial intelligence and consciousness
- Consciousness studies courses
This is a "Wikibook" and, in this edition, has more breadth than depth.
In some areas, particularly in the huge field of the philosophy of
consciousness, topics are introduced and the obvious flaws or successes
pointed out but a fully referenced, in-depth treatment is sometimes
absent at this stage. We need your help and contributions from scholars
in the field are invited. Please contribute but please, at the very
least, scan the book first to ensure that your prospective contribution
has not been included already! In particular contributors who wish to
write "all self respecting scientists think that the brain is a digital
computer" should read the section on information theory and add their
contribution to the section on the possibility of conscious digital
computers.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Introduction#Intended audience and how to read this book
Everyone has their own view of the nature of consciousness based on
their education and background. The intention of this book is to expand
this view by providing an insight into the various ideas and beliefs on
the subject as well as a review of current work in neuroscience. The
neuroscientist should find the philosophical discussion interesting
because this provides first-person insights into the nature of
consciousness and also provides some subtle arguments about why
consciousness is not a simple problem. The student of philosophy will
find a useful introduction to the subject and information about
neuroscience and physics that is difficult to acquire elsewhere.
It is often said that consciousness cannot be defined. This is not true;
philosophers have indeed defined it in its own terms. It can be
described in terms of two principal components: firstly **phenomenal
consciousness** which consists of our experience with things laid out in
space and time, sensations, emotions, thoughts, etc., and secondly
**access consciousness** which is the processes that act on the things
in experience. Phenomenal consciousness is much like the "perceptual
space" of psychological and physiological research. It is the many
simultaneous events that become the space of experience in general and
it is now a legitimate target of scientific research.
As will be seen in the following pages, the issue for the scientist and
philosopher is to determine the location and form of the things in
phenomenal consciousness and even to consider whether such a thing could
exist. Is phenomenal consciousness directly things in the world beyond
the body, is it brain activity based on things in the world and internal
processes --- a sort of virtual reality --- or is it some spiritual or
other phenomenon?
## A note on Naive Realism
The study of consciousness may seem to be esoteric or outside of the
main stream but it includes some very real problems in science and
philosophy. The most obvious problem is how we can see anything at all.
Many people with a smattering of geometry tend to believe that they have
a \'point eye\' that sees the world, and this idea is known as
perceptual \"Naive Realism\". Physical considerations show that this
idea is highly contentious; we have two eyes with different images in
each, normally the only images in the world are created by optical
instruments such as the eye, and the photons that carry light to the
observer cannot and do not all converge at a single point. Some of the
discrepancies between the physical reality and our experience are shown
in the illustrations.
![](Constudnaive1.png "Constudnaive1.png")
![](constudnaive2.GIF "constudnaive2.GIF")
The naive realist idea of perception involves a point eye looking at a
geometrical form. But the physics is different; there are two eyes with
sometimes very different images in each. Light is refracted over the
entire area of the cornea and directed over the entire area of the
retina - there is no \'point eye\'.
The cloud of photons that compose light must get in the way of the view
but naive realism neglects this, regarding the photons as somehow
transparent yet gathering as an impossible group of millions of photons
in a viewing point.
Light rays go everywhere, it is only after light has passed through an
optical instrument such as the eye that an image is formed. Hold up a
sheet of paper - there are no images on it.
![](Constudnaive4.png "Constudnaive4.png")The illustrations show the
nature of one of the most difficult problems studied by neuroscience:
how can the images on the two retinas become experience? How can we
imagine things or experience dreams and hallucinations? Studies on the
neural basis of binocular rivalry and MRI studies of imagination are
leading the way in our comprehension of these problems but there is
still **no physical theory that is congruent with sensory experience**.
The problem of *binding* also takes us further from Naive Realism; we
experience speech at the mouth of the speaker even though we might be
listening through headphones, how is sound, touch etc. bound to vision?
The objective of the scientific study of consciousness is to discover
how we convert data from the world into our experience.
A degree of Naive Realism is a sensible idea for coping with the
everyday problems of working and living. Most physical scientists and
people in general are, to some extent, Naive Realists until they study
the biology of sensation and the problems of perception and
consciousness. There is often a suspicion, or even fear, amongst Naive
Realists that any analysis of conscious experience is a suggestion that
the world does not exist or everything is imaginary. These fears are
unfounded: Neuroscience is a study of the part of the physical world
represented by brain activity and is part of medicine.
## Intended audience and how to read this book
This book is intended as a complementary text for neuroscience and
philosophy degree courses. The book is divided into four parts. If you
are not interested in some part, skip to the next. The first part is a
detailed historical review of the philosophy of phenomenal
consciousness. The second part is a discussion of philosophical
theories, it is intended to be challenging and even irritating.
Philosophy undergraduates are encouraged to criticise and react to this
part. The third part is a review of the neuroscience of consciousness
and is suitable for undergraduate studies in the field. The end of the
book is a discussion of theories of consciousness.
Being freely available to all students the book can serve as a source
for seminars even if you disagree with the content i.e.: "Why is (a
given section) an oversimplification/biased/out of date etc.?"
The text covers a difficult area that straddles the humanities and
science faculties. It is probably more oriented towards the scientist
who needs a scientific insight into philosophical theory rather than
vice versa. It is suitable as a **supplementary text** for the following
**undergraduate** modules, units and courses:
- Neurophysiology/Neurobiology modules (physiology of perception,
physiology of consciousness, neuronal basis of consciousness)
- Neuropsychology modules
- Neuroanatomy modules
- Cognitive psychology/Cognitive science
- Psychology of consciousness
- Psychology - behaviourism vs cognitivism debate
- Philosophy of mind and metaphysics
- Computing - Artificial intelligence and consciousness
- Consciousness studies courses
This is a "Wikibook" and, in this edition, has more breadth than depth.
In some areas, particularly in the huge field of the philosophy of
consciousness, topics are introduced and the obvious flaws or successes
pointed out but a fully referenced, in-depth treatment is sometimes
absent at this stage. We need your help and contributions from scholars
in the field are invited. Please contribute but please, at the very
least, scan the book first to ensure that your prospective contribution
has not been included already! In particular contributors who wish to
write "all self respecting scientists think that the brain is a digital
computer" should read the section on information theory and add their
contribution to the section on the possibility of conscious digital
computers.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Early Ideas
*This section is an academic review of major contributions to
consciousness studies. Readers who are interested in the current
philosophy of consciousness will find this in Part II and readers
interested in the neuroscience of consciousness should refer to Part
III.*
Vedic Sciences are present the first known ideas related to
consciousness, dating back to at least 1500 years ago according to The
British Library. The ten books of Rig Veda, which are attributed to the
end of the Bronze period, which are on of the ten oldest living texts of
the world, illuminates us on ultimate or supreme consciousness. In the
Rig Veda (R.V. IV. XL. 5) Nrishad is the dweller amongst humans; Nrishad
is explained as Chaitanya or \'Consciousness\' or Prana or \'vitality\'
because both dwell in humans.
In his commentary on the Isha Upanishad,\[5\] Sri Aurobindo explains
that the Atman, the Self manifests through a seven-fold movement of
Prakrti. These seven folds of consciousness, along with their dominant
principles are:\[6\]
annamaya puruṣa - physical prāṇamaya puruṣa - nervous / vital manomaya
puruṣa - mental / mind vijñānamaya puruṣa - knowledge and truth
ānandamaya puruṣa - Aurobindo\'s concept of Delight, otherwise known as
Bliss caitanya puruṣa - infinite divine self-awareness\[7\] sat puruṣa -
state of pure divine existence
The first five of these are arranged according to the specification of
the panchakosha from the second chapter of the Taittiriya Upanishad. The
final three elements make up satcitananda, with cit being referred to as
chaitanya.
The essential nature of Brahman as revealed in deep sleep and Yoga is
Chaitanya (pure consciousness).\[8\]
The earliest use of the word soul or Ātman in Indian texts is also found
in the Rig Veda (c. 1500 BC)(RV X.97.11).\[20\] Yāska, the ancient
Indian grammarian, commenting on this Rigvedic verse, accepts the
following meanings of Ātman: the pervading principle, the organism in
which other elements are united and the ultimate sentient
principle.\[21\]
Other hymns of Rig Veda where the word Ātman appears include I.115.1,
VII.87.2, VII.101.6, VIII.3.24, IX.2.10, IX.6.8, and X.168.4.\[22\]
The Rig Veda takes one from before creation, through creation of the
world, to creation of self, and ends with the creation of creation
itself, after which creation of the universe came. Upon close reading,
one can trace the various stages of consciousness to the material world,
from absolute truth or Sat to absolute material or Asat, two recurring
concepts that run through the entire Rig Veda.
The Greeks had no exact equivalent for the term \'consciousness\', which
has a wide range of meanings in modern usage, but in the thinkers below
we find an analysis of phenomenal consciousness and the source of many
ideas developed by later Socratics, especially the Stoics, and by
Christian thinkers like Augustine.
## Aristotle (c. 350 BC) *On the Soul*
(De Anima) <http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/Aristotle/De-anima/>
!AristotleAristotle, perhaps more
than any other ancient Greek philosopher, set the terms of reference for
the future discussion of the problem of consciousness. His idea of the
mind is summarised in the illustration
below.![](Constudaristotle.png "Constudaristotle.png")
Aristotle was a physicalist, believing that things are embodied in the
material universe:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"\... That is precisely why the
study of the soul \[psyche\] must fall within the science of Nature, at
least so far as in its affections it manifests this double character.
Hence a physicist would define an affection of soul differently from a
dialectician; the latter would define e.g. anger as the appetite for
returning pain for pain, or something like that, while the former would
define it as a boiling of the blood or warm substance surround the
heart. The latter assigns the material conditions, the former the form
or formulable essence; for what he states is the formulable essence of
the fact, though for its actual existence there must be embodiment of it
in a material such as is described by the other.\"(Book I,
403a)`</font>`{=html}
The works of Aristotle provide our first clear account of the concept of
signals and information. He was aware that an event can change the state
of matter and this change of state can be transmitted to other locations
where it can further change a state of matter:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"If what has colour is placed in
immediate contact with the eye, it cannot be seen. Colour sets in
movement not the sense organ but what is transparent, e.g. the air, and
that, extending continuously from the object to the organ, sets the
latter in movement. Democritus misrepresents the facts when he expresses
the opinion that if the interspace were empty one could distinctly see
an ant on the vault of the sky; that is an impossibility. Seeing is due
to an affection or change of what has the perceptive faculty, and it
cannot be affected by the seen colour itself; it remains that it must be
affected by what comes between. Hence it is indispensable that there be
something in between-if there were nothing, so far from seeing with
greater distinctness, we should see nothing at all.\" (Book II,
419a\])`</font>`{=html}
He was also clear about the relationship of information to \'state\':
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"By a \'sense\' is meant what has
the power of receiving into itself the sensible forms of things without
the matter. This must be conceived of as taking place in the way in
which a piece of wax takes on the impress of a signet-ring without the
iron or gold; we say that what produces the impression is a signet of
bronze or gold, but its particular metallic constitution makes no
difference: in a similar way the sense is affected by what is coloured
or flavoured or sounding, but it is indifferent what in each case the
substance is; what alone matters is what quality it has, i.e. in what
ratio its constituents are combined\"(Book II, 424a)`</font>`{=html}
Aristotle also mentioned the problem of the simultaneity of experience.
The explanation predates Galilean and modern physics so lacks our modern
language to explain how many things could be at a point and an instant:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"\... just as what is called a
\'point\' is, as being at once one and two, properly said to be
divisible, so here, that which discriminates is qua undivided one, and
active in a single moment of time, while so far forth as it is divisible
it twice over uses the same dot at one and the same time. So far forth
then as it takes the limit as two\' it discriminates two separate
objects with what in a sense is divided: while so far as it takes it as
one, it does so with what is one and occupies in its activity a single
moment of time. (Book III, 427a)`</font>`{=html}
He described the problem of recursion that would occur if the mind were
due to the flow of material things in space:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"\...mind is either without parts
or is continuous in some other way than that which characterizes a
spatial magnitude. How, indeed, if it were a spatial magnitude, could
mind possibly think? Will it think with any one indifferently of its
parts? In this case, the \'part\' must be understood either in the sense
of a spatial magnitude or in the sense of a point (if a point can be
called a part of a spatial magnitude). If we accept the latter
alternative, the points being infinite in number, obviously the mind can
never exhaustively traverse them; if the former, the mind must think the
same thing over and over again, indeed an infinite number of times
(whereas it is manifestly possible to think a thing once only).\"(Book
I, 407a)`</font>`{=html}
Aristotle explicitly mentions the regress:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"..we must fall into an infinite
regress or we must assume a sense which is aware of itself.\" (Book
III,425b)`</font>`{=html}
However, this regress was not as problematic for Aristotle as it is for
philosophers who are steeped in nineteenth century ideas. Aristotle was
a physicalist who was not burdened with materialism and so was able to
escape from the idea that the only possibility for the mind is a flow of
material from place to place over a succession of disconnected instants.
He was able to propose that subjects and objects are part of the same
thing, he notes that thought is both temporally and spatially extended:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"But that which mind thinks and
the time in which it thinks are in this case divisible only incidentally
and not as such. For in them too there is something indivisible (though,
it may be, not isolable) which gives unity to the time and the whole of
length; and this is found equally in every continuum whether temporal or
spatial.\" (Book III,430b)`</font>`{=html}
This idea of time allowed him to identify thinking with the object of
thought, there being no need to cycle thoughts from instant to instant
because mental time is extended:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"In every case the mind which is
actively thinking is the objects which it thinks.\"`</font>`{=html}
He considered imagination to be a disturbance of the sense organs:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"And because imaginations remain
in the organs of sense and resemble sensations, animals in their actions
are largely guided by them, some (i.e. the brutes) because of the
non-existence in them of mind, others (i.e. men) because of the
temporary eclipse in them of mind by feeling or disease or sleep.(Book
III, 429a)\"`</font>`{=html}
And considered that all thought occurs as images:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"To the thinking soul images
serve as if they were contents of perception (and when it asserts or
denies them to be good or bad it avoids or pursues them). That is why
the soul never thinks without an image.\"(Book III, ).`</font>`{=html}
Aristotle also described the debate between the cognitive and
behaviourist approaches with their overtones of the conflict between
modern physicalism and pre twentieth century materialism:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Some thinkers, accepting both
premisses, viz. that the soul is both originative of movement and
cognitive, have compounded it of both and declared the soul to be a
self-moving number.\"(Book I, 404b)`</font>`{=html}
The idea of a \'self-moving number\' is not as absurd as it seems, like
much of Ancient Greek philosophy.
Aristotle was also clear about there being two forms involved in
perception. He proposed that the form and properties of the things that
are directly in the mind are incontrovertible but that our inferences
about the form and properties of the things in the world that give rise
to the things in the mind can be false:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Perception (1) of the special
objects of sense is never in error or admits the least possible amount
of falsehood. (2) That of the concomitance of the objects concomitant
with the sensible qualities comes next: in this case certainly we may be
deceived; for while the perception that there is white before us cannot
be false, the perception that what is white is this or that may be
false. (3) Third comes the perception of the universal attributes which
accompany the concomitant objects to which the special sensibles attach
(I mean e.g. of movement and magnitude); it is in respect of these that
the greatest amount of sense-illusion is possible.\"(Book III,
428b)`</font>`{=html}
Imagination, according to this model, lays out things in the senses.
## Galen
The \'physicians\' (most especially Galen) incorporated ideas from the
Hippocractics and from Plato into a view in which 3 (or more) inner
senses---most basically memory, estimation, and imagination---were
associated with 3 ventricles in the brain.
*This is a **stub** that needs further expansion*.
## Homer (c. 800-900 BC) The *Iliad* and *Odyssey*
Odyssey
!HomerPanpsychism and
panexperientialism can be traced to, at least, Homer\'s Iliad. Just
reading the book allows us to experience what a different focus of
consciousness feels like. It is a way of being, being a Homeric Greek,
thus distinct from being a modern man. Both states of consciousness
result in different ways of experiencing the world.
As we read the Iliad, we are drawn into the book through the images it
creates in us and the feelings it evokes in us through the meter and the
language. The reader becomes the book. \"The reader became the book, and
the summer night was like the conscious being of the book\" (Wallace
Stevens). That experience of becoming the book, of losing yourself in
the book, is the experience of a different aspect of consciousness,
being a Homeric Greek.
Homer frequently ascribes even our emotions to the world around us. The
ancients do not just fear but fear grips them, for example: \"So spake
Athene, and pale fear gat hold of them all. The arms flew from their
hands in their terror and fell all upon the ground, as the goddess
uttered her voice\" (Odyssey book XXIV).
The German classicist Bruno Snell, in *The Discovery of the Mind*
provides us with \"a convincing account of the enormous change in \...
human personality which took place during the centuries covered by Homer
(to) Socrates.\"(The London Times Literary Supplement). Snell\'s book
establishes two distinct aspects of consciousness. He says, \"The
experience of Homer differs from our own\" (p.v); \"For Homer, psyche is
the force which keeps the human being alive\...\"(p. 8). When the psyche
leaves, the owner loses consciousness. The Homeric *psyche* is where
pan-psychism originates. It begins in a conception of consciousness as a
force that is separate from the body. Snell compares Homer to the
tragedy of Orestes, which focuses on the individual. \"Homer
concentrates on the action (process) and the situation in preference to
the agent\...\"(p. 211) Orestes is in a different state of
consciousness, \"a new state of consciousness\"(p. 211).
## Plato (427-347 BC)
The Republic <http://www.constitution.org/pla/repub_00.htm> Especially
book VI <http://www.constitution.org/pla/repub_06.htm> and book VII (the
Cave) <http://www.constitution.org/pla/repub_07.htm>
!PlatoPlato\'s most interesting contributions to
consciousness studies are in book VI of *The Republic*. His idea of the
mind is illustrated below.
![](Constudplato.png "Constudplato.png")
He believes that light activates pre-existing capabilities in the eyes:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Sight being, as I conceive, in
the eyes, and he who has eyes wanting to see; color being also present
in them, still unless there be a third nature specially adapted to the
purpose, the owner of the eyes will see nothing and the colors will be
invisible.\"`</font>`{=html}
However, it is in the metaphor of **the divided line** that Plato
introduces a fascinating account of the relationships and properties of
things. He points out that analysis deals in terms of the relationships
of pure forms:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"And do you not know also that
although they make use of the visible forms and reason about them, they
are thinking not of these, but of the ideals which they resemble; not of
the figures which they draw, but of the absolute square and the absolute
diameter, and so on \-- the forms which they draw or make, and which
have shadows and reflections in water of their own, are converted by
them into images, but they are really seeking to behold the things
themselves, which can only be seen with the eye of the
mind?\"`</font>`{=html}
Notice how he introduces the notion of a mind\'s eye observing mental
content arranged as geometrical forms. He proposes that through this
mode of ideas we gain understanding:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"And the habit which is concerned
with geometry and the cognate sciences I suppose that you would term
understanding, and not reason, as being intermediate between opinion and
reason.\"`</font>`{=html}
However, the understanding can also contemplate knowledge:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"..I understand you to say that
knowledge and being, which the science of dialectic contemplates, are
clearer than the notions of the arts, as they are termed, which proceed
from hypotheses only: these are also contemplated by the understanding,
and not by the senses: yet, because they start from hypotheses and do
not ascend to a principle, those who contemplate them appear to you not
to exercise the higher reason upon them, although when a first principle
is added to them they are cognizable by the higher reason.
\"`</font>`{=html}
Plato\'s work is not usually discussed in this way but is extended to
universals such as the idea of the colour red as a universal that can be
applied to many specific instances of things.
In \"Plato\'s Cave\" (Book VII) Plato describes how experience could be
some transfer from or copy of real things rather than the things
themselves:
!Plato\'s
Cave`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"And
now, I said, let me show in a figure how far our nature is enlightened
or unenlightened: --- Behold! human beings living in a underground den,
which has a mouth open towards the light and reaching all along the den;
here they have been from their childhood, and have their legs and necks
chained so that they cannot move, and can only see before them, being
prevented by the chains from turning round their heads. Above and behind
them a fire is blazing at a distance, and between the fire and the
prisoners there is a raised way; and you will see, if you look, a low
wall built along the way, like the screen which marionette players have
in front of them, over which they show the puppets.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}I see.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}And do you see, I said, men
passing along the wall carrying all sorts of vessels, and statues and
figures of animals made of wood and stone and various materials, which
appear over the wall? Some of them are talking, others
silent.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}You have shown me a strange image,
and they are strange prisoners.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}Like ourselves, I replied; and
they see only their own shadows, or the shadows of one another, which
the fire throws on the opposite wall of the cave?`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}True, he said; how could they see
anything but the shadows if they were never allowed to move their
heads?`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}And of the objects which are being
carried in like manner they would only see the shadows?`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}Yes, he said.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}And if they were able to converse
with one another, would they not suppose that they were naming what was
actually before them?`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}Very true.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}And suppose further that the
prison had an echo which came from the other side, would they not be
sure to fancy when one of the passers-by spoke that the voice which they
heard came from the passing shadow?`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}No question, he
replied.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}To them, I said, the truth would
be literally nothing but the shadows of the images.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}That is certain.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}And now look again, and see what
will naturally follow it, the prisoners are released and disabused of
their error. At first, when any of them is liberated and compelled
suddenly to stand up and turn his neck round and walk and look towards
the light, he will suffer sharp pains; the glare will distress him, and
he will be unable to see the realities of which in his former state he
had seen the shadows; and then conceive some one saying to him, that
what he saw before was an illusion, but that now, when he is approaching
nearer to being and his eye is turned towards more real existence, he
has a clearer vision, --- what will be his reply? And you may further
imagine that his instructor is pointing to the objects as they pass and
requiring him to name them, --- will he not be perplexed? Will he not
fancy that the shadows which he formerly saw are truer than the objects
which are now shown to him?\"`</font>`{=html}
This early intuition of information theory predates Aristotle\'s concept
of the transfer of states from one place to another.
## Parmenides (c. 480 BC) *On Nature*
## Siddhartha Gautama (c. 500 BC) Buddhist Texts
!BuddhaSiddhartha Gautama was born about
563BC. He became known as \'Buddha\' (\'the awakened one\') from the age
of about thirty five. Buddha handed down a way of life that might lead,
eventually, to an enlightened state called Nirvana. In the three
centuries after his death Buddhism split into two factions, the Mahayana
(greater raft or vehicle) and the Theravada (the way of the elders). The
Mahayana use the slightly derogatory term Hinayana (lesser raft or
vehicle) for Theravada Buddhism. Mahayana Buddhism gave rise to other
sects such as Zen Buddhism in Japan and Vajrayana Buddhism in Tibet.
Mahayana Buddhism is more like a religion, complete with god like
entities whereas Theravada Buddhism is more like a philosophy.
Theravada Buddhist meditation is described in books called the Pali
Canon which contains the \'Vinayas\' that describe monastic life, the
\'Suttas\' which are the central teachings of Theravada Buddhism and the
\'Abhidhamma\' which is an analysis of the other two parts or
\'pitakas\'. Two meditational systems are described: the development of
serenity (samathabhavana) and the development of insight
(vipassanabhavana). The two systems are complementary, serenity
meditation providing a steady foundation for the development of insight.
As meditation proceeds the practitioner passes through a series of
stages called \'jhanas\'. There are four of these stages of meditation
and then a final stage known as the stage of the \'immaterial jhanas\'.
**The Jhanas**
The first jhana is a stage of preparation where the meditator rids
themselves of the hindrances (sensual desire, ill will, sloth and
torpor, restlessness and worry, and doubt). This is best achieved by
seclusion. During the process of getting rid of the hindrances the
meditator develops the five factors: applied thought, sustained thought,
rapture, happiness and one-pointedness of mind. This is done by
concentrating on a practice object until it can be easily visualised.
Eventually the meditator experiences a luminous replica of the object
called the counterpart sign (patibhaganimitta).
Applied thought involves examining, visualising and thinking about the
object. Sustained thought involves always returning to the object, not
drifting away from it. Rapture involves a oneness with the object and is
an ecstacy that helps absorption with and in the object. Happiness is
the feeling of happiness that everyone has when something good happens
(unlike rapture, which is a oneness with the object of contemplation).
One-pointedness of mind is the ability to focus on a single thing
without being distracted.
The second jhana involves attaining the first without effort, there is
no need for applied or sustained thought, only rapture, happiness and
one-pointedness of mind remain. The second jhana is achieved by
contemplating the first jhana. The second jhana is a stage of effortless
concentration.
The third jhana involves mindfulness and discernment. The mindfulness
allows an object of meditation to be held effortlessly in the mind. The
discernment consists of discerning the nature of the object without
delusion and hence avoiding rapture.
In the fourth jhana mindfulness is maintained but the delusion of
happiness is contemplated. Eventually mindfulness remains without
pleasure or pain. In the fourth jhana the meditator achieves \"purity of
mindfulness due to equanimity\" (upekkhasatiparisuddhi).
**The Immaterial Jhanas**
The first four jhanas will be familiar from earlier, Hindu meditational
techniques. Once the fourth jhana has been achieved the meditator can
embark on the immaterial jhanas. There are four immaterial jhanas: the
base of boundless space, the base of boundless consciousness, the base
of nothingness, and the base of neither-perception-nor-non-perception.
The base of boundless space is achieved by meditating on the absence of
the meditation object. It is realised that the space occupied by the
object is boundless and that the mind too is boundless space. The base
of boundless consciousness involves a realisation that the boundless
space is boundless consciousness. The base of nothingness is a
realisation that the present does not exist, the meditator should \"give
attention to the present non-existence, voidness, secluded aspect of
that same past consciousness belonging to the base consisting of
boundless space\" (Gunaratana 1988). The base of
neither-perception-nor-non-perception is a realisation that nothing is
perceived in the void.
In Theravada Buddhism the attainment of the fourth jhana and its
immaterial jhanas represents a mastery of serenity meditation. This is a
foundation for insight meditation.
Buddhism is very practical and eschews delusions. It is realised that
serenity meditation is a state of mind, a steady foundation that might,
nowadays be called a physiological state. It is through insight
meditation where the practitioner becomes a philosopher that
enlightenment is obtained.
**Further reading**
The Buddhist Publication Society. Especially: The Jhanas In Theravada
Buddhist Meditation by Henepola Gunaratana. The Wheel Publication No.
351/353 . 1988 Buddhist Publication
Society. <http://www.accesstoinsight.org/lib/bps/index.html>
|
# Consciousness Studies/Medieval Concepts
It is sometimes said that before the 17th century, there was no
distinction between conscience and consciousness (both being referenced
by the same Latin word \'conscius---from \'conscientia\'). One feature
of the soul being its ability to know itself, and the soul being
witnessed also by God, there was a sense in which conscience was a
knowledge of the inner life shared with God. In fact, Boris Hennig [^1]
proposes that Descartes did not invent an entirely new sense of
conscience, but if anything adapted this Augustinian sense of the term.
The Augustinians themselves can be said to have adapted this use of
conscius from the Latin Stoics like Seneca. On the other hand the
Ancient Greek philosophers were clear that there was a problem of mind
and the work of Descartes can be seen as more directly connected with
Aristotle rather than with medieval philosophy.
## References
[^1]: \"Cartesian Conscientia\", *British Journal for the History of
Philosophy* 15(3) 2007: 455 -- 484.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Seventeenth And Eighteenth Century Philosophy
## Rene Descartes (1596-1650)
Descartes was also known as Cartesius. He had an empirical approach to
consciousness and the mind, describing in his *Meditations on First
Philosophy* (1641) what it is like to be human. His idea of perception
is summarised in the diagram below.
![](Constuddescart3.png "Constuddescart3.png")
### Dubitability
Descartes is probably most famous for his statement:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"But immediately upon this I
observed that, whilst I thus wished to think that all was false, it was
absolutely necessary that I, who thus thought, should be somewhat; and
as I observed that this truth, I think, therefore I am (COGITO ERGO
SUM), was so certain and of such evidence that no ground of doubt,
however extravagant, could be alleged by the sceptics capable of shaking
it, I concluded that I might, without scruple, accept it as the first
principle of the philosophy of which I was in search.\"`</font>`{=html}
Descartes is clear that what he means by *thought* is all the things
that occur in experience, whether dreams, sensations, symbols etc.:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"5. Of my thoughts some are, as
it were, images of things, and to these alone properly belongs the name
IDEA; as when I think \[ represent to my mind \] a man, a chimera, the
sky, an angel or God. Others, again, have certain other forms; as when I
will, fear, affirm, or deny, I always, indeed, apprehend something as
the object of my thought, but I also embrace in thought something more
than the representation of the object; and of this class of thoughts
some are called volitions or affections, and others judgments.\"
(Meditation III).`</font>`{=html}
He repeats this general description of thought in many places in the
Meditations and elsewhere. What Descartes is saying is that his
meditator has thoughts; that there are thoughts and this cannot be
doubted when and where they occur (Russell (1945) makes this clear).
Needless to say the basic *cogito* put forward by Descartes has provoked
endless debate, much of it based on the false premise that Descartes was
presenting an inference or argument rather than just saying that thought
certainly exists. However, the extent to which the philosopher can go
beyond this certainty to concepts such as God, science or the soul is
highly problematical.
### The description of thoughts and mind
!DescartesDescartes uses the words
\"ideas\" and \"imagination\" in a rather unusual fashion. The word
\"idea\" he defines as follows:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"5. Of my thoughts some are, as
it were, images of things, and to these alone properly belongs the name
IDEA; as when I think \[ represent to my mind \] a man, a chimera, the
sky, an angel or God.\" (Meditation III).`</font>`{=html}
As will be seen later, Descartes regards his mind as an unextended thing
(a point) so \"images of things\" or \"IDEAS\" require some way of being
extended. In the *Treatise on Man* (see below) he is explicit that ideas
are extended things in the brain, on the surface of the \"common
sense\". In *Rules for the Direction of the Mind* he notes that we
\"receive ideas from the common sensibility\", an extended part of the
brain. This usage of the term \"ideas\" is very strange to the modern
reader and the source of many mistaken interpretations. It should be
noted that occasionally Descartes uses the term \'idea\' according to
its usual meaning where it is almost interchangeable with \'thought\' in
general but usually he means a representation laid out in the brain.
Descartes considers the imagination to be the way that the mind \"turns
towards the body\" (by which Descartes means the part of the brain in
the body called the senses communis):
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"3. I remark, besides, that this
power of imagination which I possess, in as far as it differs from the
power of conceiving, is in no way necessary to my \[nature or\] essence,
that is, to the essence of my mind; for although I did not possess it, I
should still remain the same that I now am, from which it seems we may
conclude that it depends on something different from the mind. And I
easily understand that, if some body exists, with which my mind is so
conjoined and united as to be able, as it were, to consider it when it
chooses, it may thus imagine corporeal objects; so that this mode of
thinking differs from pure intellection only in this respect, that the
mind in conceiving turns in some way upon itself, and considers some one
of the ideas it possesses within itself; but in imagining it turns
toward the body, and contemplates in it some object conformed to the
idea which it either of itself conceived or apprehended by sense.\"
Meditations VI `</font>`{=html}
So ideas, where they become imagined images of things were thought by
Descartes to involve a phase of creating a form in the brain.
Descartes gives a clear description of his experience as a container
that allows length, breadth, depth, continuity and time with contents
arranged within it:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"2. But before considering
whether such objects as I conceive exist without me, I must examine
their ideas in so far as these are to be found in my consciousness, and
discover which of them are distinct and which confused.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}3. In the first place, I
distinctly imagine that quantity which the philosophers commonly call
continuous, or the extension in length, breadth, and depth that is in
this quantity, or rather in the object to which it is attributed.
Further, I can enumerate in it many diverse parts, and attribute to each
of these all sorts of sizes, figures, situations, and local motions;
and, in fine, I can assign to each of these motions all degrees of
duration.\"(Meditation V).`</font>`{=html}
He points out that sensation occurs by way of the brain, conceptualising
the brain as the place in the body where the extended experiences are
found : Meditations VI:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"20. I remark, in the next place,
that the mind does not immediately receive the impression from all the
parts of the body, but only from the brain, or perhaps even from one
small part of it, viz., that in which the common sense (senses communis)
is said to be, which as often as it is affected in the same way gives
rise to the same perception in the mind, although meanwhile the other
parts of the body may be diversely disposed, as is proved by innumerable
experiments, which it is unnecessary here to enumerate.\"
`</font>`{=html}
He finds that both imaginings and perceptions are extended things and
hence in the (brain part) of the body. The area of extended things is
called the *res extensa*, it includes the brain, body and world beyond.
He also considers the origin of intuitions, suggesting that they can
enter the mind without being consciously created: Meditations VI, 10 :
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"10. Moreover, I find in myself
diverse faculties of thinking that have each their special mode: for
example, I find I possess the faculties of imagining and perceiving,
without which I can indeed clearly and distinctly conceive myself as
entire, but I cannot reciprocally conceive them without conceiving
myself, that is to say, without an intelligent substance in which they
reside, for \[in the notion we have of them, or to use the terms of the
schools\] in their formal concept, they comprise some sort of
intellection; whence I perceive that they are distinct from myself as
modes are from things. I remark likewise certain other faculties, as the
power of changing place, of assuming diverse figures, and the like, that
cannot be conceived and cannot therefore exist, any more than the
preceding, apart from a substance in which they inhere. It is very
evident, however, that these faculties, if they really exist, must
belong to some corporeal or extended substance, since in their clear and
distinct concept there is contained some sort of extension, but no
intellection at all. Further, I cannot doubt but that there is in me a
certain passive faculty of perception, that is, of receiving and taking
knowledge of the ideas of sensible things; but this would be useless to
me, if there did not also exist in me, or in some other thing, another
active faculty capable of forming and producing those ideas. But this
active faculty cannot be in me \[in as far as I am but a thinking
thing\], seeing that it does not presuppose thought, and also that those
ideas are frequently produced in my mind without my contributing to it
in any way, and even frequently contrary to my will. This faculty must
therefore exist in some substance different from me, in which all the
objective reality of the ideas that are produced by this faculty is
contained formally or eminently, as I before remarked; and this
substance is either a body, that is to say, a corporeal nature in which
is contained formally \[and in effect\] all that is objectively \[and by
representation\] in those ideas; or it is God himself, or some other
creature, of a rank superior to body, in which the same is contained
eminently. But as God is no deceiver, it is manifest that he does not of
himself and immediately communicate those ideas to me, nor even by the
intervention of any creature in which their objective reality is not
formally, but only eminently, contained. For as he has given me no
faculty whereby I can discover this to be the case, but, on the
contrary, a very strong inclination to believe that those ideas arise
from corporeal objects, I do not see how he could be vindicated from the
charge of deceit, if in truth they proceeded from any other source, or
were produced by other causes than corporeal things: and accordingly it
must be concluded, that corporeal objects exist. Nevertheless, they are
not perhaps exactly such as we perceive by the senses, for their
comprehension by the senses is, in many instances, very obscure and
confused; but it is at least necessary to admit that all which I clearly
and distinctly conceive as in them, that is, generally speaking all that
is comprehended in the object of speculative geometry, really exists
external to me. \"`</font>`{=html}
He considers that the mind itself is the thing that generates thoughts
and is not extended (occupies no space). This \'mind\' is known as the
*res cogitans*. The mind works on the imaginings and perceptions that
exist in that part of the body called the brain. This is Descartes\'
dualism: it is the proposition that there is an unextended place called
the mind that acts upon the extended things in the brain. Meditations
VI, 9:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"\... And although I may, or
rather, as I will shortly say, although I certainly do possess a body
with which I am very closely conjoined; nevertheless, because, on the
one hand, I have a clear and distinct idea of myself, in as far as I am
only a thinking and unextended thing, and as, on the other hand, I
possess a distinct idea of body, in as far as it is only an extended and
unthinking thing, it is certain that I, \[that is, my mind, by which I
am what I am\], is entirely and truly distinct from my body, and may
exist without it.\"`</font>`{=html}
Notice that the intellection associated with ideas is part of an
\"active faculty capable of forming and producing those ideas\" that has
a \"corporeal nature\" (it is in the brain). This suggests that the
\"thinking\" in the passage above applies only to those thoughts that
are unextended, however, it is difficult to find a definition of these
particular thoughts.
\"Rules for the Direction of the Mind\" demonstrates Descartes\'
dualism. He describes the brain as the part of the body that contains
images or phantasies of the world but believes that there is a further,
spiritual mind that processes the images in the brain:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"My fourth supposition is that
the power of movement, in fact the nerves, originate in the brain, where
the phantasy is seated; and that the phantasy moves them in various
ways, as the external sense `<organ>`{=html} moves the
`<organ of>`{=html} common sensibility, or as the whole pen is moved by
its tip. This illustration also shows how it is that the phantasy can
cause various movements in the nerves, although it has not images of
these formed in itself, but certain other images, of which these
movements are possible effects. For the pen as a whole does not move in
the same way as its tip; indeed, the greater part of the pen seems to go
along with an altogether different, contrary motion. This enables us to
understand how the movements of all other animals are accomplished,
although we suppose them to have no consciousness (rerum cognitio) but
only a bodily `<organ of>`{=html} phantasy; and furthermore, how it is
that in ourselves those operations are performed which occur without any
aid of reason.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}My fifth and last supposition is
that the power of cognition properly so called is purely spiritual, and
is just as distinct from the body as a whole as blood is from bone or a
hand from an eye; and that it is a single power. Sometimes it receives
images from the common sensibility at the same time as the phantasy
does; sometimes it applies itself to the images preserved in memory;
sometimes it forms new images, and these so occupy the imagination that
often it is not able at the same time to receive ideas from the common
sensibility, or to pass them on to the locomotive power in the way that
the body left to itself -would. \"`</font>`{=html}
Descartes sums up his concept of a point soul seeing forms in the world
via forms in the sensus communis in *Passions of the Soul*, 35:
\"By this means the two images which are in the brain form but one upon
the gland, which, acting immediately upon the soul, causes it to see the
form in the mind\".
### Anatomical and physiological ideas
In his *Treatise on Man* Descartes summarises his ideas on how we
perceive and react to things as well as how consciousness is achieved
anatomically and physiologically. The \'Treatise\' was written at a time
when even galvanic electricity was unknown. The excerpt given below
covers Descartes\' analysis of perception and stimulus-response
processing.
![](Constuddescart1.png "Constuddescart1.png")
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html} \"Thus for example \[in Fig 1\],
if fire A is close to foot B, the tiny parts of this fire (which, as you
know, move about very rapidly) have the power also to move the area of
skin which they touch. In this way they pull the tiny fibre *cc* which
you see attached to it, and simultaneously open the entrance to the pore
*de*, located opposite the point where this fiber terminates - just as
when you pull one end of a string, you cause a bell hanging at the other
end to ring at the same time.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}When the entrance to the pore or
small tube *de* is opened in this way, the animal spirits from cavity F
enter and are carried through it - some to muscles which serve to pull
the foot away from the fire, some to muscles which turn the eyes and
head to look at it, and some to muscles which make the hands move and
the whole body turn in order to protect it.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}Now I maintain that when God
unites a rational soul to this machine (in a way that I intend to
explain later) he will place its principle seat in the brain, and will
make its nature such that the soul will have different sensations
corresponding to the different ways in which the entrances to the pores
in the internal surface of the brain are opened by means of
nerves.`</font>`{=html}
![](Constuddescart2.png "Constuddescart2.png")
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}In order to see clearly how ideas
are formed of the objects which strike the senses, observe in this
diagram \[fig 2\] the tiny fibres 12, 34, 56, and the like, which make
up the optic nerve and stretch from the back of the eye at 1, 3, 5 to
the internal surface of the brain at 2, 4, 6. Now assume that these
fibres are so arranged that if the rays coming, for example, from point
A of the object happen to press upon the back of the eye at point 1,
they pull the whole of fibre 12 and enlarge the opening of the tiny tube
marked 2. In the same way, the rays which come from point B enlarge the
opening of the tiny tube 4, and likewise for the others. We have already
described how, depending on the different ways in which the points 1, 3,
5 are pressed by these rays, a figure is traced on the back of the eye
corresponding to that of the object ABC. Similarly it is obvious that,
depending on the different ways in which the tiny tubes 2, 4, 6 are
opened by the fibres 12, 34, 56 etc., a corresponding figure must also
be traced on the internal surface of the brain.`</font>`{=html}
\.....
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}And note that by \'figures\' I
mean not only things which somehow represent the position of the edges
and surfaces of objects, but also anything which, as I said above, can
give the soul occasion to perceive movement, size, distance, colours,
sounds, smells and other such qualities. And I also include anything
that can make the soul feel pleasure, pain, hunger, thirst, joy, sadness
and other such passions.`</font>`{=html}
\...
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}Now among these figures, it is not
those imprinted on the external sense organs, or on the internal surface
of the brain, which should be taken to be ideas - but only those which
are traced in the spirits on the surface of gland H (*where the seat of
the imagination and the \'common sense\' is located*). That is to say,
it is only the latter figures which should be taken to be the forms or
images which the rational soul united to this machine will consider
directly when it imagines some object or perceives it by the
senses.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}And note that I say \'imagines or
perceives by the senses\'. For I wish to apply the term \'idea\'
generally to all impressions which the spirits can receive as they leave
gland H. These are to be attributed to the \'common\' sense when they
depend on the presence of objects; but they may also proceed from many
other causes (as I shall explain later), and they should then be
attributed to the imagination. \"`</font>`{=html}
The *common sense* is referred to by philosophers as the *senses
communis*. Descartes considered this to be the place where all the
sensations were bound together and proposed the pineal gland for this
role. This was in the days before the concept of \'dominance\' of parts
of the brain had been developed so Descartes reasoned that only a single
organ could host a bound representation.
Notice how Descartes is explicit about ideas being **traced in the
spirits on the surface of the gland**. Notice also how the rational soul
will consider forms on the common sense **directly**.
Descartes believed that animals are not conscious because, although he
thought they possessed the stimulus-response loop in the same way as
humans he believed that they do not possess a soul.
## John Locke (1632-1704)
Locke\'s most important philosophical work on the human mind was \"An
Essay Concerning Human Understanding\" written in 1689. His idea of
perception is summarised in the diagram below:
![](Constudlocke1.png "Constudlocke1.png")
Locke is an Indirect Realist, admitting of external objects but
describing these as represented within the mind. The objects themselves
are thought to have a form and properties that are the *archetype* of
the object and these give rise in the brain and mind to derived copies
called *ektypa*.
Like Descartes, he believes that people have souls that produce
thoughts. Locke considers that sensations make their way from the senses
to the brain where they are laid out for understanding as a \'view\':
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"And if these organs, or the
nerves which are the conduits to convey them from without to their
audience in the brain,- the mind\'s presence-room (as I may so call it)-
are any of them so disordered as not to perform their functions, they
have no postern to be admitted by; no other way to bring themselves into
view, and be perceived by the understanding.\" (Chapter III,
1).`</font>`{=html}
He considers that what is sensed becomes a mental thing: Chapter IX: Of
Perception paragraph 1:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"This is certain, that whatever
alterations are made in the body, if they reach not the mind; whatever
impressions are made on the outward parts, if they are not taken notice
of within, there is no perception. Fire may burn our bodies with no
other effect than it does a billet, unless the motion be continued to
the brain, and there the sense of heat, or idea of pain, be produced in
the mind; wherein consists actual perception. \"`</font>`{=html}
!LockeLocke calls the contents of
consciousness \"ideas\" (cf: Descartes, Malebranche) and regards
sensation, imagination etc. as being similar or even alike. Chapter I:
Of Ideas in general, and their Original:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"1. Idea is the object of
thinking. Every man being conscious to himself that he thinks; and that
which his mind is applied about whilst thinking being the ideas that are
there, it is past doubt that men have in their minds several ideas,-
such as are those expressed by the words whiteness, hardness, sweetness,
thinking, motion, man, elephant, army, drunkenness, and others: it is in
the first place then to be inquired, How he comes by them?
`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}I know it is a received doctrine,
that men have native ideas, and original characters, stamped upon their
minds in their very first being. This opinion I have at large examined
already; and, I suppose what I have said in the foregoing Book will be
much more easily admitted, when I have shown whence the understanding
may get all the ideas it has; and by what ways and degrees they may come
into the mind;- for which I shall appeal to every one\'s own observation
and experience. `</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}2. All ideas come from sensation
or reflection. Let us then suppose the mind to be, as we say, white
paper, void of all characters, without any ideas:- How comes it to be
furnished? Whence comes it by that vast store which the busy and
boundless fancy of man has painted on it with an almost endless variety?
Whence has it all the materials of reason and knowledge? To this I
answer, in one word, from EXPERIENCE. In that all our knowledge is
founded; and from that it ultimately derives itself. Our observation
employed either, about external sensible objects, or about the internal
operations of our minds perceived and reflected on by ourselves, is that
which supplies our understandings with all the materials of thinking.
These two are the fountains of knowledge, from whence all the ideas we
have, or can naturally have, do spring. `</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}3. The objects of sensation one
source of ideas. First, our Senses, conversant about particular sensible
objects, do convey into the mind several distinct perceptions of things,
according to those various ways wherein those objects do affect them.
And thus we come by those ideas we have of yellow, white, heat, cold,
soft, hard, bitter, sweet, and all those which we call sensible
qualities; which when I say the senses convey into the mind, I mean,
they from external objects convey into the mind what produces there
those perceptions. This great source of most of the ideas we have,
depending wholly upon our senses, and derived by them to the
understanding, I call SENSATION.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}4. The operations of our minds,
the other source of them. Secondly, the other fountain from which
experience furnisheth the understanding with ideas is,- the perception
of the operations of our own mind within us, as it is employed about the
ideas it has got;- which operations, when the soul comes to reflect on
and consider, do furnish the understanding with another set of ideas,
which could not be had from things without. And such are perception,
thinking, doubting, believing, reasoning, knowing, willing, and all the
different actings of our own minds;- which we being conscious of, and
observing in ourselves, do from these receive into our understandings as
distinct ideas as we do from bodies affecting our senses. This source of
ideas every man has wholly in himself; and though it be not sense, as
having nothing to do with external objects, yet it is very like it, and
might properly enough be called internal sense. But as I call the other
SENSATION, so I Call this REFLECTION, the ideas it affords being such
only as the mind gets by reflecting on its own operations within itself.
By reflection then, in the following part of this discourse, I would be
understood to mean, that notice which the mind takes of its own
operations, and the manner of them, by reason whereof there come to be
ideas of these operations in the understanding. These two, I say, viz.
external material things, as the objects of SENSATION, and the
operations of our own minds within, as the objects of REFLECTION, are to
me the only originals from whence all our ideas take their beginnings.
The term operations here I use in a large sense, as comprehending not
barely the actions of the mind about its ideas, but some sort of
passions arising sometimes from them, such as is the satisfaction or
uneasiness arising from any thought.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}5. All our ideas are of the one or
the other of these. The understanding seems to me not to have the least
glimmering of any ideas which it doth not receive from one of these two.
External objects furnish the mind with the ideas of sensible qualities,
which are all those different perceptions they produce in us; and the
mind furnishes the understanding with ideas of its own operations.
\"`</font>`{=html}
He calls ideas that come directly from the senses *primary qualities*
and those that come from reflection upon these he calls *secondary
qualities*:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"9. Primary qualities of bodies.
Qualities thus considered in bodies are, First, such as are utterly
inseparable from the body, in what state soever it be; and such as in
all the alterations and changes it suffers, all the force can be used
upon it, it constantly keeps; and such as sense constantly finds in
every particle of matter which has bulk enough to be perceived; and the
mind finds inseparable from every particle of matter, though less than
to make itself singly be perceived by our senses: \...\...\.... These I
call original or primary qualities of body, which I think we may observe
to produce simple ideas in us, viz. solidity, extension, figure, motion
or rest, and number. 10. Secondary qualities of bodies. Secondly, such
qualities which in truth are nothing in the objects themselves but power
to produce various sensations in us by their primary qualities\.....\"
(Chapter VIII).`</font>`{=html}
He gives examples of secondary qualities:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"13. How secondary qualities
produce their ideas. After the same manner, that the ideas of these
original qualities are produced in us, we may conceive that the ideas of
secondary qualities are also produced, viz. by the operation of
insensible particles on our senses. \.....v.g. that a violet, by the
impulse of such insensible particles of matter, of peculiar figures and
bulks, and in different degrees and modifications of their motions,
causes the ideas of the blue colour, and sweet scent of that flower to
be produced in our minds. It being no more impossible to conceive that
God should annex such ideas to such motions, with which they have no
similitude, than that he should annex the idea of pain to the motion of
a piece of steel dividing our flesh, with which that idea hath no
resemblance.\" (Chapter VIII).`</font>`{=html}
He argues against all conscious experience being in mental space (does
not consider that taste might be on the tongue or a smell come from a
cheese): Chapter XIII: Complex Ideas of Simple Modes:- and First, of the
Simple Modes of the Idea of Space - paragraph 25:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"I shall not now argue with those
men, who take the measure and possibility of all being only from their
narrow and gross imaginations: but having here to do only with those who
conclude the essence of body to be extension, because they say they
cannot imagine any sensible quality of any body without extension,- I
shall desire them to consider, that, had they reflected on their ideas
of tastes and smells as much as on those of sight and touch; nay, had
they examined their ideas of hunger and thirst, and several other pains,
they would have found that they included in them no idea of extension at
all, which is but an affection of body, as well as the rest,
discoverable by our senses, which are scarce acute enough to look into
the pure essences of things.\"`</font>`{=html}
Locke understood the \"specious\" or extended present but conflates this
with longer periods of time: Chapter XIV. Idea of Duration and its
Simple Modes - paragraph 1:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Duration is fleeting extension.
There is another sort of distance, or length, the idea whereof we get
not from the permanent parts of space, but from the fleeting and
perpetually perishing parts of succession. This we call duration; the
simple modes whereof are any different lengths of it whereof we have
distinct ideas, as hours, days, years, &c., time and eternity.\"
`</font>`{=html}
Locke is uncertain about whether extended ideas are viewed from an
unextended soul.
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"He that considers how hardly
sensation is, in our thoughts, reconcilable to extended matter; or
existence to anything that has no extension at all, will confess that he
is very far from certainly knowing what his soul is. It is a point which
seems to me to be put out of the reach of our knowledge: and he who will
give himself leave to consider freely, and look into the dark and
intricate part of each hypothesis, will scarce find his reason able to
determine him fixedly for or against the soul\'s materiality. Since, on
which side soever he views it, either as an unextended substance, or as
a thinking extended matter, the difficulty to conceive either will,
whilst either alone is in his thoughts, still drive him to the contrary
side.\"(Chapter III, 6).`</font>`{=html}
## David Hume (1711-1776)
**Hume (1739--40). A Treatise of Human Nature: Being An Attempt to
Introduce the Experimental Method of Reasoning Into Moral Subjects.**
!HumeHume represents a type of pure empiricism
where certainty is only assigned to present experience. As we can only
directly know the mind he works within this constraint. He admits that
there can be consistent bodies of knowledge within experience and would
probably regard himself as an Indirect Realist but with the caveat that
the things that are inferred to be outside the mind, in the physical
world, could be no more than inferences within the mind.
Hume has a clear concept of mental space and time that is informed by
the senses:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"The idea of space is convey\'d
to the mind by two senses, the sight and touch; nor does anything ever
appear extended, that is not either visible or tangible. That compound
impression, which represents extension, consists of several lesser
impressions, that are indivisible to the eye or feeling, and may be
call\'d impressions of atoms or corpuscles endow\'d with colour and
solidity. But this is not all. \'Tis not only requisite, that these
atoms shou\'d be colour\'d or tangible, in order to discover themselves
to our senses; \'tis also necessary we shou\'d preserve the idea of
their colour or tangibility in order to comprehend them by our
imagination. There is nothing but the idea of their colour or
tangibility, which can render them conceivable by the mind. Upon the
removal of the ideas of these sensible qualities, they are utterly
annihilated to the thought or imagination.\'`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}Now such as the parts are, such is
the whole. If a point be not consider\'d as colour\'d or tangible, it
can convey to us no idea; and consequently the idea of extension, which
is compos\'d of the ideas of these points, can never possibly exist. But
if the idea of extension really can exist, as we are conscious it does,
its parts must also exist; and in order to that, must be consider\'d as
colour\'d or tangible. We have therefore no idea of space or extension,
but when we regard it as an object either of our sight or
feeling.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}The same reasoning will prove,
that the indivisible moments of time must be fill\'d with some real
object or existence, whose succession forms the duration, and makes it
be conceivable by the mind.\"`</font>`{=html}
In common with Locke and Eastern Philosophy, Hume considers reflection
and sensation to be similar, perhaps identical:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Thus it appears, that the belief
or assent, which always attends the memory and senses, is nothing but
the vivacity of those perceptions they present; and that this alone
distinguishes them from the imagination. To believe is in this case to
feel an immediate impression of the senses, or a repetition of that
impression in the memory. \'Tis merely the force and liveliness of the
perception, which constitutes the first act of the judgment, and lays
the foundation of that reasoning, which we build upon it, when we trace
the relation of cause and effect.\"`</font>`{=html}
Hume considers that the origin of sensation can never be known,
believing that the canvass of the mind contains our view of the world
whatever the ultimate source of the images within the view and that we
can construct consistent bodies of knowledge within these constraints:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"As to those impressions, which
arise from the senses, their ultimate cause is, in my opinion, perfectly
inexplicable by human reason, and \'twill always be impossible to decide
with certainty, whether they arise immediately from the object, or are
produc\'d by the creative power of the mind, or are deriv\'d from the
author of our being. Nor is such a question any way material to our
present purpose. We may draw inferences from the coherence of our
perceptions, whether they be true or false; whether they represent
nature justly, or be mere illusions of the senses.\"`</font>`{=html}
It may be possible to trace the origins of Jackson\'s Knowledge Argument
in Hume\'s work:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\" Suppose therefore a person to
have enjoyed his sight for thirty years, and to have become perfectly
well acquainted with colours of all kinds, excepting one particular
shade of blue, for instance, which it never has been his fortune to meet
with. Let all the different shades of that colour, except that single
one, be plac\'d before him, descending gradually from the deepest to the
lightest; \'tis plain, that he will perceive a blank, where that shade
is wanting, said will be sensible, that there is a greater distance in
that place betwixt the contiguous colours, than in any other. Now I ask,
whether \'tis possible for him, from his own imagination, to supply this
deficiency, and raise up to himself the idea of that particular shade,
tho\' it had never been conveyed to him by his senses? I believe i here
are few but will be of opinion that he can; and this may serve as a
proof, that the simple ideas are not always derived from the
correspondent impressions; tho\' the instance is so particular and
singular, that \'tis scarce worth our observing, and does not merit that
for it alone we should alter our general maxim.\"`</font>`{=html}
**David Hume (1748) An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding**
Hume\'s view of Locke and Malebranche:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"The fame of Cicero flourishes at
present; but that of Aristotle is utterly decayed. La Bruyere passes the
seas, and still maintains his reputation: But the glory of Malebranche
is confined to his own nation, and to his own age. And Addison, perhaps,
will be read with pleasure, when Locke shall be entirely
forgotten.\"`</font>`{=html}
He is clear about relational knowledge in space and time:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"13. .. But though our thought
seems to possess this unbounded liberty, we shall find, upon a nearer
examination, that it is really confined within very narrow limits, and
that all this creative power of the mind amounts to no more than the
faculty of compounding, transposing, augmenting, or diminishing the
materials afforded us by the senses and experience. When we think of a
golden mountain, we only join two consistent ideas, gold, and mountain,
with which we were formerly acquainted.\"`</font>`{=html}
\...
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}19. Though it be too obvious to
escape observation, that different ideas are connected together; I do
not find that any philosopher has attempted to enumerate or class all
the principles of association; a subject, however, that seems worthy of
curiosity. To me, there appear to be only three principles of connexion
among ideas, namely, Resemblance, Contiguity in time or place, and Cause
or Effect.\"`</font>`{=html}
He is also clear that, although we experience the output of processes,
we do not experience the processes themselves:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"29. It must certainly be
allowed, that nature has kept us at a great distance from all her
secrets, and has afforded us only the knowledge of a few superficial
qualities of objects; while she conceals from us those powers and
principles on which the influence of those objects entirely depends. Our
senses inform us of the colour, weight, and consistence of bread; but
neither sense nor reason can ever inform us of those qualities which fit
it for the nourishment and support of a human body. Sight or feeling
conveys an idea of the actual motion of bodies; but as to that wonderful
force or power, which would carry on a moving body for ever in a
continued change of place, and which bodies never lose but by
communicating it to others; of this we cannot form the most distant
conception. ..`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}58. \... All events seem entirely
loose and separate. One event follows another; but we never can observe
any tie between them. They seem conjoined, but never connected. And as
we can have no idea of any thing which never appeared to our outward
sense or inward sentiment, the necessary conclusion seems to be that we
have no idea of connexion or power at all, and that these words are
absolutely without any meaning, when employed either in philosophical
reasonings or common life. \"`</font>`{=html}
Our idea of process is not a direct experience but seems to originate
from remembering the repetition of events:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"59 ..It appears, then, that this
idea of a necessary connexion among events arises from a number of
similar instances which occur of the constant conjunction of these
events; nor can that idea ever be suggested by any one of these
instances, surveyed in all possible lights and positions. But there is
nothing in a number of instances, different from every single instance,
which is supposed to be exactly similar; except only, that after a
repetition of similar instances, the mind is carried by habit, upon the
appearance of one event, to expect its usual attendant, and to believe
that it will exist.\"`</font>`{=html}
## Emmanuel Kant (1724-1804)
!kantKant\'s greatest work on the subject
of consciousness and the mind is Critique of Pure Reason (1781). Kant
describes his objective in this work as discovering the axioms (\"a
priori concepts\") and then the processes of \'understanding\'.
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}P12 \"This enquiry, which is
somewhat deeply grounded, has two sides. The one refers to the objects
of pure understanding, and is intended to expound and render
intelligible the objective validity of its a priori concepts. It is
therefore essential to my purposes. The other seeks to investigate the
pure understanding itself, its possibility and the cognitive faculties
upon which it rests; and so deals with it in its subjective aspect.
Although this latter exposition is of great importance for my chief
purpose, it does not form an essential part of it. For the chief
question is always simply this: - what and how much can the
understanding and reason know apart from all
experience?\"`</font>`{=html}
Kant\'s idea of perception and mind is summarised in the illustration
below:
![](Constudkant.png "Constudkant.png")
\'Experience\' is simply accepted. Kant believes that the physical world
exists but is not known directly:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}P 24 \"For we are brought to the
conclusion that we can never transcend the limits of possible
experience, though that is precisely what this science is concerned,
above all else, to achieve. This situation yields, however, just the
very experiment by which, indirectly, we are enabled to prove the truth
of this first estimate of our a priori knowledge of reason, namely, that
such knowledge has to do only with appearances, and must leave the thing
in itself as indeed real per se, but as not known by us.
\"`</font>`{=html}
Kant is clear about the form and content of conscious experience. He
notes that we can only experience things that have appearance and
\'form\' - content and geometrical arrangement.
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}P65-66 \"IN whatever manner and by
whatever means a mode of knowledge may relate to objects, intuition is
that through which it is in immediate relation to them, and to which all
thought as a means is directed. But intuition takes place only in so far
as the object is given to us. This again is only possible, to man at
least, in so far as the mind is affected in a certain way. The capacity
(receptivity) for receiving representations through the mode in which we
are affected by objects, is entitled sensibility. Objects are given to
us by means of sensibility, and it alone yields us intuitions; they are
thought through the understanding, and from the understanding arise
concepts. But all thought must, directly or indirectly, by way of
certain characters relate ultimately to intuitions, and therefore, with
us, to sensibility, because in no other way can an object be given to
us. The effect of an object upon the faculty of representation, so far
as we are affected by it, is sensation. That intuition which is in
relation to the object through sensation, is entitled empirical. The
undetermined object of an empirical intuition is entitled appearance.
That in the appearance which corresponds to sensation I term its matter;
but that which so determines the manifold of appearance that it allows
of being ordered in certain relations, I term the form of appearance.
That in which alone the sensations can be posited and ordered in a
certain form, cannot itself be sensation; and therefore, while the
matter of all appearance is given to us a posteriori only, its form must
lie ready for the sensations a priori in the mind, and so must allow of
being considered apart from all sensation. \"`</font>`{=html}
Furthermore he realises that experience exists without much content.
That consciousness depends on form:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}P66 \"The pure form of sensible
intuitions in general, in which all the manifold of intuition is
intuited in certain relations, must be found in the mind a priori. This
pure form of sensibility may also itself be called pure intuition. Thus,
if I take away from the representation of a body that which the
understanding thinks in regard to it, substance, force, divisibility,
etc. , and likewise what belongs to sensation, impenetrability,
hardness, colour, etc. , something still remains over from this
empirical intuition, namely, extension and figure. These belong to pure
intuition, which, even without any actual object of the senses or of
sensation, exists in the mind a priori as a mere form of sensibility.
The science of all principles of a priori sensibility I call
transcendental aesthetic.\"`</font>`{=html}
Kant proposes that space exists in our experience and that experience
could not exist without it (apodeictic means \'incontrovertible):
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}P 68 \"1. Space is not an
empirical concept which has been derived from outer experiences. For in
order that certain sensations be referred to something outside me (that
is, to something in another region of space from that in which I find
myself), and similarly in order that I may be able to represent them as
outside and alongside one another, and accordingly as not only different
but as in different places, the representation of space must be
presupposed. The representation of space cannot, therefore, be
empirically obtained from the relations of outer appearance. On the
contrary, this outer experience is itself possible at all only through
that representation. 2. Space is a necessary a priori representation,
which underlies all outer intuitions. We can never represent to
ourselves the absence of space, though we can quite well think it as
empty of objects. It must therefore be regarded as the condition of the
possibility of appearances, and not as a determina- tion dependent upon
them. It is an a priori representation, which necessarily underlies
outer appearances. \* 3. The apodeictic certainty of all geometrical
propositions and the possibility of their a priori construction is
grounded in this a priori necessity of space.
\...\...\...\"`</font>`{=html}
He is equally clear about the necessity of time as part of experience
but he has no clear exposition of the (specious present) extended
present:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}P 74 \"1. Time is not an empirical
concept that has been derived from any experience. For neither
coexistence nor succession would ever come within our perception, if the
representation of time were not presupposed as underlying them a priori.
Only on the presupposition of time can we represent to ourselves a
number of things as existing at one and the same time (simultaneously)
or at different times (successively). They are connected with the
appearances only as effects accidentally added by the particular
constitution of the sense organs. Accordingly, they are not a priori
representations, but are grounded in sensation, and, indeed, in the case
of taste, even upon feeling (pleasure and pain), as an effect of
sensation. Further, no one can have a priori a representation of a
colour or of any taste; whereas, since space concerns only the pure form
of intuition, and therefore involves no sensation whatsoever, and
nothing empirical, all kinds and determinations of space can and must be
represented a priori, if concepts of figures and of their relations are
to arise. Through space alone is it possible that things should be outer
objects to us. ..2. 3.. 4.. 5\...\"`</font>`{=html}
Kant has a model of experience as a succession of 3D instants, based on
conventional 18th century thinking, allowing his reason to overcome his
observation. He says of time that:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}P 79 \" It is nothing but the form
of our inner intuition. If we take away from our inner intuition the
peculiar condition of our sensibility, the concept of time likewise
vanishes; it does not inhere in the objects, but merely in the subject
which intuits them. I can indeed say that my representations follow one
another; but this is only to say that we are conscious of them as in a
time sequence, that is, in conformity with the form of inner sense. Time
is not, therefore, something in itself, nor is it an objective
determination inherent in things.\"`</font>`{=html}
This analysis is strange because if uses the geometric term \"form\" but
then uses the processing term \"succession\".
## Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716)
!LeibnizLeibniz is one of
the first to notice that there is a problem with the proposition that
computational machines could be conscious:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"One is obliged to admit that
perception and what depends upon it is inexplicable on mechanical
principles, that is, by figures and motions. In imagining that there is
a machine whose construction would enable it to think, to sense, and to
have perception, one could conceive it enlarged while retaining the same
proportions, so that one could enter into it, just like into a windmill.
Supposing this, one should, when visiting within it, find only parts
pushing one another, and never anything by which to explain a
perception. Thus it is in the simple substance, and not in the composite
or in the machine, that one must look for perception.\" Monadology,
17.`</font>`{=html}
Leibniz considered that the world was composed of \"monads\":
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"1. The Monad, of which we shall
here speak, is nothing but a simple substance, which enters into
compounds. By \'simple\' is meant \'without parts.\' (Theod. 10.)
`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}2. And there must be simple
substances, since there are compounds; for a compound is nothing but a
collection or aggregatum of simple things.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}3. Now where there are no parts,
there can be neither extension nor form \[figure\] nor divisibility.
These Monads are the real atoms of nature and, in a word, the elements
of things. \" (Monadology 1714).`</font>`{=html}
These monads are considered to be capable of perception through the
meeting of things at a point:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"They cannot have shapes, because
then they would have parts; and therefore one monad in itself, and at a
moment, cannot be distinguished from another except by its internal
qualities and actions; which can only be its *perceptions* (that is, the
representations of the composite, or of what is external, in the
simple), or its *appetitions* (its tending to move from one perception
to another, that is), which are the principles of change. For the
simplicity of a substance does not in any way rule out a multiplicity in
the modifications which must exist together in one simple substance; and
those modifications must consist in the variety of its relationships to
things outside it - like the way in which in a *centre*, or a *point*,
although it is completely simple, there are an infinity of angles formed
which meet in it.\" (Principles of Nature and Grace
1714).`</font>`{=html}
Leibniz also describes this in his \"New System\":
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"It is only atoms of substance,
that is to say real unities absolutely devoid of parts, that can be the
sources of actions, and the absolute first principles of the composition
of things, and as it were the ultimate elements in the analysis of
substances `<substantial things>`{=html}. They might be called
*metaphysical points*; they have *something of the nature of life* and a
kind of *perception*, and *mathematical points* are their *point of
view* for expressing the universe.\"(New System (11)
1695).`</font>`{=html}
Having identified perception with metaphysical points Leibniz realises
that there is a problem connecting the points with the world (cf:
epiphenomenalism):
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Having decided these things, I
thought I had reached port, but when I set myself to think about the
union of the soul with the body I was as it were carried back into the
open sea. For I could find no way of explaining how the body can make
something pass over into the soul or vice versa, or how one created
substance can communicate with another.\"(New System (12)
1695).`</font>`{=html}
Leibniz devises a theory of \"pre-established harmony\" to overcome this
epiphenomenalism. He discusses how two separate clocks could come to
tell the same time and proposes that this could be due to mutual
influence of one clock on the other (\"the way of influence\"),
continual adjustment by a workman (\"the way of assistance\") or by
making the clocks so well that they are always in agreement (\"the way
of pre-established agreement\" or harmony). He considers each of these
alternatives for harmonising the perceptions with the world and
concludes that only the third is viable:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Thus there remains only my
theory, *the way of pre-established harmony*, set up by a contrivance of
divine foreknowledge, which formed each of these substances from the
outset in so perfect, so regular, and so exact a manner, that merely by
following out its own laws, which were given to it when it was brought
into being, each substance is nevertheless in harmony with the other,
just as if there were a mutual influence between them, or as if in
addition to his general concurrence God were continually operating upon
them. (Third Explanation of the New System (5), 1696).\"`</font>`{=html}
This means that he must explain how perceptions involving the world take
place:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Because of the plenitude of the
world everything is linked, and every body acts to a greater or lesser
extent on every other body in proportion to distance, and is affected by
it in return. It therefore follows that every monad is a living mirror,
or a mirror endowed with internal activity, representing the universe in
accordance with its own point of view, and as orderly as the universe
itself. The perceptions of monads arise one out of another by the laws
of appetite, or of the *final causes of good and evil* (which are
prominent perceptions, orderly or disorderly), just as changes in bodies
or in external phenomena arise one from another by the laws of
*efficient causes*, of motion that is. Thus there is perfect *harmony*
between the perceptions of the monad and the motions of bodies,
pre-established from the outset, between the system of efficient causes
and that of final causes. And it is that harmony that the agreement or
physical union between the soul and body consists, without either of
them being able to change the laws of the other.\" (Principles of Nature
and Grace (3) 1714).`</font>`{=html}
The \"laws of appetite\" are defined as:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"The action of the internal
principle which brings about change, or the passage from one perception
to another, can be called *appetition*. In fact appetite cannot always
attain in its entirety the whole of the perception towards which it
tends, but it always obtains some part of it, and attains new
perceptions. Monadology 15.`</font>`{=html}
Leibniz thought animals had souls but not minds:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"But *true* reasoning depends on
necessary or eternal truths like those of logic, numbers, and geometry,
which make indubitable connections between ideas, and conclusions which
are inevitable. Animals in which such conclusions are never perceived
are called *brutes*; but those which recognise such necessary truths are
what are rightly called *rational animals* and their souls are called
*minds*. (Principles of Nature and Grace (5) 1714).`</font>`{=html}
Minds allow reflection and awareness:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"And it is by the knowledge of
necessary truths, and by the abstractions they involve, that we are
raised to *acts of reflection*, which make us aware of what we call
*myself*, and make us think of this or that thing as in *ourselves*. And
in this way, by thinking of ourselves, we think of being, of substance,
of simples and composites, of the immaterial - and, by realising that
what is limited in us is limitless in him, of God himself. And so these
*acts of reflection* provide the principle objects of our reasonings.\"
Monadology, 30.`</font>`{=html}
## George Berkeley (1685 - 1753)
A Treatise on the Principles of Human Knowledge. 1710
!BerkeleyBerkeley
introduces the Principles of Human Knowledge with a diatribe against
abstract ideas. He uses the abstract ideas of animals as an example:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Introduction. 9\...\.....The
constituent parts of the abstract idea of animal are body, life, sense,
and spontaneous motion. By body is meant body without any particular
shape or figure, there being no one shape or figure common to all
animals, without covering, either of hair, or feathers, or scales, &c.,
nor yet naked: hair, feathers, scales, and nakedness being the
distinguishing properties of particular animals, and for that reason
left out of the abstract idea. Upon the same account the spontaneous
motion must be neither walking, nor flying, nor creeping; it is
nevertheless a motion, but what that motion is it is not easy to
conceive. `</font>`{=html}
He then declares that such abstractions cannot be imagined. He
emphasises that ideas are \"represented to myself\" and have shape and
colour:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Introduction. 10. Whether others
have this wonderful faculty of abstracting their ideas, they best can
tell: for myself, I find indeed I have a faculty of imagining, or
representing to myself, the ideas of those particular things I have
perceived, and of variously compounding and dividing them. I can imagine
a man with two heads, or the upper parts of a man joined to the body of
a horse. I can consider the hand, the eye, the nose, each by itself
abstracted or separated from the rest of the body. But then whatever
hand or eye I imagine, it must have some particular shape and colour.
Likewise the idea of man that I frame to myself must be either of a
white, or a black, or a tawny, a straight, or a crooked, a tall, or a
low, or a middle-sized man. I cannot by any effort of thought conceive
the abstract idea above described. And it is equally impossible for me
to form the abstract idea of motion distinct from the body moving, and
which is neither swift nor slow, curvilinear nor rectilinear; and the
like may be said of all other abstract general ideas
whatsoever.\"`</font>`{=html}
This concept of ideas as extended things, or representations, is typical
of the usage amongst philosophers in the 17th and 18th century and can
cause confusion in modern readers. Berkeley considers that words that
are used to describe classes of things in the abstract can only be
conceived as particular cases:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Introduction. 15\... Thus, when
I demonstrate any proposition concerning triangles, it is to be supposed
that I have in view the universal idea of a triangle; which ought not to
be understood as if I could frame an idea of a triangle which was
neither equilateral, nor scalenon, nor equicrural; but only that the
particular triangle I consider, whether of this or that sort it matters
not, doth equally stand for and represent all rectilinear triangles
whatsoever, and is in that sense universal. All which seems very plain
and not to include any difficulty in it.`</font>`{=html}
Intriguingly, he considers that language is used to directly excite
emotions as well as to communicate ideas:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Introduction. 20. \... I entreat
the reader to reflect with himself, and see if it doth not often happen,
either in hearing or reading a discourse, that the passions of fear,
love, hatred, admiration, disdain, and the like, arise immediately in
his mind upon the perception of certain words, without any ideas coming
between.`</font>`{=html}
Berkeley considers that extension is a quality of mind:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"11. Again, great and small,
swift and slow, are allowed to exist nowhere without the mind, being
entirely relative, and changing as the frame or position of the organs
of sense varies. The extension therefore which exists without the mind
is neither great nor small, the motion neither swift nor slow, that is,
they are nothing at all. But, say you, they are extension in general,
and motion in general: thus we see how much the tenet of extended
movable substances existing without the mind depends on the strange
doctrine of abstract ideas.\" `</font>`{=html}
He notes that the rate at which things pass may be related to the mind:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"14\..... Is it not as reasonable
to say that motion is not without the mind, since if the succession of
ideas in the mind become swifter, the motion, it is acknowledged, shall
appear slower without any alteration in any external object?
`</font>`{=html}
Berkeley raises the issue of whether objects exist without being
perceived. He bases his argument on the concept of perception being the
perceiving of \"our own ideas or sensations\":
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"4. It is indeed an opinion
strangely prevailing amongst men, that houses, mountains, rivers, and in
a word all sensible objects, have an existence, natural or real,
distinct from their being perceived by the understanding. But, with how
great an assurance and acquiescence soever this principle may be
entertained in the world, yet whoever shall find in his heart to call it
in question may, if I mistake not, perceive it to involve a manifest
contradiction. For, what are the fore-mentioned objects but the things
we perceive by sense? and what do we perceive besides our own ideas or
sensations? and is it not plainly repugnant that any one of these, or
any combination of them, should exist unperceived?\"`</font>`{=html}
He further explains this concept in terms of some Eternal Spirit
allowing continued existence. Berkeley is clear that the contents of the
mind have \"colour, figure, motion, smell, taste etc.\":
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"7. From what has been said it
follows there is not any other Substance than Spirit, or that which
perceives. But, for the fuller proof of this point, let it be considered
the sensible qualities are colour, figure, motion, smell, taste, etc.,
i.e. the ideas perceived by sense. Now, for an idea to exist in an
unperceiving thing is a manifest contradiction, for to have an idea is
all one as to perceive; that therefore wherein colour, figure, and the
like qualities exist must perceive them; hence it is clear there can be
no unthinking substance or substratum of those ideas.\"`</font>`{=html}
He elaborates the concept that there is no unthinking substance or
substratum for ideas and all is mind:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"18. But, though it were possible
that solid, figured, movable substances may exist without the mind,
corresponding to the ideas we have of bodies, yet how is it possible for
us to know this? Either we must know it by sense or by reason. As for
our senses, by them we have the knowledge only of our sensations, ideas,
or those things that are immediately perceived by sense, call them what
you will: but they do not inform us that things exist without the mind,
or unperceived, like to those which are perceived. This the materialists
themselves acknowledge. It remains therefore that if we have any
knowledge at all of external things, it must be by reason, inferring
their existence from what is immediately perceived by sense. But what
reason can induce us to believe the existence of bodies without the
mind, from what we perceive, since the very patrons of Matter themselves
do not pretend there is any necessary connexion betwixt them and our
ideas? I say it is granted on all hands (and what happens in dreams,
phrensies, and the like, puts it beyond dispute) that it is possible we
might be affected with all the ideas we have now, though there were no
bodies existing without resembling them. Hence, it is evident the
supposition of external bodies is not necessary for the producing our
ideas; since it is granted they are produced sometimes, and might
possibly be produced always in the same order, we see them in at
present, without their concurrence. \"`</font>`{=html}
and stresses that there is no apparent connection between mind and the
proposed material substrate of ideas:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"19. But, though we might
possibly have all our sensations without them, yet perhaps it may be
thought easier to conceive and explain the manner of their production,
by supposing external bodies in their likeness rather than otherwise;
and so it might be at least probable there are such things as bodies
that excite their ideas in our minds. But neither can this be said; for,
though we give the materialists their external bodies, they by their own
confession are never the nearer knowing how our ideas are produced;
since they own themselves unable to comprehend in what manner body can
act upon spirit, or how it is possible it should imprint any idea in the
mind. \..... `</font>`{=html}
Berkeley makes a crucial observation, that had also been noticed by
Descartes, that ideas are passive:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"25. All our ideas, sensations,
notions, or the things which we perceive, by whatsoever names they may
be distinguished, are visibly inactive- there is nothing of power or
agency included in them. So that one idea or object of thought cannot
produce or make any alteration in another. To be satisfied of the truth
of this, there is nothing else requisite but a bare observation of our
ideas. For, since they and every part of them exist only in the mind, it
follows that there is nothing in them but what is perceived: but whoever
shall attend to his ideas, whether of sense or reflexion, will not
perceive in them any power or activity; there is, therefore, no such
thing contained in them. A little attention will discover to us that the
very being of an idea implies passiveness and inertness in it, insomuch
that it is impossible for an idea to do anything, or, strictly speaking,
to be the cause of anything: neither can it be the resemblance or
pattern of any active being, as is evident from sect. 8. Whence it
plainly follows that extension, figure, and motion cannot be the cause
of our sensations. To say, therefore, that these are the effects of
powers resulting from the configuration, number, motion, and size of
corpuscles, must certainly be false. `</font>`{=html}
He considers that \"the cause of ideas is an incorporeal active
substance or Spirit (26)\".
He summarises the concept of an Eternal Spirit that governs real things
and a representational mind that copies the form of the world as
follows:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"33. The ideas imprinted on the
Senses by the Author of nature are called real things; and those excited
in the imagination being less regular, vivid, and constant, are more
properly termed ideas, or images of things, which they copy and
represent. But then our sensations, be they never so vivid and distinct,
are nevertheless ideas, that is, they exist in the mind, or are
perceived by it, as truly as the ideas of its own framing. The ideas of
Sense are allowed to have more reality in them, that is, to be more
strong, orderly, and coherent than the creatures of the mind; but this
is no argument that they exist without the mind. They are also less
dependent on the spirit, or thinking substance which perceives them, in
that they are excited by the will of another and more powerful spirit;
yet still they are ideas, and certainly no idea, whether faint or
strong, can exist otherwise than in a mind perceiving it.
`</font>`{=html}
Berkeley considers that the concept of distance is a concept in the mind
and also that dreams can be compared directly with sensations:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"42. Thirdly, it will be objected
that we see things actually without or at distance from us, and which
consequently do not exist in the mind; it being absurd that those things
which are seen at the distance of several miles should be as near to us
as our own thoughts. In answer to this, I desire it may be considered
that in a dream we do oft perceive things as existing at a great
distance off, and yet for all that, those things are acknowledged to
have their existence only in the mind.\"`</font>`{=html}
He considers that ideas can be extended without the mind being extended:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"49. Fifthly, it may perhaps be
objected that if extension and figure exist only in the mind, it follows
that the mind is extended and figured; since extension is a mode or
attribute which (to speak with the schools) is predicated of the subject
in which it exists. I answer, those qualities are in the mind only as
they are perceived by it- that is, not by way of mode or attribute, but
only by way of idea; and it no more follows the soul or mind is
extended, because extension exists in it alone, than it does that it is
red or blue, because those colours are on all hands acknowledged to
exist in it, and nowhere else. As to what philosophers say of subject
and mode, that seems very groundless and unintelligible. For instance,
in this proposition \"a die is hard, extended, and square,\" they will
have it that the word die denotes a subject or substance, distinct from
the hardness, extension, and figure which are predicated of it, and in
which they exist. This I cannot comprehend: to me a die seems to be
nothing distinct from those things which are termed its modes or
accidents. And, to say a die is hard, extended, and square is not to
attribute those qualities to a subject distinct from and supporting
them, but only an explication of the meaning of the word die.
`</font>`{=html}
Berkeley proposes that time is related to the succession of ideas:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"98. For my own part, whenever I
attempt to frame a simple idea of time, abstracted from the succession
of ideas in my mind, which flows uniformly and is participated by all
beings, I am lost and embrangled in inextricable difficulties. I have no
notion of it at all, only I hear others say it is infinitely divisible,
and speak of it in such a manner as leads me to entertain odd thoughts
of my existence; since that doctrine lays one under an absolute
necessity of thinking, either that he passes away innumerable ages
without a thought, or else that he is annihilated every moment of his
life, both which seem equally absurd. Time therefore being nothing,
abstracted from the succession of ideas in our minds, it follows that
the duration of any finite spirit must be estimated by the number of
ideas or actions succeeding each other in that same spirit or mind.
Hence, it is a plain consequence that the soul always thinks; and in
truth whoever shall go about to divide in his thoughts, or abstract the
existence of a spirit from its cogitation, will, I believe, find it no
easy task. `</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"99. So likewise when we attempt
to abstract extension and motion from all other qualities, and consider
them by themselves, we presently lose sight of them, and run into great
extravagances. All which depend on a twofold abstraction; first, it is
supposed that extension, for example, may be abstracted from all other
sensible qualities; and secondly, that the entity of extension may be
abstracted from its being perceived. But, whoever shall reflect, and
take care to understand what he says, will, if I mistake not,
acknowledge that all sensible qualities are alike sensations and alike
real; that where the extension is, there is the colour, too, i.e., in
his mind, and that their archetypes can exist only in some other mind;
and that the objects of sense are nothing but those sensations combined,
blended, or (if one may so speak) concreted together; none of all which
can be supposed to exist unperceived.\" `</font>`{=html}
He regards \"spirit\" as something separate from ideas and attempts to
answer the charge that as spirit is not an idea it cannot be known:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"139. But it will be objected
that, if there is no idea signified by the terms soul, spirit, and
substance, they are wholly insignificant, or have no meaning in them. I
answer, those words do mean or signify a real thing, which is neither an
idea nor like an idea, but that which perceives ideas, and wills, and
reasons about them. \....`</font>`{=html}
## Thomas Reid (1710-1796)
!ReidThomas Reid is generally regarded as the
founder of Direct Realism. Reid was a Presbyterian minister for the
living of Newmachar near Aberdeen from 1737. He is explicit about the
\'directness\' of his realism:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"It is therefore acknowledged by
this philosopher to be a natural instinct or prepossession, a universal
and primary opinion of all men, a primary instinct of nature, that the
objects which we immediately perceive by our senses are not images in
our minds, but external objects, and that their existence is independent
of us and our perception. (Thomas Reid Essays, 14)\"`</font>`{=html}
In common with Descartes and Malebranche, Reid considers that the mind
itself is an unextended thing:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\".. I take it for granted, upon
the testimony of common sense, that my mind is a substance-that is, a
permanent subject of thought; and my reason convinces me that it is an
unextended and invisible substance; and hence I infer that there cannot
be in it anything that resembles extension (Inquiry)\".`</font>`{=html}
Reid is also anxious to equate the unextended mind with the soul:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"The soul, without being present
to the images of the things perceived, could not possibly perceive them.
A living substance can only there perceive, where it is present, either
to the things themselves, (as the omnipresent God is to the whole
universe,) or to the images of things, as the soul is in its proper
sensorium.\"`</font>`{=html}
Reid\'s Direct Realism is therefore the idea that the physical objects
in the world are in some way presented directly to a soul. This approach
is known as \"Natural Dualism\".
Reid\'s views show his knowledge of Aristotle\'s ideas:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"When we perceive an object by
our senses, there is, first, some impression made by the object upon the
organ of sense, either immediately, or by means of some medium. By this,
an impression is made upon the brain, in consequence of which we feel
some sensation. \" (Reid 1785)`</font>`{=html}
He differs from Aristotle because he believes that the content of
phenomenal consciousness is things in themselves, not signals derived
from things in the brain. However, he has no idea how such a phenomenon
could occur:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"How a sensation should instantly
make us conceive and believe the existence of an external thing
altogether unlike it, I do not pretend to know; and when I say that the
one suggests the other, I mean not to explain the manner of their
connection, but to express a fact, which everyone may be conscious of
namely, that, by a law of our nature, such a conception and belief
constantly and immediately follow the sensation.\" (Reid
1764).`</font>`{=html}
Reid\'s idea of mind is almost impossible to illustrate because it lacks
sufficient physical definition. It is like naive realism but without any
communication by light between object and observer. Reid was largely
ignored until the rise of modern Direct Realism.
![](Constudreid.png "Constudreid.png")
Reading between the lines, it seems that Reid is voicing the ancient
intuition that the observer and the content of an observation are
directly connected in some way. As will be seen later, this intuition
cannot distinguish between a direct connection with the world itself and
a direct connection with signals from the world beyond the body that are
formed into a virtual reality in the brain.
## References
- Descartes, R. (1628). Rules For The Direction of The Mind.
- Descartes, R. (1637). DISCOURSE ON THE METHOD OF RIGHTLY CONDUCTING
THE REASON, AND SEEKING TRUTH IN THE SCIENCES.
- Descartes, R. (1641). Meditations on First Philosophy.
- Descartes, R. (1664) \"Treatise on Man\". Translated by John
Cottingham, et al. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, Vol. 1
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985) 99-108.
- Kant, I. (1781) Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Norman Kemp Smith
with preface by Howard Caygill. Pub: Palgrave Macmillan.
- Locke, J. (1689). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding
- Reid, T. (1785). Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man. Edited by
Brookes, Derek. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2002.
- Reid, T. (1764). An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of
Common Sense. Edited by Brookes, Derek. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 1997.
- Russell, B. (1945). A History of Western Philosophy. New York: Simon
and Schuster.
**Further Reading**
See: \"Thomas Reid\" at
Wikisource
- Cartesian Conscientia by Robert Hennig
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Description Of Consciousness
*This section presents the empirical idea of consciousness. What
consciousness is like before theories are applied to explain it. It is
based on descriptions from the Historical Review.*
## The definition and description of phenomenal consciousness
What is it like to be conscious? Before embarking on the analysis of
phenomenal consciousness it is important to have a definition of what it
is that we are attempting to explain. The article below considers
empirical descriptions of phenomenal consciousness. It shows that
phenomenal consciousness is the space, time and content of our minds
(where the content contains intuitions and feelings). As will be seen in
later parts of the book not all philosophers and scientists accept that
this \"phenomenal consciousness\" actually exists.
### Introduction
Empirical descriptions of phenomenal consciousness have been available
in Western literature for centuries and in Eastern literature for
millennia. It is often maintained that no-one can define consciousness
but there is a large body of literature that gives a clear empirical
description of it. Perhaps the claim that no-one can define
consciousness is frustration at the fact that no-one can explain
consciousness.
Weiskrantz (1988) asserted that \"Each of us will have his or her own
idea of what, if anything, is meant by consciousness\...\" and that
insisting upon a precise definition would be a mistake. Koch and Crick
(1999) stated that \"Consciousness is a vague term with many usages and
will, in the fullness of time, be replaced by a vocabulary that more
accurately reflects the contribution of different brain processes.\"
But is consciousness really a \"vague term\" and should we each have our
own idea of what it means? The empirical descriptions of Descartes, Kant
and others are summarised below under the headings of space, time,
qualia and awareness. These descriptions show that consciousness is not
a vague term at all.
### Space and Time
Kant (1781) argued that our minds must be capable of representing
objects in space and time. Experiences presuppose space and time as pure
concepts of reason. Without space, objects could not be differentiated
and would have no properties. Without representation in time, the
concepts of succession of events and simultaneity would be unknown to
us. James(1904) also describes experience as extended in space and says
that the idea that \"inner experience is absolutely inextensive seems to
me little short of absurd\". Descartes (1641, Meditation V, 3) was also
clear that imaginings and perceptions are experiences where things are
arranged in space and time: \"In the first place, I distinctly imagine
that quantity which the philosophers commonly call continuous, or the
extension in length, breadth, and depth that is in this quantity, or
rather in the object to which it is attributed. Further, I can enumerate
in it many diverse parts, and attribute to each of these all sorts of
sizes, figures, situations, and local motions; and, in time, I can
assign to each of these motions all degrees of duration.\" Descartes
was, as was so often the case, well ahead of his time by describing
continuity and dimensionality, the factors that define his view of space
as an actual vector space accessible to mathematical and physical
analysis (See section on
Descartes
for a full discussion.)
Gregory (1966) also pointed out that we see things as if they are
projected into space around us. The idea of projection was implicit in
Kant's and Descartes' descriptions, which are from the viewpoint of an
observer looking out at contents of experience, but Gregory is explicit
(although he believes that explanations based on the projection are
absurd).
Kant and Descartes describe consciousness as something extended in time
but it is Clay and James who draw this fully to our attention. James
(1890) quotes E.R. Clay who coined the term \"specious present\" to
describe how we exist for more than a durationless instant and then goes
on to say: \"In short, the practically cognized present is no
knife-edge, but a saddle-back, with a certain breadth of its own on
which we sit perched, and from which we look in two directions into
time. The unit of composition of our perception of time is a duration,
with a bow and a stern, as it were\--a rearward\--and a forward-looking
end. It is only \[p. 610\] as parts of this duration-block that the
relation of succession of one end to the other is perceived. We do not
first feel one end and then feel the other after it, and from the
perception of the succession infer an interval of time between, but we
seem to feel the interval of time as a whole, with its two ends embedded
in it.\" Notice how James' observer is at an instant but the mind is
stretched over time.
James' mental time is probably not the same as physical time. Hermann
Weyl, the Nobel prize-winning physicist, wrote that reality is a
\"four-dimensional continuum which is neither \'time\' nor \'space.\'
Only the consciousness that passes on in one portion of this world
experiences the detached piece which comes to meet it and passes behind
it, as history, that is, as a process that is going forward in time and
takes place in space\" (Weyl 1918). In other words consciousness has a
way of containing events in the same order as they occur in the world
but seems to use a mental time that is different from physical time.
### Qualia
Qualia are types of things that occur in conscious experience. The
colour purple is a good example of a quale (Tye, 1997). Hume (1739)
pointed out of things in the mind that \"\[t\]here is nothing but the
idea of their colour or tangibility, which can render them conceivable
by the mind;\" in other words, qualia might be things in the mind rather
than attributes. Qualia appear to be exceptional and inexplicable:
Churchland (1988) writes \"How on earth can a feeling of pain result
from ions passing across a membrane?\" Descartes (Meditations VI, 6,
1641) clearly describes qualia.
### Awareness
Descartes, Locke, Hume, Reid and Kant describe conscious phenomena as if
there is an observer in their mind looking out at qualia or feeling
qualia in the space and time around about. Descartes and Kant thought
that the mind must also contain a conceptualisation or intuition of the
meaning of its space, time and content so that the qualia become grouped
into objects, the objects into events and the events into meaning and
expectation.
As Kant put it, we have \"intuitions\" about the relations between
things. In modern parlance our conscious experience appears to contain
the output from an unconscious processor; although Kant\'s term,
\"intuition,\" is a more scientific approach because it is an
observation without assumptions about causes. If the present is extended
in time, or a \"specious\" present as Clay put it, then many moments are
available through which it is possible to apprehend both a question and
its answer: the processor can frame the question and provide the answer.
The observation that our minds extend through time means that this
processor does not need to be recursive to provide the outputs we
experience as intuitions (one moment can contain an intuition about
another whilst both are in the mind).
Descartes (Meditations VI, 10, 1641) considered the origin of
intuitions: \"Further, I cannot doubt but that there is in me a certain
passive faculty of perception, that is, of receiving and taking
knowledge of the ideas of sensible things; but this would be useless to
me, if there did not also exist in me, or in some other thing, another
active faculty capable of forming and producing those ideas. But this
active faculty cannot be in me \[in as far as I am but a thinking
thing\], seeing that it does not presuppose thought, and also that those
ideas are frequently produced in my mind without my contributing to it
in any way, and even frequently contrary to my will.\" Descartes
suspected that the ideas were formed unconsciously, probably in the
brain.
### Types of Consciousness
It is sometimes held that there are many types of consciousness, Antony
(2001) lists: phenomenal consciousness, access consciousness, state
consciousness, creature consciousness, introspective consciousness and
self-consciousness. Antony takes the view that these are all
\'modulations\' of the term consciousness and do not mean that there are
in fact different types of consciousness. In other words these \'types
of consciousness\' are modulations of the intuition of content arranged
in space and time that is the singular consciousness described by Kant
and Descartes. According to this explanation access consciousness is the
time extended form of processes in phenomenal consciousness,
self-consciousness is the time extended form of bodily processes and
inner speech etc.. As an example, if we say a word then think it
soundlessly it is evident that inner speech is whole, time extended
words coming from the vague direction of the vocal chords (or both
ears), when we move a limb much of the whole movement is present in our
experience as a set of displacements at the position of the limb and
extended through time.
The nature of consciousness as described above, i.e. phenomenal or
subjective consciousness, must be distinguished from the type of
consciousness used in Medical clinical states. Clinical consciousness is
determined partly by the ascending reticular activating system (ARAS) in
the brain stem extending into higher anatomic levels of the brain
including the cortex. Alerting or arousal is the function of the ARAS
and is the doorway to awareness. Failure of this system or its
components results in clinical states ranging from a temporary loss of
consciousness as noted in head injuries (concussion) all the way to
complete coma. The comatose state includes failure of eye opening to
stimulation, a motor response more than just simple reflex withdrawal
movements and lack of verbalization. Coma can be produced by structural
lesions of the brain, metabolic and nutritional disorders, exogenous
toxins, central nervous system infections, seizures, temperature-related
extremes (e.g. hypothermia or hyperthermia) and most commonly trauma.
Included in this extreme are such entities as persistent vegetative
state and the minimally conscious state. The gamut ranges through
stupor, prolonged concussion, and transient concussion. This use of the
term 'consciousness' is not the nature of 'consciousness' as used in
this article and must be distinguished as such.
### Observations and Denials
There can be little doubt that most descriptions of conscious
phenomenology have described the same things although some have used
terms such as \'continuity\' for time and \'representation\' for space.
Our conscious experiences are the experience of being an observer that
has qualia distributed in space and time around a point. This experience
is imbued with intuitions.
Contrary to the views of Weiskrantz and of Koch and Crick there seems to
be no need to await a definition of consciousness. It has been described
for centuries. So why did these authors feel a need to suspend any
definition?
The answer is that over the years there has been no widely accepted
theory of how this empirical consciousness could occur. This led certain
philosophers such as Ryle (1949) to question whether the description of
consciousness was credible.
In most cases this sceptical analysis begins with an explanatory
discussion of consciousness such as: if information travels from the
observation to the observer then the observer contains the information
so there must be another observer within to observe this second set of
information. In this case the conclusion is that this implies an
impossible homunculus or Ryle's \"ghost in the machine\" so observation
and observer's cannot occur in the mind. This is an interesting argument
but it can also be framed to give exactly the opposite result. The
scientific form of the argument would be: the observed form of conscious
experience cannot occur if it relies on information transfer, therefore
the hypothesis that information transfer is all that is required to
explain consciousness is wrong and some other explanation is needed.
(This means that although the content of consciousness is derived from
the senses via signals in neurones, conscious experience is not these
signals flowing into a nexus). In science the observation is paramount
and cannot be discarded because it conflicts with theory.
The process of discounting an observation when an explanation fails also
applies to other aspects of consciousness studies. As Gregory (1988) put
it: \" \'If you can't explain it -- deny it\' is one strategy for
dealing with embarrassing questions such as \'what is consciousness?\'
\". If we discount these denials then the empirical observations of Kant
and Descartes and the other empiricists are the bedrock of consciousness
studies and consciousness can indeed be described as an observation
containing the space, time and content of our minds (where the content
contains intuitions and feelings).
This simple definition of the experience we call consciousness is
internally consistent and can be expressed in mathematical language.
Phenomenal consciousness is a multidimensional manifold with vectors
pointing towards the centre (the apparent observation point). The
content can be both the input and output of processors that are external
to the manifold.
*Adapted from the article The description and definition of
consciousness by
Alex Green in Science and Consciousness Review
(with permission of the author).*
A non-mathematical description of consciousness is: a collection of
events arranged in time and space that form directed elements that all
point at the same place and instant.
### The viewing point and the observer
Green\'s summary of phenomenal consciousness deserves further
elaboration and description. Science begins with empirical descriptions.
To experience phenomenal consciousness simply lean back with your eyes
open and listen. Phenomenal consciousness is the observational space and
time that is occurring and the simultaneous things within it that point
at the apparent viewing point. It includes bodily sensations, inner
speech and the smell on and around things etc. Phenomenal consciousness
is experience itself. If the experience is a lucid dream it may contain
a fantastical image, if it is a perception it may contain information
about something in the world beyond the body. Experience is not usually
an experience **of** the content of experience, experience is already
there, arranged in space and time (see note below).
![](constudgreen1.gif "constudgreen1.gif") The illustrations show the
difference between an actual 3D part of the world, 2D representations of
that part of the world, conscious experience itself and naive realism.
It is well known that a 3D object cannot be shown on a 2D surface. Its
form is specified as sets of coordinates.
![](constudgreen2.gif "constudgreen2.gif")Most visual experiences are
arranged as views. Views are represented on paper using perspective
drawings. Pictures that use perspective are scaled images of the world
as it would appear on the retina of one eye.
![](constudgreen3.gif "constudgreen3.gif")In experience itself things
are arranged as things directed at a point (vectors). Nothing flows into
the point. Experience is a manifold of events that are loosely based on
data from the retinas and other sense organs. It has contents like the
drawing on paper but instead of being a collection of ink particles
confined to 2D it is a set of vectors directed at a point.
![](constudgreen4.gif "constudgreen4.gif")Experience also involves
things arranged in time. Things can be simultaneous and there is
continuity. Arrangements in time are independent of arrangements in
space. The phonemes of a word do not overlap each other and the stages
of a movement do not create a smear. These independent arrangements in
time are akin to the way that things that are arranged left and right do
not overlap things that are arranged up and down. Left and right are
independent of up and down. In a similar way, time seems to be an
independent direction for arranging things.
![](constudgreen5.gif "constudgreen5.gif")Our experience differs from
naive realism. In naive realism experience is believed to be an
impossible physical meeting of light rays at a single point in the eye
that through some unspecified mechanism project back to their source.
**Naive realism is a primitive dynamical interpretation of experience**,
an attempt to explain an empirical geometrical form in terms of flows of
matter. In contrast, in experience there seems to be a set of vectors
directed at a point.
![](constudgreen6.gif "constudgreen6.gif") An intriguing feature of the
empirical form of experience is that things seem to be separated by
angular separations. This allows objects of any size to be represented
and explains how a page of text on our laps and the dome of a
planetarium can be encompassed in the same form.
The apparent viewing point has caused considerable difficulty for many
empiricist philosophers (although the British Empiricists tended to
avoid it). When philosophers have stopped describing conscious
experience and tried to explain the viewing point they have often
resorted to the supernatural: Descartes, Malebranche and Reid all
explained the viewing point in terms of a supernatural soul at a point
that does the seeing or experiencing. But none of the empiricists
describe anything flowing into the viewing point; indeed nothing does
flow or could flow into and through a point. The empirical truth is that
the viewing point is a geometrical phenomenon, not the recipient of some
simultaneous flow of everything in experience. Just look, your viewing
point is where everything in experience is directed but things are not
pouring into it and it, itself, is a point, it cannot and does not
contain anything. This seems to be Aristotle\'s insight when he wrote
\"In every case the mind which is actively thinking is the objects which
it thinks.\"
The field of vectors that are the content of consciousness are also
difficult to interpret; some philosophers believe that they are in the
brain and form a representation of the world whilst others believe that
they are directly attached to things in the world beyond the body.
The empirical description of consciousness allows us to make a sharp
distinction between the scientific activities of measurement and
observation. Measurement is the change in state of a measuring
instrument in response to an event in the environment. Observation is
the occurrence of events in the geometrical manifold that we call our
conscious experience.
This section has used the descriptions provided by generations of
philosophers to characterise the **phenomenon** of consciousness. Many
modern philosophers assume that readers are familiar with these
empirical descriptions and use \"what it is like to be conscious\" as a
shorthand for these empirical reports. From the seventeenth century
onwards it was realised that these descriptions are difficult to explain
using Newtonian physics or elementary information theory.
`<font size=1>`{=html}\* Note: the term \"experience of\" should be
reserved for things that act as a source of the content of experience,
such as the QM fields that constitute the things that are sensed. We
have an \"experience of\" a flower when signals from the flower are
composed into the form of a flower in our experience. Sometimes there is
an \"experience of\" the content of consciousness, for instance when
intuitions about the content occur. See later modules for a
discussion.`</font>`{=html}
### References
- Antony,M.V. Is \'Consciousness\' Ambiguous? Journal of Consciousness
Studies 8(2), 2001, 19-44.
<http://research.haifa.ac.il/~antony/papers/Ambiguous.htm>
- Block, N. 1995. On a Confusion about a Function of Consciousness,
The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18, 2 (June 1995): 227-247.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000231/00/199712004.html>
- Churchland, P.S. 1988. Reduction and the neurobiological basis of
consciousness. Chapter 14 in Consciousness in Contemporary Science.
(Editors: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E.). Oxford Science
Publications.
- Descartes, R. 1641. Meditations on First Philosophy
<http://www.orst.edu/instruct/phl302/texts/descartes/meditations/meditations.html>
- James, W. 1890. The Principles of Psychology
<http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/James/Principles/prin15.htm>
- James, W. 1904. Does consciousness exist? Journal of Philosophy,
Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1, 477-491.
<http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/James/consciousness.htm>
- Gregory, R.L. 1966. Eye and Brain. London: Weidenfield and Nicolson.
- Gregory, R.L. 1988. Consciousness in science and philosophy:
conscience and con-science. Chapter 12 in Consciousness in
Contemporary Science. (Editors: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E.).
Oxford Science Publications.
- Kant, I. 1781. The Transcendental Aesthetic. Critique of Pure
Reason. Tr. Norman Kemp-Smith. Macmillan Press Ltd.
<http://www.arts.cuhk.edu.hk/Philosophy/Kant/cpr/cpr-open.html> See
also this link <http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/k/kantmeta.htm>
- Koch, C and Crick, F. 1999. 116, Consciousness, neural basis of.
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/Elsevier-NCC.html>
- McGinn, C. 1995. Consciousness and Space. In: Conscious Experience,
Thomas Metzinger (Ed). 1995, Imprint Academic.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/courses/consciousness97/papers/ConsciousnessSpace.html>
- Ryle, G. 1949. The Concept of Mind. Hutchinson & Co. London.
- Tye, M. 1997. Qualia, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia>
- Weiskrantz, L. 1988. Some contributions of neuropsychology of vision
and memory to the problem of consciousness. Chapter 8 in
Consciousness in Contemporary Science. (Editors: Marcel, A.J. and
Bisiach, E.). Oxford Science Publications.
- Weyl, H. 1918. Space Time Matter. Dover Edition 1952, p. 217.
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Conflict
*This section is about how regression and recursion seem to undermine
the idea of conscious experience being anywhere in the universe.*.
## The conflict - supervenience and the location of the contents of phenomenal consciousness
When we touch something or look at a view what we are probably touching
or seeing is a thing in the world, out there, beyond our bodies. Many
philosophers and almost all scientists would agree with this surmise.
But is our conscious experience itself directly the things we touch or
more like a picture of those things on television or something else
entirely? Furthermore, can we really be certain that what we believe we
experience truly occurs?
Suppose for the moment that our experience truly does occur and consists
of things laid out in time and space. Conscious experience appears to be
a simultaneous set of things (i.e.: things arranged in space) but where
are these things and what is this space? The things that occur in
conscious experience could be a virtual reality in the brain based on
the world beyond the body, or they could be the things themselves,
viewed directly through some unknown phenomenon or it has even been
suggested that they could be something non-physical.
The problem of where the contents of conscious experience are located
has provoked some of the fiercest battles in the philosophy of
consciousness. There are three broad positions, the first is Direct
Realism in which it is held that the contents of conscious experience
are directly things in the world, the second is Indirect Realism where
it is proposed that the contents of conscious experience are
representations, usually in the physical brain, based on things \'out
there\' in the world and the third is idealism where it is held that
there is no physical world, only non-physical conscious experience.
These three classifications overlap considerably, for instance some
Natural Dualists believe that the contents of sensory experience are
directly the world beyond the body but some thoughts are based in a
non-physical soul and some philosophers introduce the dualist notion of
a \"logical space\" containing disembodied information.
Philosophers often use the concept of \'supervenience\' to examine the
location of the contents of consciousness. Supervenience is the relation
between two sets of properties. Supervenience can be simple; for example
a golden ring supervenes on a piece of the metal gold. Supervenience can
also be quite complex such as the idea that life supervenes on the
biological processes in a cell. The most difficult cases of
supervenience are where a high level description is related to simpler
physical properties such as form and content. There are formal
statements of supervenience:
`The properties of A supervene on the properties of B if no two possible`\
`situations are identical with respect to the properties of A while`\
`differing with respect to the properties of B (after Chalmers 1996).`
Lewis gives a simpler, if less technical, definition of supervenience:
`A dot-matrix picture has global properties -- it is symmetrical, `\
`it is cluttered, and whatnot -- and yet all there is to the picture `\
`is dots and non-dots at each point of the matrix. The global `\
`properties are nothing but patterns in the dots. They supervene: no `\
`two pictures could differ in their global properties without `\
`differing, somewhere, in whether there is or there isn't a dot". `\
`Lewis, D., 1986, On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford: Blackwell`
One set of properties is said to supervene *locally* on another set of
properties if the second set is determined by the first. Shape is an
example of local supervenience; for instance a gold wire forged in a
circle determines a gold ring. A set of properties is said to supervene
*globally* on another if the entire context of the properties must be
included; for instance, two organisms could be physically identical but
demonstrate different behaviours in different environments. In this case
the physical form of an organism does not totally determine the
behaviour. Philosophers also divide supervenience into logical
supervenience and natural supervenience. Logical supervenience deals
with possible relations in possible worlds while natural supervenience
deals with relations that occur in the natural world.
See elementary information
theory
for a discussion of supervenience in information systems.
A particular problem posed by consciousness studies is whether conscious
phenomenal experience supervenes on the physical world and, if so,
where. To answer these questions philosophers and neuroscientists must
have a good understanding of physics. They should be aware of elementary
physical ontology such as kinetic energy being the relativistic mass
increase of a particle in a four dimensional universe and Newton\'s laws
being due to the exploration of all paths in space-time. Without a good
knowledge of physics there is the danger that we will be asking whether
phenomenal consciousness supervenes on an abstract model of the world
which does not supervene on the world itself (i.e.: *we may be asking if
conscious phenomenal experience supervenes on Newtonian physics or
supervenes on information systems theory rather than asking how
phenomenal consciousness might supervene on the natural world*).
The possibility that conscious experience does not really occur, at
least in the form that we believe it occurs, is known as the problem of
the \"Incorrigibility of the cogito\" (Harrison 1984). If Descartes\'
idea that \"I think therefore I am\" is not beyond question
(incorrigible) then the idea of phenomenal consciousness may be
incorrect.
(See for instance:
Special relativity for beginners
Special relativity for
beginners
Quantum physics explains Newton's laws of motion
<http://www.eftaylor.com/pub/OgbornTaylor.pdf> )
## The problem of regression
The philosopher Gilbert Ryle was concerned with what he called the
intellectualist legend which requires intelligent acts to be the product
of the conscious application of mental rules. The intellectualist legend
is also known as the \"Dogma of the Ghost in the Machine,\" the
\"Two-Lives Legend,\" the \"Two-Worlds Story,\" or the \"Double-Life
Legend\". Ralph Waldo Emerson summarised the intellectualist legend in
the statement that \"The ancestor of every action is a thought.\" Ryle
argued against the idea that every action requires a conscious thought
and showed that this \'intellectualist legend\' results in an infinite
regress of thought:
`"According to the legend, whenever an agent does anything `\
`intelligently, his act is preceded and steered by another internal `\
`act of considering a regulative proposition appropriate to his `\
`practical problem. [...] Must we then say that for the hero's `\
`reflections how to act to be intelligent he must first reflect how `\
`best to reflect how to act? The endlessness of this implied regress `\
`shows that the application of the criterion of appropriateness does `\
`not entail the occurrence of a process of considering this criterion."`\
`(The Concept of Mind (1949)) `
image:constudregress.gif
`"The crucial objection to the intellectualist legend is this. The `\
`consideration of propositions is itself an operation the execution `\
`of which can be more or less intelligent, less or more stupid. But if, `\
`for any operation to be intelligently executed, a prior theoretical `\
`operation had first to be performed and performed intelligently, it `\
`would be a logical impossibility for anyone ever to break into the `\
`circle." `
Variants of Ryle\'s regress are commonly aimed at cognitivist theories.
For instance, in order to explain the behavior of rats, Edward Tolman
suggested that the rats were constructing a \"cognitive map\" that
helped them locate reinforcers, and he used intentional terms (e.g.,
expectancies, purposes, meanings) to describe their behavior. This led
to a famous attack on Tolman\'s work by Guthrie who pointed out that if
one was implying that every action must be preceded by a cognitive
\'action\' (a \'thought\' or \'schema\' or \'script\' or whatever), then
what \'causes\' this act? Clearly it must be preceded by another
cognitive action, which must in turn must be preceded by another and so
on, in an infinite regress unless an external input occurs at some
stage.
As a further example, we may take note of the following statement from
The Concept of Mind (1949):
\"The main object of this chapter is to show that there are many
activities which directly display qualities of mind, yet are neither
themselves intellectual operations nor yet effects of intellectual
operations. Intelligent practice is not a step-child of theory. On the
contrary theorizing is one practice amongst others and is itself
intelligently or stupidly conducted.\"
Ryle noted that \"theorizing is one practice amongst others.\" and hence
would translate the statement by Emerson into, \"The ancestor of every
action is an action.\" or \"The ancestor of every behavior is a
behavior,\". Each behaviour would require yet another behavior to
preface it as its ancestor, and an infinite regress would occur.
It should be noted that Ryle's regress is a critique of cognitivism
which arises from the Behaviorist tradition. Near the end of The Concept
of Mind, Ryle states, \"The Behaviorists' methodological program has
been of revolutionary importance to the program of psychology. But more,
it has been one of the main sources of the philosophical suspicion that
the two-worlds story is a myth.\" But Ryle's brand of logical
behaviorism is not to be confused with the radical behaviorism of B. F.
Skinner or the methodological behaviorism of John B. Watson. For as Alex
Byrne noted, \"Ryle was indeed, as he reportedly said, 'only one arm and
one leg a behaviorist'.\"
Arguments that involve regress are well known in philosophy. In fact any
reflexive, or self referencing process or argument will involve a
regress if there is no external input. This applies whether the agent
that engages in the process is a digital computer or intelligent agent
(cf: Smith (1986), Yates (1991)).
Ryle\'s regress suggests that intelligent acts are not created within
phenomenal consciousness. They may have non-conscious components or even
be entirely non-conscious. Ryle argued that this might mean that
consciousness is just a \"ghost in the machine\" of the brain because
consciousness would be epiphenomenal if it is not the creator of
intelligent acts. However, as will be seen below, this conclusion may be
premature and certainly cannot be used to dismiss phenomenal
consciousness as non-existent or not present in the brain.
## The Subject-Object paradox
This paradox was clearly enunciated by William James in 1904:
\"Throughout the history of philosophy the subject and its object have
been treated as absolutely discontinuous entities; and thereupon the
presence of the latter to the former, or the \'apprehension\' by the
former of the latter, has assumed a paradoxical character which all
sorts of theories had to be invented to overcome.\" James (1904).
The Subject-Object paradox points out that a conscious subject appears
to observe itself as an object. But if it observes itself as an object
then, as an object it cannot be a subject. As Bermudez(1998) puts it:
\"Any theory that tries to elucidate the capacity to think first-person
thoughts through linguistic mastery of the first-person pronoun will be
circular, because the explanandum is part of the explanans..\"
Thomas Reid uses this paradox to suggest that everything that is
observed must be external to the soul and hence proposed that experience
was the world itself.
Wittgenstein (1949) offers a way out of the paradox by denying the
existence of the subject:
`<span style="font-family:times new roman;">`{=html}\"5.63 1. The
thinking, presenting subject; there is no such thing. If I wrote a book
The World as I Found It, I should also have therein to report on my body
and say which members obey my will and which do not, etc. This then
would be a method of isolating the subject or rather of showing that in
an important sense there is no subject: that is to say, of it alone in
this book mention could not be made. 5.632. The subject does not belong
to the world but it is a limit of the world. 5.633. Where in the world
is a metaphysical subject to be noted? You say that this case is
altogether like that of the eye and the field of sight. But you do not
really see the eye. And from nothing in the field of sight can it be
concluded that it is seen from an eye\... 5.64 1. \...The philosophical
I is not the man, not the human body or the human soul of which
psychology treats, but the metaphysical subject, the limit --- not a
part of the world.\"`</span>`{=html}(Wittgenstein 1949).
Wittgenstein\'s view is similar to that voiced by Green (2002) in which
there is nothing at the point centre of the manifold of events (there is
no point eye). James (1904), Lektorsky (1980) and many others have also
attempted to resolve the paradox by proposing that there is really no
observer, only the observation or \'reflexive act\' of perception. This
idea reaches its zenith in Brentano\'s concept of \"intentionality\" in
which the subject and object are fused into a form of \"aboutness\":
`<span style="font-family:times new roman;">`{=html}\"Every psychical
phenomenon is characterized by what the Scholastics of the Middle Ages
called the intentional (or sometimes the mental) inexistence of an
object, and what we should like to call, although not quite
unambiguously, the reference (Beziehung) to a content, the directedness
(Richtung) toward an object (which in this context is not to be
understood as something real) or the immanent-object quality (immanente
Gegenständlichkeit). Each contains something as its object, though not
each in the same manner. In the representation (Vorstellung) something
is represented, in the judgment something is acknowledged or rejected,
in desiring it is desired, etc. This intentional inexistence is peculiar
alone to psychical phenomena. No physical phenomenon shows anything like
it. And thus we can define psychical phenomena by saying that they are
such phenomena as contain objects in themselves by way of intention
(intentional).\"`</span>`{=html} Brentano, F. (1874).
These authors have all identified the content of perception with either
the world itself, the manifold of events or a synthetic \'about\' the
world itself in an attempt at avoiding the paradox, however, as will be
seen later, there are other solutions to the paradox.
Bermúdez, J. (1998), The Paradox of Self-Consciousness, Bradford/MIT
Press.
Brentano, F. (1874). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. Vol1.
<http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/philosophy/works/ge/brentano.htm>
William James (1904). A World of Pure Experience. First published in
Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1, 533-543,
561-570. <http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/James/experience.htm>
## The homunculus fallacy in philosophy of mind
A Homunculus argument accounts for a phenomenon in terms of the very
phenomenon that it is supposed to explain (Richard Gregory (1987)).
Homunculus arguments are always fallacious. In the psychology and
philosophy of mind \'homunculus arguments\' are extremely useful for
detecting where theories of mind fail or are incomplete.
Homunculus arguments are common in the theory of vision. Imagine a
person watching a movie. He sees the images as something separate from
himself, projected on the screen. How is this done? A simple theory
might propose that the light from the screen forms an image on the
retinas in the eyes and something in the brain looks at these as if they
are the screen. The Homunculus Argument shows this is not a full
explanation because all that has been done is to place an entire person,
or homunculus, behind the eye who gazes at the retinas. A more
sophisticated argument might propose that the images on the retinas are
transferred to the visual cortex where it is scanned. Again this cannot
be a full explanation because all that has been done is to place a
little person in the brain behind the cortex. In the theory of vision
the Homunculus Argument invalidates theories that do not explain
\'projection\', the experience that the viewing point is separate from
the things that are seen. (Adapted from Gregory (1987), (1990)).
In the case of vision it is sometimes suggested that each homunculus
would need a homunculus inside it ad infinitum. This is the
**recursion** form of the homunculus concept. Notice that, unlike the
case of regress, the recursion would occur after the event.
An homunculus argument should be phrased in such a way that the
conclusion is always that if a homunculus is required then the theory is
wrong. After all, homunculi do not exist.
Very few people would propose that there actually is a little man in the
brain looking at brain activity. However, this proposal has been used as
a \'straw man\' in theories of mind. Gilbert Ryle (1949) proposed that
the human mind is known by its intelligent acts. (see Ryle\'s Regress).
He argued that if there is an inner being inside the brain that could
steer its own thoughts then this would lead to an absurd repetitive
cycle or \'regress\' before a thought could occur:
\"According to the legend, whenever an agent does anything
intelligently, his act is preceded and steered by another internal act
of considering a regulative proposition appropriate to his practical
problem.\"
\"\.... Must we then say that for the ..\[agent\'s\].. reflections how
to act to be intelligent he must first reflect how best to reflect how
to act? The endlessness of this implied regress shows that the
application of the appropriateness does not entail the occurrence of a
process of considering this criterion.\"
The homunculus argument and the regress argument are often considered to
be the same but this is not the case. The homunculus argument says that
if there is a need for a \'little man\' to complete a theory then the
theory is wrong. The regress argument says that an intelligent agent
would need to think before it could have a thought.
Ryle\'s theory is that intelligent acts cannot be a property of an inner
being or mind, if such a thing were to exist.
The idea that conscious experience is a flow of information into an
unextended place (a point eye) leaves itself open to the charge of
inserting an homunculus beyond the point eye. On careful reading few, if
any, real theories actually propose a flow through the point eye but
suggest some sort of nebulous direct relation with the information in
front of the eye. For instance, Descartes has a point soul directly
considering the contents of the common sense and Reid has a point eye
directly considering the world itself.
`<span style="font-size:x-small;">`{=html}Questions: It might be said
that the homunculus fallacy means that either the materialist
interpretation of conscious experience is wrong or conscious experience
does not exist: discuss. Physicalism is not materialism, discuss. Could
physical phenomena such as entanglement or space-time theories of
observation, where the observed vectors are constrained to the manifold,
avoid the homunculus fallacy?`</span>`{=html}
## Berkeley\'s \"passive ideas\"
Ryle\'s regress, when applied to consciousness, is based on an analysis
of conscious intellectual activity as a succession of states. At any
moment the conscious intellect contains one state such as \'I will think
of a word\'. This means that either the state has just popped into mind
or there was a previous state that gave rise to it such as \'I will
think of thinking of a word\'. Descartes and other empiricists have
noted that thoughts do indeed just pop into mind. So if we transfer
Ryle\'s analysis to the real world we discover that the regress is
avoided by removing the starting point of a series of thoughts from
conscious phenomenal experience. A train of thought just begins, it has
no conscious origin and Descartes\' implication is that it has probably
been synthesised non-consciously.
Suppose Descartes and our own experience are correct, suppose thoughts
do just pop into mind, if this happens can there still be a conscious
intellectual agent or are intellectual agents largely non-conscious? One
of the simplest intellectual processes is a test for equality i.e.:
\'does A equal B?\' and a routing of flow as a result of the test i.e.:
\'if A = B then goto\'. Can an intellectual agent perform an equality
test in conscious phenomenal experience?
Consider the test of whether \'A = A\', you attend to the left \'A\'
then the right \'A\' and declare them equal. What have you actually
done? The feeling that the symbols are equal just pops into mind.
Psychologists and philosophers use the word \'intuition\' for this
popping of answers into mind (Kant 1781). It is usually accompanied by
emotional experience (Damasio 1994, Bierman 2004).
If intellectual activity is actually a succession of things that just
pop into phenomenal consciousness then Ryle\'s conclusion that
phenomenal consciousness is like a \"ghost in the machine\" of the brain
would to some extent justified. Phenomenal consciousness would not be
intellectual activity. Phenomenal consciousness would contain the
stages, or succession of states, of intellectual activity but would not
contain the processes that connect these stages. This observation that
conscious experience is a succession of **passive ideas** is well known
in philosophy (cf: George Berkeley, Principles of Human Knowledge, 25).
## More on the conflict
Click above for more on Phenomenal consciousness, access consciousness,
Direct Realism, Indirect Realism, Dualism, Idealism and Panpsychism.
## References
- Harrison, J. (1984). The incorrigibility of the cogito. Mind: New
Series, Vol. 93, No. XCIII, 1984.
The problem of regression
- Ryle, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind. The University of Chicago
Press, 1949.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Smith, Q. (1986). The infinite regress of temporal attributions. The
Southern Journal of Philosophy (1986) Vol. XXIV, No. 3, 383 (Section
3).
<http://web.archive.org/web/20060507144913/http://www.qsmithwmu.com/the_infinite_regress.htm>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Yates, S. (1991). Self referential arguments in philosophy. Reason
Papers 16. (Fall 1991) 133-164.
<http://www.mises.org/reasonpapers/pdf/16/rp_16_7.pdf>
The homunculus argument
- Gregory, R.L. (1990) Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing, Oxford
University Press Inc. New York.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gregory, T.L. (1987). The Oxford Companion to Mind. Oxford
University Press.
Subject-object paradox
- James, W. (1904)Does \'Consciousness\' Exist? Journal of
Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1,
477-491.
- Hegel, G.W.F. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND: SECTION I. MIND SUBJECTIVE B.
PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND CONSCIOUSNESS Part Three of the Encyclopaedia
of the Philosophical
Sciences
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Velmans, M. (1996) Consciousness and the \"Casual Paradox\".
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 19 (3):
538-542.
- \[Bermudez, J.L. (1999) The Paradox of Self-Consciousness
(representation and Mind) Psycoloquy:
10,#35
Ontological status
- Bierman, D.J. (2004) Non Conscious Processes Preceding Intuitive
decisions
<http://m0134.fmg.uva.nl/~djb/publications/2004/Intuition_bialsymp2004.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Damasio, A.R. (1994). Descartes\' error: Emotion, reason and the
human brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam Book.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason
<http://www.arts.cuhk.edu.hk/Philosophy/Kant/cpr/>
Direct Realism
- Aydede, M. (2001) Naturalism, introspection, and direct realism
about pain. Consciousness and Emotion, Vol. 2, No. 1, 2001, pp.
29-73.
<http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/maydede/pain.pdf>
- Chapman, C.R., and Y. Nakamura (1999). A Passion of the Soul: An
Introduction to Pain for Consciousness Researchers. Consciousness
and Cognition, 8: 391-422.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Fowler C A (1986): "An event approach to the study of speech
perception from a direct-realist perspective", J of Phonetics
14(1):3-28.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gibson, J. J. (1966) The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems.
Houghton Mifflin Company,Boston.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gibson, J. J. (1979) Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Hillsdate.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gregory, R.L. 1988. Consciousness in science and philosophy:
conscience and con-science. Chapter 12 in Consciousness in
Contemporary Science. (Editors: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E.).
Oxford Science Publications.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Le Morvan, Pierre (2004). Arguments against direct realism and how
to counter them. *The American Philosophical Quarterly*, *41*(3),
221-234.\] (pdf) <http://www.tcnj.edu/~lemorvan/DR_web.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Oliveira, André L. G. and Oliveira, Luis F. (2002) Toward an
ecological conception of timbre. In Proceedings Auditory Perception
Cognition and Action Meeting 2002, Kansas City.
<http://cogprints.org/2713/>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Skinner, B. F. Science and Human Behavior . New York: Macmillan,
1953.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Skinner, B. F. 1971. Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New York: Knopf.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Skinner, B. F. 1948. Walden Two. New York: Macmillan.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tye, M. (2004). ANOTHER LOOK AT REPRESENTATIONALISM ABOUT PAIN.
Consciousness and Emotion 2004, special issue on pain, edited by
Murat Aydede (with replies by M. Aydede, N. Block, B. Maund, and P.
Noordhof
<http://sun.soci.niu.edu/~phildept/MT/RepresentationalismAndPain.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Vygotsky, L.S.(1925) Consciousness as a problem in the psychology of
behavior. Undiscovered Vygotsky: Etudes on the pre-history of
cultural-historical psychology (European Studies in the History of
Science and Ideas. Vol. 8), pp. 251-281. Peter Lang Publishing.
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/1925/consciousness.htm>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Ziff, Paul. \"About Behaviourism.\" Analysis 18 (1958): 132-136.
Quoted by Larry Hauser in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/b/behavior.htm#B>. F. Skinner:
Radical Behaviorism
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Conflict#The regression argument
*This section is about how regression and recursion seem to undermine
the idea of conscious experience being anywhere in the universe.*.
## The conflict - supervenience and the location of the contents of phenomenal consciousness
When we touch something or look at a view what we are probably touching
or seeing is a thing in the world, out there, beyond our bodies. Many
philosophers and almost all scientists would agree with this surmise.
But is our conscious experience itself directly the things we touch or
more like a picture of those things on television or something else
entirely? Furthermore, can we really be certain that what we believe we
experience truly occurs?
Suppose for the moment that our experience truly does occur and consists
of things laid out in time and space. Conscious experience appears to be
a simultaneous set of things (i.e.: things arranged in space) but where
are these things and what is this space? The things that occur in
conscious experience could be a virtual reality in the brain based on
the world beyond the body, or they could be the things themselves,
viewed directly through some unknown phenomenon or it has even been
suggested that they could be something non-physical.
The problem of where the contents of conscious experience are located
has provoked some of the fiercest battles in the philosophy of
consciousness. There are three broad positions, the first is Direct
Realism in which it is held that the contents of conscious experience
are directly things in the world, the second is Indirect Realism where
it is proposed that the contents of conscious experience are
representations, usually in the physical brain, based on things \'out
there\' in the world and the third is idealism where it is held that
there is no physical world, only non-physical conscious experience.
These three classifications overlap considerably, for instance some
Natural Dualists believe that the contents of sensory experience are
directly the world beyond the body but some thoughts are based in a
non-physical soul and some philosophers introduce the dualist notion of
a \"logical space\" containing disembodied information.
Philosophers often use the concept of \'supervenience\' to examine the
location of the contents of consciousness. Supervenience is the relation
between two sets of properties. Supervenience can be simple; for example
a golden ring supervenes on a piece of the metal gold. Supervenience can
also be quite complex such as the idea that life supervenes on the
biological processes in a cell. The most difficult cases of
supervenience are where a high level description is related to simpler
physical properties such as form and content. There are formal
statements of supervenience:
`The properties of A supervene on the properties of B if no two possible`\
`situations are identical with respect to the properties of A while`\
`differing with respect to the properties of B (after Chalmers 1996).`
Lewis gives a simpler, if less technical, definition of supervenience:
`A dot-matrix picture has global properties -- it is symmetrical, `\
`it is cluttered, and whatnot -- and yet all there is to the picture `\
`is dots and non-dots at each point of the matrix. The global `\
`properties are nothing but patterns in the dots. They supervene: no `\
`two pictures could differ in their global properties without `\
`differing, somewhere, in whether there is or there isn't a dot". `\
`Lewis, D., 1986, On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford: Blackwell`
One set of properties is said to supervene *locally* on another set of
properties if the second set is determined by the first. Shape is an
example of local supervenience; for instance a gold wire forged in a
circle determines a gold ring. A set of properties is said to supervene
*globally* on another if the entire context of the properties must be
included; for instance, two organisms could be physically identical but
demonstrate different behaviours in different environments. In this case
the physical form of an organism does not totally determine the
behaviour. Philosophers also divide supervenience into logical
supervenience and natural supervenience. Logical supervenience deals
with possible relations in possible worlds while natural supervenience
deals with relations that occur in the natural world.
See elementary information
theory
for a discussion of supervenience in information systems.
A particular problem posed by consciousness studies is whether conscious
phenomenal experience supervenes on the physical world and, if so,
where. To answer these questions philosophers and neuroscientists must
have a good understanding of physics. They should be aware of elementary
physical ontology such as kinetic energy being the relativistic mass
increase of a particle in a four dimensional universe and Newton\'s laws
being due to the exploration of all paths in space-time. Without a good
knowledge of physics there is the danger that we will be asking whether
phenomenal consciousness supervenes on an abstract model of the world
which does not supervene on the world itself (i.e.: *we may be asking if
conscious phenomenal experience supervenes on Newtonian physics or
supervenes on information systems theory rather than asking how
phenomenal consciousness might supervene on the natural world*).
The possibility that conscious experience does not really occur, at
least in the form that we believe it occurs, is known as the problem of
the \"Incorrigibility of the cogito\" (Harrison 1984). If Descartes\'
idea that \"I think therefore I am\" is not beyond question
(incorrigible) then the idea of phenomenal consciousness may be
incorrect.
(See for instance:
Special relativity for beginners
Special relativity for
beginners
Quantum physics explains Newton's laws of motion
<http://www.eftaylor.com/pub/OgbornTaylor.pdf> )
## The problem of regression
The philosopher Gilbert Ryle was concerned with what he called the
intellectualist legend which requires intelligent acts to be the product
of the conscious application of mental rules. The intellectualist legend
is also known as the \"Dogma of the Ghost in the Machine,\" the
\"Two-Lives Legend,\" the \"Two-Worlds Story,\" or the \"Double-Life
Legend\". Ralph Waldo Emerson summarised the intellectualist legend in
the statement that \"The ancestor of every action is a thought.\" Ryle
argued against the idea that every action requires a conscious thought
and showed that this \'intellectualist legend\' results in an infinite
regress of thought:
`"According to the legend, whenever an agent does anything `\
`intelligently, his act is preceded and steered by another internal `\
`act of considering a regulative proposition appropriate to his `\
`practical problem. [...] Must we then say that for the hero's `\
`reflections how to act to be intelligent he must first reflect how `\
`best to reflect how to act? The endlessness of this implied regress `\
`shows that the application of the criterion of appropriateness does `\
`not entail the occurrence of a process of considering this criterion."`\
`(The Concept of Mind (1949)) `
image:constudregress.gif
`"The crucial objection to the intellectualist legend is this. The `\
`consideration of propositions is itself an operation the execution `\
`of which can be more or less intelligent, less or more stupid. But if, `\
`for any operation to be intelligently executed, a prior theoretical `\
`operation had first to be performed and performed intelligently, it `\
`would be a logical impossibility for anyone ever to break into the `\
`circle." `
Variants of Ryle\'s regress are commonly aimed at cognitivist theories.
For instance, in order to explain the behavior of rats, Edward Tolman
suggested that the rats were constructing a \"cognitive map\" that
helped them locate reinforcers, and he used intentional terms (e.g.,
expectancies, purposes, meanings) to describe their behavior. This led
to a famous attack on Tolman\'s work by Guthrie who pointed out that if
one was implying that every action must be preceded by a cognitive
\'action\' (a \'thought\' or \'schema\' or \'script\' or whatever), then
what \'causes\' this act? Clearly it must be preceded by another
cognitive action, which must in turn must be preceded by another and so
on, in an infinite regress unless an external input occurs at some
stage.
As a further example, we may take note of the following statement from
The Concept of Mind (1949):
\"The main object of this chapter is to show that there are many
activities which directly display qualities of mind, yet are neither
themselves intellectual operations nor yet effects of intellectual
operations. Intelligent practice is not a step-child of theory. On the
contrary theorizing is one practice amongst others and is itself
intelligently or stupidly conducted.\"
Ryle noted that \"theorizing is one practice amongst others.\" and hence
would translate the statement by Emerson into, \"The ancestor of every
action is an action.\" or \"The ancestor of every behavior is a
behavior,\". Each behaviour would require yet another behavior to
preface it as its ancestor, and an infinite regress would occur.
It should be noted that Ryle's regress is a critique of cognitivism
which arises from the Behaviorist tradition. Near the end of The Concept
of Mind, Ryle states, \"The Behaviorists' methodological program has
been of revolutionary importance to the program of psychology. But more,
it has been one of the main sources of the philosophical suspicion that
the two-worlds story is a myth.\" But Ryle's brand of logical
behaviorism is not to be confused with the radical behaviorism of B. F.
Skinner or the methodological behaviorism of John B. Watson. For as Alex
Byrne noted, \"Ryle was indeed, as he reportedly said, 'only one arm and
one leg a behaviorist'.\"
Arguments that involve regress are well known in philosophy. In fact any
reflexive, or self referencing process or argument will involve a
regress if there is no external input. This applies whether the agent
that engages in the process is a digital computer or intelligent agent
(cf: Smith (1986), Yates (1991)).
Ryle\'s regress suggests that intelligent acts are not created within
phenomenal consciousness. They may have non-conscious components or even
be entirely non-conscious. Ryle argued that this might mean that
consciousness is just a \"ghost in the machine\" of the brain because
consciousness would be epiphenomenal if it is not the creator of
intelligent acts. However, as will be seen below, this conclusion may be
premature and certainly cannot be used to dismiss phenomenal
consciousness as non-existent or not present in the brain.
## The Subject-Object paradox
This paradox was clearly enunciated by William James in 1904:
\"Throughout the history of philosophy the subject and its object have
been treated as absolutely discontinuous entities; and thereupon the
presence of the latter to the former, or the \'apprehension\' by the
former of the latter, has assumed a paradoxical character which all
sorts of theories had to be invented to overcome.\" James (1904).
The Subject-Object paradox points out that a conscious subject appears
to observe itself as an object. But if it observes itself as an object
then, as an object it cannot be a subject. As Bermudez(1998) puts it:
\"Any theory that tries to elucidate the capacity to think first-person
thoughts through linguistic mastery of the first-person pronoun will be
circular, because the explanandum is part of the explanans..\"
Thomas Reid uses this paradox to suggest that everything that is
observed must be external to the soul and hence proposed that experience
was the world itself.
Wittgenstein (1949) offers a way out of the paradox by denying the
existence of the subject:
`<span style="font-family:times new roman;">`{=html}\"5.63 1. The
thinking, presenting subject; there is no such thing. If I wrote a book
The World as I Found It, I should also have therein to report on my body
and say which members obey my will and which do not, etc. This then
would be a method of isolating the subject or rather of showing that in
an important sense there is no subject: that is to say, of it alone in
this book mention could not be made. 5.632. The subject does not belong
to the world but it is a limit of the world. 5.633. Where in the world
is a metaphysical subject to be noted? You say that this case is
altogether like that of the eye and the field of sight. But you do not
really see the eye. And from nothing in the field of sight can it be
concluded that it is seen from an eye\... 5.64 1. \...The philosophical
I is not the man, not the human body or the human soul of which
psychology treats, but the metaphysical subject, the limit --- not a
part of the world.\"`</span>`{=html}(Wittgenstein 1949).
Wittgenstein\'s view is similar to that voiced by Green (2002) in which
there is nothing at the point centre of the manifold of events (there is
no point eye). James (1904), Lektorsky (1980) and many others have also
attempted to resolve the paradox by proposing that there is really no
observer, only the observation or \'reflexive act\' of perception. This
idea reaches its zenith in Brentano\'s concept of \"intentionality\" in
which the subject and object are fused into a form of \"aboutness\":
`<span style="font-family:times new roman;">`{=html}\"Every psychical
phenomenon is characterized by what the Scholastics of the Middle Ages
called the intentional (or sometimes the mental) inexistence of an
object, and what we should like to call, although not quite
unambiguously, the reference (Beziehung) to a content, the directedness
(Richtung) toward an object (which in this context is not to be
understood as something real) or the immanent-object quality (immanente
Gegenständlichkeit). Each contains something as its object, though not
each in the same manner. In the representation (Vorstellung) something
is represented, in the judgment something is acknowledged or rejected,
in desiring it is desired, etc. This intentional inexistence is peculiar
alone to psychical phenomena. No physical phenomenon shows anything like
it. And thus we can define psychical phenomena by saying that they are
such phenomena as contain objects in themselves by way of intention
(intentional).\"`</span>`{=html} Brentano, F. (1874).
These authors have all identified the content of perception with either
the world itself, the manifold of events or a synthetic \'about\' the
world itself in an attempt at avoiding the paradox, however, as will be
seen later, there are other solutions to the paradox.
Bermúdez, J. (1998), The Paradox of Self-Consciousness, Bradford/MIT
Press.
Brentano, F. (1874). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. Vol1.
<http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/philosophy/works/ge/brentano.htm>
William James (1904). A World of Pure Experience. First published in
Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1, 533-543,
561-570. <http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/James/experience.htm>
## The homunculus fallacy in philosophy of mind
A Homunculus argument accounts for a phenomenon in terms of the very
phenomenon that it is supposed to explain (Richard Gregory (1987)).
Homunculus arguments are always fallacious. In the psychology and
philosophy of mind \'homunculus arguments\' are extremely useful for
detecting where theories of mind fail or are incomplete.
Homunculus arguments are common in the theory of vision. Imagine a
person watching a movie. He sees the images as something separate from
himself, projected on the screen. How is this done? A simple theory
might propose that the light from the screen forms an image on the
retinas in the eyes and something in the brain looks at these as if they
are the screen. The Homunculus Argument shows this is not a full
explanation because all that has been done is to place an entire person,
or homunculus, behind the eye who gazes at the retinas. A more
sophisticated argument might propose that the images on the retinas are
transferred to the visual cortex where it is scanned. Again this cannot
be a full explanation because all that has been done is to place a
little person in the brain behind the cortex. In the theory of vision
the Homunculus Argument invalidates theories that do not explain
\'projection\', the experience that the viewing point is separate from
the things that are seen. (Adapted from Gregory (1987), (1990)).
In the case of vision it is sometimes suggested that each homunculus
would need a homunculus inside it ad infinitum. This is the
**recursion** form of the homunculus concept. Notice that, unlike the
case of regress, the recursion would occur after the event.
An homunculus argument should be phrased in such a way that the
conclusion is always that if a homunculus is required then the theory is
wrong. After all, homunculi do not exist.
Very few people would propose that there actually is a little man in the
brain looking at brain activity. However, this proposal has been used as
a \'straw man\' in theories of mind. Gilbert Ryle (1949) proposed that
the human mind is known by its intelligent acts. (see Ryle\'s Regress).
He argued that if there is an inner being inside the brain that could
steer its own thoughts then this would lead to an absurd repetitive
cycle or \'regress\' before a thought could occur:
\"According to the legend, whenever an agent does anything
intelligently, his act is preceded and steered by another internal act
of considering a regulative proposition appropriate to his practical
problem.\"
\"\.... Must we then say that for the ..\[agent\'s\].. reflections how
to act to be intelligent he must first reflect how best to reflect how
to act? The endlessness of this implied regress shows that the
application of the appropriateness does not entail the occurrence of a
process of considering this criterion.\"
The homunculus argument and the regress argument are often considered to
be the same but this is not the case. The homunculus argument says that
if there is a need for a \'little man\' to complete a theory then the
theory is wrong. The regress argument says that an intelligent agent
would need to think before it could have a thought.
Ryle\'s theory is that intelligent acts cannot be a property of an inner
being or mind, if such a thing were to exist.
The idea that conscious experience is a flow of information into an
unextended place (a point eye) leaves itself open to the charge of
inserting an homunculus beyond the point eye. On careful reading few, if
any, real theories actually propose a flow through the point eye but
suggest some sort of nebulous direct relation with the information in
front of the eye. For instance, Descartes has a point soul directly
considering the contents of the common sense and Reid has a point eye
directly considering the world itself.
`<span style="font-size:x-small;">`{=html}Questions: It might be said
that the homunculus fallacy means that either the materialist
interpretation of conscious experience is wrong or conscious experience
does not exist: discuss. Physicalism is not materialism, discuss. Could
physical phenomena such as entanglement or space-time theories of
observation, where the observed vectors are constrained to the manifold,
avoid the homunculus fallacy?`</span>`{=html}
## Berkeley\'s \"passive ideas\"
Ryle\'s regress, when applied to consciousness, is based on an analysis
of conscious intellectual activity as a succession of states. At any
moment the conscious intellect contains one state such as \'I will think
of a word\'. This means that either the state has just popped into mind
or there was a previous state that gave rise to it such as \'I will
think of thinking of a word\'. Descartes and other empiricists have
noted that thoughts do indeed just pop into mind. So if we transfer
Ryle\'s analysis to the real world we discover that the regress is
avoided by removing the starting point of a series of thoughts from
conscious phenomenal experience. A train of thought just begins, it has
no conscious origin and Descartes\' implication is that it has probably
been synthesised non-consciously.
Suppose Descartes and our own experience are correct, suppose thoughts
do just pop into mind, if this happens can there still be a conscious
intellectual agent or are intellectual agents largely non-conscious? One
of the simplest intellectual processes is a test for equality i.e.:
\'does A equal B?\' and a routing of flow as a result of the test i.e.:
\'if A = B then goto\'. Can an intellectual agent perform an equality
test in conscious phenomenal experience?
Consider the test of whether \'A = A\', you attend to the left \'A\'
then the right \'A\' and declare them equal. What have you actually
done? The feeling that the symbols are equal just pops into mind.
Psychologists and philosophers use the word \'intuition\' for this
popping of answers into mind (Kant 1781). It is usually accompanied by
emotional experience (Damasio 1994, Bierman 2004).
If intellectual activity is actually a succession of things that just
pop into phenomenal consciousness then Ryle\'s conclusion that
phenomenal consciousness is like a \"ghost in the machine\" of the brain
would to some extent justified. Phenomenal consciousness would not be
intellectual activity. Phenomenal consciousness would contain the
stages, or succession of states, of intellectual activity but would not
contain the processes that connect these stages. This observation that
conscious experience is a succession of **passive ideas** is well known
in philosophy (cf: George Berkeley, Principles of Human Knowledge, 25).
## More on the conflict
Click above for more on Phenomenal consciousness, access consciousness,
Direct Realism, Indirect Realism, Dualism, Idealism and Panpsychism.
## References
- Harrison, J. (1984). The incorrigibility of the cogito. Mind: New
Series, Vol. 93, No. XCIII, 1984.
The problem of regression
- Ryle, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind. The University of Chicago
Press, 1949.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Smith, Q. (1986). The infinite regress of temporal attributions. The
Southern Journal of Philosophy (1986) Vol. XXIV, No. 3, 383 (Section
3).
<http://web.archive.org/web/20060507144913/http://www.qsmithwmu.com/the_infinite_regress.htm>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Yates, S. (1991). Self referential arguments in philosophy. Reason
Papers 16. (Fall 1991) 133-164.
<http://www.mises.org/reasonpapers/pdf/16/rp_16_7.pdf>
The homunculus argument
- Gregory, R.L. (1990) Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing, Oxford
University Press Inc. New York.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gregory, T.L. (1987). The Oxford Companion to Mind. Oxford
University Press.
Subject-object paradox
- James, W. (1904)Does \'Consciousness\' Exist? Journal of
Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1,
477-491.
- Hegel, G.W.F. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND: SECTION I. MIND SUBJECTIVE B.
PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND CONSCIOUSNESS Part Three of the Encyclopaedia
of the Philosophical
Sciences
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Velmans, M. (1996) Consciousness and the \"Casual Paradox\".
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 19 (3):
538-542.
- \[Bermudez, J.L. (1999) The Paradox of Self-Consciousness
(representation and Mind) Psycoloquy:
10,#35
Ontological status
- Bierman, D.J. (2004) Non Conscious Processes Preceding Intuitive
decisions
<http://m0134.fmg.uva.nl/~djb/publications/2004/Intuition_bialsymp2004.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Damasio, A.R. (1994). Descartes\' error: Emotion, reason and the
human brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam Book.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason
<http://www.arts.cuhk.edu.hk/Philosophy/Kant/cpr/>
Direct Realism
- Aydede, M. (2001) Naturalism, introspection, and direct realism
about pain. Consciousness and Emotion, Vol. 2, No. 1, 2001, pp.
29-73.
<http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/maydede/pain.pdf>
- Chapman, C.R., and Y. Nakamura (1999). A Passion of the Soul: An
Introduction to Pain for Consciousness Researchers. Consciousness
and Cognition, 8: 391-422.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Fowler C A (1986): "An event approach to the study of speech
perception from a direct-realist perspective", J of Phonetics
14(1):3-28.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gibson, J. J. (1966) The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems.
Houghton Mifflin Company,Boston.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gibson, J. J. (1979) Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Hillsdate.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gregory, R.L. 1988. Consciousness in science and philosophy:
conscience and con-science. Chapter 12 in Consciousness in
Contemporary Science. (Editors: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E.).
Oxford Science Publications.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Le Morvan, Pierre (2004). Arguments against direct realism and how
to counter them. *The American Philosophical Quarterly*, *41*(3),
221-234.\] (pdf) <http://www.tcnj.edu/~lemorvan/DR_web.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Oliveira, André L. G. and Oliveira, Luis F. (2002) Toward an
ecological conception of timbre. In Proceedings Auditory Perception
Cognition and Action Meeting 2002, Kansas City.
<http://cogprints.org/2713/>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Skinner, B. F. Science and Human Behavior . New York: Macmillan,
1953.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Skinner, B. F. 1971. Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New York: Knopf.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Skinner, B. F. 1948. Walden Two. New York: Macmillan.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tye, M. (2004). ANOTHER LOOK AT REPRESENTATIONALISM ABOUT PAIN.
Consciousness and Emotion 2004, special issue on pain, edited by
Murat Aydede (with replies by M. Aydede, N. Block, B. Maund, and P.
Noordhof
<http://sun.soci.niu.edu/~phildept/MT/RepresentationalismAndPain.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Vygotsky, L.S.(1925) Consciousness as a problem in the psychology of
behavior. Undiscovered Vygotsky: Etudes on the pre-history of
cultural-historical psychology (European Studies in the History of
Science and Ideas. Vol. 8), pp. 251-281. Peter Lang Publishing.
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/1925/consciousness.htm>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Ziff, Paul. \"About Behaviourism.\" Analysis 18 (1958): 132-136.
Quoted by Larry Hauser in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/b/behavior.htm#B>. F. Skinner:
Radical Behaviorism
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Conflict#The subject-object paradox
*This section is about how regression and recursion seem to undermine
the idea of conscious experience being anywhere in the universe.*.
## The conflict - supervenience and the location of the contents of phenomenal consciousness
When we touch something or look at a view what we are probably touching
or seeing is a thing in the world, out there, beyond our bodies. Many
philosophers and almost all scientists would agree with this surmise.
But is our conscious experience itself directly the things we touch or
more like a picture of those things on television or something else
entirely? Furthermore, can we really be certain that what we believe we
experience truly occurs?
Suppose for the moment that our experience truly does occur and consists
of things laid out in time and space. Conscious experience appears to be
a simultaneous set of things (i.e.: things arranged in space) but where
are these things and what is this space? The things that occur in
conscious experience could be a virtual reality in the brain based on
the world beyond the body, or they could be the things themselves,
viewed directly through some unknown phenomenon or it has even been
suggested that they could be something non-physical.
The problem of where the contents of conscious experience are located
has provoked some of the fiercest battles in the philosophy of
consciousness. There are three broad positions, the first is Direct
Realism in which it is held that the contents of conscious experience
are directly things in the world, the second is Indirect Realism where
it is proposed that the contents of conscious experience are
representations, usually in the physical brain, based on things \'out
there\' in the world and the third is idealism where it is held that
there is no physical world, only non-physical conscious experience.
These three classifications overlap considerably, for instance some
Natural Dualists believe that the contents of sensory experience are
directly the world beyond the body but some thoughts are based in a
non-physical soul and some philosophers introduce the dualist notion of
a \"logical space\" containing disembodied information.
Philosophers often use the concept of \'supervenience\' to examine the
location of the contents of consciousness. Supervenience is the relation
between two sets of properties. Supervenience can be simple; for example
a golden ring supervenes on a piece of the metal gold. Supervenience can
also be quite complex such as the idea that life supervenes on the
biological processes in a cell. The most difficult cases of
supervenience are where a high level description is related to simpler
physical properties such as form and content. There are formal
statements of supervenience:
`The properties of A supervene on the properties of B if no two possible`\
`situations are identical with respect to the properties of A while`\
`differing with respect to the properties of B (after Chalmers 1996).`
Lewis gives a simpler, if less technical, definition of supervenience:
`A dot-matrix picture has global properties -- it is symmetrical, `\
`it is cluttered, and whatnot -- and yet all there is to the picture `\
`is dots and non-dots at each point of the matrix. The global `\
`properties are nothing but patterns in the dots. They supervene: no `\
`two pictures could differ in their global properties without `\
`differing, somewhere, in whether there is or there isn't a dot". `\
`Lewis, D., 1986, On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford: Blackwell`
One set of properties is said to supervene *locally* on another set of
properties if the second set is determined by the first. Shape is an
example of local supervenience; for instance a gold wire forged in a
circle determines a gold ring. A set of properties is said to supervene
*globally* on another if the entire context of the properties must be
included; for instance, two organisms could be physically identical but
demonstrate different behaviours in different environments. In this case
the physical form of an organism does not totally determine the
behaviour. Philosophers also divide supervenience into logical
supervenience and natural supervenience. Logical supervenience deals
with possible relations in possible worlds while natural supervenience
deals with relations that occur in the natural world.
See elementary information
theory
for a discussion of supervenience in information systems.
A particular problem posed by consciousness studies is whether conscious
phenomenal experience supervenes on the physical world and, if so,
where. To answer these questions philosophers and neuroscientists must
have a good understanding of physics. They should be aware of elementary
physical ontology such as kinetic energy being the relativistic mass
increase of a particle in a four dimensional universe and Newton\'s laws
being due to the exploration of all paths in space-time. Without a good
knowledge of physics there is the danger that we will be asking whether
phenomenal consciousness supervenes on an abstract model of the world
which does not supervene on the world itself (i.e.: *we may be asking if
conscious phenomenal experience supervenes on Newtonian physics or
supervenes on information systems theory rather than asking how
phenomenal consciousness might supervene on the natural world*).
The possibility that conscious experience does not really occur, at
least in the form that we believe it occurs, is known as the problem of
the \"Incorrigibility of the cogito\" (Harrison 1984). If Descartes\'
idea that \"I think therefore I am\" is not beyond question
(incorrigible) then the idea of phenomenal consciousness may be
incorrect.
(See for instance:
Special relativity for beginners
Special relativity for
beginners
Quantum physics explains Newton's laws of motion
<http://www.eftaylor.com/pub/OgbornTaylor.pdf> )
## The problem of regression
The philosopher Gilbert Ryle was concerned with what he called the
intellectualist legend which requires intelligent acts to be the product
of the conscious application of mental rules. The intellectualist legend
is also known as the \"Dogma of the Ghost in the Machine,\" the
\"Two-Lives Legend,\" the \"Two-Worlds Story,\" or the \"Double-Life
Legend\". Ralph Waldo Emerson summarised the intellectualist legend in
the statement that \"The ancestor of every action is a thought.\" Ryle
argued against the idea that every action requires a conscious thought
and showed that this \'intellectualist legend\' results in an infinite
regress of thought:
`"According to the legend, whenever an agent does anything `\
`intelligently, his act is preceded and steered by another internal `\
`act of considering a regulative proposition appropriate to his `\
`practical problem. [...] Must we then say that for the hero's `\
`reflections how to act to be intelligent he must first reflect how `\
`best to reflect how to act? The endlessness of this implied regress `\
`shows that the application of the criterion of appropriateness does `\
`not entail the occurrence of a process of considering this criterion."`\
`(The Concept of Mind (1949)) `
image:constudregress.gif
`"The crucial objection to the intellectualist legend is this. The `\
`consideration of propositions is itself an operation the execution `\
`of which can be more or less intelligent, less or more stupid. But if, `\
`for any operation to be intelligently executed, a prior theoretical `\
`operation had first to be performed and performed intelligently, it `\
`would be a logical impossibility for anyone ever to break into the `\
`circle." `
Variants of Ryle\'s regress are commonly aimed at cognitivist theories.
For instance, in order to explain the behavior of rats, Edward Tolman
suggested that the rats were constructing a \"cognitive map\" that
helped them locate reinforcers, and he used intentional terms (e.g.,
expectancies, purposes, meanings) to describe their behavior. This led
to a famous attack on Tolman\'s work by Guthrie who pointed out that if
one was implying that every action must be preceded by a cognitive
\'action\' (a \'thought\' or \'schema\' or \'script\' or whatever), then
what \'causes\' this act? Clearly it must be preceded by another
cognitive action, which must in turn must be preceded by another and so
on, in an infinite regress unless an external input occurs at some
stage.
As a further example, we may take note of the following statement from
The Concept of Mind (1949):
\"The main object of this chapter is to show that there are many
activities which directly display qualities of mind, yet are neither
themselves intellectual operations nor yet effects of intellectual
operations. Intelligent practice is not a step-child of theory. On the
contrary theorizing is one practice amongst others and is itself
intelligently or stupidly conducted.\"
Ryle noted that \"theorizing is one practice amongst others.\" and hence
would translate the statement by Emerson into, \"The ancestor of every
action is an action.\" or \"The ancestor of every behavior is a
behavior,\". Each behaviour would require yet another behavior to
preface it as its ancestor, and an infinite regress would occur.
It should be noted that Ryle's regress is a critique of cognitivism
which arises from the Behaviorist tradition. Near the end of The Concept
of Mind, Ryle states, \"The Behaviorists' methodological program has
been of revolutionary importance to the program of psychology. But more,
it has been one of the main sources of the philosophical suspicion that
the two-worlds story is a myth.\" But Ryle's brand of logical
behaviorism is not to be confused with the radical behaviorism of B. F.
Skinner or the methodological behaviorism of John B. Watson. For as Alex
Byrne noted, \"Ryle was indeed, as he reportedly said, 'only one arm and
one leg a behaviorist'.\"
Arguments that involve regress are well known in philosophy. In fact any
reflexive, or self referencing process or argument will involve a
regress if there is no external input. This applies whether the agent
that engages in the process is a digital computer or intelligent agent
(cf: Smith (1986), Yates (1991)).
Ryle\'s regress suggests that intelligent acts are not created within
phenomenal consciousness. They may have non-conscious components or even
be entirely non-conscious. Ryle argued that this might mean that
consciousness is just a \"ghost in the machine\" of the brain because
consciousness would be epiphenomenal if it is not the creator of
intelligent acts. However, as will be seen below, this conclusion may be
premature and certainly cannot be used to dismiss phenomenal
consciousness as non-existent or not present in the brain.
## The Subject-Object paradox
This paradox was clearly enunciated by William James in 1904:
\"Throughout the history of philosophy the subject and its object have
been treated as absolutely discontinuous entities; and thereupon the
presence of the latter to the former, or the \'apprehension\' by the
former of the latter, has assumed a paradoxical character which all
sorts of theories had to be invented to overcome.\" James (1904).
The Subject-Object paradox points out that a conscious subject appears
to observe itself as an object. But if it observes itself as an object
then, as an object it cannot be a subject. As Bermudez(1998) puts it:
\"Any theory that tries to elucidate the capacity to think first-person
thoughts through linguistic mastery of the first-person pronoun will be
circular, because the explanandum is part of the explanans..\"
Thomas Reid uses this paradox to suggest that everything that is
observed must be external to the soul and hence proposed that experience
was the world itself.
Wittgenstein (1949) offers a way out of the paradox by denying the
existence of the subject:
`<span style="font-family:times new roman;">`{=html}\"5.63 1. The
thinking, presenting subject; there is no such thing. If I wrote a book
The World as I Found It, I should also have therein to report on my body
and say which members obey my will and which do not, etc. This then
would be a method of isolating the subject or rather of showing that in
an important sense there is no subject: that is to say, of it alone in
this book mention could not be made. 5.632. The subject does not belong
to the world but it is a limit of the world. 5.633. Where in the world
is a metaphysical subject to be noted? You say that this case is
altogether like that of the eye and the field of sight. But you do not
really see the eye. And from nothing in the field of sight can it be
concluded that it is seen from an eye\... 5.64 1. \...The philosophical
I is not the man, not the human body or the human soul of which
psychology treats, but the metaphysical subject, the limit --- not a
part of the world.\"`</span>`{=html}(Wittgenstein 1949).
Wittgenstein\'s view is similar to that voiced by Green (2002) in which
there is nothing at the point centre of the manifold of events (there is
no point eye). James (1904), Lektorsky (1980) and many others have also
attempted to resolve the paradox by proposing that there is really no
observer, only the observation or \'reflexive act\' of perception. This
idea reaches its zenith in Brentano\'s concept of \"intentionality\" in
which the subject and object are fused into a form of \"aboutness\":
`<span style="font-family:times new roman;">`{=html}\"Every psychical
phenomenon is characterized by what the Scholastics of the Middle Ages
called the intentional (or sometimes the mental) inexistence of an
object, and what we should like to call, although not quite
unambiguously, the reference (Beziehung) to a content, the directedness
(Richtung) toward an object (which in this context is not to be
understood as something real) or the immanent-object quality (immanente
Gegenständlichkeit). Each contains something as its object, though not
each in the same manner. In the representation (Vorstellung) something
is represented, in the judgment something is acknowledged or rejected,
in desiring it is desired, etc. This intentional inexistence is peculiar
alone to psychical phenomena. No physical phenomenon shows anything like
it. And thus we can define psychical phenomena by saying that they are
such phenomena as contain objects in themselves by way of intention
(intentional).\"`</span>`{=html} Brentano, F. (1874).
These authors have all identified the content of perception with either
the world itself, the manifold of events or a synthetic \'about\' the
world itself in an attempt at avoiding the paradox, however, as will be
seen later, there are other solutions to the paradox.
Bermúdez, J. (1998), The Paradox of Self-Consciousness, Bradford/MIT
Press.
Brentano, F. (1874). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. Vol1.
<http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/philosophy/works/ge/brentano.htm>
William James (1904). A World of Pure Experience. First published in
Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1, 533-543,
561-570. <http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/James/experience.htm>
## The homunculus fallacy in philosophy of mind
A Homunculus argument accounts for a phenomenon in terms of the very
phenomenon that it is supposed to explain (Richard Gregory (1987)).
Homunculus arguments are always fallacious. In the psychology and
philosophy of mind \'homunculus arguments\' are extremely useful for
detecting where theories of mind fail or are incomplete.
Homunculus arguments are common in the theory of vision. Imagine a
person watching a movie. He sees the images as something separate from
himself, projected on the screen. How is this done? A simple theory
might propose that the light from the screen forms an image on the
retinas in the eyes and something in the brain looks at these as if they
are the screen. The Homunculus Argument shows this is not a full
explanation because all that has been done is to place an entire person,
or homunculus, behind the eye who gazes at the retinas. A more
sophisticated argument might propose that the images on the retinas are
transferred to the visual cortex where it is scanned. Again this cannot
be a full explanation because all that has been done is to place a
little person in the brain behind the cortex. In the theory of vision
the Homunculus Argument invalidates theories that do not explain
\'projection\', the experience that the viewing point is separate from
the things that are seen. (Adapted from Gregory (1987), (1990)).
In the case of vision it is sometimes suggested that each homunculus
would need a homunculus inside it ad infinitum. This is the
**recursion** form of the homunculus concept. Notice that, unlike the
case of regress, the recursion would occur after the event.
An homunculus argument should be phrased in such a way that the
conclusion is always that if a homunculus is required then the theory is
wrong. After all, homunculi do not exist.
Very few people would propose that there actually is a little man in the
brain looking at brain activity. However, this proposal has been used as
a \'straw man\' in theories of mind. Gilbert Ryle (1949) proposed that
the human mind is known by its intelligent acts. (see Ryle\'s Regress).
He argued that if there is an inner being inside the brain that could
steer its own thoughts then this would lead to an absurd repetitive
cycle or \'regress\' before a thought could occur:
\"According to the legend, whenever an agent does anything
intelligently, his act is preceded and steered by another internal act
of considering a regulative proposition appropriate to his practical
problem.\"
\"\.... Must we then say that for the ..\[agent\'s\].. reflections how
to act to be intelligent he must first reflect how best to reflect how
to act? The endlessness of this implied regress shows that the
application of the appropriateness does not entail the occurrence of a
process of considering this criterion.\"
The homunculus argument and the regress argument are often considered to
be the same but this is not the case. The homunculus argument says that
if there is a need for a \'little man\' to complete a theory then the
theory is wrong. The regress argument says that an intelligent agent
would need to think before it could have a thought.
Ryle\'s theory is that intelligent acts cannot be a property of an inner
being or mind, if such a thing were to exist.
The idea that conscious experience is a flow of information into an
unextended place (a point eye) leaves itself open to the charge of
inserting an homunculus beyond the point eye. On careful reading few, if
any, real theories actually propose a flow through the point eye but
suggest some sort of nebulous direct relation with the information in
front of the eye. For instance, Descartes has a point soul directly
considering the contents of the common sense and Reid has a point eye
directly considering the world itself.
`<span style="font-size:x-small;">`{=html}Questions: It might be said
that the homunculus fallacy means that either the materialist
interpretation of conscious experience is wrong or conscious experience
does not exist: discuss. Physicalism is not materialism, discuss. Could
physical phenomena such as entanglement or space-time theories of
observation, where the observed vectors are constrained to the manifold,
avoid the homunculus fallacy?`</span>`{=html}
## Berkeley\'s \"passive ideas\"
Ryle\'s regress, when applied to consciousness, is based on an analysis
of conscious intellectual activity as a succession of states. At any
moment the conscious intellect contains one state such as \'I will think
of a word\'. This means that either the state has just popped into mind
or there was a previous state that gave rise to it such as \'I will
think of thinking of a word\'. Descartes and other empiricists have
noted that thoughts do indeed just pop into mind. So if we transfer
Ryle\'s analysis to the real world we discover that the regress is
avoided by removing the starting point of a series of thoughts from
conscious phenomenal experience. A train of thought just begins, it has
no conscious origin and Descartes\' implication is that it has probably
been synthesised non-consciously.
Suppose Descartes and our own experience are correct, suppose thoughts
do just pop into mind, if this happens can there still be a conscious
intellectual agent or are intellectual agents largely non-conscious? One
of the simplest intellectual processes is a test for equality i.e.:
\'does A equal B?\' and a routing of flow as a result of the test i.e.:
\'if A = B then goto\'. Can an intellectual agent perform an equality
test in conscious phenomenal experience?
Consider the test of whether \'A = A\', you attend to the left \'A\'
then the right \'A\' and declare them equal. What have you actually
done? The feeling that the symbols are equal just pops into mind.
Psychologists and philosophers use the word \'intuition\' for this
popping of answers into mind (Kant 1781). It is usually accompanied by
emotional experience (Damasio 1994, Bierman 2004).
If intellectual activity is actually a succession of things that just
pop into phenomenal consciousness then Ryle\'s conclusion that
phenomenal consciousness is like a \"ghost in the machine\" of the brain
would to some extent justified. Phenomenal consciousness would not be
intellectual activity. Phenomenal consciousness would contain the
stages, or succession of states, of intellectual activity but would not
contain the processes that connect these stages. This observation that
conscious experience is a succession of **passive ideas** is well known
in philosophy (cf: George Berkeley, Principles of Human Knowledge, 25).
## More on the conflict
Click above for more on Phenomenal consciousness, access consciousness,
Direct Realism, Indirect Realism, Dualism, Idealism and Panpsychism.
## References
- Harrison, J. (1984). The incorrigibility of the cogito. Mind: New
Series, Vol. 93, No. XCIII, 1984.
The problem of regression
- Ryle, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind. The University of Chicago
Press, 1949.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Smith, Q. (1986). The infinite regress of temporal attributions. The
Southern Journal of Philosophy (1986) Vol. XXIV, No. 3, 383 (Section
3).
<http://web.archive.org/web/20060507144913/http://www.qsmithwmu.com/the_infinite_regress.htm>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Yates, S. (1991). Self referential arguments in philosophy. Reason
Papers 16. (Fall 1991) 133-164.
<http://www.mises.org/reasonpapers/pdf/16/rp_16_7.pdf>
The homunculus argument
- Gregory, R.L. (1990) Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing, Oxford
University Press Inc. New York.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gregory, T.L. (1987). The Oxford Companion to Mind. Oxford
University Press.
Subject-object paradox
- James, W. (1904)Does \'Consciousness\' Exist? Journal of
Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1,
477-491.
- Hegel, G.W.F. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND: SECTION I. MIND SUBJECTIVE B.
PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND CONSCIOUSNESS Part Three of the Encyclopaedia
of the Philosophical
Sciences
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Velmans, M. (1996) Consciousness and the \"Casual Paradox\".
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 19 (3):
538-542.
- \[Bermudez, J.L. (1999) The Paradox of Self-Consciousness
(representation and Mind) Psycoloquy:
10,#35
Ontological status
- Bierman, D.J. (2004) Non Conscious Processes Preceding Intuitive
decisions
<http://m0134.fmg.uva.nl/~djb/publications/2004/Intuition_bialsymp2004.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Damasio, A.R. (1994). Descartes\' error: Emotion, reason and the
human brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam Book.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason
<http://www.arts.cuhk.edu.hk/Philosophy/Kant/cpr/>
Direct Realism
- Aydede, M. (2001) Naturalism, introspection, and direct realism
about pain. Consciousness and Emotion, Vol. 2, No. 1, 2001, pp.
29-73.
<http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/maydede/pain.pdf>
- Chapman, C.R., and Y. Nakamura (1999). A Passion of the Soul: An
Introduction to Pain for Consciousness Researchers. Consciousness
and Cognition, 8: 391-422.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Fowler C A (1986): "An event approach to the study of speech
perception from a direct-realist perspective", J of Phonetics
14(1):3-28.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gibson, J. J. (1966) The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems.
Houghton Mifflin Company,Boston.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gibson, J. J. (1979) Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Hillsdate.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gregory, R.L. 1988. Consciousness in science and philosophy:
conscience and con-science. Chapter 12 in Consciousness in
Contemporary Science. (Editors: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E.).
Oxford Science Publications.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Le Morvan, Pierre (2004). Arguments against direct realism and how
to counter them. *The American Philosophical Quarterly*, *41*(3),
221-234.\] (pdf) <http://www.tcnj.edu/~lemorvan/DR_web.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Oliveira, André L. G. and Oliveira, Luis F. (2002) Toward an
ecological conception of timbre. In Proceedings Auditory Perception
Cognition and Action Meeting 2002, Kansas City.
<http://cogprints.org/2713/>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Skinner, B. F. Science and Human Behavior . New York: Macmillan,
1953.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Skinner, B. F. 1971. Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New York: Knopf.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Skinner, B. F. 1948. Walden Two. New York: Macmillan.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tye, M. (2004). ANOTHER LOOK AT REPRESENTATIONALISM ABOUT PAIN.
Consciousness and Emotion 2004, special issue on pain, edited by
Murat Aydede (with replies by M. Aydede, N. Block, B. Maund, and P.
Noordhof
<http://sun.soci.niu.edu/~phildept/MT/RepresentationalismAndPain.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Vygotsky, L.S.(1925) Consciousness as a problem in the psychology of
behavior. Undiscovered Vygotsky: Etudes on the pre-history of
cultural-historical psychology (European Studies in the History of
Science and Ideas. Vol. 8), pp. 251-281. Peter Lang Publishing.
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/1925/consciousness.htm>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Ziff, Paul. \"About Behaviourism.\" Analysis 18 (1958): 132-136.
Quoted by Larry Hauser in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/b/behavior.htm#B>. F. Skinner:
Radical Behaviorism
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Conflict#The homunculus argument
*This section is about how regression and recursion seem to undermine
the idea of conscious experience being anywhere in the universe.*.
## The conflict - supervenience and the location of the contents of phenomenal consciousness
When we touch something or look at a view what we are probably touching
or seeing is a thing in the world, out there, beyond our bodies. Many
philosophers and almost all scientists would agree with this surmise.
But is our conscious experience itself directly the things we touch or
more like a picture of those things on television or something else
entirely? Furthermore, can we really be certain that what we believe we
experience truly occurs?
Suppose for the moment that our experience truly does occur and consists
of things laid out in time and space. Conscious experience appears to be
a simultaneous set of things (i.e.: things arranged in space) but where
are these things and what is this space? The things that occur in
conscious experience could be a virtual reality in the brain based on
the world beyond the body, or they could be the things themselves,
viewed directly through some unknown phenomenon or it has even been
suggested that they could be something non-physical.
The problem of where the contents of conscious experience are located
has provoked some of the fiercest battles in the philosophy of
consciousness. There are three broad positions, the first is Direct
Realism in which it is held that the contents of conscious experience
are directly things in the world, the second is Indirect Realism where
it is proposed that the contents of conscious experience are
representations, usually in the physical brain, based on things \'out
there\' in the world and the third is idealism where it is held that
there is no physical world, only non-physical conscious experience.
These three classifications overlap considerably, for instance some
Natural Dualists believe that the contents of sensory experience are
directly the world beyond the body but some thoughts are based in a
non-physical soul and some philosophers introduce the dualist notion of
a \"logical space\" containing disembodied information.
Philosophers often use the concept of \'supervenience\' to examine the
location of the contents of consciousness. Supervenience is the relation
between two sets of properties. Supervenience can be simple; for example
a golden ring supervenes on a piece of the metal gold. Supervenience can
also be quite complex such as the idea that life supervenes on the
biological processes in a cell. The most difficult cases of
supervenience are where a high level description is related to simpler
physical properties such as form and content. There are formal
statements of supervenience:
`The properties of A supervene on the properties of B if no two possible`\
`situations are identical with respect to the properties of A while`\
`differing with respect to the properties of B (after Chalmers 1996).`
Lewis gives a simpler, if less technical, definition of supervenience:
`A dot-matrix picture has global properties -- it is symmetrical, `\
`it is cluttered, and whatnot -- and yet all there is to the picture `\
`is dots and non-dots at each point of the matrix. The global `\
`properties are nothing but patterns in the dots. They supervene: no `\
`two pictures could differ in their global properties without `\
`differing, somewhere, in whether there is or there isn't a dot". `\
`Lewis, D., 1986, On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford: Blackwell`
One set of properties is said to supervene *locally* on another set of
properties if the second set is determined by the first. Shape is an
example of local supervenience; for instance a gold wire forged in a
circle determines a gold ring. A set of properties is said to supervene
*globally* on another if the entire context of the properties must be
included; for instance, two organisms could be physically identical but
demonstrate different behaviours in different environments. In this case
the physical form of an organism does not totally determine the
behaviour. Philosophers also divide supervenience into logical
supervenience and natural supervenience. Logical supervenience deals
with possible relations in possible worlds while natural supervenience
deals with relations that occur in the natural world.
See elementary information
theory
for a discussion of supervenience in information systems.
A particular problem posed by consciousness studies is whether conscious
phenomenal experience supervenes on the physical world and, if so,
where. To answer these questions philosophers and neuroscientists must
have a good understanding of physics. They should be aware of elementary
physical ontology such as kinetic energy being the relativistic mass
increase of a particle in a four dimensional universe and Newton\'s laws
being due to the exploration of all paths in space-time. Without a good
knowledge of physics there is the danger that we will be asking whether
phenomenal consciousness supervenes on an abstract model of the world
which does not supervene on the world itself (i.e.: *we may be asking if
conscious phenomenal experience supervenes on Newtonian physics or
supervenes on information systems theory rather than asking how
phenomenal consciousness might supervene on the natural world*).
The possibility that conscious experience does not really occur, at
least in the form that we believe it occurs, is known as the problem of
the \"Incorrigibility of the cogito\" (Harrison 1984). If Descartes\'
idea that \"I think therefore I am\" is not beyond question
(incorrigible) then the idea of phenomenal consciousness may be
incorrect.
(See for instance:
Special relativity for beginners
Special relativity for
beginners
Quantum physics explains Newton's laws of motion
<http://www.eftaylor.com/pub/OgbornTaylor.pdf> )
## The problem of regression
The philosopher Gilbert Ryle was concerned with what he called the
intellectualist legend which requires intelligent acts to be the product
of the conscious application of mental rules. The intellectualist legend
is also known as the \"Dogma of the Ghost in the Machine,\" the
\"Two-Lives Legend,\" the \"Two-Worlds Story,\" or the \"Double-Life
Legend\". Ralph Waldo Emerson summarised the intellectualist legend in
the statement that \"The ancestor of every action is a thought.\" Ryle
argued against the idea that every action requires a conscious thought
and showed that this \'intellectualist legend\' results in an infinite
regress of thought:
`"According to the legend, whenever an agent does anything `\
`intelligently, his act is preceded and steered by another internal `\
`act of considering a regulative proposition appropriate to his `\
`practical problem. [...] Must we then say that for the hero's `\
`reflections how to act to be intelligent he must first reflect how `\
`best to reflect how to act? The endlessness of this implied regress `\
`shows that the application of the criterion of appropriateness does `\
`not entail the occurrence of a process of considering this criterion."`\
`(The Concept of Mind (1949)) `
image:constudregress.gif
`"The crucial objection to the intellectualist legend is this. The `\
`consideration of propositions is itself an operation the execution `\
`of which can be more or less intelligent, less or more stupid. But if, `\
`for any operation to be intelligently executed, a prior theoretical `\
`operation had first to be performed and performed intelligently, it `\
`would be a logical impossibility for anyone ever to break into the `\
`circle." `
Variants of Ryle\'s regress are commonly aimed at cognitivist theories.
For instance, in order to explain the behavior of rats, Edward Tolman
suggested that the rats were constructing a \"cognitive map\" that
helped them locate reinforcers, and he used intentional terms (e.g.,
expectancies, purposes, meanings) to describe their behavior. This led
to a famous attack on Tolman\'s work by Guthrie who pointed out that if
one was implying that every action must be preceded by a cognitive
\'action\' (a \'thought\' or \'schema\' or \'script\' or whatever), then
what \'causes\' this act? Clearly it must be preceded by another
cognitive action, which must in turn must be preceded by another and so
on, in an infinite regress unless an external input occurs at some
stage.
As a further example, we may take note of the following statement from
The Concept of Mind (1949):
\"The main object of this chapter is to show that there are many
activities which directly display qualities of mind, yet are neither
themselves intellectual operations nor yet effects of intellectual
operations. Intelligent practice is not a step-child of theory. On the
contrary theorizing is one practice amongst others and is itself
intelligently or stupidly conducted.\"
Ryle noted that \"theorizing is one practice amongst others.\" and hence
would translate the statement by Emerson into, \"The ancestor of every
action is an action.\" or \"The ancestor of every behavior is a
behavior,\". Each behaviour would require yet another behavior to
preface it as its ancestor, and an infinite regress would occur.
It should be noted that Ryle's regress is a critique of cognitivism
which arises from the Behaviorist tradition. Near the end of The Concept
of Mind, Ryle states, \"The Behaviorists' methodological program has
been of revolutionary importance to the program of psychology. But more,
it has been one of the main sources of the philosophical suspicion that
the two-worlds story is a myth.\" But Ryle's brand of logical
behaviorism is not to be confused with the radical behaviorism of B. F.
Skinner or the methodological behaviorism of John B. Watson. For as Alex
Byrne noted, \"Ryle was indeed, as he reportedly said, 'only one arm and
one leg a behaviorist'.\"
Arguments that involve regress are well known in philosophy. In fact any
reflexive, or self referencing process or argument will involve a
regress if there is no external input. This applies whether the agent
that engages in the process is a digital computer or intelligent agent
(cf: Smith (1986), Yates (1991)).
Ryle\'s regress suggests that intelligent acts are not created within
phenomenal consciousness. They may have non-conscious components or even
be entirely non-conscious. Ryle argued that this might mean that
consciousness is just a \"ghost in the machine\" of the brain because
consciousness would be epiphenomenal if it is not the creator of
intelligent acts. However, as will be seen below, this conclusion may be
premature and certainly cannot be used to dismiss phenomenal
consciousness as non-existent or not present in the brain.
## The Subject-Object paradox
This paradox was clearly enunciated by William James in 1904:
\"Throughout the history of philosophy the subject and its object have
been treated as absolutely discontinuous entities; and thereupon the
presence of the latter to the former, or the \'apprehension\' by the
former of the latter, has assumed a paradoxical character which all
sorts of theories had to be invented to overcome.\" James (1904).
The Subject-Object paradox points out that a conscious subject appears
to observe itself as an object. But if it observes itself as an object
then, as an object it cannot be a subject. As Bermudez(1998) puts it:
\"Any theory that tries to elucidate the capacity to think first-person
thoughts through linguistic mastery of the first-person pronoun will be
circular, because the explanandum is part of the explanans..\"
Thomas Reid uses this paradox to suggest that everything that is
observed must be external to the soul and hence proposed that experience
was the world itself.
Wittgenstein (1949) offers a way out of the paradox by denying the
existence of the subject:
`<span style="font-family:times new roman;">`{=html}\"5.63 1. The
thinking, presenting subject; there is no such thing. If I wrote a book
The World as I Found It, I should also have therein to report on my body
and say which members obey my will and which do not, etc. This then
would be a method of isolating the subject or rather of showing that in
an important sense there is no subject: that is to say, of it alone in
this book mention could not be made. 5.632. The subject does not belong
to the world but it is a limit of the world. 5.633. Where in the world
is a metaphysical subject to be noted? You say that this case is
altogether like that of the eye and the field of sight. But you do not
really see the eye. And from nothing in the field of sight can it be
concluded that it is seen from an eye\... 5.64 1. \...The philosophical
I is not the man, not the human body or the human soul of which
psychology treats, but the metaphysical subject, the limit --- not a
part of the world.\"`</span>`{=html}(Wittgenstein 1949).
Wittgenstein\'s view is similar to that voiced by Green (2002) in which
there is nothing at the point centre of the manifold of events (there is
no point eye). James (1904), Lektorsky (1980) and many others have also
attempted to resolve the paradox by proposing that there is really no
observer, only the observation or \'reflexive act\' of perception. This
idea reaches its zenith in Brentano\'s concept of \"intentionality\" in
which the subject and object are fused into a form of \"aboutness\":
`<span style="font-family:times new roman;">`{=html}\"Every psychical
phenomenon is characterized by what the Scholastics of the Middle Ages
called the intentional (or sometimes the mental) inexistence of an
object, and what we should like to call, although not quite
unambiguously, the reference (Beziehung) to a content, the directedness
(Richtung) toward an object (which in this context is not to be
understood as something real) or the immanent-object quality (immanente
Gegenständlichkeit). Each contains something as its object, though not
each in the same manner. In the representation (Vorstellung) something
is represented, in the judgment something is acknowledged or rejected,
in desiring it is desired, etc. This intentional inexistence is peculiar
alone to psychical phenomena. No physical phenomenon shows anything like
it. And thus we can define psychical phenomena by saying that they are
such phenomena as contain objects in themselves by way of intention
(intentional).\"`</span>`{=html} Brentano, F. (1874).
These authors have all identified the content of perception with either
the world itself, the manifold of events or a synthetic \'about\' the
world itself in an attempt at avoiding the paradox, however, as will be
seen later, there are other solutions to the paradox.
Bermúdez, J. (1998), The Paradox of Self-Consciousness, Bradford/MIT
Press.
Brentano, F. (1874). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. Vol1.
<http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/philosophy/works/ge/brentano.htm>
William James (1904). A World of Pure Experience. First published in
Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1, 533-543,
561-570. <http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/James/experience.htm>
## The homunculus fallacy in philosophy of mind
A Homunculus argument accounts for a phenomenon in terms of the very
phenomenon that it is supposed to explain (Richard Gregory (1987)).
Homunculus arguments are always fallacious. In the psychology and
philosophy of mind \'homunculus arguments\' are extremely useful for
detecting where theories of mind fail or are incomplete.
Homunculus arguments are common in the theory of vision. Imagine a
person watching a movie. He sees the images as something separate from
himself, projected on the screen. How is this done? A simple theory
might propose that the light from the screen forms an image on the
retinas in the eyes and something in the brain looks at these as if they
are the screen. The Homunculus Argument shows this is not a full
explanation because all that has been done is to place an entire person,
or homunculus, behind the eye who gazes at the retinas. A more
sophisticated argument might propose that the images on the retinas are
transferred to the visual cortex where it is scanned. Again this cannot
be a full explanation because all that has been done is to place a
little person in the brain behind the cortex. In the theory of vision
the Homunculus Argument invalidates theories that do not explain
\'projection\', the experience that the viewing point is separate from
the things that are seen. (Adapted from Gregory (1987), (1990)).
In the case of vision it is sometimes suggested that each homunculus
would need a homunculus inside it ad infinitum. This is the
**recursion** form of the homunculus concept. Notice that, unlike the
case of regress, the recursion would occur after the event.
An homunculus argument should be phrased in such a way that the
conclusion is always that if a homunculus is required then the theory is
wrong. After all, homunculi do not exist.
Very few people would propose that there actually is a little man in the
brain looking at brain activity. However, this proposal has been used as
a \'straw man\' in theories of mind. Gilbert Ryle (1949) proposed that
the human mind is known by its intelligent acts. (see Ryle\'s Regress).
He argued that if there is an inner being inside the brain that could
steer its own thoughts then this would lead to an absurd repetitive
cycle or \'regress\' before a thought could occur:
\"According to the legend, whenever an agent does anything
intelligently, his act is preceded and steered by another internal act
of considering a regulative proposition appropriate to his practical
problem.\"
\"\.... Must we then say that for the ..\[agent\'s\].. reflections how
to act to be intelligent he must first reflect how best to reflect how
to act? The endlessness of this implied regress shows that the
application of the appropriateness does not entail the occurrence of a
process of considering this criterion.\"
The homunculus argument and the regress argument are often considered to
be the same but this is not the case. The homunculus argument says that
if there is a need for a \'little man\' to complete a theory then the
theory is wrong. The regress argument says that an intelligent agent
would need to think before it could have a thought.
Ryle\'s theory is that intelligent acts cannot be a property of an inner
being or mind, if such a thing were to exist.
The idea that conscious experience is a flow of information into an
unextended place (a point eye) leaves itself open to the charge of
inserting an homunculus beyond the point eye. On careful reading few, if
any, real theories actually propose a flow through the point eye but
suggest some sort of nebulous direct relation with the information in
front of the eye. For instance, Descartes has a point soul directly
considering the contents of the common sense and Reid has a point eye
directly considering the world itself.
`<span style="font-size:x-small;">`{=html}Questions: It might be said
that the homunculus fallacy means that either the materialist
interpretation of conscious experience is wrong or conscious experience
does not exist: discuss. Physicalism is not materialism, discuss. Could
physical phenomena such as entanglement or space-time theories of
observation, where the observed vectors are constrained to the manifold,
avoid the homunculus fallacy?`</span>`{=html}
## Berkeley\'s \"passive ideas\"
Ryle\'s regress, when applied to consciousness, is based on an analysis
of conscious intellectual activity as a succession of states. At any
moment the conscious intellect contains one state such as \'I will think
of a word\'. This means that either the state has just popped into mind
or there was a previous state that gave rise to it such as \'I will
think of thinking of a word\'. Descartes and other empiricists have
noted that thoughts do indeed just pop into mind. So if we transfer
Ryle\'s analysis to the real world we discover that the regress is
avoided by removing the starting point of a series of thoughts from
conscious phenomenal experience. A train of thought just begins, it has
no conscious origin and Descartes\' implication is that it has probably
been synthesised non-consciously.
Suppose Descartes and our own experience are correct, suppose thoughts
do just pop into mind, if this happens can there still be a conscious
intellectual agent or are intellectual agents largely non-conscious? One
of the simplest intellectual processes is a test for equality i.e.:
\'does A equal B?\' and a routing of flow as a result of the test i.e.:
\'if A = B then goto\'. Can an intellectual agent perform an equality
test in conscious phenomenal experience?
Consider the test of whether \'A = A\', you attend to the left \'A\'
then the right \'A\' and declare them equal. What have you actually
done? The feeling that the symbols are equal just pops into mind.
Psychologists and philosophers use the word \'intuition\' for this
popping of answers into mind (Kant 1781). It is usually accompanied by
emotional experience (Damasio 1994, Bierman 2004).
If intellectual activity is actually a succession of things that just
pop into phenomenal consciousness then Ryle\'s conclusion that
phenomenal consciousness is like a \"ghost in the machine\" of the brain
would to some extent justified. Phenomenal consciousness would not be
intellectual activity. Phenomenal consciousness would contain the
stages, or succession of states, of intellectual activity but would not
contain the processes that connect these stages. This observation that
conscious experience is a succession of **passive ideas** is well known
in philosophy (cf: George Berkeley, Principles of Human Knowledge, 25).
## More on the conflict
Click above for more on Phenomenal consciousness, access consciousness,
Direct Realism, Indirect Realism, Dualism, Idealism and Panpsychism.
## References
- Harrison, J. (1984). The incorrigibility of the cogito. Mind: New
Series, Vol. 93, No. XCIII, 1984.
The problem of regression
- Ryle, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind. The University of Chicago
Press, 1949.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Smith, Q. (1986). The infinite regress of temporal attributions. The
Southern Journal of Philosophy (1986) Vol. XXIV, No. 3, 383 (Section
3).
<http://web.archive.org/web/20060507144913/http://www.qsmithwmu.com/the_infinite_regress.htm>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Yates, S. (1991). Self referential arguments in philosophy. Reason
Papers 16. (Fall 1991) 133-164.
<http://www.mises.org/reasonpapers/pdf/16/rp_16_7.pdf>
The homunculus argument
- Gregory, R.L. (1990) Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing, Oxford
University Press Inc. New York.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gregory, T.L. (1987). The Oxford Companion to Mind. Oxford
University Press.
Subject-object paradox
- James, W. (1904)Does \'Consciousness\' Exist? Journal of
Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1,
477-491.
- Hegel, G.W.F. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND: SECTION I. MIND SUBJECTIVE B.
PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND CONSCIOUSNESS Part Three of the Encyclopaedia
of the Philosophical
Sciences
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Velmans, M. (1996) Consciousness and the \"Casual Paradox\".
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 19 (3):
538-542.
- \[Bermudez, J.L. (1999) The Paradox of Self-Consciousness
(representation and Mind) Psycoloquy:
10,#35
Ontological status
- Bierman, D.J. (2004) Non Conscious Processes Preceding Intuitive
decisions
<http://m0134.fmg.uva.nl/~djb/publications/2004/Intuition_bialsymp2004.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Damasio, A.R. (1994). Descartes\' error: Emotion, reason and the
human brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam Book.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason
<http://www.arts.cuhk.edu.hk/Philosophy/Kant/cpr/>
Direct Realism
- Aydede, M. (2001) Naturalism, introspection, and direct realism
about pain. Consciousness and Emotion, Vol. 2, No. 1, 2001, pp.
29-73.
<http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/maydede/pain.pdf>
- Chapman, C.R., and Y. Nakamura (1999). A Passion of the Soul: An
Introduction to Pain for Consciousness Researchers. Consciousness
and Cognition, 8: 391-422.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Fowler C A (1986): "An event approach to the study of speech
perception from a direct-realist perspective", J of Phonetics
14(1):3-28.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gibson, J. J. (1966) The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems.
Houghton Mifflin Company,Boston.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gibson, J. J. (1979) Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Hillsdate.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gregory, R.L. 1988. Consciousness in science and philosophy:
conscience and con-science. Chapter 12 in Consciousness in
Contemporary Science. (Editors: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E.).
Oxford Science Publications.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Le Morvan, Pierre (2004). Arguments against direct realism and how
to counter them. *The American Philosophical Quarterly*, *41*(3),
221-234.\] (pdf) <http://www.tcnj.edu/~lemorvan/DR_web.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Oliveira, André L. G. and Oliveira, Luis F. (2002) Toward an
ecological conception of timbre. In Proceedings Auditory Perception
Cognition and Action Meeting 2002, Kansas City.
<http://cogprints.org/2713/>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Skinner, B. F. Science and Human Behavior . New York: Macmillan,
1953.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Skinner, B. F. 1971. Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New York: Knopf.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Skinner, B. F. 1948. Walden Two. New York: Macmillan.
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tye, M. (2004). ANOTHER LOOK AT REPRESENTATIONALISM ABOUT PAIN.
Consciousness and Emotion 2004, special issue on pain, edited by
Murat Aydede (with replies by M. Aydede, N. Block, B. Maund, and P.
Noordhof
<http://sun.soci.niu.edu/~phildept/MT/RepresentationalismAndPain.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Vygotsky, L.S.(1925) Consciousness as a problem in the psychology of
behavior. Undiscovered Vygotsky: Etudes on the pre-history of
cultural-historical psychology (European Studies in the History of
Science and Ideas. Vol. 8), pp. 251-281. Peter Lang Publishing.
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/1925/consciousness.htm>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Ziff, Paul. \"About Behaviourism.\" Analysis 18 (1958): 132-136.
Quoted by Larry Hauser in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/b/behavior.htm#B>. F. Skinner:
Radical Behaviorism
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Conflict2#Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness
*This part of this section is about the where and when of the experience
called consciousness. Is it in the world, in the brain or are the world
and brain within it?*
## Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness
Block(1995) drew attention to the way that there appear to be two types
of consciousness: *phenomenal* consciousness and *access* consciousness:
`Phenomenal consciousness is experience; the phenomenally`\
`conscious aspect of a state is what it is like to be in that`\
`state. The mark of access-consciousness, by contrast, is `\
`availability for use in reasoning and rationally guiding speech `\
`and action. (Block 1995).`
*See the section on Ned Block\'s
ideas
for a deeper coverage of his approach to access and phenomenal
consciousness.*
Block uses Nagel\'s famous (1974) paper, \"What is it like to be a
bat?\" as an exemplary description of phenomenal consciousness.
Excellent descriptions have also been proffered by the empiricist
philosophers who gave lengthy descriptions of consciousness as partly
experience itself. Although Block has formalised the idea of phenomenal
and access consciousness similar ideas have also been put forward by
many philosophers including Kant and Whitehead.
Access consciousness has two interpretations, in the first, used by
Block, it applies to the functions that appear to operate on phenomenal
consciousness. In the second, used by the behaviourists and
eliminativists, it is some property of the functions of the brain that
can be called \'consciousness\'.
This division between phenomenal and functional aspects of consciousness
is useful because it emphasises the idea of phenomenal consciousness as
observation rather than action. Some philosophers such as Huxley in
1874, have taken the view that because phenomenal consciousness appears
to have no function it is of no importance or cannot exist. James (1879)
introduced the term \"epiphenomenalism\" to summarise the idea that
consciousness has no function.
The idea that phenomenal consciousness cannot exist is a type of
*Eliminativism* (also known as Eliminative Materialism). Eliminativism
owes much to the work of Sellars(1956) and Feyerbend (1963). Dennett
(1978) applied Eliminativism to phenomenal consciousness and denies that
pain is real. Others such as Rey(1997) have also applied eliminativism
to phenomenal consciousness.
Dennett (1988) redefines consciousness in terms of access consciousness
alone, he argues that \"Everything real has properties, and since I
don\'t deny the reality of conscious experience, I grant that conscious
experience has properties\". Having related all consciousness to
properties he then declares that these properties are actually
judgements of properties. He considers judgements of the properties of
consciousness to be identical to the properties themselves. He writes:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"The infallibilist line on qualia treats
them as properties of one\'s experience one cannot in principle
misdiscover, and this is a mysterious doctrine (at least as mysterious
as papal infallibility) unless we shift the emphasis a little and treat
qualia as logical constructs out of subjects\' qualia-judgments: a
subject\'s experience has the quale F if and only if the subject judges
his experience to have quale F. \"`</font>`{=html}
Having identified \"properties\" with \"judgement of properties\" he can
then show that the judgements are insubstantial, hence the properties
are insubstantial and hence the qualia are insubstantial or even
non-existent. Dennett concludes that qualia can be rejected as
non-existent:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"So when we look one last time at our
original characterization of qualia, as ineffable, intrinsic, private,
directly apprehensible properties of experience, we find that there is
nothing to fill the bill. In their place are relatively or practically
ineffable public properties we can refer to indirectly via reference to
our private property-detectors\-- private only in the sense of
idiosyncratic. And insofar as we wish to cling to our subjective
authority about the occurrence within us of states of certain types or
with certain properties, we can have some authority\--not infallibility
or incorrigibility, but something better than sheer guessing\--but only
if we restrict ourselves to relational, extrinsic properties like the
power of certain internal states of ours to provoke acts of apparent re-
identification. So contrary to what seems obvious at first blush, there
simply are no qualia at all. \" (Dennett 1988)`</font>`{=html}
Dennett\'s asserts that \"a subject\'s experience has the quale F if and
only if the subject judges his experience to have quale F\". This is a
statement of the belief that qualia are the same as processes such as
judgements. Processes such as judgements are flows of data where one
state examines a previous state in a succession over time and embody
what Whitehead called the \"materialist\" concept of time. Dennett does
not consider how a scientific concept of time might affect his argument.
Dennett\'s argument has been persuasive and there are now many
philosophers and neuroscientists who believe that the problem of
phenomenal consciousness does not exist. This means that, to them, what
we call \'consciousness\' can only be a property of the functions
performed by the brain and body. According to these philosophers only
access consciousness exists.
Those who support the idea of phenomenal consciousness also tend to
frame it in terms of nineteenth century theory where one state examines
a previous state in a succession over time, for instance Edelman(1993)
places the past in memories at an instant and time within experience is
explained as continuing modelling processes:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"Primary consciousness is the state of
being mentally aware of things in the world\--of having mental images in
the present. But it is not accompanied by any sense of a person with a
past and a future\.... In contrast, higher-order consciousness involves
the recognition by a thinking subject of his or her own acts or
affections. It embodies a model of the personal, and of the past and the
future as well as the present. It exhibits direct awareness\--the
noninferential or immediate awareness of mental episodes without the
involvement of sense organs or receptors. It is what we humans have in
addition to primary consciousness. We are conscious of being
conscious.\" `</font>`{=html}
Block(2004) also suggests this flow from state to state in his idea of
\"Reflexivity\" where our idea of familiarity with an object is due to
one state being analysed by another:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"Thus in the "conscious" case, the subject
must have a state that is about the subject's own perceptual experience
(looking familiar) and thus conscious in what might be termed a
"reflexive" sense. An experience is conscious in this sense just in case
it is the object of another of the subject's states; for example, one
has a thought to the effect that one has that experience. The reflexive
sense of \'consciousness\' contrasts with phenomenality, which perhaps
attaches to some states which are not the objects of other mental
states. Reflexive consciousness might better be called 'awareness' than
'consciousness'. Reflexivity is phenomenality plus something else
(reflection) and that opens up the possibility in principle for
phenomenality without reflection. For example, it is at least
conceptually possible for there to be two people in pain, one of whom is
introspecting the pain the other not. (Perhaps infants or animals can
have pain but don't introspect it.) The first is reflexively conscious
of the pain, but both have phenomenally conscious states, since pain is
by its very nature a phenomenally conscious state. \"`</font>`{=html}
Both Block and Edelman allow phenomenal consciousness, our experience,
as an unexplained phenomenon. Block, Edelman and also Dennett\'s ideas
of consciousness are shown in the illustration below:
![](Constudphen.gif "Constudphen.gif")
This model differs from the empirical reports of phenomenal
consciousness that were considered earlier. According to the empirical
reports the present moment in our experience is extended so the
succession of outputs or stages of access consciousness could constitute
the contents of phenomenal consciousness. In other words phenomenal
consciousness is composed of periods of access consciousness. This is
how it seems to the empiricist and in our own experience but how such a
state could be explained in terms of brain activity is highly
problematical. Given that nineteenth century ideas cannot explain such a
state a scientific explanation will be required.
The idea that phenomenal consciousness misrepresents or \"misdiscovers\"
itself (Dennett 1988) deserves further discussion. According to
materialism the present instant has no duration so can only be known in
succeeding instants as a report or memory and this could be wrong.
Whitehead considered that this viewpoint originates in an archaic view
of science, particularly the concept of time in science:
\"The eighteenth and nineteenth centuries accepted as their natural
philosophy a certain circle of concepts which were as rigid and definite
as those of the philosophy of the middle ages, and were accepted with as
little critical research. I will call this natural philosophy
\'materialism.\' Not only were men of science materialists, but also
adherents of all schools of philosophy. The idealists only differed from
the philosophic materialists on question of the alignment of nature in
reference to mind. But no one had any doubt that the philosophy of
nature considered in itself was of the type which I have called
materialism. It is the philosophy which I have already examined in my
two lectures of this course preceding the present one. It can be
summarised as the belief that nature is an aggregate of material and
that this material exists in some sense at each successive member of a
one-dimensional series of extensionless instants of time. Furthermore
the mutual relations of the material entities at each instant formed
these entities into a spatial configuration in an unbounded space. It
would seem that space\-\--on this theory-would be as instantaneous as
the instants, and that some explanation is required of the relations
between the successive instantaneous spaces. The materialistic theory is
however silent on this point; and the succession of instantaneous spaces
is tacitly combined into one persistent space. This theory is a purely
intellectual rendering of experience which has had the luck to get
itself formulated at the dawn of scientific thought. It has dominated
the language and the imagination of science since science flourished in
Alexandria, with the result that it is now hardly possible to speak
without appearing to assume its immediate obviousness.\" (Whitehead
1920).
## Direct Realism and Direct Perception
Direct Realism proposes that phenomenal experience is directly objects
in the world without any intervening representation. It is motivated by
the belief that the Problem of Regression, the Subject-Object Paradox
and the recursion form of the Homunculus arguments show that phenomenal
consciousness cannot occur in the brain alone. Direct Realists reason
that if phenomenal consciousness cannot be things in the brain then it
must be something outside the brain.
There are two principle types of Direct Realism: Natural Dualism and
Behaviourism (both Radical and Analytical). Some behaviourists use the
term "Direct Perception" rather than Direct Realism and consider that
only the invariant parts of perception are direct (see for instance
Michaels and Carello 1981). Thomas Reid is generally regarded as the
founder of Direct Realism. In his Natural Dualism he proposed that the
soul is in direct contact with the contents of experience and these
contents are things in the world beyond the body. The Direct Realism of
Reid is summarised in the statement of his famous disciple Sir William
Hamilton: \"In the simplest act of perception I am conscious of myself
as the perceiving subject and of an external reality as the object
perceived\". Reid\'s Natural Dualism has now been largely replaced by
radical and analytical behaviourism which eschew the idea of a soul and
propose that phenomenal consciousness, if it exists at all, is a
behavioural reflex.
The modern justification of Direct Realism mainly consists of arguments
against Indirect Realism or Representationalism. Philosophers such as
Austin (1962) and Le Morvan (2004) have summarised the Direct Realism
debate and have identified the following arguments in favour of Indirect
Realism and given rebuttals to each of them:
1\. The Causal Argument: perception involves a succession of causal
events such as the reflection of photons, bleaching of retinal pigments
etc. so perception must involve the end of this causal chain. The Direct
Realist response is that, although there may be a causal chain in
sensation this does not inevitably imply that the end of the chain is
the content of phenomenal experience.
2\. The Time Lag Argument: it takes time for light to travel from an
object to the senses, time for chemical changes in the retina etc\...
The Direct Realist response is that direct perception may be referred
back in time.
3\. The Partial Character of Perception Argument: we only perceive the
surface of objects, and then only a part of the surface. As the whole
object would be perceived directly perception must be indirect. The
Direct Realist response is that direct perception could occur even if
only parts of an object were perceived.
4\. The Perceptual Relativity Argument: things appear to be different
shapes depending upon the point of view. The Direct Realist response is
that if perception can occur backwards in time it should have no problem
occurring back down a line of sight. However, Le Morvan\'s argument does
not seem to encompass the geometrical nature of phenomenal experience,
seeking to explain geometry in terms of movement.
5\. The Argument from Perceptual Illusion: A stick may appear bent when
projecting from the surface of water. Direct Realists apply the argument
used in (4) to this problem. The bent stick illusion is a physical event
in the world beyond the eye rather than a normal optical illusion such
as the Muller-Lyer illusion etc., see (6) for a discussion of optical
illusions.
6\. The Argument from Hallucination: Hallucinations are not in the world
beyond the body. This is highly problematical for Direct Realists
especially when phenomena such as lucid dreams, dreams and visual
imaginations are included along with hallucinations. Direct Realists
classify these phenomena as not being perceptions or deny that they
actually exist as phenomena. Indirect Realists would maintain that all
of perception is a reconstruction and use optical illusions such as the
Muller-Lyer, Ames Room etc. to justify this contention so the Direct
Realist approach to hallucination, dreams etc. might seem like an
unwillingness to accept Indirect Realism rather than an argument.
7\. The Dubitability Argument (cf: Indubitability argument): we cannot
doubt current phenomenal experience but we can doubt the world beyond
the body therefore phenomenal experience is not the world beyond the
body. Direct Realists fall back on Presentism or functional Presentism
to defeat this argument. If phenomenal experience is instantaneous and
made anew at each instant then anything can be doubted.
The points above have summarised the Direct Realist stance on visual
perception. Other sensory modalities have also been considered in the
Direct Realism debate.
Fowler (1986) considered that sounds were attached to objects in the
world. This idea is strange because sounds only seem to be closely
attached to objects in the world when these objects are seen as well as
heard. For example, when a subject is blindfolded it is found that there
can be a large error in locating the position of a sound in the world,
this is especially true for low frequency sounds. The Direct Realist
approach has difficulty explaining the transition from sounds with an
indefinite location when a subject is blindfolded to sounds that are
bound to visual events when the blindfold is removed. It also runs into
problems explaining how the sound of speech from a single loudspeaker
can become bound to lip movements on a cinema screen. If the binding
does not occur in the brain then where does it occur?
Pain is particularly problematic for Direct Realism because, unlike
colour vision where \'red\' is inferred to be a property of electrons or
light, pain is an inner experience that is not a property of tissue
damage. Tissue damage has properties such as bleeding, wheal formation
etc. but pain seems to be phenomenal experience in the brain and
\'phantom pain\' can occur without tissue damage (see Aydede (2001), Tye
(2004) and Chapman, and Nakamura (1999) for further analysis). On closer
inspection other sensations also appear to be inner experiences rather
than direct sensations. For instance, the red crosses of different hues
in the illustration below are all due to the same physical wavelengths
of light. In this case the range of hues in experience is unrelated to
the actual physical red on the page or screen.
Another problem for Direct Realism is that it does not overcome the
problems that it is supposed to solve. The argument for Direct Realism
begins with the idea that there are severe problems with
representationalism (the idea that phenomenal experience is in the
brain) and that direct perception is an alternative that does not have
these problems. However on closer inspection Direct Realism suffers from
almost same problems as representationalism. If phenomenal experience is
the world itself then Ryle\'s regress applies to the world itself and
this can only be avoided by assuming that phenomenal experience is a
subset of the world (i.e.: a representation) that receives input from
other parts of the world that are not part of phenomenal experience.
It is also commonly assumed that Direct Realism avoids the recursion
argument because it is believed that the separation of the observer from
the things that are observed is simply due to the geometry of the world.
If such simple geometry is possible between the eye and the world then
it should also be possible in the brain and a similar geometrical
explanation could be invoked to avoid recursion in representations.
These points are shown in the illustration below:
image:Constuddir1.gif
Scientists have a further problem with Direct Realism. The illustration
below demonstrates that our scientific knowledge of the world differs
markedly from our phenomenal experience.
image:constuddirect.gif
It is difficult to see how the form and content of phenomenal experience
could supervene directly on the world beyond the body. The world
inferred from measurements beyond the body seems to be a nebulous set of
quantum phenomena that are arranged as probability fields in three
dimensions at any instant. The objects in this real world are mostly
space. The world of phenomenal experience on the other hand contains
objects that are one-sided, and are like a 2 dimensional field of
vectors directed simultaneously at an observation point which is
apparently separate from them. Phenomenal experience is not three
dimensional, the rear of objects is not available within it at any
instant. Visual phenomenal experience seems to be a geometrical
relationship between an abstract observation point and the reflection
properties of the part of the world external to the body. It is a form
that crudely overlies the angular separations in inferred reality,
providing approximate directional data. It is not like things in
themselves beyond the body, not even in type, being a set of directional
vectors. (See the module on the neuroscience of perception for a
discussion of depth perception).
If the form and content of visual phenomenal experience are abstractions
separated according to the angular positions of things in the world
beyond the body then theories which propose that phenomenal experience
is the world itself are problematical. It should be noted that things
arranged according to angular positions can appear to overlie any group
of similar things along a radius from the centre point.
![](Constuddirectangle.gif "Constuddirectangle.gif")
If Direct Realists admit that things are as they appear to be, observed
according to angular positions at a \'point eye\', then any
representation of things on the inside of a sphere of any radius would
appear similar. The geometry of the \'point eye\' is problematical
whether the view contains the world itself or a representation of the
world; it cannot be the movements of lumps of matter or energy and the
point observation cannot be due to lumps all landing at a point. In
other words the \'view\' is inconsistent with nineteenth century
materialism and will require a scientific explanation.
Radical and Analytical Behaviourism tackle the problem of the difference
between the world inferred from measurements beyond the body and the
phenomenal world by denying phenomenal consciousness and maintaining
that access and reflex consciousness are all that exists or is
necessary. Radical Behaviourism is an offshoot of psychological
behaviourism and was established as a philosophical adjunct to Marxism
by Vygotsky and popularised by Burrhus Frederic Skinner (see Skinner
1953). There is another movement in psychological behaviourism which is
similar to Radical Behaviourism called Ecological Psychology (see Gibson
1966, 1979 and also Michaels and Carello 1981). Analytical Behaviourism
is a philosophical movement established by Gilbert Ryle (see Ryle 1949).
The core of Analytical and Radical Behaviourism is the assumption that
consciousness exists for a durationless instant so that the Dubitability
Argument and the Regression and Recursion Arguments can be applied (Ryle
1949, Skinner 1971 and see the sections on Ryle\'s Regress and the
Subject-Object Paradox above). As a result the Direct Realist is able to
insinuate that subjects only think that they have had a particular
experience (cf: Dennett 1991a). It is intriguing that Eliminativists
also maintain that experience is the world itself, for instance an
insight into Dennett\'s idea of the mind is to be found on pages 407-408
of Consciousness Explained:
\"It seemed to him, according to the text, as if his mind - his visual
field - were filled with intricate details of gold-green buds an
wiggling branches, but although this is how it seemed this was an
illusion. No such \"plenum\" ever came into his mind; the plenum
remained out in the world where it is didn\'t have to be represented,
but could just be. When we marvel, in those moments of heightened
self-consciousness, at the glorious richness of our conscious
experience, the richness we marvel at is actually the richness of the
world outside, in all its ravishing detail. It does not \"enter\" our
conscious minds, but is simply available\"
This is a clear description of Direct Realism (although Dennett does not
describe himself as a direct realist).
Radical Behaviourism is sometimes described as the dictum that the only
psychological events that are of importance are those that occur outside
the head. The absurdity of this has led to jokes:
Q: What does one behaviorist say to another when they meet on the
street?
A: You\'re fine. How am I?
Q: What does one behaviorist say to another after sex?
A: That was great for you. How was it for me?
(Ziff 1958)
However Vygotsky, Skinner and other Radical Behaviourists hold that
inner behaviour is possible so that events within the brain can result
in reward or punishment. Vygotsky (1925) describes this approach:
\"Consciousness is wholly reduced to the transmitting mechanisms of
reflexes operating according to general laws, i.e., no processes other
than reactions can be admitted into the organism. The way is also paved
for the solution of the problem of self-awareness and self-observation.
Inner perception and introspection are possible only thanks to the
existence of a proprioceptive field and secondary reflexes, which are
connected with it. This is always the echo of a reaction.\"
Hence Radical Behaviourists are able to make the claim that what are
believed to be representations with phenomenal content are processes.
Even events such as pain can then be explained as reflexes involving
organs within the skin. However, by opening the possibility that such
reflexes could occur at any sense organ, including the eye, this makes
Radical Behaviourism a mixed Direct Realist/Indirect Realist philosophy
with consciousness as a process, not a separate thing such as phenomenal
consciousness (see the section on representationalism and intentionality
below).
But this raises a serious issue for science: can the phenomenal
consciousness that seems to contain our observations really be argued
out of existence on the basis of a theory? As Gregory (1988) put it: "
'If you can't explain it -- deny it' is one strategy for dealing with
embarrassing questions such as 'what is consciousness?' ". But is this
the right strategy?
Direct Realism fails to overcome the problems of regression and
recursion inherent in representations. It proposes that phenomenal
consciousness is identical to the physical world beyond the body but
must then use a plethora of arguments to explain why this is evidently
not so. When confronted with these problems its proponents resort to the
argument that everything can be doubted and can misrepresent itself. Yet
it is still widely believed.
It should be noted that Direct Realism is espoused in Religious Natural
Dualism, some forms of Augustinian theology, nineteenth century
materialism and its offspring such as Marxism, post-modernism,
post-Marxism, and various sociological movements. It is also necessary
for some forms of Strong AI to occur. Perhaps this explains why few
ideas have attracted as much attention and defence as Direct Realism.
It is interesting to compare the Direct Realist and Indirect Realist
interpretations of something as simple as a cartoon on television (such
as the image below). According to Indirect Realism the cartoon would be
a moving representation constructed in the brain using data from the
senses. This leads to the prediction of brain mechanisms for modelling
motions, combining colours, binding sound and vision etc., many of which
have been verified. Can you demonstrate how the theory of Direct Realism
could explain the phenomenal experience that contains the cartoon and
produce a list of the predictions made by the theory?
![](constudcartoon.gif "constudcartoon.gif")
In science a theory should be of predictive value, for instance,
information theory describes how the state of a thing can be impressed
on a carrier so that a signal can be transmitted from one place to
another. This theory predicts what will happen when the signal arrives
at its destination and how the state of the source can be inferred from
the events at the destination, the total amount of information that can
be transmitted etc. At the destination it is the form of the signal that
is directly known by interaction and measurement, the form of the source
is inferred. Direct Realism is a direct challenge to this information
theory but does it deliver a more powerful predictive description of
phenomenal consciousness or is experience always dependent on what
happens to the information flow between things in the world and
somewhere in the brain? Does direct realism have a physical theory?
Ultimately it appears as if Direct Realism is about various
understandings of Information Theory. For example, Austin (1962)
discusses what we see when we see a church camouflaged as a barn and
comments that: \"We see, of course, a church that now looks like a
barn.\". Do we see a church or a barn? Scientific information theory is
clear about this, the church is an entity composed of selected
information from the quantum state of its constituents, the optical
image of a camouflaged church is an arrangement of photons emanating
from a screen on which it is projected, the retina has an arrangement of
chemical and electrical events based on an optical image and conscious
visual experience correlates with the arrangement of things on the
retina. The fact that conscious experience also correlates with
classifications of the retinal image as a barn or a church suggests that
conscious experience is an arrangement of things in the brain based on
both the retinal arrangement and the contents of a relational database.
Austin\'s arguments have been mythologised as a final demonstration that
\"sense data\" theories are false. However, as will be seen below, sense
data theories merely claim that there is a succession of information
states between an information state outside the body and that reported
as conscious experience i.e.: subjects report that a church is
camouflaged when it is camouflaged.
## Indirect Realism
Indirect realism proposes that phenomenal consciousness exists and is a
set of signals or **sense data**, usually in the brain. This was
proposed by philosophers from Aristotle to Locke and was probably the
most widespread idea of conscious experience until the eighteenth
century.
The idea of sense data is discussed in depth by Russell (1912).
Russell\'s original definition is given below:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Let us give the name of
\'sense-data\' to the things that are immediately known in sensation:
such things as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and so
on. We shall give the name \'sensation\' to the experience of being
immediately aware of these things. Thus, whenever we see a colour, we
have a sensation of the colour, but the colour itself is a sense-datum,
not a sensation. The colour is that of which we are immediately aware,
and the awareness itself is the sensation. It is plain that if we are to
know anything about the table, it must be by means of the sense-data \--
brown colour, oblong shape, smoothness, etc. \-- which we associate with
the table; but, for the reasons which have been given, we cannot say
that the table is the sense-data, or even that the sense-data are
directly properties of the table.\"`</font>`{=html}
Russell\'s definition is a materialist concept in which experience is
always **of** something because the durationless instant of the present
has always gone. As such it differs from some empiricist ideas where
experience is not confined to the durationless instant.
Science is Indirect Realist because it holds that the scientist can only
make **measurements** of events in the world. These measurements give
rise to signals as a result of interaction with the event. According to
**decoherence theory** the signals are a state that is a mixture of the
state of the measuring instrument and the state of the thing being
measured. For example, the eyes are measuring instruments that are
sensitive to photons, photons are signals containing a state that is
based on the state of electrons in a surface and the state of electrons
is based on the state of the surface etc. Scientific inference allows
some aspects of the state of the surface to be inferred from the state
of the photons.
In modern Indirect Realism there is an attempt to distinguish the
phenomenal content of conscious experience from the processing involved
in accessing this phenomenal content. According to these theories
phenomenal experience is an arrangement of signals that are the content
of the experience. This arrangement forms a *representation* of things
in the world so this form of indirect realism is known as
**Representationalism**. Tye (2003) describes types of
representationalist theory:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Representationalism, as I have
presented it so far, is an identity thesis with respect to qualia:
qualia are supposedly one and the same as certain representational
contents.\"`</font>`{=html}
Tye also describes variants of this idea of representationalism:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Sometimes it is held instead
that qualia are one and the same as certain representational properties
of experiences; and sometimes it is is argued that these
representational properties are themselves irreducible (Siewert 1998).
There is also a weaker version of representationalism, according to
which it is metaphysically necessary that experiences exactly alike with
respect to their representational contents are exactly alike with
respect to their qualia. Obviously, this supervenience thesis leaves
open the further question as to the essential nature of
qualia.\"`</font>`{=html} (Tye 2003).
In a scientific sense Direct Realists believe that phenomenal experience
is the signals that occur next to things in the world beyond the body
(which they call \"things in themselves\") and Indirect Realists usually
believe that phenomenal experience is signals in the brain. It can be
seen from the pattern of signal flow that the signals travelling into
the brain preserve the spatial relationships of the original signals and
encode the properties in the original signals. This means that the
original signals next to the QM sources and the signals in the brain are
equivalent provided the latter are oriented appropriately relative to
signals from the body. Either set of signals could transmit or contain
the same information. Both Direct and Indirect Realism cannot, at
present, explain the physics of how a viewing point occurs in experience
i.e.: how we seem to see through an apparent space to the signals that
are the contents of experience. So the choice between Direct Realism and
Indirect Realism reduces to whether there is only one set of signals or
a chain of signals between the world and phenomenal experience.
The philosophical arguments for Indirect Realism are listed below:
1\. Variable perspective: when we see things the view changes so what we
see must be a different set of signals depending on the view rather than
a constant object.
2\. Illusions: we can see through fingers and see a variety of colours
where measurements tell us one exists. Direct Realists quote the \"bent
stick illusion\", which is not really an illusion at all, being a
physical event.
3\. Hallucinations: two people can have phenomenal experience containing
a table. The first may be viewing a real table whereas the second may be
hallucinating a table. If the tables are the same (phenomenally) then
experience is indirect.
4\. Double vision: press the side of one eye, two images appear (cf Hume
1739) yet there are not two things in the world.
5\. Time gap arguments: according to materialism the past has gone. The
things being seen no longer exist in the state that relates to the state
in experience. In the extreme case, some stars in the night sky no
longer exist but are still in experience so experience must be a derived
signal.
6\. Secondary qualities such as pain, colour and smell do not exist as
physical things in the source of signals and are likely to be properties
of signals in the brain.
![](constudindirect.gif "constudindirect.gif")
Indirect Realism has received strong support from recent discoveries in
neuroscience, for example, it is now clear that both the colour and
motion in phenomenal experience are added by cortical processes. In
Cerebral **Achromatopsia** patients have suffered trauma to area V4 of
the cerebral cortex and report seeing the world in greyscale with no
colour vision and in Congenital Achromatopsia people do not even
understand the meaning of \'colour\'. In an astonishing ailment called
**Akinetopsia** patients perceive movement as a succession of stationary
images (Rizzo *et al.* 1995). Akinetopsia is usually associated with
damage to cortical area V5. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) have demonstrated
that the addition of colour occurs more rapidly than the addition of
motion. The section on the Neuroscience of Consciousness describes these
discoveries and many other aspects of the creation of phenomenal
experience in the brain.
Unfortunately knowledge of the whereabouts of the signals that are the
content of conscious experience does not resolve the problem of
phenomenal consciousness. Whether these signals are next to objects in
the world or at the end of a chain of signals in the brain there still
remains the problem of how they become arranged in the form of
experience. If such a thing occurs at all.
### Intentionality and representation
There is a materialist interpretation of representationalism in which
representations are redefined as intentional states:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"One way of explaining what is
meant by 'intentionality' in the (more obscure) philosophical sense is
this: it is that aspect of mental states or events that consists in
their being of or about things (as pertains to the questions, 'What are
you thinking of?' and 'What are you thinking about?'). Intentionality is
the aboutness or directedness of mind (or states of mind) to things,
objects, states of affairs, events. So if you are thinking about San
Francisco, or about the increased cost of living there, or about your
meeting someone there at Union Square---your mind, your thinking, is
directed toward San Francisco, or the increased cost of living, or the
meeting in Union Square. To think at all is to think of or about
something in this sense. This 'directedness' conception of
intentionality plays a prominent role in the influential philosophical
writings of Franz Brentano and those whose views developed in response
to his (to be discussed further in Section 3).\"(Siewert
2003)`</font>`{=html}
This definition allows \"representation\" to be redefined as a data
stream rather than a set of things arranged in some mental or neural
state that represents things in space. Husserl thought this approach
would allow a description of consciousness that \"carefully abstains
from affirming the existence of anything in spatio-temporal reality\"
(Siewert 2003) although it could be argued that a data stream such as
any description can never escape the constraints of representation in
time at some place.
Unfortunately the concept of \"intentionality\" has become so diverse
that it could be applied to almost any aspect of the description of
consciousness. An interesting example of this is given by Loar (2001)
where \"intentionality\" is considered to overlap \"representing\" and
\"conceiving\":
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"A person\'s thoughts represent
things to her \-- conceive things \-- in many ways: perceptually,
memory-wise, descriptively, by naming, by analogy, by intuitive sorting,
theoretically, abstractly, implicitly and explicitly. These various
manners of conceiving have something in common: they have intentional
properties, and they have them essentially. `</font>`{=html}
The usage of the term \"intentional state\" has become so broad that it
now means little more than a state that is about another state.
References
Siewert, C. (2003). Consciousness and Intentionality. The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-intentionality/>
Also see Loar, B. (2001) "Phenomenal Intentionality as the Basis of
Mental Content", in Reflections and Replies, ed. M. Hahn and B.
Ramsberg, MIT.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/courses/concepts/loar.html>
Williford, K. (2002) The intentionality of consciousness and the
consciousness of intentionality. Intentionality: Past and Future, edited
by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis, Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi.
<http://web.stcloudstate.edu/kwwilliford/Intentionality%20of%20Consciousness.pdf>
Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism Defended. Philosophical Review 110
(April 2001):199-240. <http://stripe.colorado.edu/~leeds/byrne.pdf>
### Cartesian materialism
The term \"Cartesian materialism\" once meant the idea that the mind is
in the brain (see for instance Block 1995). The term had largely fallen
out of use in philosophy until revived by Daniel Dennett (1991) in the
book *Consciousness Explained*. Dennett uses a very particular
definition of the term in his discussions and also uses a particular
definition of the word \"mind\". See the section on Daniel
Dennett
for Dennett\'s critique. Philosophers who adhere to the idea that the
mind is in the brain tend to call themselves \"indirect realists\" or
\"representationalists\" where the substrate of conscious experience is
in the brain and would deny that Dennett\'s critique applies to their
proposals. Dennett\'s critique makes the materialist assumption that if
there is a representation in the brain then a further flow of material
out of this representation would be required for the representation to
become part of mind.
### Identity theories of mind
The idea that mental states are brain states is known as the **identity
theory of mind**. There are two sorts of identity theory, in **type**
identity theory it is held that mental states are identical to brain
states whereas in **token** identity theory it is held that mental
states correlate with brain states.
Type identity theory was attacked by Putnam in \"The Nature of Mental
States\" where he pointed out that if mental states are functions then
type identity theory would presuppose that animals that had the same
mental states would need to have identical brain structures. He
suggested that this is unlikely, it being more probable that animals
have functional systems that perform similar overall functions but which
are not identical. In other words, if it is assumed that conscious
experience is a set of functions then token identity theory is more
probable than type identity theory.
Putnam\'s critique does not preclude identity theories of mind that
involve \"passive ideas\" (i.e.: states that are not classical
functions).
Most identity theories of mind would be representational, the physical
states representing the world in some way. All identity theories of mind
involve Cartesian materialism in the sense of the mental states being
brain states. According to identity theories the mind is in the brain.
Putnam, H. (1967) The nature of mental states. In The Nature of Mind,
edited by Rosenthal, pp. 197--203. Originally published as
\"Psychological predicates in Art, Mind, and Religion\", edited by
Capitan and Merill, pp. 37--48.
## Dualism
Prior to considering the arguments surrounding dualism it is important
to have a clear idea of \"information\" because many of these arguments
have parallels with the difference between information as a set of
states that can be transmitted and the substrate on which this
information is expressed or from which the information is derived. See
Elementary information and information systems
theory.
### Cartesian dualism
Descartes, a philosopher, analysed his experience and developed an
empirical description of how it is arranged. He described mental images
and perceptions as extended in space and with a duration. He called
these extended things **ideas** (Cartesian ideas) and proposed that they
are patterns in the brain. Descartes thought the pineal gland was the
most likely location for these ideas because it is one of the few single
organs in the brain. He also proposed that there is a rational soul that
directly contacts these ideas:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Now among these figures, it is
not those imprinted on the external sense organs, or on the internal
surface of the brain, which should be taken to be ideas - but only those
which are traced in the spirits on the surface of gland H *(where the
seat of the imagination and the \'common sense\' is located)*. That is
to say, it is only the latter figures which should be taken to be the
forms or images which the rational soul united to this machine will
consider directly when it imagines some object or perceives it by the
senses.\" Descartes (1664)`</font>`{=html}
See section on
Descartes
for more information and references.
Descartes considered that the soul was a physical point, an unextended
entity that acts like a mind\'s eye. He called this unextended place the
*res cogitans* and concluded that it was a substance that differed from
that of material things:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\".. I thence concluded that I was
a substance whose whole essence or nature consists only in thinking, and
which, that it may exist, has need of no place, nor is dependent on any
material thing; so that \" I,\" that is to say, the mind by which I am
what I am, is wholly distinct from the body, and is even more easily
known than the latter, and is such, that although the latter were not,
it would still continue to be all that it is.\"Descartes
(1637)`</font>`{=html}
This unextended substance that is not material gives the word
\"substance\" a new meaning. It has been attacked as a concept by Locke,
Hume, Berkely and many other philosophers. The concept of there being
two substances, that which composes the physical world and that which
composes the soul, is the origin of the word **Dualism** but dualism, as
a concept, has been extended beyond this original meaning. Cartesian
dualism is a type of **substance dualism**.
Cartesian dualism is an attempt to explain our experience. According to
Descartes something supernatural would be needed for an unextended
viewing point to exist.
Reid\'s **Natural Dualism** also has a point soul looking at things but
proposes that the things in question are forms in the world rather than
in the brain.
### Property dualism
Another sort of dualism has arisen out of a particular interpretation of
the regress and homunculus arguments. These arguments show that
phenomenal experience is not due entirely to flows from place to place
(i.e.: it is not due to classical processes and functions). Property
dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the appropriate way
(i.e. in the way that living human bodies are organized), mental
properties emerge.
As Goldman (1993) pointed out, qualitative experience does not seem to
be needed in a functional description of a system:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"For any functional description
of a system that is in pain (or has an itch), it seems as if we can
imagine another system with the same functional description but lacking
the qualitative property of painfulness (or itchiness).\"
`</font>`{=html}
Certainly a functional system that merely reports the words \"I am in
pain\" when it is dropped on the floor does not require any qualitative
property of painfulness. The *absent qualia* arguments suggest that even
in a large system there would be no need for qualitative properties for
the performance of any classical function.
Chalmers (1993) commenting on Goldman\'s point, said that this implies
that **zombies** might exist, functional replicas of humans but without
qualia. He then denied that a complete functional replica of a human
could exist without also including qualia:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"It seems to me that the only way
to avoid this conclusion is to deny that Zombie Dave is a conceptual
possibility; and the only principled way to deny that Zombie Dave is a
conceptual possibility is to allow that functional organization is
conceptually constitutive of qualitative content.\" Chalmers
(1993).`</font>`{=html}
In other words he identifies qualia with function. According to Chalmers
(1996) qualia are a particular type of function:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"I claim that conscious
experience arises from fine-grained functional organization. More
specifically, I will argue for a principle of organizational invariance,
holding that given any system that has conscious experiences, then any
system that has the same fine-grained functional organization will have
qualitatively identical experiences. According to this principle,
consciousness is an organizational invariant: a property that remains
constant over all functional isomorphs of a given system. Whether the
organization is realized in silicon chips, in the population of China,
or in beer cans and ping-pong balls does not matter. As long as the
functional organisation is right, conscious experience will be
determined.\" p249`</font>`{=html}
Chalmers\' idea of functional organisation has within it a sometimes
vague implication that the functional units must have a particular form;
for instance, in the development of his argument, he refers to "fine
grained" replacement of organic functional units with inorganic units.
Chalmers is actually making two major points, firstly that qualia occur
during the motion of things (functions), secondly that qualia are
independent of any particular substrate.\*\* For the first point to be
consistent with materialism the qualia must have no effect on the
function, they must be **epiphenomenal**. Epiphenomenal qualia would not
be forbidden by the regress and homunculus arguments and would be akin
to Berkeley\'s \"passive ideas\".
Whether or not epiphenomenal qualia are physical depends upon the
definition of the word \"physical\". If physical functions cause qualia
but qualia cannot affect functions then the qualia are \"physical\" in
the sense of being caused by physical events but might be regarded as
non-physical in the sense of being isolated from further physical
events. In philosophical terms they violate the principle of **Causal
Closure**. However, there are other definitions of physicalism based on
arguments such as **Methodological Naturalism** which hold that anything
that can be investigated using the methods of natural science is a
physical thing (see Stoljar 2001). Thus, although epiphenomenal qualia
may not conform to materialism they may be encompassed by physicalism;
as events that are related to material events they are awaiting a
physical theory of how they emerge from a given function.
The reader might consider whether phenomenal consciousness is indeed
epiphenomenal. Empirical reports describe it as something that is
different from the world beyond the body (see direct
realism) -
could we generate empirical reports of an epiphenomenon?
The term **property dualism** describes how physical events might give
rise to a set of properties that cannot be predicted from the fine
structure of the physical system. The \"dualism\" is present because one
set of events is related to two sets of properties, one of which is not
related by materialism to the set of events. In the case of the proposal
about consciousness outlined above an extra assumption, beyond
materialism, would be needed to explain qualia. Property dualism might
be defined as a theory that there could be a theory of consciousness but
that this requires some new assumption.
As far as the \"when and where\" of consciousness are concerned,
property dualism states that it is somewhere in the processes performed
by the organism and the parts of the organism.
`<font size=1>`{=html} \*\* In terms of information processing, Chalmers
is proposing that qualia are the enactment of a particular information
processing structure.`</font>`{=html}
- Block, N. (2006). Max Black\'s objection to mind-body identity.
Oxford Review of Metaphysics No.3.
<http://philrsss.anu.edu.au/BlockFest/MaxBlack.rtf>
- Chalmers, D.J. (1993) Commentary on \"The Psychology of Folk
Psychology\". Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16:35-36, 1993
- Chalmers, D.J. (1996) \"The Conscious Mind: In Search of a
Fundamental Theory\". Oxford University Press. 1996.
- Goldman, A.I., (1993). The Psychology of Folk Psychology. Behavioral
and Brain Sciences 16: 15-28 (1993).
<http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Papers/Py104/goldman.psyc.html>
### Predicate dualism
Predicate dualism is the view espoused by most non-reductive
physicalists, such as Donald Davidson(1980) and Jerry Fodor(1968), who
maintain that while there is only one ontological category of substances
and properties of substances (usually physical), the predicates that we
use to describe mental events cannot be redescribed in terms of (or
reduced to) physical predicates of natural languages. If we characterize
predicate monism as the view subscribed to by eliminative materialists,
who maintain that such intentional predicates as believe, desire, think,
feel, etc., will eventually be eliminated from both the language of
science and from ordinary language because the entities to which they
refer do not exist, then predicate dualism is most easily defined as the
negation of this position. Predicate dualists believe that so-called
\"folk psychology\", with all of its propositional attitude ascriptions,
is an ineliminable part of the enterprise of describing, explaining and
understanding human mental states and behavior.
Davidson, for example, subscribes to Anomalous Monism, according to
which there can be no strict psycho-physical laws which connect mental
and physical events under their descriptions as mental and physical
events. However, all mental events also have physical descriptions. It
is in terms of the latter that such events can be connected in law-like
relations with other physical events. Mental predicates are irreducibly
different in character (rational, holistic and necessary) from physical
predicates (contingent, atomic and causal).
(Section based on Wikipedia article)
- Davidson, D (1980). Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford University
Press.
- Fodor,J. (1968) *Psychological Explanation*, Random House.
.
### The interaction between mind and brain in dualism
#### Interactionism
Interactionism is the view that mental states, such as beliefs and
desires, causally interact with physical states. This is a position
which is very appealing to common-sense intuitions, notwithstanding the
fact that it is very difficult to establish its validity or correctness
by way of logical argumentation or empirical proof. It is appealing to
common-sense because we are surrounded by such everyday occurrences as a
child\'s touching a hot stove (physical event) which causes him to feel
pain (mental event) and then yell and scream (physical event) which
causes his parents to experience a sensation of fear and protectiveness
(mental event) and so on.
#### Epiphenomalism
According to epiphenomenalism, all mental events are caused by a
physical event and have no physical consequences. So, a mental event of
deciding to pick up a rock (call it \"M\") is caused by the firing of
specific neurons in the brain (call it \"P\"), however when the arm and
hand move to pick up a rock (call it \"E\") this is only caused by P.
The physical causes are in principle reducible to fundamental physics,
and therefore mental causes are eliminated using this reductionist
explanation. If P causes M and E, there is no overdetermination in the
explanation for E.
#### Parallelism
Psycho-physical parallelism is a very unusual view about the interaction
between mental and physical events which was most prominently, and
perhaps only truly, advocated by Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz. Like
Malebranche and others before him, Leibniz recognized the weaknesses of
Descartes\' account of causal interaction taking place in a physical
location in the brain. Malebranche decided that such a material basis of
interaction between material and immaterial was impossible and therefore
formulated his doctrine of occasionalism, stating that the interactions
were really caused by the intervention of God on each individual
occasion. Leibniz idea is that God has created a pre-established harmony
such that it only seems as if physical and mental events cause, and are
caused by, one another. In reality, mental causes only have mental
effects and physical causes only have physical effects. Hence the term
parallelism is used to describe this view.
#### Occasionalism
Occasionalism argues that bodily events are the occasion of an act by
the Creator causing a corresponding mental event, and vice versa. Any
such view requires a theological structure as a premise.
#### Further reading
- Robinson, Howard, \"Dualism\", The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Fall 2003 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2003/entries/dualism/>
- Robinson, H. (2003) \"Dualism\", in S. Stich and T. Warfield (eds)
The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell, Oxford,
85-101.
- Amoroso, R.L. (2010) \"The complementarity of Mind and Body:
Realizing the Dream of Descartes, Einstein and Eccles\", New York:
Nova Science Publishers,
`, ``https://www.novapublishers.com/catalog/product_info.php?products_id=12759`
## Idealism
According to Idealism only the mental truly exists.
The form and content of personal conscious experience might be related
to the structure of the world and brain in several ways. It could be a
**solipsism** or be the mind of God.
*This is a **stub** and needs expansion*.
## Panpsychism
### Etymology
Ancient Greek *pan* (πᾶν : \"all, everything, whole\") and *psyche*
(ψυχή : \"soul, mind\").[^1] Psyche is the from
ψύχω (*psukhō*, \"I blow\") and means mind or \'life-breath\'.
Philip Goff, a proponent of panpsychism, carves out a distinction
between panexperientialism and pancognitivism. Panexperientialism is the
belief that *experience* is ubiquitous, while pancognitivism is the
belief that *cognition* is ubiquitous. Most modern purponents of
panpsychism, such as Annaka Harris and David Chalmers, are careful to
distance themselves from pancognitivism.
In some interpretations, such as monadism, Panpsychism and Idealism can
overlap because the universe is conceived as being composed of an
infinity of point consciousnesses that each contain information about
the whole universe.
The form and content of personal conscious experience might be related
to the structure of the world and brain in many ways.
*This is a **stub** and needs expansion*.
## References
Seager W. & Allen-Hermanson (2001). 'Panpsychism.' Online document:
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, \[online\],
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/panpsychism/>, \[accessed 10/2005\]
**Supervenience**
- Chalmers, D.J. (1996). The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press.
**The problem of regression**
- Ryle, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind. The University of Chicago
Press, 1949.
**The homunculus argument**
- Gregory, R.L. (1990) Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing, Oxford
University Press Inc. New York.
- Gregory, T.L. (1987). The Oxford Companion to Mind. Oxford
University Press.
**Subject-object paradox**
- James, W. (1904)Does \'Consciousness\' Exist? Journal of
Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1,
477-491.
- Hegel, G.W.F. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND: SECTION I. MIND SUBJECTIVE B.
PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND CONSCIOUSNESS Part Three of the Encyclopaedia
of the Philosophical
Sciences
- Velmans, M. (1996) Consciousness and the \"Casual Paradox\".
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 19 (3):
538-542.
- Bermudez, J.L. (1999) The Paradox of Self-Consciousness
(representation and Mind) Psycoloquy:
10,#35
**Ontological status**
- Bierman, D.J. (2004) Non Conscious Processes Preceding Intuitive
decisions
<http://m0134.fmg.uva.nl/~djb/publications/2004/Intuition_bialsymp2004.pdf>
- Damasio, A.R. (1994). Descartes\' error: Emotion, reason and the
human brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam Book.
- Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason
<http://www.arts.cuhk.edu.hk/Philosophy/Kant/cpr/>
**Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness**
Block, N. (1995) On a confusion about a function of consciousness.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 227-287.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/documents/a/00/00/04/31/bbs00000431-00/bbs.block.html>
Block, N. (2004). *The Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science*.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/ecs.pdf>
Dennett, D. (1978). Why You Can\'t Make a Computer that Feels Pain, in:
Brainstorms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 190-229.
Dennett, D. (1988). Quining Qualia. in A. Marcel and E. Bisiach, eds,
Consciousness in Modern Science, Oxford University Press 1988. Reprinted
in W. Lycan, ed., Mind and Cognition: A Reader, MIT Press, 1990, A.
Goldman, ed. Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science, MIT Press,
1993. <http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/quinqual.htm>
Edelman, G.M. (1993). Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the
Mind. New York:
Feyerabend, P. (1963). Mental Events and the Brain, Journal of
Philosophy 40:295-6.
Huxley, T. H. (1874). On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and
its History, The Fortnightly Review, n.s.16:555-580. Reprinted in Method
and Results: Essays by Thomas H. Huxley (New York: D. Appleton and
Company, 1898).
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review
LXXXIII, 4 (October 1974): 435-50.
<http://web.archive.org/19990218140703/members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html>
Rey, Georges, (1997). Contemporary Philosophy of Mind.Blackwell: Oxford
Sellars W. (1956). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, In: Feigl H
and Scriven M (eds) The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of
Psychology and Psychoanalysis: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of
Science, Vol. 1. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 253-329
Whitehead, A.N. (1920). The Concept of Nature. Chapter 3: Time.
<http://spartan.ac.brocku.ca/~lward/Whitehead/Whitehead_1920/White1_03.html>
**Direct Realism**
- Austin, J.L. (1962) Sense and Sensibilia, ed. by Geoffrey J. Warnock
(Oxford, 1962)
- Aydede, M. (2001) Naturalism, introspection, and direct realism
about pain. Consciousness and Emotion, Vol. 2, No. 1, 2001,
pp. 29--73.
<http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/maydede/pain.pdf>
- Chapman, C.R., and Y. Nakamura (1999). A Passion of the Soul: An
Introduction to Pain for Consciousness Researchers. Consciousness
and Cognition, 8: 391-422.
- Dennett, D. (1991a). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown
- Dennett, D. (1991b). Lovely and suspect qualities. Commentary on
David Rosenthal, \"The Independence of Consciousness and Sensory
Quality\" in E. Villanueva, ed., Consciousness, (SOFIA Conference,
Buenos Aires), Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview 1991.
<http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/lovely&s.htm>
- Fowler C A (1986): "An event approach to the study of speech
perception from a direct-realist perspective", J of Phonetics
14(1):3-28.
- Gibson, J. J. (1966) The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems.
Houghton Mifflin Company,Boston.
- Gibson, J. J. (1979) Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Hillsdate.
- Gregory, R.L. 1988. Consciousness in science and philosophy:
conscience and con-science. Chapter 12 in Consciousness in
Contemporary Science. (Editors: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E.).
Oxford Science Publications.
- Le Morvan, Pierre (2004). Arguments against direct realism and how
to counter them. *The American Philosophical Quarterly*, *41*(3),
221-234.\] (pdf) <http://www.tcnj.edu/~lemorvan/DR_web.pdf>
- Michaels, C. F. and Carello, C. (1981). Direct Perception. Century
Psychology Series. Prentice-Hall.
. 1981. Download this book at
<http://ione.psy.uconn.edu/~psy254/MC.pdf>
- Oliveira, André L. G. and Oliveira, Luis F. (2002) Toward an
ecological conception of timbre. In Proceedings Auditory Perception
Cognition and Action Meeting 2002, Kansas City.
<http://cogprints.org/2713/>
- Skinner, B. F. Science and Human Behavior . New York: Macmillan,
1953.
- Skinner, B. F. 1971. Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New York: Knopf.
- Skinner, B. F. 1948. Walden Two. New York: Macmillan.
- Tye, M. (2004). ANOTHER LOOK AT REPRESENTATIONALISM ABOUT PAIN.
Consciousness and Emotion 2004, special issue on pain, edited by
Murat Aydede (with replies by M. Aydede, N. Block, B. Maund, and P.
Noordhof
<http://sun.soci.niu.edu/~phildept/MT/RepresentationalismAndPain.pdf>
- Vygotsky, L.S.(1925) Consciousness as a problem in the psychology of
behavior. Undiscovered Vygotsky: Etudes on the pre-history of
cultural-historical psychology (European Studies in the History of
Science and Ideas. Vol. 8), pp. 251--281. Peter Lang Publishing.
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/1925/consciousness.htm>
- Ziff, Paul. \"About Behaviourism.\" Analysis 18 (1958): 132-136.
Quoted by Larry Hauser in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/b/behavior.htm#B>. F. Skinner:
Radical Behaviorism
**Indirect Realism**
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
- Rizzo, M., Nawrot, M. & Zihl, J. (1995). Motion and shape perception
in cerebral akinetopsia.Brain, 118. 1105-1127.
<http://nawrot.psych.ndsu.nodak.edu/Publications/Nawrot.pdf/RizzoNawrotZihl.1995.pdf>
- Russell, B. (1912). Problems of Philosophy. Home University Library.
<http://www.ditext.com/russell/rus1.html>
- Tye, M. (2003) Qualia. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia/#Repqualia>
Further reading:
- Hume, D. (1739). A Treatise of Human Nature.
<http://www.class.uidaho.edu/mickelsen/ToC/hume%20treatise%20ToC.htm>
- Firth, R. (1949) Sense Data and the Percept Theory, Mind, 58 (1949);
59 (1950). (Describes early reasons for rejecting Indirect Realism)
<http://www.ditext.com/firth/spt.html>
- Grush, R. (2000). Self, world and space: The meaning and mechanisms
of ego- and allocentric spatial representation. Brain and Mind
1(1):59-92.
<http://mind.ucsd.edu/papers/sws/sws.html>
[^1]: Clarke, D.S. *Panpsychism: Past and Recent Selected Readings*.
State University of New York Press, 2004. p.1
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Conflict2#Direct realism
*This part of this section is about the where and when of the experience
called consciousness. Is it in the world, in the brain or are the world
and brain within it?*
## Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness
Block(1995) drew attention to the way that there appear to be two types
of consciousness: *phenomenal* consciousness and *access* consciousness:
`Phenomenal consciousness is experience; the phenomenally`\
`conscious aspect of a state is what it is like to be in that`\
`state. The mark of access-consciousness, by contrast, is `\
`availability for use in reasoning and rationally guiding speech `\
`and action. (Block 1995).`
*See the section on Ned Block\'s
ideas
for a deeper coverage of his approach to access and phenomenal
consciousness.*
Block uses Nagel\'s famous (1974) paper, \"What is it like to be a
bat?\" as an exemplary description of phenomenal consciousness.
Excellent descriptions have also been proffered by the empiricist
philosophers who gave lengthy descriptions of consciousness as partly
experience itself. Although Block has formalised the idea of phenomenal
and access consciousness similar ideas have also been put forward by
many philosophers including Kant and Whitehead.
Access consciousness has two interpretations, in the first, used by
Block, it applies to the functions that appear to operate on phenomenal
consciousness. In the second, used by the behaviourists and
eliminativists, it is some property of the functions of the brain that
can be called \'consciousness\'.
This division between phenomenal and functional aspects of consciousness
is useful because it emphasises the idea of phenomenal consciousness as
observation rather than action. Some philosophers such as Huxley in
1874, have taken the view that because phenomenal consciousness appears
to have no function it is of no importance or cannot exist. James (1879)
introduced the term \"epiphenomenalism\" to summarise the idea that
consciousness has no function.
The idea that phenomenal consciousness cannot exist is a type of
*Eliminativism* (also known as Eliminative Materialism). Eliminativism
owes much to the work of Sellars(1956) and Feyerbend (1963). Dennett
(1978) applied Eliminativism to phenomenal consciousness and denies that
pain is real. Others such as Rey(1997) have also applied eliminativism
to phenomenal consciousness.
Dennett (1988) redefines consciousness in terms of access consciousness
alone, he argues that \"Everything real has properties, and since I
don\'t deny the reality of conscious experience, I grant that conscious
experience has properties\". Having related all consciousness to
properties he then declares that these properties are actually
judgements of properties. He considers judgements of the properties of
consciousness to be identical to the properties themselves. He writes:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"The infallibilist line on qualia treats
them as properties of one\'s experience one cannot in principle
misdiscover, and this is a mysterious doctrine (at least as mysterious
as papal infallibility) unless we shift the emphasis a little and treat
qualia as logical constructs out of subjects\' qualia-judgments: a
subject\'s experience has the quale F if and only if the subject judges
his experience to have quale F. \"`</font>`{=html}
Having identified \"properties\" with \"judgement of properties\" he can
then show that the judgements are insubstantial, hence the properties
are insubstantial and hence the qualia are insubstantial or even
non-existent. Dennett concludes that qualia can be rejected as
non-existent:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"So when we look one last time at our
original characterization of qualia, as ineffable, intrinsic, private,
directly apprehensible properties of experience, we find that there is
nothing to fill the bill. In their place are relatively or practically
ineffable public properties we can refer to indirectly via reference to
our private property-detectors\-- private only in the sense of
idiosyncratic. And insofar as we wish to cling to our subjective
authority about the occurrence within us of states of certain types or
with certain properties, we can have some authority\--not infallibility
or incorrigibility, but something better than sheer guessing\--but only
if we restrict ourselves to relational, extrinsic properties like the
power of certain internal states of ours to provoke acts of apparent re-
identification. So contrary to what seems obvious at first blush, there
simply are no qualia at all. \" (Dennett 1988)`</font>`{=html}
Dennett\'s asserts that \"a subject\'s experience has the quale F if and
only if the subject judges his experience to have quale F\". This is a
statement of the belief that qualia are the same as processes such as
judgements. Processes such as judgements are flows of data where one
state examines a previous state in a succession over time and embody
what Whitehead called the \"materialist\" concept of time. Dennett does
not consider how a scientific concept of time might affect his argument.
Dennett\'s argument has been persuasive and there are now many
philosophers and neuroscientists who believe that the problem of
phenomenal consciousness does not exist. This means that, to them, what
we call \'consciousness\' can only be a property of the functions
performed by the brain and body. According to these philosophers only
access consciousness exists.
Those who support the idea of phenomenal consciousness also tend to
frame it in terms of nineteenth century theory where one state examines
a previous state in a succession over time, for instance Edelman(1993)
places the past in memories at an instant and time within experience is
explained as continuing modelling processes:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"Primary consciousness is the state of
being mentally aware of things in the world\--of having mental images in
the present. But it is not accompanied by any sense of a person with a
past and a future\.... In contrast, higher-order consciousness involves
the recognition by a thinking subject of his or her own acts or
affections. It embodies a model of the personal, and of the past and the
future as well as the present. It exhibits direct awareness\--the
noninferential or immediate awareness of mental episodes without the
involvement of sense organs or receptors. It is what we humans have in
addition to primary consciousness. We are conscious of being
conscious.\" `</font>`{=html}
Block(2004) also suggests this flow from state to state in his idea of
\"Reflexivity\" where our idea of familiarity with an object is due to
one state being analysed by another:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"Thus in the "conscious" case, the subject
must have a state that is about the subject's own perceptual experience
(looking familiar) and thus conscious in what might be termed a
"reflexive" sense. An experience is conscious in this sense just in case
it is the object of another of the subject's states; for example, one
has a thought to the effect that one has that experience. The reflexive
sense of \'consciousness\' contrasts with phenomenality, which perhaps
attaches to some states which are not the objects of other mental
states. Reflexive consciousness might better be called 'awareness' than
'consciousness'. Reflexivity is phenomenality plus something else
(reflection) and that opens up the possibility in principle for
phenomenality without reflection. For example, it is at least
conceptually possible for there to be two people in pain, one of whom is
introspecting the pain the other not. (Perhaps infants or animals can
have pain but don't introspect it.) The first is reflexively conscious
of the pain, but both have phenomenally conscious states, since pain is
by its very nature a phenomenally conscious state. \"`</font>`{=html}
Both Block and Edelman allow phenomenal consciousness, our experience,
as an unexplained phenomenon. Block, Edelman and also Dennett\'s ideas
of consciousness are shown in the illustration below:
![](Constudphen.gif "Constudphen.gif")
This model differs from the empirical reports of phenomenal
consciousness that were considered earlier. According to the empirical
reports the present moment in our experience is extended so the
succession of outputs or stages of access consciousness could constitute
the contents of phenomenal consciousness. In other words phenomenal
consciousness is composed of periods of access consciousness. This is
how it seems to the empiricist and in our own experience but how such a
state could be explained in terms of brain activity is highly
problematical. Given that nineteenth century ideas cannot explain such a
state a scientific explanation will be required.
The idea that phenomenal consciousness misrepresents or \"misdiscovers\"
itself (Dennett 1988) deserves further discussion. According to
materialism the present instant has no duration so can only be known in
succeeding instants as a report or memory and this could be wrong.
Whitehead considered that this viewpoint originates in an archaic view
of science, particularly the concept of time in science:
\"The eighteenth and nineteenth centuries accepted as their natural
philosophy a certain circle of concepts which were as rigid and definite
as those of the philosophy of the middle ages, and were accepted with as
little critical research. I will call this natural philosophy
\'materialism.\' Not only were men of science materialists, but also
adherents of all schools of philosophy. The idealists only differed from
the philosophic materialists on question of the alignment of nature in
reference to mind. But no one had any doubt that the philosophy of
nature considered in itself was of the type which I have called
materialism. It is the philosophy which I have already examined in my
two lectures of this course preceding the present one. It can be
summarised as the belief that nature is an aggregate of material and
that this material exists in some sense at each successive member of a
one-dimensional series of extensionless instants of time. Furthermore
the mutual relations of the material entities at each instant formed
these entities into a spatial configuration in an unbounded space. It
would seem that space\-\--on this theory-would be as instantaneous as
the instants, and that some explanation is required of the relations
between the successive instantaneous spaces. The materialistic theory is
however silent on this point; and the succession of instantaneous spaces
is tacitly combined into one persistent space. This theory is a purely
intellectual rendering of experience which has had the luck to get
itself formulated at the dawn of scientific thought. It has dominated
the language and the imagination of science since science flourished in
Alexandria, with the result that it is now hardly possible to speak
without appearing to assume its immediate obviousness.\" (Whitehead
1920).
## Direct Realism and Direct Perception
Direct Realism proposes that phenomenal experience is directly objects
in the world without any intervening representation. It is motivated by
the belief that the Problem of Regression, the Subject-Object Paradox
and the recursion form of the Homunculus arguments show that phenomenal
consciousness cannot occur in the brain alone. Direct Realists reason
that if phenomenal consciousness cannot be things in the brain then it
must be something outside the brain.
There are two principle types of Direct Realism: Natural Dualism and
Behaviourism (both Radical and Analytical). Some behaviourists use the
term "Direct Perception" rather than Direct Realism and consider that
only the invariant parts of perception are direct (see for instance
Michaels and Carello 1981). Thomas Reid is generally regarded as the
founder of Direct Realism. In his Natural Dualism he proposed that the
soul is in direct contact with the contents of experience and these
contents are things in the world beyond the body. The Direct Realism of
Reid is summarised in the statement of his famous disciple Sir William
Hamilton: \"In the simplest act of perception I am conscious of myself
as the perceiving subject and of an external reality as the object
perceived\". Reid\'s Natural Dualism has now been largely replaced by
radical and analytical behaviourism which eschew the idea of a soul and
propose that phenomenal consciousness, if it exists at all, is a
behavioural reflex.
The modern justification of Direct Realism mainly consists of arguments
against Indirect Realism or Representationalism. Philosophers such as
Austin (1962) and Le Morvan (2004) have summarised the Direct Realism
debate and have identified the following arguments in favour of Indirect
Realism and given rebuttals to each of them:
1\. The Causal Argument: perception involves a succession of causal
events such as the reflection of photons, bleaching of retinal pigments
etc. so perception must involve the end of this causal chain. The Direct
Realist response is that, although there may be a causal chain in
sensation this does not inevitably imply that the end of the chain is
the content of phenomenal experience.
2\. The Time Lag Argument: it takes time for light to travel from an
object to the senses, time for chemical changes in the retina etc\...
The Direct Realist response is that direct perception may be referred
back in time.
3\. The Partial Character of Perception Argument: we only perceive the
surface of objects, and then only a part of the surface. As the whole
object would be perceived directly perception must be indirect. The
Direct Realist response is that direct perception could occur even if
only parts of an object were perceived.
4\. The Perceptual Relativity Argument: things appear to be different
shapes depending upon the point of view. The Direct Realist response is
that if perception can occur backwards in time it should have no problem
occurring back down a line of sight. However, Le Morvan\'s argument does
not seem to encompass the geometrical nature of phenomenal experience,
seeking to explain geometry in terms of movement.
5\. The Argument from Perceptual Illusion: A stick may appear bent when
projecting from the surface of water. Direct Realists apply the argument
used in (4) to this problem. The bent stick illusion is a physical event
in the world beyond the eye rather than a normal optical illusion such
as the Muller-Lyer illusion etc., see (6) for a discussion of optical
illusions.
6\. The Argument from Hallucination: Hallucinations are not in the world
beyond the body. This is highly problematical for Direct Realists
especially when phenomena such as lucid dreams, dreams and visual
imaginations are included along with hallucinations. Direct Realists
classify these phenomena as not being perceptions or deny that they
actually exist as phenomena. Indirect Realists would maintain that all
of perception is a reconstruction and use optical illusions such as the
Muller-Lyer, Ames Room etc. to justify this contention so the Direct
Realist approach to hallucination, dreams etc. might seem like an
unwillingness to accept Indirect Realism rather than an argument.
7\. The Dubitability Argument (cf: Indubitability argument): we cannot
doubt current phenomenal experience but we can doubt the world beyond
the body therefore phenomenal experience is not the world beyond the
body. Direct Realists fall back on Presentism or functional Presentism
to defeat this argument. If phenomenal experience is instantaneous and
made anew at each instant then anything can be doubted.
The points above have summarised the Direct Realist stance on visual
perception. Other sensory modalities have also been considered in the
Direct Realism debate.
Fowler (1986) considered that sounds were attached to objects in the
world. This idea is strange because sounds only seem to be closely
attached to objects in the world when these objects are seen as well as
heard. For example, when a subject is blindfolded it is found that there
can be a large error in locating the position of a sound in the world,
this is especially true for low frequency sounds. The Direct Realist
approach has difficulty explaining the transition from sounds with an
indefinite location when a subject is blindfolded to sounds that are
bound to visual events when the blindfold is removed. It also runs into
problems explaining how the sound of speech from a single loudspeaker
can become bound to lip movements on a cinema screen. If the binding
does not occur in the brain then where does it occur?
Pain is particularly problematic for Direct Realism because, unlike
colour vision where \'red\' is inferred to be a property of electrons or
light, pain is an inner experience that is not a property of tissue
damage. Tissue damage has properties such as bleeding, wheal formation
etc. but pain seems to be phenomenal experience in the brain and
\'phantom pain\' can occur without tissue damage (see Aydede (2001), Tye
(2004) and Chapman, and Nakamura (1999) for further analysis). On closer
inspection other sensations also appear to be inner experiences rather
than direct sensations. For instance, the red crosses of different hues
in the illustration below are all due to the same physical wavelengths
of light. In this case the range of hues in experience is unrelated to
the actual physical red on the page or screen.
Another problem for Direct Realism is that it does not overcome the
problems that it is supposed to solve. The argument for Direct Realism
begins with the idea that there are severe problems with
representationalism (the idea that phenomenal experience is in the
brain) and that direct perception is an alternative that does not have
these problems. However on closer inspection Direct Realism suffers from
almost same problems as representationalism. If phenomenal experience is
the world itself then Ryle\'s regress applies to the world itself and
this can only be avoided by assuming that phenomenal experience is a
subset of the world (i.e.: a representation) that receives input from
other parts of the world that are not part of phenomenal experience.
It is also commonly assumed that Direct Realism avoids the recursion
argument because it is believed that the separation of the observer from
the things that are observed is simply due to the geometry of the world.
If such simple geometry is possible between the eye and the world then
it should also be possible in the brain and a similar geometrical
explanation could be invoked to avoid recursion in representations.
These points are shown in the illustration below:
image:Constuddir1.gif
Scientists have a further problem with Direct Realism. The illustration
below demonstrates that our scientific knowledge of the world differs
markedly from our phenomenal experience.
image:constuddirect.gif
It is difficult to see how the form and content of phenomenal experience
could supervene directly on the world beyond the body. The world
inferred from measurements beyond the body seems to be a nebulous set of
quantum phenomena that are arranged as probability fields in three
dimensions at any instant. The objects in this real world are mostly
space. The world of phenomenal experience on the other hand contains
objects that are one-sided, and are like a 2 dimensional field of
vectors directed simultaneously at an observation point which is
apparently separate from them. Phenomenal experience is not three
dimensional, the rear of objects is not available within it at any
instant. Visual phenomenal experience seems to be a geometrical
relationship between an abstract observation point and the reflection
properties of the part of the world external to the body. It is a form
that crudely overlies the angular separations in inferred reality,
providing approximate directional data. It is not like things in
themselves beyond the body, not even in type, being a set of directional
vectors. (See the module on the neuroscience of perception for a
discussion of depth perception).
If the form and content of visual phenomenal experience are abstractions
separated according to the angular positions of things in the world
beyond the body then theories which propose that phenomenal experience
is the world itself are problematical. It should be noted that things
arranged according to angular positions can appear to overlie any group
of similar things along a radius from the centre point.
![](Constuddirectangle.gif "Constuddirectangle.gif")
If Direct Realists admit that things are as they appear to be, observed
according to angular positions at a \'point eye\', then any
representation of things on the inside of a sphere of any radius would
appear similar. The geometry of the \'point eye\' is problematical
whether the view contains the world itself or a representation of the
world; it cannot be the movements of lumps of matter or energy and the
point observation cannot be due to lumps all landing at a point. In
other words the \'view\' is inconsistent with nineteenth century
materialism and will require a scientific explanation.
Radical and Analytical Behaviourism tackle the problem of the difference
between the world inferred from measurements beyond the body and the
phenomenal world by denying phenomenal consciousness and maintaining
that access and reflex consciousness are all that exists or is
necessary. Radical Behaviourism is an offshoot of psychological
behaviourism and was established as a philosophical adjunct to Marxism
by Vygotsky and popularised by Burrhus Frederic Skinner (see Skinner
1953). There is another movement in psychological behaviourism which is
similar to Radical Behaviourism called Ecological Psychology (see Gibson
1966, 1979 and also Michaels and Carello 1981). Analytical Behaviourism
is a philosophical movement established by Gilbert Ryle (see Ryle 1949).
The core of Analytical and Radical Behaviourism is the assumption that
consciousness exists for a durationless instant so that the Dubitability
Argument and the Regression and Recursion Arguments can be applied (Ryle
1949, Skinner 1971 and see the sections on Ryle\'s Regress and the
Subject-Object Paradox above). As a result the Direct Realist is able to
insinuate that subjects only think that they have had a particular
experience (cf: Dennett 1991a). It is intriguing that Eliminativists
also maintain that experience is the world itself, for instance an
insight into Dennett\'s idea of the mind is to be found on pages 407-408
of Consciousness Explained:
\"It seemed to him, according to the text, as if his mind - his visual
field - were filled with intricate details of gold-green buds an
wiggling branches, but although this is how it seemed this was an
illusion. No such \"plenum\" ever came into his mind; the plenum
remained out in the world where it is didn\'t have to be represented,
but could just be. When we marvel, in those moments of heightened
self-consciousness, at the glorious richness of our conscious
experience, the richness we marvel at is actually the richness of the
world outside, in all its ravishing detail. It does not \"enter\" our
conscious minds, but is simply available\"
This is a clear description of Direct Realism (although Dennett does not
describe himself as a direct realist).
Radical Behaviourism is sometimes described as the dictum that the only
psychological events that are of importance are those that occur outside
the head. The absurdity of this has led to jokes:
Q: What does one behaviorist say to another when they meet on the
street?
A: You\'re fine. How am I?
Q: What does one behaviorist say to another after sex?
A: That was great for you. How was it for me?
(Ziff 1958)
However Vygotsky, Skinner and other Radical Behaviourists hold that
inner behaviour is possible so that events within the brain can result
in reward or punishment. Vygotsky (1925) describes this approach:
\"Consciousness is wholly reduced to the transmitting mechanisms of
reflexes operating according to general laws, i.e., no processes other
than reactions can be admitted into the organism. The way is also paved
for the solution of the problem of self-awareness and self-observation.
Inner perception and introspection are possible only thanks to the
existence of a proprioceptive field and secondary reflexes, which are
connected with it. This is always the echo of a reaction.\"
Hence Radical Behaviourists are able to make the claim that what are
believed to be representations with phenomenal content are processes.
Even events such as pain can then be explained as reflexes involving
organs within the skin. However, by opening the possibility that such
reflexes could occur at any sense organ, including the eye, this makes
Radical Behaviourism a mixed Direct Realist/Indirect Realist philosophy
with consciousness as a process, not a separate thing such as phenomenal
consciousness (see the section on representationalism and intentionality
below).
But this raises a serious issue for science: can the phenomenal
consciousness that seems to contain our observations really be argued
out of existence on the basis of a theory? As Gregory (1988) put it: "
'If you can't explain it -- deny it' is one strategy for dealing with
embarrassing questions such as 'what is consciousness?' ". But is this
the right strategy?
Direct Realism fails to overcome the problems of regression and
recursion inherent in representations. It proposes that phenomenal
consciousness is identical to the physical world beyond the body but
must then use a plethora of arguments to explain why this is evidently
not so. When confronted with these problems its proponents resort to the
argument that everything can be doubted and can misrepresent itself. Yet
it is still widely believed.
It should be noted that Direct Realism is espoused in Religious Natural
Dualism, some forms of Augustinian theology, nineteenth century
materialism and its offspring such as Marxism, post-modernism,
post-Marxism, and various sociological movements. It is also necessary
for some forms of Strong AI to occur. Perhaps this explains why few
ideas have attracted as much attention and defence as Direct Realism.
It is interesting to compare the Direct Realist and Indirect Realist
interpretations of something as simple as a cartoon on television (such
as the image below). According to Indirect Realism the cartoon would be
a moving representation constructed in the brain using data from the
senses. This leads to the prediction of brain mechanisms for modelling
motions, combining colours, binding sound and vision etc., many of which
have been verified. Can you demonstrate how the theory of Direct Realism
could explain the phenomenal experience that contains the cartoon and
produce a list of the predictions made by the theory?
![](constudcartoon.gif "constudcartoon.gif")
In science a theory should be of predictive value, for instance,
information theory describes how the state of a thing can be impressed
on a carrier so that a signal can be transmitted from one place to
another. This theory predicts what will happen when the signal arrives
at its destination and how the state of the source can be inferred from
the events at the destination, the total amount of information that can
be transmitted etc. At the destination it is the form of the signal that
is directly known by interaction and measurement, the form of the source
is inferred. Direct Realism is a direct challenge to this information
theory but does it deliver a more powerful predictive description of
phenomenal consciousness or is experience always dependent on what
happens to the information flow between things in the world and
somewhere in the brain? Does direct realism have a physical theory?
Ultimately it appears as if Direct Realism is about various
understandings of Information Theory. For example, Austin (1962)
discusses what we see when we see a church camouflaged as a barn and
comments that: \"We see, of course, a church that now looks like a
barn.\". Do we see a church or a barn? Scientific information theory is
clear about this, the church is an entity composed of selected
information from the quantum state of its constituents, the optical
image of a camouflaged church is an arrangement of photons emanating
from a screen on which it is projected, the retina has an arrangement of
chemical and electrical events based on an optical image and conscious
visual experience correlates with the arrangement of things on the
retina. The fact that conscious experience also correlates with
classifications of the retinal image as a barn or a church suggests that
conscious experience is an arrangement of things in the brain based on
both the retinal arrangement and the contents of a relational database.
Austin\'s arguments have been mythologised as a final demonstration that
\"sense data\" theories are false. However, as will be seen below, sense
data theories merely claim that there is a succession of information
states between an information state outside the body and that reported
as conscious experience i.e.: subjects report that a church is
camouflaged when it is camouflaged.
## Indirect Realism
Indirect realism proposes that phenomenal consciousness exists and is a
set of signals or **sense data**, usually in the brain. This was
proposed by philosophers from Aristotle to Locke and was probably the
most widespread idea of conscious experience until the eighteenth
century.
The idea of sense data is discussed in depth by Russell (1912).
Russell\'s original definition is given below:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Let us give the name of
\'sense-data\' to the things that are immediately known in sensation:
such things as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and so
on. We shall give the name \'sensation\' to the experience of being
immediately aware of these things. Thus, whenever we see a colour, we
have a sensation of the colour, but the colour itself is a sense-datum,
not a sensation. The colour is that of which we are immediately aware,
and the awareness itself is the sensation. It is plain that if we are to
know anything about the table, it must be by means of the sense-data \--
brown colour, oblong shape, smoothness, etc. \-- which we associate with
the table; but, for the reasons which have been given, we cannot say
that the table is the sense-data, or even that the sense-data are
directly properties of the table.\"`</font>`{=html}
Russell\'s definition is a materialist concept in which experience is
always **of** something because the durationless instant of the present
has always gone. As such it differs from some empiricist ideas where
experience is not confined to the durationless instant.
Science is Indirect Realist because it holds that the scientist can only
make **measurements** of events in the world. These measurements give
rise to signals as a result of interaction with the event. According to
**decoherence theory** the signals are a state that is a mixture of the
state of the measuring instrument and the state of the thing being
measured. For example, the eyes are measuring instruments that are
sensitive to photons, photons are signals containing a state that is
based on the state of electrons in a surface and the state of electrons
is based on the state of the surface etc. Scientific inference allows
some aspects of the state of the surface to be inferred from the state
of the photons.
In modern Indirect Realism there is an attempt to distinguish the
phenomenal content of conscious experience from the processing involved
in accessing this phenomenal content. According to these theories
phenomenal experience is an arrangement of signals that are the content
of the experience. This arrangement forms a *representation* of things
in the world so this form of indirect realism is known as
**Representationalism**. Tye (2003) describes types of
representationalist theory:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Representationalism, as I have
presented it so far, is an identity thesis with respect to qualia:
qualia are supposedly one and the same as certain representational
contents.\"`</font>`{=html}
Tye also describes variants of this idea of representationalism:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Sometimes it is held instead
that qualia are one and the same as certain representational properties
of experiences; and sometimes it is is argued that these
representational properties are themselves irreducible (Siewert 1998).
There is also a weaker version of representationalism, according to
which it is metaphysically necessary that experiences exactly alike with
respect to their representational contents are exactly alike with
respect to their qualia. Obviously, this supervenience thesis leaves
open the further question as to the essential nature of
qualia.\"`</font>`{=html} (Tye 2003).
In a scientific sense Direct Realists believe that phenomenal experience
is the signals that occur next to things in the world beyond the body
(which they call \"things in themselves\") and Indirect Realists usually
believe that phenomenal experience is signals in the brain. It can be
seen from the pattern of signal flow that the signals travelling into
the brain preserve the spatial relationships of the original signals and
encode the properties in the original signals. This means that the
original signals next to the QM sources and the signals in the brain are
equivalent provided the latter are oriented appropriately relative to
signals from the body. Either set of signals could transmit or contain
the same information. Both Direct and Indirect Realism cannot, at
present, explain the physics of how a viewing point occurs in experience
i.e.: how we seem to see through an apparent space to the signals that
are the contents of experience. So the choice between Direct Realism and
Indirect Realism reduces to whether there is only one set of signals or
a chain of signals between the world and phenomenal experience.
The philosophical arguments for Indirect Realism are listed below:
1\. Variable perspective: when we see things the view changes so what we
see must be a different set of signals depending on the view rather than
a constant object.
2\. Illusions: we can see through fingers and see a variety of colours
where measurements tell us one exists. Direct Realists quote the \"bent
stick illusion\", which is not really an illusion at all, being a
physical event.
3\. Hallucinations: two people can have phenomenal experience containing
a table. The first may be viewing a real table whereas the second may be
hallucinating a table. If the tables are the same (phenomenally) then
experience is indirect.
4\. Double vision: press the side of one eye, two images appear (cf Hume
1739) yet there are not two things in the world.
5\. Time gap arguments: according to materialism the past has gone. The
things being seen no longer exist in the state that relates to the state
in experience. In the extreme case, some stars in the night sky no
longer exist but are still in experience so experience must be a derived
signal.
6\. Secondary qualities such as pain, colour and smell do not exist as
physical things in the source of signals and are likely to be properties
of signals in the brain.
![](constudindirect.gif "constudindirect.gif")
Indirect Realism has received strong support from recent discoveries in
neuroscience, for example, it is now clear that both the colour and
motion in phenomenal experience are added by cortical processes. In
Cerebral **Achromatopsia** patients have suffered trauma to area V4 of
the cerebral cortex and report seeing the world in greyscale with no
colour vision and in Congenital Achromatopsia people do not even
understand the meaning of \'colour\'. In an astonishing ailment called
**Akinetopsia** patients perceive movement as a succession of stationary
images (Rizzo *et al.* 1995). Akinetopsia is usually associated with
damage to cortical area V5. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) have demonstrated
that the addition of colour occurs more rapidly than the addition of
motion. The section on the Neuroscience of Consciousness describes these
discoveries and many other aspects of the creation of phenomenal
experience in the brain.
Unfortunately knowledge of the whereabouts of the signals that are the
content of conscious experience does not resolve the problem of
phenomenal consciousness. Whether these signals are next to objects in
the world or at the end of a chain of signals in the brain there still
remains the problem of how they become arranged in the form of
experience. If such a thing occurs at all.
### Intentionality and representation
There is a materialist interpretation of representationalism in which
representations are redefined as intentional states:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"One way of explaining what is
meant by 'intentionality' in the (more obscure) philosophical sense is
this: it is that aspect of mental states or events that consists in
their being of or about things (as pertains to the questions, 'What are
you thinking of?' and 'What are you thinking about?'). Intentionality is
the aboutness or directedness of mind (or states of mind) to things,
objects, states of affairs, events. So if you are thinking about San
Francisco, or about the increased cost of living there, or about your
meeting someone there at Union Square---your mind, your thinking, is
directed toward San Francisco, or the increased cost of living, or the
meeting in Union Square. To think at all is to think of or about
something in this sense. This 'directedness' conception of
intentionality plays a prominent role in the influential philosophical
writings of Franz Brentano and those whose views developed in response
to his (to be discussed further in Section 3).\"(Siewert
2003)`</font>`{=html}
This definition allows \"representation\" to be redefined as a data
stream rather than a set of things arranged in some mental or neural
state that represents things in space. Husserl thought this approach
would allow a description of consciousness that \"carefully abstains
from affirming the existence of anything in spatio-temporal reality\"
(Siewert 2003) although it could be argued that a data stream such as
any description can never escape the constraints of representation in
time at some place.
Unfortunately the concept of \"intentionality\" has become so diverse
that it could be applied to almost any aspect of the description of
consciousness. An interesting example of this is given by Loar (2001)
where \"intentionality\" is considered to overlap \"representing\" and
\"conceiving\":
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"A person\'s thoughts represent
things to her \-- conceive things \-- in many ways: perceptually,
memory-wise, descriptively, by naming, by analogy, by intuitive sorting,
theoretically, abstractly, implicitly and explicitly. These various
manners of conceiving have something in common: they have intentional
properties, and they have them essentially. `</font>`{=html}
The usage of the term \"intentional state\" has become so broad that it
now means little more than a state that is about another state.
References
Siewert, C. (2003). Consciousness and Intentionality. The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-intentionality/>
Also see Loar, B. (2001) "Phenomenal Intentionality as the Basis of
Mental Content", in Reflections and Replies, ed. M. Hahn and B.
Ramsberg, MIT.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/courses/concepts/loar.html>
Williford, K. (2002) The intentionality of consciousness and the
consciousness of intentionality. Intentionality: Past and Future, edited
by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis, Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi.
<http://web.stcloudstate.edu/kwwilliford/Intentionality%20of%20Consciousness.pdf>
Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism Defended. Philosophical Review 110
(April 2001):199-240. <http://stripe.colorado.edu/~leeds/byrne.pdf>
### Cartesian materialism
The term \"Cartesian materialism\" once meant the idea that the mind is
in the brain (see for instance Block 1995). The term had largely fallen
out of use in philosophy until revived by Daniel Dennett (1991) in the
book *Consciousness Explained*. Dennett uses a very particular
definition of the term in his discussions and also uses a particular
definition of the word \"mind\". See the section on Daniel
Dennett
for Dennett\'s critique. Philosophers who adhere to the idea that the
mind is in the brain tend to call themselves \"indirect realists\" or
\"representationalists\" where the substrate of conscious experience is
in the brain and would deny that Dennett\'s critique applies to their
proposals. Dennett\'s critique makes the materialist assumption that if
there is a representation in the brain then a further flow of material
out of this representation would be required for the representation to
become part of mind.
### Identity theories of mind
The idea that mental states are brain states is known as the **identity
theory of mind**. There are two sorts of identity theory, in **type**
identity theory it is held that mental states are identical to brain
states whereas in **token** identity theory it is held that mental
states correlate with brain states.
Type identity theory was attacked by Putnam in \"The Nature of Mental
States\" where he pointed out that if mental states are functions then
type identity theory would presuppose that animals that had the same
mental states would need to have identical brain structures. He
suggested that this is unlikely, it being more probable that animals
have functional systems that perform similar overall functions but which
are not identical. In other words, if it is assumed that conscious
experience is a set of functions then token identity theory is more
probable than type identity theory.
Putnam\'s critique does not preclude identity theories of mind that
involve \"passive ideas\" (i.e.: states that are not classical
functions).
Most identity theories of mind would be representational, the physical
states representing the world in some way. All identity theories of mind
involve Cartesian materialism in the sense of the mental states being
brain states. According to identity theories the mind is in the brain.
Putnam, H. (1967) The nature of mental states. In The Nature of Mind,
edited by Rosenthal, pp. 197--203. Originally published as
\"Psychological predicates in Art, Mind, and Religion\", edited by
Capitan and Merill, pp. 37--48.
## Dualism
Prior to considering the arguments surrounding dualism it is important
to have a clear idea of \"information\" because many of these arguments
have parallels with the difference between information as a set of
states that can be transmitted and the substrate on which this
information is expressed or from which the information is derived. See
Elementary information and information systems
theory.
### Cartesian dualism
Descartes, a philosopher, analysed his experience and developed an
empirical description of how it is arranged. He described mental images
and perceptions as extended in space and with a duration. He called
these extended things **ideas** (Cartesian ideas) and proposed that they
are patterns in the brain. Descartes thought the pineal gland was the
most likely location for these ideas because it is one of the few single
organs in the brain. He also proposed that there is a rational soul that
directly contacts these ideas:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Now among these figures, it is
not those imprinted on the external sense organs, or on the internal
surface of the brain, which should be taken to be ideas - but only those
which are traced in the spirits on the surface of gland H *(where the
seat of the imagination and the \'common sense\' is located)*. That is
to say, it is only the latter figures which should be taken to be the
forms or images which the rational soul united to this machine will
consider directly when it imagines some object or perceives it by the
senses.\" Descartes (1664)`</font>`{=html}
See section on
Descartes
for more information and references.
Descartes considered that the soul was a physical point, an unextended
entity that acts like a mind\'s eye. He called this unextended place the
*res cogitans* and concluded that it was a substance that differed from
that of material things:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\".. I thence concluded that I was
a substance whose whole essence or nature consists only in thinking, and
which, that it may exist, has need of no place, nor is dependent on any
material thing; so that \" I,\" that is to say, the mind by which I am
what I am, is wholly distinct from the body, and is even more easily
known than the latter, and is such, that although the latter were not,
it would still continue to be all that it is.\"Descartes
(1637)`</font>`{=html}
This unextended substance that is not material gives the word
\"substance\" a new meaning. It has been attacked as a concept by Locke,
Hume, Berkely and many other philosophers. The concept of there being
two substances, that which composes the physical world and that which
composes the soul, is the origin of the word **Dualism** but dualism, as
a concept, has been extended beyond this original meaning. Cartesian
dualism is a type of **substance dualism**.
Cartesian dualism is an attempt to explain our experience. According to
Descartes something supernatural would be needed for an unextended
viewing point to exist.
Reid\'s **Natural Dualism** also has a point soul looking at things but
proposes that the things in question are forms in the world rather than
in the brain.
### Property dualism
Another sort of dualism has arisen out of a particular interpretation of
the regress and homunculus arguments. These arguments show that
phenomenal experience is not due entirely to flows from place to place
(i.e.: it is not due to classical processes and functions). Property
dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the appropriate way
(i.e. in the way that living human bodies are organized), mental
properties emerge.
As Goldman (1993) pointed out, qualitative experience does not seem to
be needed in a functional description of a system:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"For any functional description
of a system that is in pain (or has an itch), it seems as if we can
imagine another system with the same functional description but lacking
the qualitative property of painfulness (or itchiness).\"
`</font>`{=html}
Certainly a functional system that merely reports the words \"I am in
pain\" when it is dropped on the floor does not require any qualitative
property of painfulness. The *absent qualia* arguments suggest that even
in a large system there would be no need for qualitative properties for
the performance of any classical function.
Chalmers (1993) commenting on Goldman\'s point, said that this implies
that **zombies** might exist, functional replicas of humans but without
qualia. He then denied that a complete functional replica of a human
could exist without also including qualia:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"It seems to me that the only way
to avoid this conclusion is to deny that Zombie Dave is a conceptual
possibility; and the only principled way to deny that Zombie Dave is a
conceptual possibility is to allow that functional organization is
conceptually constitutive of qualitative content.\" Chalmers
(1993).`</font>`{=html}
In other words he identifies qualia with function. According to Chalmers
(1996) qualia are a particular type of function:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"I claim that conscious
experience arises from fine-grained functional organization. More
specifically, I will argue for a principle of organizational invariance,
holding that given any system that has conscious experiences, then any
system that has the same fine-grained functional organization will have
qualitatively identical experiences. According to this principle,
consciousness is an organizational invariant: a property that remains
constant over all functional isomorphs of a given system. Whether the
organization is realized in silicon chips, in the population of China,
or in beer cans and ping-pong balls does not matter. As long as the
functional organisation is right, conscious experience will be
determined.\" p249`</font>`{=html}
Chalmers\' idea of functional organisation has within it a sometimes
vague implication that the functional units must have a particular form;
for instance, in the development of his argument, he refers to "fine
grained" replacement of organic functional units with inorganic units.
Chalmers is actually making two major points, firstly that qualia occur
during the motion of things (functions), secondly that qualia are
independent of any particular substrate.\*\* For the first point to be
consistent with materialism the qualia must have no effect on the
function, they must be **epiphenomenal**. Epiphenomenal qualia would not
be forbidden by the regress and homunculus arguments and would be akin
to Berkeley\'s \"passive ideas\".
Whether or not epiphenomenal qualia are physical depends upon the
definition of the word \"physical\". If physical functions cause qualia
but qualia cannot affect functions then the qualia are \"physical\" in
the sense of being caused by physical events but might be regarded as
non-physical in the sense of being isolated from further physical
events. In philosophical terms they violate the principle of **Causal
Closure**. However, there are other definitions of physicalism based on
arguments such as **Methodological Naturalism** which hold that anything
that can be investigated using the methods of natural science is a
physical thing (see Stoljar 2001). Thus, although epiphenomenal qualia
may not conform to materialism they may be encompassed by physicalism;
as events that are related to material events they are awaiting a
physical theory of how they emerge from a given function.
The reader might consider whether phenomenal consciousness is indeed
epiphenomenal. Empirical reports describe it as something that is
different from the world beyond the body (see direct
realism) -
could we generate empirical reports of an epiphenomenon?
The term **property dualism** describes how physical events might give
rise to a set of properties that cannot be predicted from the fine
structure of the physical system. The \"dualism\" is present because one
set of events is related to two sets of properties, one of which is not
related by materialism to the set of events. In the case of the proposal
about consciousness outlined above an extra assumption, beyond
materialism, would be needed to explain qualia. Property dualism might
be defined as a theory that there could be a theory of consciousness but
that this requires some new assumption.
As far as the \"when and where\" of consciousness are concerned,
property dualism states that it is somewhere in the processes performed
by the organism and the parts of the organism.
`<font size=1>`{=html} \*\* In terms of information processing, Chalmers
is proposing that qualia are the enactment of a particular information
processing structure.`</font>`{=html}
- Block, N. (2006). Max Black\'s objection to mind-body identity.
Oxford Review of Metaphysics No.3.
<http://philrsss.anu.edu.au/BlockFest/MaxBlack.rtf>
- Chalmers, D.J. (1993) Commentary on \"The Psychology of Folk
Psychology\". Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16:35-36, 1993
- Chalmers, D.J. (1996) \"The Conscious Mind: In Search of a
Fundamental Theory\". Oxford University Press. 1996.
- Goldman, A.I., (1993). The Psychology of Folk Psychology. Behavioral
and Brain Sciences 16: 15-28 (1993).
<http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Papers/Py104/goldman.psyc.html>
### Predicate dualism
Predicate dualism is the view espoused by most non-reductive
physicalists, such as Donald Davidson(1980) and Jerry Fodor(1968), who
maintain that while there is only one ontological category of substances
and properties of substances (usually physical), the predicates that we
use to describe mental events cannot be redescribed in terms of (or
reduced to) physical predicates of natural languages. If we characterize
predicate monism as the view subscribed to by eliminative materialists,
who maintain that such intentional predicates as believe, desire, think,
feel, etc., will eventually be eliminated from both the language of
science and from ordinary language because the entities to which they
refer do not exist, then predicate dualism is most easily defined as the
negation of this position. Predicate dualists believe that so-called
\"folk psychology\", with all of its propositional attitude ascriptions,
is an ineliminable part of the enterprise of describing, explaining and
understanding human mental states and behavior.
Davidson, for example, subscribes to Anomalous Monism, according to
which there can be no strict psycho-physical laws which connect mental
and physical events under their descriptions as mental and physical
events. However, all mental events also have physical descriptions. It
is in terms of the latter that such events can be connected in law-like
relations with other physical events. Mental predicates are irreducibly
different in character (rational, holistic and necessary) from physical
predicates (contingent, atomic and causal).
(Section based on Wikipedia article)
- Davidson, D (1980). Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford University
Press.
- Fodor,J. (1968) *Psychological Explanation*, Random House.
.
### The interaction between mind and brain in dualism
#### Interactionism
Interactionism is the view that mental states, such as beliefs and
desires, causally interact with physical states. This is a position
which is very appealing to common-sense intuitions, notwithstanding the
fact that it is very difficult to establish its validity or correctness
by way of logical argumentation or empirical proof. It is appealing to
common-sense because we are surrounded by such everyday occurrences as a
child\'s touching a hot stove (physical event) which causes him to feel
pain (mental event) and then yell and scream (physical event) which
causes his parents to experience a sensation of fear and protectiveness
(mental event) and so on.
#### Epiphenomalism
According to epiphenomenalism, all mental events are caused by a
physical event and have no physical consequences. So, a mental event of
deciding to pick up a rock (call it \"M\") is caused by the firing of
specific neurons in the brain (call it \"P\"), however when the arm and
hand move to pick up a rock (call it \"E\") this is only caused by P.
The physical causes are in principle reducible to fundamental physics,
and therefore mental causes are eliminated using this reductionist
explanation. If P causes M and E, there is no overdetermination in the
explanation for E.
#### Parallelism
Psycho-physical parallelism is a very unusual view about the interaction
between mental and physical events which was most prominently, and
perhaps only truly, advocated by Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz. Like
Malebranche and others before him, Leibniz recognized the weaknesses of
Descartes\' account of causal interaction taking place in a physical
location in the brain. Malebranche decided that such a material basis of
interaction between material and immaterial was impossible and therefore
formulated his doctrine of occasionalism, stating that the interactions
were really caused by the intervention of God on each individual
occasion. Leibniz idea is that God has created a pre-established harmony
such that it only seems as if physical and mental events cause, and are
caused by, one another. In reality, mental causes only have mental
effects and physical causes only have physical effects. Hence the term
parallelism is used to describe this view.
#### Occasionalism
Occasionalism argues that bodily events are the occasion of an act by
the Creator causing a corresponding mental event, and vice versa. Any
such view requires a theological structure as a premise.
#### Further reading
- Robinson, Howard, \"Dualism\", The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Fall 2003 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2003/entries/dualism/>
- Robinson, H. (2003) \"Dualism\", in S. Stich and T. Warfield (eds)
The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell, Oxford,
85-101.
- Amoroso, R.L. (2010) \"The complementarity of Mind and Body:
Realizing the Dream of Descartes, Einstein and Eccles\", New York:
Nova Science Publishers,
`, ``https://www.novapublishers.com/catalog/product_info.php?products_id=12759`
## Idealism
According to Idealism only the mental truly exists.
The form and content of personal conscious experience might be related
to the structure of the world and brain in several ways. It could be a
**solipsism** or be the mind of God.
*This is a **stub** and needs expansion*.
## Panpsychism
### Etymology
Ancient Greek *pan* (πᾶν : \"all, everything, whole\") and *psyche*
(ψυχή : \"soul, mind\").[^1] Psyche is the from
ψύχω (*psukhō*, \"I blow\") and means mind or \'life-breath\'.
Philip Goff, a proponent of panpsychism, carves out a distinction
between panexperientialism and pancognitivism. Panexperientialism is the
belief that *experience* is ubiquitous, while pancognitivism is the
belief that *cognition* is ubiquitous. Most modern purponents of
panpsychism, such as Annaka Harris and David Chalmers, are careful to
distance themselves from pancognitivism.
In some interpretations, such as monadism, Panpsychism and Idealism can
overlap because the universe is conceived as being composed of an
infinity of point consciousnesses that each contain information about
the whole universe.
The form and content of personal conscious experience might be related
to the structure of the world and brain in many ways.
*This is a **stub** and needs expansion*.
## References
Seager W. & Allen-Hermanson (2001). 'Panpsychism.' Online document:
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, \[online\],
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/panpsychism/>, \[accessed 10/2005\]
**Supervenience**
- Chalmers, D.J. (1996). The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press.
**The problem of regression**
- Ryle, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind. The University of Chicago
Press, 1949.
**The homunculus argument**
- Gregory, R.L. (1990) Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing, Oxford
University Press Inc. New York.
- Gregory, T.L. (1987). The Oxford Companion to Mind. Oxford
University Press.
**Subject-object paradox**
- James, W. (1904)Does \'Consciousness\' Exist? Journal of
Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1,
477-491.
- Hegel, G.W.F. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND: SECTION I. MIND SUBJECTIVE B.
PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND CONSCIOUSNESS Part Three of the Encyclopaedia
of the Philosophical
Sciences
- Velmans, M. (1996) Consciousness and the \"Casual Paradox\".
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 19 (3):
538-542.
- Bermudez, J.L. (1999) The Paradox of Self-Consciousness
(representation and Mind) Psycoloquy:
10,#35
**Ontological status**
- Bierman, D.J. (2004) Non Conscious Processes Preceding Intuitive
decisions
<http://m0134.fmg.uva.nl/~djb/publications/2004/Intuition_bialsymp2004.pdf>
- Damasio, A.R. (1994). Descartes\' error: Emotion, reason and the
human brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam Book.
- Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason
<http://www.arts.cuhk.edu.hk/Philosophy/Kant/cpr/>
**Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness**
Block, N. (1995) On a confusion about a function of consciousness.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 227-287.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/documents/a/00/00/04/31/bbs00000431-00/bbs.block.html>
Block, N. (2004). *The Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science*.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/ecs.pdf>
Dennett, D. (1978). Why You Can\'t Make a Computer that Feels Pain, in:
Brainstorms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 190-229.
Dennett, D. (1988). Quining Qualia. in A. Marcel and E. Bisiach, eds,
Consciousness in Modern Science, Oxford University Press 1988. Reprinted
in W. Lycan, ed., Mind and Cognition: A Reader, MIT Press, 1990, A.
Goldman, ed. Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science, MIT Press,
1993. <http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/quinqual.htm>
Edelman, G.M. (1993). Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the
Mind. New York:
Feyerabend, P. (1963). Mental Events and the Brain, Journal of
Philosophy 40:295-6.
Huxley, T. H. (1874). On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and
its History, The Fortnightly Review, n.s.16:555-580. Reprinted in Method
and Results: Essays by Thomas H. Huxley (New York: D. Appleton and
Company, 1898).
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review
LXXXIII, 4 (October 1974): 435-50.
<http://web.archive.org/19990218140703/members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html>
Rey, Georges, (1997). Contemporary Philosophy of Mind.Blackwell: Oxford
Sellars W. (1956). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, In: Feigl H
and Scriven M (eds) The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of
Psychology and Psychoanalysis: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of
Science, Vol. 1. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 253-329
Whitehead, A.N. (1920). The Concept of Nature. Chapter 3: Time.
<http://spartan.ac.brocku.ca/~lward/Whitehead/Whitehead_1920/White1_03.html>
**Direct Realism**
- Austin, J.L. (1962) Sense and Sensibilia, ed. by Geoffrey J. Warnock
(Oxford, 1962)
- Aydede, M. (2001) Naturalism, introspection, and direct realism
about pain. Consciousness and Emotion, Vol. 2, No. 1, 2001,
pp. 29--73.
<http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/maydede/pain.pdf>
- Chapman, C.R., and Y. Nakamura (1999). A Passion of the Soul: An
Introduction to Pain for Consciousness Researchers. Consciousness
and Cognition, 8: 391-422.
- Dennett, D. (1991a). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown
- Dennett, D. (1991b). Lovely and suspect qualities. Commentary on
David Rosenthal, \"The Independence of Consciousness and Sensory
Quality\" in E. Villanueva, ed., Consciousness, (SOFIA Conference,
Buenos Aires), Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview 1991.
<http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/lovely&s.htm>
- Fowler C A (1986): "An event approach to the study of speech
perception from a direct-realist perspective", J of Phonetics
14(1):3-28.
- Gibson, J. J. (1966) The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems.
Houghton Mifflin Company,Boston.
- Gibson, J. J. (1979) Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Hillsdate.
- Gregory, R.L. 1988. Consciousness in science and philosophy:
conscience and con-science. Chapter 12 in Consciousness in
Contemporary Science. (Editors: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E.).
Oxford Science Publications.
- Le Morvan, Pierre (2004). Arguments against direct realism and how
to counter them. *The American Philosophical Quarterly*, *41*(3),
221-234.\] (pdf) <http://www.tcnj.edu/~lemorvan/DR_web.pdf>
- Michaels, C. F. and Carello, C. (1981). Direct Perception. Century
Psychology Series. Prentice-Hall.
. 1981. Download this book at
<http://ione.psy.uconn.edu/~psy254/MC.pdf>
- Oliveira, André L. G. and Oliveira, Luis F. (2002) Toward an
ecological conception of timbre. In Proceedings Auditory Perception
Cognition and Action Meeting 2002, Kansas City.
<http://cogprints.org/2713/>
- Skinner, B. F. Science and Human Behavior . New York: Macmillan,
1953.
- Skinner, B. F. 1971. Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New York: Knopf.
- Skinner, B. F. 1948. Walden Two. New York: Macmillan.
- Tye, M. (2004). ANOTHER LOOK AT REPRESENTATIONALISM ABOUT PAIN.
Consciousness and Emotion 2004, special issue on pain, edited by
Murat Aydede (with replies by M. Aydede, N. Block, B. Maund, and P.
Noordhof
<http://sun.soci.niu.edu/~phildept/MT/RepresentationalismAndPain.pdf>
- Vygotsky, L.S.(1925) Consciousness as a problem in the psychology of
behavior. Undiscovered Vygotsky: Etudes on the pre-history of
cultural-historical psychology (European Studies in the History of
Science and Ideas. Vol. 8), pp. 251--281. Peter Lang Publishing.
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/1925/consciousness.htm>
- Ziff, Paul. \"About Behaviourism.\" Analysis 18 (1958): 132-136.
Quoted by Larry Hauser in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/b/behavior.htm#B>. F. Skinner:
Radical Behaviorism
**Indirect Realism**
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
- Rizzo, M., Nawrot, M. & Zihl, J. (1995). Motion and shape perception
in cerebral akinetopsia.Brain, 118. 1105-1127.
<http://nawrot.psych.ndsu.nodak.edu/Publications/Nawrot.pdf/RizzoNawrotZihl.1995.pdf>
- Russell, B. (1912). Problems of Philosophy. Home University Library.
<http://www.ditext.com/russell/rus1.html>
- Tye, M. (2003) Qualia. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia/#Repqualia>
Further reading:
- Hume, D. (1739). A Treatise of Human Nature.
<http://www.class.uidaho.edu/mickelsen/ToC/hume%20treatise%20ToC.htm>
- Firth, R. (1949) Sense Data and the Percept Theory, Mind, 58 (1949);
59 (1950). (Describes early reasons for rejecting Indirect Realism)
<http://www.ditext.com/firth/spt.html>
- Grush, R. (2000). Self, world and space: The meaning and mechanisms
of ego- and allocentric spatial representation. Brain and Mind
1(1):59-92.
<http://mind.ucsd.edu/papers/sws/sws.html>
[^1]: Clarke, D.S. *Panpsychism: Past and Recent Selected Readings*.
State University of New York Press, 2004. p.1
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Conflict2#Indirect realism
*This part of this section is about the where and when of the experience
called consciousness. Is it in the world, in the brain or are the world
and brain within it?*
## Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness
Block(1995) drew attention to the way that there appear to be two types
of consciousness: *phenomenal* consciousness and *access* consciousness:
`Phenomenal consciousness is experience; the phenomenally`\
`conscious aspect of a state is what it is like to be in that`\
`state. The mark of access-consciousness, by contrast, is `\
`availability for use in reasoning and rationally guiding speech `\
`and action. (Block 1995).`
*See the section on Ned Block\'s
ideas
for a deeper coverage of his approach to access and phenomenal
consciousness.*
Block uses Nagel\'s famous (1974) paper, \"What is it like to be a
bat?\" as an exemplary description of phenomenal consciousness.
Excellent descriptions have also been proffered by the empiricist
philosophers who gave lengthy descriptions of consciousness as partly
experience itself. Although Block has formalised the idea of phenomenal
and access consciousness similar ideas have also been put forward by
many philosophers including Kant and Whitehead.
Access consciousness has two interpretations, in the first, used by
Block, it applies to the functions that appear to operate on phenomenal
consciousness. In the second, used by the behaviourists and
eliminativists, it is some property of the functions of the brain that
can be called \'consciousness\'.
This division between phenomenal and functional aspects of consciousness
is useful because it emphasises the idea of phenomenal consciousness as
observation rather than action. Some philosophers such as Huxley in
1874, have taken the view that because phenomenal consciousness appears
to have no function it is of no importance or cannot exist. James (1879)
introduced the term \"epiphenomenalism\" to summarise the idea that
consciousness has no function.
The idea that phenomenal consciousness cannot exist is a type of
*Eliminativism* (also known as Eliminative Materialism). Eliminativism
owes much to the work of Sellars(1956) and Feyerbend (1963). Dennett
(1978) applied Eliminativism to phenomenal consciousness and denies that
pain is real. Others such as Rey(1997) have also applied eliminativism
to phenomenal consciousness.
Dennett (1988) redefines consciousness in terms of access consciousness
alone, he argues that \"Everything real has properties, and since I
don\'t deny the reality of conscious experience, I grant that conscious
experience has properties\". Having related all consciousness to
properties he then declares that these properties are actually
judgements of properties. He considers judgements of the properties of
consciousness to be identical to the properties themselves. He writes:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"The infallibilist line on qualia treats
them as properties of one\'s experience one cannot in principle
misdiscover, and this is a mysterious doctrine (at least as mysterious
as papal infallibility) unless we shift the emphasis a little and treat
qualia as logical constructs out of subjects\' qualia-judgments: a
subject\'s experience has the quale F if and only if the subject judges
his experience to have quale F. \"`</font>`{=html}
Having identified \"properties\" with \"judgement of properties\" he can
then show that the judgements are insubstantial, hence the properties
are insubstantial and hence the qualia are insubstantial or even
non-existent. Dennett concludes that qualia can be rejected as
non-existent:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"So when we look one last time at our
original characterization of qualia, as ineffable, intrinsic, private,
directly apprehensible properties of experience, we find that there is
nothing to fill the bill. In their place are relatively or practically
ineffable public properties we can refer to indirectly via reference to
our private property-detectors\-- private only in the sense of
idiosyncratic. And insofar as we wish to cling to our subjective
authority about the occurrence within us of states of certain types or
with certain properties, we can have some authority\--not infallibility
or incorrigibility, but something better than sheer guessing\--but only
if we restrict ourselves to relational, extrinsic properties like the
power of certain internal states of ours to provoke acts of apparent re-
identification. So contrary to what seems obvious at first blush, there
simply are no qualia at all. \" (Dennett 1988)`</font>`{=html}
Dennett\'s asserts that \"a subject\'s experience has the quale F if and
only if the subject judges his experience to have quale F\". This is a
statement of the belief that qualia are the same as processes such as
judgements. Processes such as judgements are flows of data where one
state examines a previous state in a succession over time and embody
what Whitehead called the \"materialist\" concept of time. Dennett does
not consider how a scientific concept of time might affect his argument.
Dennett\'s argument has been persuasive and there are now many
philosophers and neuroscientists who believe that the problem of
phenomenal consciousness does not exist. This means that, to them, what
we call \'consciousness\' can only be a property of the functions
performed by the brain and body. According to these philosophers only
access consciousness exists.
Those who support the idea of phenomenal consciousness also tend to
frame it in terms of nineteenth century theory where one state examines
a previous state in a succession over time, for instance Edelman(1993)
places the past in memories at an instant and time within experience is
explained as continuing modelling processes:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"Primary consciousness is the state of
being mentally aware of things in the world\--of having mental images in
the present. But it is not accompanied by any sense of a person with a
past and a future\.... In contrast, higher-order consciousness involves
the recognition by a thinking subject of his or her own acts or
affections. It embodies a model of the personal, and of the past and the
future as well as the present. It exhibits direct awareness\--the
noninferential or immediate awareness of mental episodes without the
involvement of sense organs or receptors. It is what we humans have in
addition to primary consciousness. We are conscious of being
conscious.\" `</font>`{=html}
Block(2004) also suggests this flow from state to state in his idea of
\"Reflexivity\" where our idea of familiarity with an object is due to
one state being analysed by another:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"Thus in the "conscious" case, the subject
must have a state that is about the subject's own perceptual experience
(looking familiar) and thus conscious in what might be termed a
"reflexive" sense. An experience is conscious in this sense just in case
it is the object of another of the subject's states; for example, one
has a thought to the effect that one has that experience. The reflexive
sense of \'consciousness\' contrasts with phenomenality, which perhaps
attaches to some states which are not the objects of other mental
states. Reflexive consciousness might better be called 'awareness' than
'consciousness'. Reflexivity is phenomenality plus something else
(reflection) and that opens up the possibility in principle for
phenomenality without reflection. For example, it is at least
conceptually possible for there to be two people in pain, one of whom is
introspecting the pain the other not. (Perhaps infants or animals can
have pain but don't introspect it.) The first is reflexively conscious
of the pain, but both have phenomenally conscious states, since pain is
by its very nature a phenomenally conscious state. \"`</font>`{=html}
Both Block and Edelman allow phenomenal consciousness, our experience,
as an unexplained phenomenon. Block, Edelman and also Dennett\'s ideas
of consciousness are shown in the illustration below:
![](Constudphen.gif "Constudphen.gif")
This model differs from the empirical reports of phenomenal
consciousness that were considered earlier. According to the empirical
reports the present moment in our experience is extended so the
succession of outputs or stages of access consciousness could constitute
the contents of phenomenal consciousness. In other words phenomenal
consciousness is composed of periods of access consciousness. This is
how it seems to the empiricist and in our own experience but how such a
state could be explained in terms of brain activity is highly
problematical. Given that nineteenth century ideas cannot explain such a
state a scientific explanation will be required.
The idea that phenomenal consciousness misrepresents or \"misdiscovers\"
itself (Dennett 1988) deserves further discussion. According to
materialism the present instant has no duration so can only be known in
succeeding instants as a report or memory and this could be wrong.
Whitehead considered that this viewpoint originates in an archaic view
of science, particularly the concept of time in science:
\"The eighteenth and nineteenth centuries accepted as their natural
philosophy a certain circle of concepts which were as rigid and definite
as those of the philosophy of the middle ages, and were accepted with as
little critical research. I will call this natural philosophy
\'materialism.\' Not only were men of science materialists, but also
adherents of all schools of philosophy. The idealists only differed from
the philosophic materialists on question of the alignment of nature in
reference to mind. But no one had any doubt that the philosophy of
nature considered in itself was of the type which I have called
materialism. It is the philosophy which I have already examined in my
two lectures of this course preceding the present one. It can be
summarised as the belief that nature is an aggregate of material and
that this material exists in some sense at each successive member of a
one-dimensional series of extensionless instants of time. Furthermore
the mutual relations of the material entities at each instant formed
these entities into a spatial configuration in an unbounded space. It
would seem that space\-\--on this theory-would be as instantaneous as
the instants, and that some explanation is required of the relations
between the successive instantaneous spaces. The materialistic theory is
however silent on this point; and the succession of instantaneous spaces
is tacitly combined into one persistent space. This theory is a purely
intellectual rendering of experience which has had the luck to get
itself formulated at the dawn of scientific thought. It has dominated
the language and the imagination of science since science flourished in
Alexandria, with the result that it is now hardly possible to speak
without appearing to assume its immediate obviousness.\" (Whitehead
1920).
## Direct Realism and Direct Perception
Direct Realism proposes that phenomenal experience is directly objects
in the world without any intervening representation. It is motivated by
the belief that the Problem of Regression, the Subject-Object Paradox
and the recursion form of the Homunculus arguments show that phenomenal
consciousness cannot occur in the brain alone. Direct Realists reason
that if phenomenal consciousness cannot be things in the brain then it
must be something outside the brain.
There are two principle types of Direct Realism: Natural Dualism and
Behaviourism (both Radical and Analytical). Some behaviourists use the
term "Direct Perception" rather than Direct Realism and consider that
only the invariant parts of perception are direct (see for instance
Michaels and Carello 1981). Thomas Reid is generally regarded as the
founder of Direct Realism. In his Natural Dualism he proposed that the
soul is in direct contact with the contents of experience and these
contents are things in the world beyond the body. The Direct Realism of
Reid is summarised in the statement of his famous disciple Sir William
Hamilton: \"In the simplest act of perception I am conscious of myself
as the perceiving subject and of an external reality as the object
perceived\". Reid\'s Natural Dualism has now been largely replaced by
radical and analytical behaviourism which eschew the idea of a soul and
propose that phenomenal consciousness, if it exists at all, is a
behavioural reflex.
The modern justification of Direct Realism mainly consists of arguments
against Indirect Realism or Representationalism. Philosophers such as
Austin (1962) and Le Morvan (2004) have summarised the Direct Realism
debate and have identified the following arguments in favour of Indirect
Realism and given rebuttals to each of them:
1\. The Causal Argument: perception involves a succession of causal
events such as the reflection of photons, bleaching of retinal pigments
etc. so perception must involve the end of this causal chain. The Direct
Realist response is that, although there may be a causal chain in
sensation this does not inevitably imply that the end of the chain is
the content of phenomenal experience.
2\. The Time Lag Argument: it takes time for light to travel from an
object to the senses, time for chemical changes in the retina etc\...
The Direct Realist response is that direct perception may be referred
back in time.
3\. The Partial Character of Perception Argument: we only perceive the
surface of objects, and then only a part of the surface. As the whole
object would be perceived directly perception must be indirect. The
Direct Realist response is that direct perception could occur even if
only parts of an object were perceived.
4\. The Perceptual Relativity Argument: things appear to be different
shapes depending upon the point of view. The Direct Realist response is
that if perception can occur backwards in time it should have no problem
occurring back down a line of sight. However, Le Morvan\'s argument does
not seem to encompass the geometrical nature of phenomenal experience,
seeking to explain geometry in terms of movement.
5\. The Argument from Perceptual Illusion: A stick may appear bent when
projecting from the surface of water. Direct Realists apply the argument
used in (4) to this problem. The bent stick illusion is a physical event
in the world beyond the eye rather than a normal optical illusion such
as the Muller-Lyer illusion etc., see (6) for a discussion of optical
illusions.
6\. The Argument from Hallucination: Hallucinations are not in the world
beyond the body. This is highly problematical for Direct Realists
especially when phenomena such as lucid dreams, dreams and visual
imaginations are included along with hallucinations. Direct Realists
classify these phenomena as not being perceptions or deny that they
actually exist as phenomena. Indirect Realists would maintain that all
of perception is a reconstruction and use optical illusions such as the
Muller-Lyer, Ames Room etc. to justify this contention so the Direct
Realist approach to hallucination, dreams etc. might seem like an
unwillingness to accept Indirect Realism rather than an argument.
7\. The Dubitability Argument (cf: Indubitability argument): we cannot
doubt current phenomenal experience but we can doubt the world beyond
the body therefore phenomenal experience is not the world beyond the
body. Direct Realists fall back on Presentism or functional Presentism
to defeat this argument. If phenomenal experience is instantaneous and
made anew at each instant then anything can be doubted.
The points above have summarised the Direct Realist stance on visual
perception. Other sensory modalities have also been considered in the
Direct Realism debate.
Fowler (1986) considered that sounds were attached to objects in the
world. This idea is strange because sounds only seem to be closely
attached to objects in the world when these objects are seen as well as
heard. For example, when a subject is blindfolded it is found that there
can be a large error in locating the position of a sound in the world,
this is especially true for low frequency sounds. The Direct Realist
approach has difficulty explaining the transition from sounds with an
indefinite location when a subject is blindfolded to sounds that are
bound to visual events when the blindfold is removed. It also runs into
problems explaining how the sound of speech from a single loudspeaker
can become bound to lip movements on a cinema screen. If the binding
does not occur in the brain then where does it occur?
Pain is particularly problematic for Direct Realism because, unlike
colour vision where \'red\' is inferred to be a property of electrons or
light, pain is an inner experience that is not a property of tissue
damage. Tissue damage has properties such as bleeding, wheal formation
etc. but pain seems to be phenomenal experience in the brain and
\'phantom pain\' can occur without tissue damage (see Aydede (2001), Tye
(2004) and Chapman, and Nakamura (1999) for further analysis). On closer
inspection other sensations also appear to be inner experiences rather
than direct sensations. For instance, the red crosses of different hues
in the illustration below are all due to the same physical wavelengths
of light. In this case the range of hues in experience is unrelated to
the actual physical red on the page or screen.
Another problem for Direct Realism is that it does not overcome the
problems that it is supposed to solve. The argument for Direct Realism
begins with the idea that there are severe problems with
representationalism (the idea that phenomenal experience is in the
brain) and that direct perception is an alternative that does not have
these problems. However on closer inspection Direct Realism suffers from
almost same problems as representationalism. If phenomenal experience is
the world itself then Ryle\'s regress applies to the world itself and
this can only be avoided by assuming that phenomenal experience is a
subset of the world (i.e.: a representation) that receives input from
other parts of the world that are not part of phenomenal experience.
It is also commonly assumed that Direct Realism avoids the recursion
argument because it is believed that the separation of the observer from
the things that are observed is simply due to the geometry of the world.
If such simple geometry is possible between the eye and the world then
it should also be possible in the brain and a similar geometrical
explanation could be invoked to avoid recursion in representations.
These points are shown in the illustration below:
image:Constuddir1.gif
Scientists have a further problem with Direct Realism. The illustration
below demonstrates that our scientific knowledge of the world differs
markedly from our phenomenal experience.
image:constuddirect.gif
It is difficult to see how the form and content of phenomenal experience
could supervene directly on the world beyond the body. The world
inferred from measurements beyond the body seems to be a nebulous set of
quantum phenomena that are arranged as probability fields in three
dimensions at any instant. The objects in this real world are mostly
space. The world of phenomenal experience on the other hand contains
objects that are one-sided, and are like a 2 dimensional field of
vectors directed simultaneously at an observation point which is
apparently separate from them. Phenomenal experience is not three
dimensional, the rear of objects is not available within it at any
instant. Visual phenomenal experience seems to be a geometrical
relationship between an abstract observation point and the reflection
properties of the part of the world external to the body. It is a form
that crudely overlies the angular separations in inferred reality,
providing approximate directional data. It is not like things in
themselves beyond the body, not even in type, being a set of directional
vectors. (See the module on the neuroscience of perception for a
discussion of depth perception).
If the form and content of visual phenomenal experience are abstractions
separated according to the angular positions of things in the world
beyond the body then theories which propose that phenomenal experience
is the world itself are problematical. It should be noted that things
arranged according to angular positions can appear to overlie any group
of similar things along a radius from the centre point.
![](Constuddirectangle.gif "Constuddirectangle.gif")
If Direct Realists admit that things are as they appear to be, observed
according to angular positions at a \'point eye\', then any
representation of things on the inside of a sphere of any radius would
appear similar. The geometry of the \'point eye\' is problematical
whether the view contains the world itself or a representation of the
world; it cannot be the movements of lumps of matter or energy and the
point observation cannot be due to lumps all landing at a point. In
other words the \'view\' is inconsistent with nineteenth century
materialism and will require a scientific explanation.
Radical and Analytical Behaviourism tackle the problem of the difference
between the world inferred from measurements beyond the body and the
phenomenal world by denying phenomenal consciousness and maintaining
that access and reflex consciousness are all that exists or is
necessary. Radical Behaviourism is an offshoot of psychological
behaviourism and was established as a philosophical adjunct to Marxism
by Vygotsky and popularised by Burrhus Frederic Skinner (see Skinner
1953). There is another movement in psychological behaviourism which is
similar to Radical Behaviourism called Ecological Psychology (see Gibson
1966, 1979 and also Michaels and Carello 1981). Analytical Behaviourism
is a philosophical movement established by Gilbert Ryle (see Ryle 1949).
The core of Analytical and Radical Behaviourism is the assumption that
consciousness exists for a durationless instant so that the Dubitability
Argument and the Regression and Recursion Arguments can be applied (Ryle
1949, Skinner 1971 and see the sections on Ryle\'s Regress and the
Subject-Object Paradox above). As a result the Direct Realist is able to
insinuate that subjects only think that they have had a particular
experience (cf: Dennett 1991a). It is intriguing that Eliminativists
also maintain that experience is the world itself, for instance an
insight into Dennett\'s idea of the mind is to be found on pages 407-408
of Consciousness Explained:
\"It seemed to him, according to the text, as if his mind - his visual
field - were filled with intricate details of gold-green buds an
wiggling branches, but although this is how it seemed this was an
illusion. No such \"plenum\" ever came into his mind; the plenum
remained out in the world where it is didn\'t have to be represented,
but could just be. When we marvel, in those moments of heightened
self-consciousness, at the glorious richness of our conscious
experience, the richness we marvel at is actually the richness of the
world outside, in all its ravishing detail. It does not \"enter\" our
conscious minds, but is simply available\"
This is a clear description of Direct Realism (although Dennett does not
describe himself as a direct realist).
Radical Behaviourism is sometimes described as the dictum that the only
psychological events that are of importance are those that occur outside
the head. The absurdity of this has led to jokes:
Q: What does one behaviorist say to another when they meet on the
street?
A: You\'re fine. How am I?
Q: What does one behaviorist say to another after sex?
A: That was great for you. How was it for me?
(Ziff 1958)
However Vygotsky, Skinner and other Radical Behaviourists hold that
inner behaviour is possible so that events within the brain can result
in reward or punishment. Vygotsky (1925) describes this approach:
\"Consciousness is wholly reduced to the transmitting mechanisms of
reflexes operating according to general laws, i.e., no processes other
than reactions can be admitted into the organism. The way is also paved
for the solution of the problem of self-awareness and self-observation.
Inner perception and introspection are possible only thanks to the
existence of a proprioceptive field and secondary reflexes, which are
connected with it. This is always the echo of a reaction.\"
Hence Radical Behaviourists are able to make the claim that what are
believed to be representations with phenomenal content are processes.
Even events such as pain can then be explained as reflexes involving
organs within the skin. However, by opening the possibility that such
reflexes could occur at any sense organ, including the eye, this makes
Radical Behaviourism a mixed Direct Realist/Indirect Realist philosophy
with consciousness as a process, not a separate thing such as phenomenal
consciousness (see the section on representationalism and intentionality
below).
But this raises a serious issue for science: can the phenomenal
consciousness that seems to contain our observations really be argued
out of existence on the basis of a theory? As Gregory (1988) put it: "
'If you can't explain it -- deny it' is one strategy for dealing with
embarrassing questions such as 'what is consciousness?' ". But is this
the right strategy?
Direct Realism fails to overcome the problems of regression and
recursion inherent in representations. It proposes that phenomenal
consciousness is identical to the physical world beyond the body but
must then use a plethora of arguments to explain why this is evidently
not so. When confronted with these problems its proponents resort to the
argument that everything can be doubted and can misrepresent itself. Yet
it is still widely believed.
It should be noted that Direct Realism is espoused in Religious Natural
Dualism, some forms of Augustinian theology, nineteenth century
materialism and its offspring such as Marxism, post-modernism,
post-Marxism, and various sociological movements. It is also necessary
for some forms of Strong AI to occur. Perhaps this explains why few
ideas have attracted as much attention and defence as Direct Realism.
It is interesting to compare the Direct Realist and Indirect Realist
interpretations of something as simple as a cartoon on television (such
as the image below). According to Indirect Realism the cartoon would be
a moving representation constructed in the brain using data from the
senses. This leads to the prediction of brain mechanisms for modelling
motions, combining colours, binding sound and vision etc., many of which
have been verified. Can you demonstrate how the theory of Direct Realism
could explain the phenomenal experience that contains the cartoon and
produce a list of the predictions made by the theory?
![](constudcartoon.gif "constudcartoon.gif")
In science a theory should be of predictive value, for instance,
information theory describes how the state of a thing can be impressed
on a carrier so that a signal can be transmitted from one place to
another. This theory predicts what will happen when the signal arrives
at its destination and how the state of the source can be inferred from
the events at the destination, the total amount of information that can
be transmitted etc. At the destination it is the form of the signal that
is directly known by interaction and measurement, the form of the source
is inferred. Direct Realism is a direct challenge to this information
theory but does it deliver a more powerful predictive description of
phenomenal consciousness or is experience always dependent on what
happens to the information flow between things in the world and
somewhere in the brain? Does direct realism have a physical theory?
Ultimately it appears as if Direct Realism is about various
understandings of Information Theory. For example, Austin (1962)
discusses what we see when we see a church camouflaged as a barn and
comments that: \"We see, of course, a church that now looks like a
barn.\". Do we see a church or a barn? Scientific information theory is
clear about this, the church is an entity composed of selected
information from the quantum state of its constituents, the optical
image of a camouflaged church is an arrangement of photons emanating
from a screen on which it is projected, the retina has an arrangement of
chemical and electrical events based on an optical image and conscious
visual experience correlates with the arrangement of things on the
retina. The fact that conscious experience also correlates with
classifications of the retinal image as a barn or a church suggests that
conscious experience is an arrangement of things in the brain based on
both the retinal arrangement and the contents of a relational database.
Austin\'s arguments have been mythologised as a final demonstration that
\"sense data\" theories are false. However, as will be seen below, sense
data theories merely claim that there is a succession of information
states between an information state outside the body and that reported
as conscious experience i.e.: subjects report that a church is
camouflaged when it is camouflaged.
## Indirect Realism
Indirect realism proposes that phenomenal consciousness exists and is a
set of signals or **sense data**, usually in the brain. This was
proposed by philosophers from Aristotle to Locke and was probably the
most widespread idea of conscious experience until the eighteenth
century.
The idea of sense data is discussed in depth by Russell (1912).
Russell\'s original definition is given below:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Let us give the name of
\'sense-data\' to the things that are immediately known in sensation:
such things as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and so
on. We shall give the name \'sensation\' to the experience of being
immediately aware of these things. Thus, whenever we see a colour, we
have a sensation of the colour, but the colour itself is a sense-datum,
not a sensation. The colour is that of which we are immediately aware,
and the awareness itself is the sensation. It is plain that if we are to
know anything about the table, it must be by means of the sense-data \--
brown colour, oblong shape, smoothness, etc. \-- which we associate with
the table; but, for the reasons which have been given, we cannot say
that the table is the sense-data, or even that the sense-data are
directly properties of the table.\"`</font>`{=html}
Russell\'s definition is a materialist concept in which experience is
always **of** something because the durationless instant of the present
has always gone. As such it differs from some empiricist ideas where
experience is not confined to the durationless instant.
Science is Indirect Realist because it holds that the scientist can only
make **measurements** of events in the world. These measurements give
rise to signals as a result of interaction with the event. According to
**decoherence theory** the signals are a state that is a mixture of the
state of the measuring instrument and the state of the thing being
measured. For example, the eyes are measuring instruments that are
sensitive to photons, photons are signals containing a state that is
based on the state of electrons in a surface and the state of electrons
is based on the state of the surface etc. Scientific inference allows
some aspects of the state of the surface to be inferred from the state
of the photons.
In modern Indirect Realism there is an attempt to distinguish the
phenomenal content of conscious experience from the processing involved
in accessing this phenomenal content. According to these theories
phenomenal experience is an arrangement of signals that are the content
of the experience. This arrangement forms a *representation* of things
in the world so this form of indirect realism is known as
**Representationalism**. Tye (2003) describes types of
representationalist theory:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Representationalism, as I have
presented it so far, is an identity thesis with respect to qualia:
qualia are supposedly one and the same as certain representational
contents.\"`</font>`{=html}
Tye also describes variants of this idea of representationalism:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Sometimes it is held instead
that qualia are one and the same as certain representational properties
of experiences; and sometimes it is is argued that these
representational properties are themselves irreducible (Siewert 1998).
There is also a weaker version of representationalism, according to
which it is metaphysically necessary that experiences exactly alike with
respect to their representational contents are exactly alike with
respect to their qualia. Obviously, this supervenience thesis leaves
open the further question as to the essential nature of
qualia.\"`</font>`{=html} (Tye 2003).
In a scientific sense Direct Realists believe that phenomenal experience
is the signals that occur next to things in the world beyond the body
(which they call \"things in themselves\") and Indirect Realists usually
believe that phenomenal experience is signals in the brain. It can be
seen from the pattern of signal flow that the signals travelling into
the brain preserve the spatial relationships of the original signals and
encode the properties in the original signals. This means that the
original signals next to the QM sources and the signals in the brain are
equivalent provided the latter are oriented appropriately relative to
signals from the body. Either set of signals could transmit or contain
the same information. Both Direct and Indirect Realism cannot, at
present, explain the physics of how a viewing point occurs in experience
i.e.: how we seem to see through an apparent space to the signals that
are the contents of experience. So the choice between Direct Realism and
Indirect Realism reduces to whether there is only one set of signals or
a chain of signals between the world and phenomenal experience.
The philosophical arguments for Indirect Realism are listed below:
1\. Variable perspective: when we see things the view changes so what we
see must be a different set of signals depending on the view rather than
a constant object.
2\. Illusions: we can see through fingers and see a variety of colours
where measurements tell us one exists. Direct Realists quote the \"bent
stick illusion\", which is not really an illusion at all, being a
physical event.
3\. Hallucinations: two people can have phenomenal experience containing
a table. The first may be viewing a real table whereas the second may be
hallucinating a table. If the tables are the same (phenomenally) then
experience is indirect.
4\. Double vision: press the side of one eye, two images appear (cf Hume
1739) yet there are not two things in the world.
5\. Time gap arguments: according to materialism the past has gone. The
things being seen no longer exist in the state that relates to the state
in experience. In the extreme case, some stars in the night sky no
longer exist but are still in experience so experience must be a derived
signal.
6\. Secondary qualities such as pain, colour and smell do not exist as
physical things in the source of signals and are likely to be properties
of signals in the brain.
![](constudindirect.gif "constudindirect.gif")
Indirect Realism has received strong support from recent discoveries in
neuroscience, for example, it is now clear that both the colour and
motion in phenomenal experience are added by cortical processes. In
Cerebral **Achromatopsia** patients have suffered trauma to area V4 of
the cerebral cortex and report seeing the world in greyscale with no
colour vision and in Congenital Achromatopsia people do not even
understand the meaning of \'colour\'. In an astonishing ailment called
**Akinetopsia** patients perceive movement as a succession of stationary
images (Rizzo *et al.* 1995). Akinetopsia is usually associated with
damage to cortical area V5. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) have demonstrated
that the addition of colour occurs more rapidly than the addition of
motion. The section on the Neuroscience of Consciousness describes these
discoveries and many other aspects of the creation of phenomenal
experience in the brain.
Unfortunately knowledge of the whereabouts of the signals that are the
content of conscious experience does not resolve the problem of
phenomenal consciousness. Whether these signals are next to objects in
the world or at the end of a chain of signals in the brain there still
remains the problem of how they become arranged in the form of
experience. If such a thing occurs at all.
### Intentionality and representation
There is a materialist interpretation of representationalism in which
representations are redefined as intentional states:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"One way of explaining what is
meant by 'intentionality' in the (more obscure) philosophical sense is
this: it is that aspect of mental states or events that consists in
their being of or about things (as pertains to the questions, 'What are
you thinking of?' and 'What are you thinking about?'). Intentionality is
the aboutness or directedness of mind (or states of mind) to things,
objects, states of affairs, events. So if you are thinking about San
Francisco, or about the increased cost of living there, or about your
meeting someone there at Union Square---your mind, your thinking, is
directed toward San Francisco, or the increased cost of living, or the
meeting in Union Square. To think at all is to think of or about
something in this sense. This 'directedness' conception of
intentionality plays a prominent role in the influential philosophical
writings of Franz Brentano and those whose views developed in response
to his (to be discussed further in Section 3).\"(Siewert
2003)`</font>`{=html}
This definition allows \"representation\" to be redefined as a data
stream rather than a set of things arranged in some mental or neural
state that represents things in space. Husserl thought this approach
would allow a description of consciousness that \"carefully abstains
from affirming the existence of anything in spatio-temporal reality\"
(Siewert 2003) although it could be argued that a data stream such as
any description can never escape the constraints of representation in
time at some place.
Unfortunately the concept of \"intentionality\" has become so diverse
that it could be applied to almost any aspect of the description of
consciousness. An interesting example of this is given by Loar (2001)
where \"intentionality\" is considered to overlap \"representing\" and
\"conceiving\":
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"A person\'s thoughts represent
things to her \-- conceive things \-- in many ways: perceptually,
memory-wise, descriptively, by naming, by analogy, by intuitive sorting,
theoretically, abstractly, implicitly and explicitly. These various
manners of conceiving have something in common: they have intentional
properties, and they have them essentially. `</font>`{=html}
The usage of the term \"intentional state\" has become so broad that it
now means little more than a state that is about another state.
References
Siewert, C. (2003). Consciousness and Intentionality. The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-intentionality/>
Also see Loar, B. (2001) "Phenomenal Intentionality as the Basis of
Mental Content", in Reflections and Replies, ed. M. Hahn and B.
Ramsberg, MIT.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/courses/concepts/loar.html>
Williford, K. (2002) The intentionality of consciousness and the
consciousness of intentionality. Intentionality: Past and Future, edited
by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis, Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi.
<http://web.stcloudstate.edu/kwwilliford/Intentionality%20of%20Consciousness.pdf>
Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism Defended. Philosophical Review 110
(April 2001):199-240. <http://stripe.colorado.edu/~leeds/byrne.pdf>
### Cartesian materialism
The term \"Cartesian materialism\" once meant the idea that the mind is
in the brain (see for instance Block 1995). The term had largely fallen
out of use in philosophy until revived by Daniel Dennett (1991) in the
book *Consciousness Explained*. Dennett uses a very particular
definition of the term in his discussions and also uses a particular
definition of the word \"mind\". See the section on Daniel
Dennett
for Dennett\'s critique. Philosophers who adhere to the idea that the
mind is in the brain tend to call themselves \"indirect realists\" or
\"representationalists\" where the substrate of conscious experience is
in the brain and would deny that Dennett\'s critique applies to their
proposals. Dennett\'s critique makes the materialist assumption that if
there is a representation in the brain then a further flow of material
out of this representation would be required for the representation to
become part of mind.
### Identity theories of mind
The idea that mental states are brain states is known as the **identity
theory of mind**. There are two sorts of identity theory, in **type**
identity theory it is held that mental states are identical to brain
states whereas in **token** identity theory it is held that mental
states correlate with brain states.
Type identity theory was attacked by Putnam in \"The Nature of Mental
States\" where he pointed out that if mental states are functions then
type identity theory would presuppose that animals that had the same
mental states would need to have identical brain structures. He
suggested that this is unlikely, it being more probable that animals
have functional systems that perform similar overall functions but which
are not identical. In other words, if it is assumed that conscious
experience is a set of functions then token identity theory is more
probable than type identity theory.
Putnam\'s critique does not preclude identity theories of mind that
involve \"passive ideas\" (i.e.: states that are not classical
functions).
Most identity theories of mind would be representational, the physical
states representing the world in some way. All identity theories of mind
involve Cartesian materialism in the sense of the mental states being
brain states. According to identity theories the mind is in the brain.
Putnam, H. (1967) The nature of mental states. In The Nature of Mind,
edited by Rosenthal, pp. 197--203. Originally published as
\"Psychological predicates in Art, Mind, and Religion\", edited by
Capitan and Merill, pp. 37--48.
## Dualism
Prior to considering the arguments surrounding dualism it is important
to have a clear idea of \"information\" because many of these arguments
have parallels with the difference between information as a set of
states that can be transmitted and the substrate on which this
information is expressed or from which the information is derived. See
Elementary information and information systems
theory.
### Cartesian dualism
Descartes, a philosopher, analysed his experience and developed an
empirical description of how it is arranged. He described mental images
and perceptions as extended in space and with a duration. He called
these extended things **ideas** (Cartesian ideas) and proposed that they
are patterns in the brain. Descartes thought the pineal gland was the
most likely location for these ideas because it is one of the few single
organs in the brain. He also proposed that there is a rational soul that
directly contacts these ideas:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Now among these figures, it is
not those imprinted on the external sense organs, or on the internal
surface of the brain, which should be taken to be ideas - but only those
which are traced in the spirits on the surface of gland H *(where the
seat of the imagination and the \'common sense\' is located)*. That is
to say, it is only the latter figures which should be taken to be the
forms or images which the rational soul united to this machine will
consider directly when it imagines some object or perceives it by the
senses.\" Descartes (1664)`</font>`{=html}
See section on
Descartes
for more information and references.
Descartes considered that the soul was a physical point, an unextended
entity that acts like a mind\'s eye. He called this unextended place the
*res cogitans* and concluded that it was a substance that differed from
that of material things:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\".. I thence concluded that I was
a substance whose whole essence or nature consists only in thinking, and
which, that it may exist, has need of no place, nor is dependent on any
material thing; so that \" I,\" that is to say, the mind by which I am
what I am, is wholly distinct from the body, and is even more easily
known than the latter, and is such, that although the latter were not,
it would still continue to be all that it is.\"Descartes
(1637)`</font>`{=html}
This unextended substance that is not material gives the word
\"substance\" a new meaning. It has been attacked as a concept by Locke,
Hume, Berkely and many other philosophers. The concept of there being
two substances, that which composes the physical world and that which
composes the soul, is the origin of the word **Dualism** but dualism, as
a concept, has been extended beyond this original meaning. Cartesian
dualism is a type of **substance dualism**.
Cartesian dualism is an attempt to explain our experience. According to
Descartes something supernatural would be needed for an unextended
viewing point to exist.
Reid\'s **Natural Dualism** also has a point soul looking at things but
proposes that the things in question are forms in the world rather than
in the brain.
### Property dualism
Another sort of dualism has arisen out of a particular interpretation of
the regress and homunculus arguments. These arguments show that
phenomenal experience is not due entirely to flows from place to place
(i.e.: it is not due to classical processes and functions). Property
dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the appropriate way
(i.e. in the way that living human bodies are organized), mental
properties emerge.
As Goldman (1993) pointed out, qualitative experience does not seem to
be needed in a functional description of a system:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"For any functional description
of a system that is in pain (or has an itch), it seems as if we can
imagine another system with the same functional description but lacking
the qualitative property of painfulness (or itchiness).\"
`</font>`{=html}
Certainly a functional system that merely reports the words \"I am in
pain\" when it is dropped on the floor does not require any qualitative
property of painfulness. The *absent qualia* arguments suggest that even
in a large system there would be no need for qualitative properties for
the performance of any classical function.
Chalmers (1993) commenting on Goldman\'s point, said that this implies
that **zombies** might exist, functional replicas of humans but without
qualia. He then denied that a complete functional replica of a human
could exist without also including qualia:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"It seems to me that the only way
to avoid this conclusion is to deny that Zombie Dave is a conceptual
possibility; and the only principled way to deny that Zombie Dave is a
conceptual possibility is to allow that functional organization is
conceptually constitutive of qualitative content.\" Chalmers
(1993).`</font>`{=html}
In other words he identifies qualia with function. According to Chalmers
(1996) qualia are a particular type of function:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"I claim that conscious
experience arises from fine-grained functional organization. More
specifically, I will argue for a principle of organizational invariance,
holding that given any system that has conscious experiences, then any
system that has the same fine-grained functional organization will have
qualitatively identical experiences. According to this principle,
consciousness is an organizational invariant: a property that remains
constant over all functional isomorphs of a given system. Whether the
organization is realized in silicon chips, in the population of China,
or in beer cans and ping-pong balls does not matter. As long as the
functional organisation is right, conscious experience will be
determined.\" p249`</font>`{=html}
Chalmers\' idea of functional organisation has within it a sometimes
vague implication that the functional units must have a particular form;
for instance, in the development of his argument, he refers to "fine
grained" replacement of organic functional units with inorganic units.
Chalmers is actually making two major points, firstly that qualia occur
during the motion of things (functions), secondly that qualia are
independent of any particular substrate.\*\* For the first point to be
consistent with materialism the qualia must have no effect on the
function, they must be **epiphenomenal**. Epiphenomenal qualia would not
be forbidden by the regress and homunculus arguments and would be akin
to Berkeley\'s \"passive ideas\".
Whether or not epiphenomenal qualia are physical depends upon the
definition of the word \"physical\". If physical functions cause qualia
but qualia cannot affect functions then the qualia are \"physical\" in
the sense of being caused by physical events but might be regarded as
non-physical in the sense of being isolated from further physical
events. In philosophical terms they violate the principle of **Causal
Closure**. However, there are other definitions of physicalism based on
arguments such as **Methodological Naturalism** which hold that anything
that can be investigated using the methods of natural science is a
physical thing (see Stoljar 2001). Thus, although epiphenomenal qualia
may not conform to materialism they may be encompassed by physicalism;
as events that are related to material events they are awaiting a
physical theory of how they emerge from a given function.
The reader might consider whether phenomenal consciousness is indeed
epiphenomenal. Empirical reports describe it as something that is
different from the world beyond the body (see direct
realism) -
could we generate empirical reports of an epiphenomenon?
The term **property dualism** describes how physical events might give
rise to a set of properties that cannot be predicted from the fine
structure of the physical system. The \"dualism\" is present because one
set of events is related to two sets of properties, one of which is not
related by materialism to the set of events. In the case of the proposal
about consciousness outlined above an extra assumption, beyond
materialism, would be needed to explain qualia. Property dualism might
be defined as a theory that there could be a theory of consciousness but
that this requires some new assumption.
As far as the \"when and where\" of consciousness are concerned,
property dualism states that it is somewhere in the processes performed
by the organism and the parts of the organism.
`<font size=1>`{=html} \*\* In terms of information processing, Chalmers
is proposing that qualia are the enactment of a particular information
processing structure.`</font>`{=html}
- Block, N. (2006). Max Black\'s objection to mind-body identity.
Oxford Review of Metaphysics No.3.
<http://philrsss.anu.edu.au/BlockFest/MaxBlack.rtf>
- Chalmers, D.J. (1993) Commentary on \"The Psychology of Folk
Psychology\". Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16:35-36, 1993
- Chalmers, D.J. (1996) \"The Conscious Mind: In Search of a
Fundamental Theory\". Oxford University Press. 1996.
- Goldman, A.I., (1993). The Psychology of Folk Psychology. Behavioral
and Brain Sciences 16: 15-28 (1993).
<http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Papers/Py104/goldman.psyc.html>
### Predicate dualism
Predicate dualism is the view espoused by most non-reductive
physicalists, such as Donald Davidson(1980) and Jerry Fodor(1968), who
maintain that while there is only one ontological category of substances
and properties of substances (usually physical), the predicates that we
use to describe mental events cannot be redescribed in terms of (or
reduced to) physical predicates of natural languages. If we characterize
predicate monism as the view subscribed to by eliminative materialists,
who maintain that such intentional predicates as believe, desire, think,
feel, etc., will eventually be eliminated from both the language of
science and from ordinary language because the entities to which they
refer do not exist, then predicate dualism is most easily defined as the
negation of this position. Predicate dualists believe that so-called
\"folk psychology\", with all of its propositional attitude ascriptions,
is an ineliminable part of the enterprise of describing, explaining and
understanding human mental states and behavior.
Davidson, for example, subscribes to Anomalous Monism, according to
which there can be no strict psycho-physical laws which connect mental
and physical events under their descriptions as mental and physical
events. However, all mental events also have physical descriptions. It
is in terms of the latter that such events can be connected in law-like
relations with other physical events. Mental predicates are irreducibly
different in character (rational, holistic and necessary) from physical
predicates (contingent, atomic and causal).
(Section based on Wikipedia article)
- Davidson, D (1980). Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford University
Press.
- Fodor,J. (1968) *Psychological Explanation*, Random House.
.
### The interaction between mind and brain in dualism
#### Interactionism
Interactionism is the view that mental states, such as beliefs and
desires, causally interact with physical states. This is a position
which is very appealing to common-sense intuitions, notwithstanding the
fact that it is very difficult to establish its validity or correctness
by way of logical argumentation or empirical proof. It is appealing to
common-sense because we are surrounded by such everyday occurrences as a
child\'s touching a hot stove (physical event) which causes him to feel
pain (mental event) and then yell and scream (physical event) which
causes his parents to experience a sensation of fear and protectiveness
(mental event) and so on.
#### Epiphenomalism
According to epiphenomenalism, all mental events are caused by a
physical event and have no physical consequences. So, a mental event of
deciding to pick up a rock (call it \"M\") is caused by the firing of
specific neurons in the brain (call it \"P\"), however when the arm and
hand move to pick up a rock (call it \"E\") this is only caused by P.
The physical causes are in principle reducible to fundamental physics,
and therefore mental causes are eliminated using this reductionist
explanation. If P causes M and E, there is no overdetermination in the
explanation for E.
#### Parallelism
Psycho-physical parallelism is a very unusual view about the interaction
between mental and physical events which was most prominently, and
perhaps only truly, advocated by Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz. Like
Malebranche and others before him, Leibniz recognized the weaknesses of
Descartes\' account of causal interaction taking place in a physical
location in the brain. Malebranche decided that such a material basis of
interaction between material and immaterial was impossible and therefore
formulated his doctrine of occasionalism, stating that the interactions
were really caused by the intervention of God on each individual
occasion. Leibniz idea is that God has created a pre-established harmony
such that it only seems as if physical and mental events cause, and are
caused by, one another. In reality, mental causes only have mental
effects and physical causes only have physical effects. Hence the term
parallelism is used to describe this view.
#### Occasionalism
Occasionalism argues that bodily events are the occasion of an act by
the Creator causing a corresponding mental event, and vice versa. Any
such view requires a theological structure as a premise.
#### Further reading
- Robinson, Howard, \"Dualism\", The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Fall 2003 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2003/entries/dualism/>
- Robinson, H. (2003) \"Dualism\", in S. Stich and T. Warfield (eds)
The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell, Oxford,
85-101.
- Amoroso, R.L. (2010) \"The complementarity of Mind and Body:
Realizing the Dream of Descartes, Einstein and Eccles\", New York:
Nova Science Publishers,
`, ``https://www.novapublishers.com/catalog/product_info.php?products_id=12759`
## Idealism
According to Idealism only the mental truly exists.
The form and content of personal conscious experience might be related
to the structure of the world and brain in several ways. It could be a
**solipsism** or be the mind of God.
*This is a **stub** and needs expansion*.
## Panpsychism
### Etymology
Ancient Greek *pan* (πᾶν : \"all, everything, whole\") and *psyche*
(ψυχή : \"soul, mind\").[^1] Psyche is the from
ψύχω (*psukhō*, \"I blow\") and means mind or \'life-breath\'.
Philip Goff, a proponent of panpsychism, carves out a distinction
between panexperientialism and pancognitivism. Panexperientialism is the
belief that *experience* is ubiquitous, while pancognitivism is the
belief that *cognition* is ubiquitous. Most modern purponents of
panpsychism, such as Annaka Harris and David Chalmers, are careful to
distance themselves from pancognitivism.
In some interpretations, such as monadism, Panpsychism and Idealism can
overlap because the universe is conceived as being composed of an
infinity of point consciousnesses that each contain information about
the whole universe.
The form and content of personal conscious experience might be related
to the structure of the world and brain in many ways.
*This is a **stub** and needs expansion*.
## References
Seager W. & Allen-Hermanson (2001). 'Panpsychism.' Online document:
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, \[online\],
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/panpsychism/>, \[accessed 10/2005\]
**Supervenience**
- Chalmers, D.J. (1996). The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press.
**The problem of regression**
- Ryle, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind. The University of Chicago
Press, 1949.
**The homunculus argument**
- Gregory, R.L. (1990) Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing, Oxford
University Press Inc. New York.
- Gregory, T.L. (1987). The Oxford Companion to Mind. Oxford
University Press.
**Subject-object paradox**
- James, W. (1904)Does \'Consciousness\' Exist? Journal of
Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1,
477-491.
- Hegel, G.W.F. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND: SECTION I. MIND SUBJECTIVE B.
PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND CONSCIOUSNESS Part Three of the Encyclopaedia
of the Philosophical
Sciences
- Velmans, M. (1996) Consciousness and the \"Casual Paradox\".
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 19 (3):
538-542.
- Bermudez, J.L. (1999) The Paradox of Self-Consciousness
(representation and Mind) Psycoloquy:
10,#35
**Ontological status**
- Bierman, D.J. (2004) Non Conscious Processes Preceding Intuitive
decisions
<http://m0134.fmg.uva.nl/~djb/publications/2004/Intuition_bialsymp2004.pdf>
- Damasio, A.R. (1994). Descartes\' error: Emotion, reason and the
human brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam Book.
- Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason
<http://www.arts.cuhk.edu.hk/Philosophy/Kant/cpr/>
**Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness**
Block, N. (1995) On a confusion about a function of consciousness.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 227-287.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/documents/a/00/00/04/31/bbs00000431-00/bbs.block.html>
Block, N. (2004). *The Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science*.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/ecs.pdf>
Dennett, D. (1978). Why You Can\'t Make a Computer that Feels Pain, in:
Brainstorms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 190-229.
Dennett, D. (1988). Quining Qualia. in A. Marcel and E. Bisiach, eds,
Consciousness in Modern Science, Oxford University Press 1988. Reprinted
in W. Lycan, ed., Mind and Cognition: A Reader, MIT Press, 1990, A.
Goldman, ed. Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science, MIT Press,
1993. <http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/quinqual.htm>
Edelman, G.M. (1993). Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the
Mind. New York:
Feyerabend, P. (1963). Mental Events and the Brain, Journal of
Philosophy 40:295-6.
Huxley, T. H. (1874). On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and
its History, The Fortnightly Review, n.s.16:555-580. Reprinted in Method
and Results: Essays by Thomas H. Huxley (New York: D. Appleton and
Company, 1898).
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review
LXXXIII, 4 (October 1974): 435-50.
<http://web.archive.org/19990218140703/members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html>
Rey, Georges, (1997). Contemporary Philosophy of Mind.Blackwell: Oxford
Sellars W. (1956). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, In: Feigl H
and Scriven M (eds) The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of
Psychology and Psychoanalysis: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of
Science, Vol. 1. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 253-329
Whitehead, A.N. (1920). The Concept of Nature. Chapter 3: Time.
<http://spartan.ac.brocku.ca/~lward/Whitehead/Whitehead_1920/White1_03.html>
**Direct Realism**
- Austin, J.L. (1962) Sense and Sensibilia, ed. by Geoffrey J. Warnock
(Oxford, 1962)
- Aydede, M. (2001) Naturalism, introspection, and direct realism
about pain. Consciousness and Emotion, Vol. 2, No. 1, 2001,
pp. 29--73.
<http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/maydede/pain.pdf>
- Chapman, C.R., and Y. Nakamura (1999). A Passion of the Soul: An
Introduction to Pain for Consciousness Researchers. Consciousness
and Cognition, 8: 391-422.
- Dennett, D. (1991a). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown
- Dennett, D. (1991b). Lovely and suspect qualities. Commentary on
David Rosenthal, \"The Independence of Consciousness and Sensory
Quality\" in E. Villanueva, ed., Consciousness, (SOFIA Conference,
Buenos Aires), Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview 1991.
<http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/lovely&s.htm>
- Fowler C A (1986): "An event approach to the study of speech
perception from a direct-realist perspective", J of Phonetics
14(1):3-28.
- Gibson, J. J. (1966) The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems.
Houghton Mifflin Company,Boston.
- Gibson, J. J. (1979) Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Hillsdate.
- Gregory, R.L. 1988. Consciousness in science and philosophy:
conscience and con-science. Chapter 12 in Consciousness in
Contemporary Science. (Editors: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E.).
Oxford Science Publications.
- Le Morvan, Pierre (2004). Arguments against direct realism and how
to counter them. *The American Philosophical Quarterly*, *41*(3),
221-234.\] (pdf) <http://www.tcnj.edu/~lemorvan/DR_web.pdf>
- Michaels, C. F. and Carello, C. (1981). Direct Perception. Century
Psychology Series. Prentice-Hall.
. 1981. Download this book at
<http://ione.psy.uconn.edu/~psy254/MC.pdf>
- Oliveira, André L. G. and Oliveira, Luis F. (2002) Toward an
ecological conception of timbre. In Proceedings Auditory Perception
Cognition and Action Meeting 2002, Kansas City.
<http://cogprints.org/2713/>
- Skinner, B. F. Science and Human Behavior . New York: Macmillan,
1953.
- Skinner, B. F. 1971. Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New York: Knopf.
- Skinner, B. F. 1948. Walden Two. New York: Macmillan.
- Tye, M. (2004). ANOTHER LOOK AT REPRESENTATIONALISM ABOUT PAIN.
Consciousness and Emotion 2004, special issue on pain, edited by
Murat Aydede (with replies by M. Aydede, N. Block, B. Maund, and P.
Noordhof
<http://sun.soci.niu.edu/~phildept/MT/RepresentationalismAndPain.pdf>
- Vygotsky, L.S.(1925) Consciousness as a problem in the psychology of
behavior. Undiscovered Vygotsky: Etudes on the pre-history of
cultural-historical psychology (European Studies in the History of
Science and Ideas. Vol. 8), pp. 251--281. Peter Lang Publishing.
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/1925/consciousness.htm>
- Ziff, Paul. \"About Behaviourism.\" Analysis 18 (1958): 132-136.
Quoted by Larry Hauser in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/b/behavior.htm#B>. F. Skinner:
Radical Behaviorism
**Indirect Realism**
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
- Rizzo, M., Nawrot, M. & Zihl, J. (1995). Motion and shape perception
in cerebral akinetopsia.Brain, 118. 1105-1127.
<http://nawrot.psych.ndsu.nodak.edu/Publications/Nawrot.pdf/RizzoNawrotZihl.1995.pdf>
- Russell, B. (1912). Problems of Philosophy. Home University Library.
<http://www.ditext.com/russell/rus1.html>
- Tye, M. (2003) Qualia. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia/#Repqualia>
Further reading:
- Hume, D. (1739). A Treatise of Human Nature.
<http://www.class.uidaho.edu/mickelsen/ToC/hume%20treatise%20ToC.htm>
- Firth, R. (1949) Sense Data and the Percept Theory, Mind, 58 (1949);
59 (1950). (Describes early reasons for rejecting Indirect Realism)
<http://www.ditext.com/firth/spt.html>
- Grush, R. (2000). Self, world and space: The meaning and mechanisms
of ego- and allocentric spatial representation. Brain and Mind
1(1):59-92.
<http://mind.ucsd.edu/papers/sws/sws.html>
[^1]: Clarke, D.S. *Panpsychism: Past and Recent Selected Readings*.
State University of New York Press, 2004. p.1
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Conflict2#Dualism
*This part of this section is about the where and when of the experience
called consciousness. Is it in the world, in the brain or are the world
and brain within it?*
## Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness
Block(1995) drew attention to the way that there appear to be two types
of consciousness: *phenomenal* consciousness and *access* consciousness:
`Phenomenal consciousness is experience; the phenomenally`\
`conscious aspect of a state is what it is like to be in that`\
`state. The mark of access-consciousness, by contrast, is `\
`availability for use in reasoning and rationally guiding speech `\
`and action. (Block 1995).`
*See the section on Ned Block\'s
ideas
for a deeper coverage of his approach to access and phenomenal
consciousness.*
Block uses Nagel\'s famous (1974) paper, \"What is it like to be a
bat?\" as an exemplary description of phenomenal consciousness.
Excellent descriptions have also been proffered by the empiricist
philosophers who gave lengthy descriptions of consciousness as partly
experience itself. Although Block has formalised the idea of phenomenal
and access consciousness similar ideas have also been put forward by
many philosophers including Kant and Whitehead.
Access consciousness has two interpretations, in the first, used by
Block, it applies to the functions that appear to operate on phenomenal
consciousness. In the second, used by the behaviourists and
eliminativists, it is some property of the functions of the brain that
can be called \'consciousness\'.
This division between phenomenal and functional aspects of consciousness
is useful because it emphasises the idea of phenomenal consciousness as
observation rather than action. Some philosophers such as Huxley in
1874, have taken the view that because phenomenal consciousness appears
to have no function it is of no importance or cannot exist. James (1879)
introduced the term \"epiphenomenalism\" to summarise the idea that
consciousness has no function.
The idea that phenomenal consciousness cannot exist is a type of
*Eliminativism* (also known as Eliminative Materialism). Eliminativism
owes much to the work of Sellars(1956) and Feyerbend (1963). Dennett
(1978) applied Eliminativism to phenomenal consciousness and denies that
pain is real. Others such as Rey(1997) have also applied eliminativism
to phenomenal consciousness.
Dennett (1988) redefines consciousness in terms of access consciousness
alone, he argues that \"Everything real has properties, and since I
don\'t deny the reality of conscious experience, I grant that conscious
experience has properties\". Having related all consciousness to
properties he then declares that these properties are actually
judgements of properties. He considers judgements of the properties of
consciousness to be identical to the properties themselves. He writes:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"The infallibilist line on qualia treats
them as properties of one\'s experience one cannot in principle
misdiscover, and this is a mysterious doctrine (at least as mysterious
as papal infallibility) unless we shift the emphasis a little and treat
qualia as logical constructs out of subjects\' qualia-judgments: a
subject\'s experience has the quale F if and only if the subject judges
his experience to have quale F. \"`</font>`{=html}
Having identified \"properties\" with \"judgement of properties\" he can
then show that the judgements are insubstantial, hence the properties
are insubstantial and hence the qualia are insubstantial or even
non-existent. Dennett concludes that qualia can be rejected as
non-existent:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"So when we look one last time at our
original characterization of qualia, as ineffable, intrinsic, private,
directly apprehensible properties of experience, we find that there is
nothing to fill the bill. In their place are relatively or practically
ineffable public properties we can refer to indirectly via reference to
our private property-detectors\-- private only in the sense of
idiosyncratic. And insofar as we wish to cling to our subjective
authority about the occurrence within us of states of certain types or
with certain properties, we can have some authority\--not infallibility
or incorrigibility, but something better than sheer guessing\--but only
if we restrict ourselves to relational, extrinsic properties like the
power of certain internal states of ours to provoke acts of apparent re-
identification. So contrary to what seems obvious at first blush, there
simply are no qualia at all. \" (Dennett 1988)`</font>`{=html}
Dennett\'s asserts that \"a subject\'s experience has the quale F if and
only if the subject judges his experience to have quale F\". This is a
statement of the belief that qualia are the same as processes such as
judgements. Processes such as judgements are flows of data where one
state examines a previous state in a succession over time and embody
what Whitehead called the \"materialist\" concept of time. Dennett does
not consider how a scientific concept of time might affect his argument.
Dennett\'s argument has been persuasive and there are now many
philosophers and neuroscientists who believe that the problem of
phenomenal consciousness does not exist. This means that, to them, what
we call \'consciousness\' can only be a property of the functions
performed by the brain and body. According to these philosophers only
access consciousness exists.
Those who support the idea of phenomenal consciousness also tend to
frame it in terms of nineteenth century theory where one state examines
a previous state in a succession over time, for instance Edelman(1993)
places the past in memories at an instant and time within experience is
explained as continuing modelling processes:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"Primary consciousness is the state of
being mentally aware of things in the world\--of having mental images in
the present. But it is not accompanied by any sense of a person with a
past and a future\.... In contrast, higher-order consciousness involves
the recognition by a thinking subject of his or her own acts or
affections. It embodies a model of the personal, and of the past and the
future as well as the present. It exhibits direct awareness\--the
noninferential or immediate awareness of mental episodes without the
involvement of sense organs or receptors. It is what we humans have in
addition to primary consciousness. We are conscious of being
conscious.\" `</font>`{=html}
Block(2004) also suggests this flow from state to state in his idea of
\"Reflexivity\" where our idea of familiarity with an object is due to
one state being analysed by another:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"Thus in the "conscious" case, the subject
must have a state that is about the subject's own perceptual experience
(looking familiar) and thus conscious in what might be termed a
"reflexive" sense. An experience is conscious in this sense just in case
it is the object of another of the subject's states; for example, one
has a thought to the effect that one has that experience. The reflexive
sense of \'consciousness\' contrasts with phenomenality, which perhaps
attaches to some states which are not the objects of other mental
states. Reflexive consciousness might better be called 'awareness' than
'consciousness'. Reflexivity is phenomenality plus something else
(reflection) and that opens up the possibility in principle for
phenomenality without reflection. For example, it is at least
conceptually possible for there to be two people in pain, one of whom is
introspecting the pain the other not. (Perhaps infants or animals can
have pain but don't introspect it.) The first is reflexively conscious
of the pain, but both have phenomenally conscious states, since pain is
by its very nature a phenomenally conscious state. \"`</font>`{=html}
Both Block and Edelman allow phenomenal consciousness, our experience,
as an unexplained phenomenon. Block, Edelman and also Dennett\'s ideas
of consciousness are shown in the illustration below:
![](Constudphen.gif "Constudphen.gif")
This model differs from the empirical reports of phenomenal
consciousness that were considered earlier. According to the empirical
reports the present moment in our experience is extended so the
succession of outputs or stages of access consciousness could constitute
the contents of phenomenal consciousness. In other words phenomenal
consciousness is composed of periods of access consciousness. This is
how it seems to the empiricist and in our own experience but how such a
state could be explained in terms of brain activity is highly
problematical. Given that nineteenth century ideas cannot explain such a
state a scientific explanation will be required.
The idea that phenomenal consciousness misrepresents or \"misdiscovers\"
itself (Dennett 1988) deserves further discussion. According to
materialism the present instant has no duration so can only be known in
succeeding instants as a report or memory and this could be wrong.
Whitehead considered that this viewpoint originates in an archaic view
of science, particularly the concept of time in science:
\"The eighteenth and nineteenth centuries accepted as their natural
philosophy a certain circle of concepts which were as rigid and definite
as those of the philosophy of the middle ages, and were accepted with as
little critical research. I will call this natural philosophy
\'materialism.\' Not only were men of science materialists, but also
adherents of all schools of philosophy. The idealists only differed from
the philosophic materialists on question of the alignment of nature in
reference to mind. But no one had any doubt that the philosophy of
nature considered in itself was of the type which I have called
materialism. It is the philosophy which I have already examined in my
two lectures of this course preceding the present one. It can be
summarised as the belief that nature is an aggregate of material and
that this material exists in some sense at each successive member of a
one-dimensional series of extensionless instants of time. Furthermore
the mutual relations of the material entities at each instant formed
these entities into a spatial configuration in an unbounded space. It
would seem that space\-\--on this theory-would be as instantaneous as
the instants, and that some explanation is required of the relations
between the successive instantaneous spaces. The materialistic theory is
however silent on this point; and the succession of instantaneous spaces
is tacitly combined into one persistent space. This theory is a purely
intellectual rendering of experience which has had the luck to get
itself formulated at the dawn of scientific thought. It has dominated
the language and the imagination of science since science flourished in
Alexandria, with the result that it is now hardly possible to speak
without appearing to assume its immediate obviousness.\" (Whitehead
1920).
## Direct Realism and Direct Perception
Direct Realism proposes that phenomenal experience is directly objects
in the world without any intervening representation. It is motivated by
the belief that the Problem of Regression, the Subject-Object Paradox
and the recursion form of the Homunculus arguments show that phenomenal
consciousness cannot occur in the brain alone. Direct Realists reason
that if phenomenal consciousness cannot be things in the brain then it
must be something outside the brain.
There are two principle types of Direct Realism: Natural Dualism and
Behaviourism (both Radical and Analytical). Some behaviourists use the
term "Direct Perception" rather than Direct Realism and consider that
only the invariant parts of perception are direct (see for instance
Michaels and Carello 1981). Thomas Reid is generally regarded as the
founder of Direct Realism. In his Natural Dualism he proposed that the
soul is in direct contact with the contents of experience and these
contents are things in the world beyond the body. The Direct Realism of
Reid is summarised in the statement of his famous disciple Sir William
Hamilton: \"In the simplest act of perception I am conscious of myself
as the perceiving subject and of an external reality as the object
perceived\". Reid\'s Natural Dualism has now been largely replaced by
radical and analytical behaviourism which eschew the idea of a soul and
propose that phenomenal consciousness, if it exists at all, is a
behavioural reflex.
The modern justification of Direct Realism mainly consists of arguments
against Indirect Realism or Representationalism. Philosophers such as
Austin (1962) and Le Morvan (2004) have summarised the Direct Realism
debate and have identified the following arguments in favour of Indirect
Realism and given rebuttals to each of them:
1\. The Causal Argument: perception involves a succession of causal
events such as the reflection of photons, bleaching of retinal pigments
etc. so perception must involve the end of this causal chain. The Direct
Realist response is that, although there may be a causal chain in
sensation this does not inevitably imply that the end of the chain is
the content of phenomenal experience.
2\. The Time Lag Argument: it takes time for light to travel from an
object to the senses, time for chemical changes in the retina etc\...
The Direct Realist response is that direct perception may be referred
back in time.
3\. The Partial Character of Perception Argument: we only perceive the
surface of objects, and then only a part of the surface. As the whole
object would be perceived directly perception must be indirect. The
Direct Realist response is that direct perception could occur even if
only parts of an object were perceived.
4\. The Perceptual Relativity Argument: things appear to be different
shapes depending upon the point of view. The Direct Realist response is
that if perception can occur backwards in time it should have no problem
occurring back down a line of sight. However, Le Morvan\'s argument does
not seem to encompass the geometrical nature of phenomenal experience,
seeking to explain geometry in terms of movement.
5\. The Argument from Perceptual Illusion: A stick may appear bent when
projecting from the surface of water. Direct Realists apply the argument
used in (4) to this problem. The bent stick illusion is a physical event
in the world beyond the eye rather than a normal optical illusion such
as the Muller-Lyer illusion etc., see (6) for a discussion of optical
illusions.
6\. The Argument from Hallucination: Hallucinations are not in the world
beyond the body. This is highly problematical for Direct Realists
especially when phenomena such as lucid dreams, dreams and visual
imaginations are included along with hallucinations. Direct Realists
classify these phenomena as not being perceptions or deny that they
actually exist as phenomena. Indirect Realists would maintain that all
of perception is a reconstruction and use optical illusions such as the
Muller-Lyer, Ames Room etc. to justify this contention so the Direct
Realist approach to hallucination, dreams etc. might seem like an
unwillingness to accept Indirect Realism rather than an argument.
7\. The Dubitability Argument (cf: Indubitability argument): we cannot
doubt current phenomenal experience but we can doubt the world beyond
the body therefore phenomenal experience is not the world beyond the
body. Direct Realists fall back on Presentism or functional Presentism
to defeat this argument. If phenomenal experience is instantaneous and
made anew at each instant then anything can be doubted.
The points above have summarised the Direct Realist stance on visual
perception. Other sensory modalities have also been considered in the
Direct Realism debate.
Fowler (1986) considered that sounds were attached to objects in the
world. This idea is strange because sounds only seem to be closely
attached to objects in the world when these objects are seen as well as
heard. For example, when a subject is blindfolded it is found that there
can be a large error in locating the position of a sound in the world,
this is especially true for low frequency sounds. The Direct Realist
approach has difficulty explaining the transition from sounds with an
indefinite location when a subject is blindfolded to sounds that are
bound to visual events when the blindfold is removed. It also runs into
problems explaining how the sound of speech from a single loudspeaker
can become bound to lip movements on a cinema screen. If the binding
does not occur in the brain then where does it occur?
Pain is particularly problematic for Direct Realism because, unlike
colour vision where \'red\' is inferred to be a property of electrons or
light, pain is an inner experience that is not a property of tissue
damage. Tissue damage has properties such as bleeding, wheal formation
etc. but pain seems to be phenomenal experience in the brain and
\'phantom pain\' can occur without tissue damage (see Aydede (2001), Tye
(2004) and Chapman, and Nakamura (1999) for further analysis). On closer
inspection other sensations also appear to be inner experiences rather
than direct sensations. For instance, the red crosses of different hues
in the illustration below are all due to the same physical wavelengths
of light. In this case the range of hues in experience is unrelated to
the actual physical red on the page or screen.
Another problem for Direct Realism is that it does not overcome the
problems that it is supposed to solve. The argument for Direct Realism
begins with the idea that there are severe problems with
representationalism (the idea that phenomenal experience is in the
brain) and that direct perception is an alternative that does not have
these problems. However on closer inspection Direct Realism suffers from
almost same problems as representationalism. If phenomenal experience is
the world itself then Ryle\'s regress applies to the world itself and
this can only be avoided by assuming that phenomenal experience is a
subset of the world (i.e.: a representation) that receives input from
other parts of the world that are not part of phenomenal experience.
It is also commonly assumed that Direct Realism avoids the recursion
argument because it is believed that the separation of the observer from
the things that are observed is simply due to the geometry of the world.
If such simple geometry is possible between the eye and the world then
it should also be possible in the brain and a similar geometrical
explanation could be invoked to avoid recursion in representations.
These points are shown in the illustration below:
image:Constuddir1.gif
Scientists have a further problem with Direct Realism. The illustration
below demonstrates that our scientific knowledge of the world differs
markedly from our phenomenal experience.
image:constuddirect.gif
It is difficult to see how the form and content of phenomenal experience
could supervene directly on the world beyond the body. The world
inferred from measurements beyond the body seems to be a nebulous set of
quantum phenomena that are arranged as probability fields in three
dimensions at any instant. The objects in this real world are mostly
space. The world of phenomenal experience on the other hand contains
objects that are one-sided, and are like a 2 dimensional field of
vectors directed simultaneously at an observation point which is
apparently separate from them. Phenomenal experience is not three
dimensional, the rear of objects is not available within it at any
instant. Visual phenomenal experience seems to be a geometrical
relationship between an abstract observation point and the reflection
properties of the part of the world external to the body. It is a form
that crudely overlies the angular separations in inferred reality,
providing approximate directional data. It is not like things in
themselves beyond the body, not even in type, being a set of directional
vectors. (See the module on the neuroscience of perception for a
discussion of depth perception).
If the form and content of visual phenomenal experience are abstractions
separated according to the angular positions of things in the world
beyond the body then theories which propose that phenomenal experience
is the world itself are problematical. It should be noted that things
arranged according to angular positions can appear to overlie any group
of similar things along a radius from the centre point.
![](Constuddirectangle.gif "Constuddirectangle.gif")
If Direct Realists admit that things are as they appear to be, observed
according to angular positions at a \'point eye\', then any
representation of things on the inside of a sphere of any radius would
appear similar. The geometry of the \'point eye\' is problematical
whether the view contains the world itself or a representation of the
world; it cannot be the movements of lumps of matter or energy and the
point observation cannot be due to lumps all landing at a point. In
other words the \'view\' is inconsistent with nineteenth century
materialism and will require a scientific explanation.
Radical and Analytical Behaviourism tackle the problem of the difference
between the world inferred from measurements beyond the body and the
phenomenal world by denying phenomenal consciousness and maintaining
that access and reflex consciousness are all that exists or is
necessary. Radical Behaviourism is an offshoot of psychological
behaviourism and was established as a philosophical adjunct to Marxism
by Vygotsky and popularised by Burrhus Frederic Skinner (see Skinner
1953). There is another movement in psychological behaviourism which is
similar to Radical Behaviourism called Ecological Psychology (see Gibson
1966, 1979 and also Michaels and Carello 1981). Analytical Behaviourism
is a philosophical movement established by Gilbert Ryle (see Ryle 1949).
The core of Analytical and Radical Behaviourism is the assumption that
consciousness exists for a durationless instant so that the Dubitability
Argument and the Regression and Recursion Arguments can be applied (Ryle
1949, Skinner 1971 and see the sections on Ryle\'s Regress and the
Subject-Object Paradox above). As a result the Direct Realist is able to
insinuate that subjects only think that they have had a particular
experience (cf: Dennett 1991a). It is intriguing that Eliminativists
also maintain that experience is the world itself, for instance an
insight into Dennett\'s idea of the mind is to be found on pages 407-408
of Consciousness Explained:
\"It seemed to him, according to the text, as if his mind - his visual
field - were filled with intricate details of gold-green buds an
wiggling branches, but although this is how it seemed this was an
illusion. No such \"plenum\" ever came into his mind; the plenum
remained out in the world where it is didn\'t have to be represented,
but could just be. When we marvel, in those moments of heightened
self-consciousness, at the glorious richness of our conscious
experience, the richness we marvel at is actually the richness of the
world outside, in all its ravishing detail. It does not \"enter\" our
conscious minds, but is simply available\"
This is a clear description of Direct Realism (although Dennett does not
describe himself as a direct realist).
Radical Behaviourism is sometimes described as the dictum that the only
psychological events that are of importance are those that occur outside
the head. The absurdity of this has led to jokes:
Q: What does one behaviorist say to another when they meet on the
street?
A: You\'re fine. How am I?
Q: What does one behaviorist say to another after sex?
A: That was great for you. How was it for me?
(Ziff 1958)
However Vygotsky, Skinner and other Radical Behaviourists hold that
inner behaviour is possible so that events within the brain can result
in reward or punishment. Vygotsky (1925) describes this approach:
\"Consciousness is wholly reduced to the transmitting mechanisms of
reflexes operating according to general laws, i.e., no processes other
than reactions can be admitted into the organism. The way is also paved
for the solution of the problem of self-awareness and self-observation.
Inner perception and introspection are possible only thanks to the
existence of a proprioceptive field and secondary reflexes, which are
connected with it. This is always the echo of a reaction.\"
Hence Radical Behaviourists are able to make the claim that what are
believed to be representations with phenomenal content are processes.
Even events such as pain can then be explained as reflexes involving
organs within the skin. However, by opening the possibility that such
reflexes could occur at any sense organ, including the eye, this makes
Radical Behaviourism a mixed Direct Realist/Indirect Realist philosophy
with consciousness as a process, not a separate thing such as phenomenal
consciousness (see the section on representationalism and intentionality
below).
But this raises a serious issue for science: can the phenomenal
consciousness that seems to contain our observations really be argued
out of existence on the basis of a theory? As Gregory (1988) put it: "
'If you can't explain it -- deny it' is one strategy for dealing with
embarrassing questions such as 'what is consciousness?' ". But is this
the right strategy?
Direct Realism fails to overcome the problems of regression and
recursion inherent in representations. It proposes that phenomenal
consciousness is identical to the physical world beyond the body but
must then use a plethora of arguments to explain why this is evidently
not so. When confronted with these problems its proponents resort to the
argument that everything can be doubted and can misrepresent itself. Yet
it is still widely believed.
It should be noted that Direct Realism is espoused in Religious Natural
Dualism, some forms of Augustinian theology, nineteenth century
materialism and its offspring such as Marxism, post-modernism,
post-Marxism, and various sociological movements. It is also necessary
for some forms of Strong AI to occur. Perhaps this explains why few
ideas have attracted as much attention and defence as Direct Realism.
It is interesting to compare the Direct Realist and Indirect Realist
interpretations of something as simple as a cartoon on television (such
as the image below). According to Indirect Realism the cartoon would be
a moving representation constructed in the brain using data from the
senses. This leads to the prediction of brain mechanisms for modelling
motions, combining colours, binding sound and vision etc., many of which
have been verified. Can you demonstrate how the theory of Direct Realism
could explain the phenomenal experience that contains the cartoon and
produce a list of the predictions made by the theory?
![](constudcartoon.gif "constudcartoon.gif")
In science a theory should be of predictive value, for instance,
information theory describes how the state of a thing can be impressed
on a carrier so that a signal can be transmitted from one place to
another. This theory predicts what will happen when the signal arrives
at its destination and how the state of the source can be inferred from
the events at the destination, the total amount of information that can
be transmitted etc. At the destination it is the form of the signal that
is directly known by interaction and measurement, the form of the source
is inferred. Direct Realism is a direct challenge to this information
theory but does it deliver a more powerful predictive description of
phenomenal consciousness or is experience always dependent on what
happens to the information flow between things in the world and
somewhere in the brain? Does direct realism have a physical theory?
Ultimately it appears as if Direct Realism is about various
understandings of Information Theory. For example, Austin (1962)
discusses what we see when we see a church camouflaged as a barn and
comments that: \"We see, of course, a church that now looks like a
barn.\". Do we see a church or a barn? Scientific information theory is
clear about this, the church is an entity composed of selected
information from the quantum state of its constituents, the optical
image of a camouflaged church is an arrangement of photons emanating
from a screen on which it is projected, the retina has an arrangement of
chemical and electrical events based on an optical image and conscious
visual experience correlates with the arrangement of things on the
retina. The fact that conscious experience also correlates with
classifications of the retinal image as a barn or a church suggests that
conscious experience is an arrangement of things in the brain based on
both the retinal arrangement and the contents of a relational database.
Austin\'s arguments have been mythologised as a final demonstration that
\"sense data\" theories are false. However, as will be seen below, sense
data theories merely claim that there is a succession of information
states between an information state outside the body and that reported
as conscious experience i.e.: subjects report that a church is
camouflaged when it is camouflaged.
## Indirect Realism
Indirect realism proposes that phenomenal consciousness exists and is a
set of signals or **sense data**, usually in the brain. This was
proposed by philosophers from Aristotle to Locke and was probably the
most widespread idea of conscious experience until the eighteenth
century.
The idea of sense data is discussed in depth by Russell (1912).
Russell\'s original definition is given below:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Let us give the name of
\'sense-data\' to the things that are immediately known in sensation:
such things as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and so
on. We shall give the name \'sensation\' to the experience of being
immediately aware of these things. Thus, whenever we see a colour, we
have a sensation of the colour, but the colour itself is a sense-datum,
not a sensation. The colour is that of which we are immediately aware,
and the awareness itself is the sensation. It is plain that if we are to
know anything about the table, it must be by means of the sense-data \--
brown colour, oblong shape, smoothness, etc. \-- which we associate with
the table; but, for the reasons which have been given, we cannot say
that the table is the sense-data, or even that the sense-data are
directly properties of the table.\"`</font>`{=html}
Russell\'s definition is a materialist concept in which experience is
always **of** something because the durationless instant of the present
has always gone. As such it differs from some empiricist ideas where
experience is not confined to the durationless instant.
Science is Indirect Realist because it holds that the scientist can only
make **measurements** of events in the world. These measurements give
rise to signals as a result of interaction with the event. According to
**decoherence theory** the signals are a state that is a mixture of the
state of the measuring instrument and the state of the thing being
measured. For example, the eyes are measuring instruments that are
sensitive to photons, photons are signals containing a state that is
based on the state of electrons in a surface and the state of electrons
is based on the state of the surface etc. Scientific inference allows
some aspects of the state of the surface to be inferred from the state
of the photons.
In modern Indirect Realism there is an attempt to distinguish the
phenomenal content of conscious experience from the processing involved
in accessing this phenomenal content. According to these theories
phenomenal experience is an arrangement of signals that are the content
of the experience. This arrangement forms a *representation* of things
in the world so this form of indirect realism is known as
**Representationalism**. Tye (2003) describes types of
representationalist theory:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Representationalism, as I have
presented it so far, is an identity thesis with respect to qualia:
qualia are supposedly one and the same as certain representational
contents.\"`</font>`{=html}
Tye also describes variants of this idea of representationalism:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Sometimes it is held instead
that qualia are one and the same as certain representational properties
of experiences; and sometimes it is is argued that these
representational properties are themselves irreducible (Siewert 1998).
There is also a weaker version of representationalism, according to
which it is metaphysically necessary that experiences exactly alike with
respect to their representational contents are exactly alike with
respect to their qualia. Obviously, this supervenience thesis leaves
open the further question as to the essential nature of
qualia.\"`</font>`{=html} (Tye 2003).
In a scientific sense Direct Realists believe that phenomenal experience
is the signals that occur next to things in the world beyond the body
(which they call \"things in themselves\") and Indirect Realists usually
believe that phenomenal experience is signals in the brain. It can be
seen from the pattern of signal flow that the signals travelling into
the brain preserve the spatial relationships of the original signals and
encode the properties in the original signals. This means that the
original signals next to the QM sources and the signals in the brain are
equivalent provided the latter are oriented appropriately relative to
signals from the body. Either set of signals could transmit or contain
the same information. Both Direct and Indirect Realism cannot, at
present, explain the physics of how a viewing point occurs in experience
i.e.: how we seem to see through an apparent space to the signals that
are the contents of experience. So the choice between Direct Realism and
Indirect Realism reduces to whether there is only one set of signals or
a chain of signals between the world and phenomenal experience.
The philosophical arguments for Indirect Realism are listed below:
1\. Variable perspective: when we see things the view changes so what we
see must be a different set of signals depending on the view rather than
a constant object.
2\. Illusions: we can see through fingers and see a variety of colours
where measurements tell us one exists. Direct Realists quote the \"bent
stick illusion\", which is not really an illusion at all, being a
physical event.
3\. Hallucinations: two people can have phenomenal experience containing
a table. The first may be viewing a real table whereas the second may be
hallucinating a table. If the tables are the same (phenomenally) then
experience is indirect.
4\. Double vision: press the side of one eye, two images appear (cf Hume
1739) yet there are not two things in the world.
5\. Time gap arguments: according to materialism the past has gone. The
things being seen no longer exist in the state that relates to the state
in experience. In the extreme case, some stars in the night sky no
longer exist but are still in experience so experience must be a derived
signal.
6\. Secondary qualities such as pain, colour and smell do not exist as
physical things in the source of signals and are likely to be properties
of signals in the brain.
![](constudindirect.gif "constudindirect.gif")
Indirect Realism has received strong support from recent discoveries in
neuroscience, for example, it is now clear that both the colour and
motion in phenomenal experience are added by cortical processes. In
Cerebral **Achromatopsia** patients have suffered trauma to area V4 of
the cerebral cortex and report seeing the world in greyscale with no
colour vision and in Congenital Achromatopsia people do not even
understand the meaning of \'colour\'. In an astonishing ailment called
**Akinetopsia** patients perceive movement as a succession of stationary
images (Rizzo *et al.* 1995). Akinetopsia is usually associated with
damage to cortical area V5. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) have demonstrated
that the addition of colour occurs more rapidly than the addition of
motion. The section on the Neuroscience of Consciousness describes these
discoveries and many other aspects of the creation of phenomenal
experience in the brain.
Unfortunately knowledge of the whereabouts of the signals that are the
content of conscious experience does not resolve the problem of
phenomenal consciousness. Whether these signals are next to objects in
the world or at the end of a chain of signals in the brain there still
remains the problem of how they become arranged in the form of
experience. If such a thing occurs at all.
### Intentionality and representation
There is a materialist interpretation of representationalism in which
representations are redefined as intentional states:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"One way of explaining what is
meant by 'intentionality' in the (more obscure) philosophical sense is
this: it is that aspect of mental states or events that consists in
their being of or about things (as pertains to the questions, 'What are
you thinking of?' and 'What are you thinking about?'). Intentionality is
the aboutness or directedness of mind (or states of mind) to things,
objects, states of affairs, events. So if you are thinking about San
Francisco, or about the increased cost of living there, or about your
meeting someone there at Union Square---your mind, your thinking, is
directed toward San Francisco, or the increased cost of living, or the
meeting in Union Square. To think at all is to think of or about
something in this sense. This 'directedness' conception of
intentionality plays a prominent role in the influential philosophical
writings of Franz Brentano and those whose views developed in response
to his (to be discussed further in Section 3).\"(Siewert
2003)`</font>`{=html}
This definition allows \"representation\" to be redefined as a data
stream rather than a set of things arranged in some mental or neural
state that represents things in space. Husserl thought this approach
would allow a description of consciousness that \"carefully abstains
from affirming the existence of anything in spatio-temporal reality\"
(Siewert 2003) although it could be argued that a data stream such as
any description can never escape the constraints of representation in
time at some place.
Unfortunately the concept of \"intentionality\" has become so diverse
that it could be applied to almost any aspect of the description of
consciousness. An interesting example of this is given by Loar (2001)
where \"intentionality\" is considered to overlap \"representing\" and
\"conceiving\":
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"A person\'s thoughts represent
things to her \-- conceive things \-- in many ways: perceptually,
memory-wise, descriptively, by naming, by analogy, by intuitive sorting,
theoretically, abstractly, implicitly and explicitly. These various
manners of conceiving have something in common: they have intentional
properties, and they have them essentially. `</font>`{=html}
The usage of the term \"intentional state\" has become so broad that it
now means little more than a state that is about another state.
References
Siewert, C. (2003). Consciousness and Intentionality. The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-intentionality/>
Also see Loar, B. (2001) "Phenomenal Intentionality as the Basis of
Mental Content", in Reflections and Replies, ed. M. Hahn and B.
Ramsberg, MIT.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/courses/concepts/loar.html>
Williford, K. (2002) The intentionality of consciousness and the
consciousness of intentionality. Intentionality: Past and Future, edited
by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis, Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi.
<http://web.stcloudstate.edu/kwwilliford/Intentionality%20of%20Consciousness.pdf>
Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism Defended. Philosophical Review 110
(April 2001):199-240. <http://stripe.colorado.edu/~leeds/byrne.pdf>
### Cartesian materialism
The term \"Cartesian materialism\" once meant the idea that the mind is
in the brain (see for instance Block 1995). The term had largely fallen
out of use in philosophy until revived by Daniel Dennett (1991) in the
book *Consciousness Explained*. Dennett uses a very particular
definition of the term in his discussions and also uses a particular
definition of the word \"mind\". See the section on Daniel
Dennett
for Dennett\'s critique. Philosophers who adhere to the idea that the
mind is in the brain tend to call themselves \"indirect realists\" or
\"representationalists\" where the substrate of conscious experience is
in the brain and would deny that Dennett\'s critique applies to their
proposals. Dennett\'s critique makes the materialist assumption that if
there is a representation in the brain then a further flow of material
out of this representation would be required for the representation to
become part of mind.
### Identity theories of mind
The idea that mental states are brain states is known as the **identity
theory of mind**. There are two sorts of identity theory, in **type**
identity theory it is held that mental states are identical to brain
states whereas in **token** identity theory it is held that mental
states correlate with brain states.
Type identity theory was attacked by Putnam in \"The Nature of Mental
States\" where he pointed out that if mental states are functions then
type identity theory would presuppose that animals that had the same
mental states would need to have identical brain structures. He
suggested that this is unlikely, it being more probable that animals
have functional systems that perform similar overall functions but which
are not identical. In other words, if it is assumed that conscious
experience is a set of functions then token identity theory is more
probable than type identity theory.
Putnam\'s critique does not preclude identity theories of mind that
involve \"passive ideas\" (i.e.: states that are not classical
functions).
Most identity theories of mind would be representational, the physical
states representing the world in some way. All identity theories of mind
involve Cartesian materialism in the sense of the mental states being
brain states. According to identity theories the mind is in the brain.
Putnam, H. (1967) The nature of mental states. In The Nature of Mind,
edited by Rosenthal, pp. 197--203. Originally published as
\"Psychological predicates in Art, Mind, and Religion\", edited by
Capitan and Merill, pp. 37--48.
## Dualism
Prior to considering the arguments surrounding dualism it is important
to have a clear idea of \"information\" because many of these arguments
have parallels with the difference between information as a set of
states that can be transmitted and the substrate on which this
information is expressed or from which the information is derived. See
Elementary information and information systems
theory.
### Cartesian dualism
Descartes, a philosopher, analysed his experience and developed an
empirical description of how it is arranged. He described mental images
and perceptions as extended in space and with a duration. He called
these extended things **ideas** (Cartesian ideas) and proposed that they
are patterns in the brain. Descartes thought the pineal gland was the
most likely location for these ideas because it is one of the few single
organs in the brain. He also proposed that there is a rational soul that
directly contacts these ideas:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Now among these figures, it is
not those imprinted on the external sense organs, or on the internal
surface of the brain, which should be taken to be ideas - but only those
which are traced in the spirits on the surface of gland H *(where the
seat of the imagination and the \'common sense\' is located)*. That is
to say, it is only the latter figures which should be taken to be the
forms or images which the rational soul united to this machine will
consider directly when it imagines some object or perceives it by the
senses.\" Descartes (1664)`</font>`{=html}
See section on
Descartes
for more information and references.
Descartes considered that the soul was a physical point, an unextended
entity that acts like a mind\'s eye. He called this unextended place the
*res cogitans* and concluded that it was a substance that differed from
that of material things:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\".. I thence concluded that I was
a substance whose whole essence or nature consists only in thinking, and
which, that it may exist, has need of no place, nor is dependent on any
material thing; so that \" I,\" that is to say, the mind by which I am
what I am, is wholly distinct from the body, and is even more easily
known than the latter, and is such, that although the latter were not,
it would still continue to be all that it is.\"Descartes
(1637)`</font>`{=html}
This unextended substance that is not material gives the word
\"substance\" a new meaning. It has been attacked as a concept by Locke,
Hume, Berkely and many other philosophers. The concept of there being
two substances, that which composes the physical world and that which
composes the soul, is the origin of the word **Dualism** but dualism, as
a concept, has been extended beyond this original meaning. Cartesian
dualism is a type of **substance dualism**.
Cartesian dualism is an attempt to explain our experience. According to
Descartes something supernatural would be needed for an unextended
viewing point to exist.
Reid\'s **Natural Dualism** also has a point soul looking at things but
proposes that the things in question are forms in the world rather than
in the brain.
### Property dualism
Another sort of dualism has arisen out of a particular interpretation of
the regress and homunculus arguments. These arguments show that
phenomenal experience is not due entirely to flows from place to place
(i.e.: it is not due to classical processes and functions). Property
dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the appropriate way
(i.e. in the way that living human bodies are organized), mental
properties emerge.
As Goldman (1993) pointed out, qualitative experience does not seem to
be needed in a functional description of a system:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"For any functional description
of a system that is in pain (or has an itch), it seems as if we can
imagine another system with the same functional description but lacking
the qualitative property of painfulness (or itchiness).\"
`</font>`{=html}
Certainly a functional system that merely reports the words \"I am in
pain\" when it is dropped on the floor does not require any qualitative
property of painfulness. The *absent qualia* arguments suggest that even
in a large system there would be no need for qualitative properties for
the performance of any classical function.
Chalmers (1993) commenting on Goldman\'s point, said that this implies
that **zombies** might exist, functional replicas of humans but without
qualia. He then denied that a complete functional replica of a human
could exist without also including qualia:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"It seems to me that the only way
to avoid this conclusion is to deny that Zombie Dave is a conceptual
possibility; and the only principled way to deny that Zombie Dave is a
conceptual possibility is to allow that functional organization is
conceptually constitutive of qualitative content.\" Chalmers
(1993).`</font>`{=html}
In other words he identifies qualia with function. According to Chalmers
(1996) qualia are a particular type of function:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"I claim that conscious
experience arises from fine-grained functional organization. More
specifically, I will argue for a principle of organizational invariance,
holding that given any system that has conscious experiences, then any
system that has the same fine-grained functional organization will have
qualitatively identical experiences. According to this principle,
consciousness is an organizational invariant: a property that remains
constant over all functional isomorphs of a given system. Whether the
organization is realized in silicon chips, in the population of China,
or in beer cans and ping-pong balls does not matter. As long as the
functional organisation is right, conscious experience will be
determined.\" p249`</font>`{=html}
Chalmers\' idea of functional organisation has within it a sometimes
vague implication that the functional units must have a particular form;
for instance, in the development of his argument, he refers to "fine
grained" replacement of organic functional units with inorganic units.
Chalmers is actually making two major points, firstly that qualia occur
during the motion of things (functions), secondly that qualia are
independent of any particular substrate.\*\* For the first point to be
consistent with materialism the qualia must have no effect on the
function, they must be **epiphenomenal**. Epiphenomenal qualia would not
be forbidden by the regress and homunculus arguments and would be akin
to Berkeley\'s \"passive ideas\".
Whether or not epiphenomenal qualia are physical depends upon the
definition of the word \"physical\". If physical functions cause qualia
but qualia cannot affect functions then the qualia are \"physical\" in
the sense of being caused by physical events but might be regarded as
non-physical in the sense of being isolated from further physical
events. In philosophical terms they violate the principle of **Causal
Closure**. However, there are other definitions of physicalism based on
arguments such as **Methodological Naturalism** which hold that anything
that can be investigated using the methods of natural science is a
physical thing (see Stoljar 2001). Thus, although epiphenomenal qualia
may not conform to materialism they may be encompassed by physicalism;
as events that are related to material events they are awaiting a
physical theory of how they emerge from a given function.
The reader might consider whether phenomenal consciousness is indeed
epiphenomenal. Empirical reports describe it as something that is
different from the world beyond the body (see direct
realism) -
could we generate empirical reports of an epiphenomenon?
The term **property dualism** describes how physical events might give
rise to a set of properties that cannot be predicted from the fine
structure of the physical system. The \"dualism\" is present because one
set of events is related to two sets of properties, one of which is not
related by materialism to the set of events. In the case of the proposal
about consciousness outlined above an extra assumption, beyond
materialism, would be needed to explain qualia. Property dualism might
be defined as a theory that there could be a theory of consciousness but
that this requires some new assumption.
As far as the \"when and where\" of consciousness are concerned,
property dualism states that it is somewhere in the processes performed
by the organism and the parts of the organism.
`<font size=1>`{=html} \*\* In terms of information processing, Chalmers
is proposing that qualia are the enactment of a particular information
processing structure.`</font>`{=html}
- Block, N. (2006). Max Black\'s objection to mind-body identity.
Oxford Review of Metaphysics No.3.
<http://philrsss.anu.edu.au/BlockFest/MaxBlack.rtf>
- Chalmers, D.J. (1993) Commentary on \"The Psychology of Folk
Psychology\". Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16:35-36, 1993
- Chalmers, D.J. (1996) \"The Conscious Mind: In Search of a
Fundamental Theory\". Oxford University Press. 1996.
- Goldman, A.I., (1993). The Psychology of Folk Psychology. Behavioral
and Brain Sciences 16: 15-28 (1993).
<http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Papers/Py104/goldman.psyc.html>
### Predicate dualism
Predicate dualism is the view espoused by most non-reductive
physicalists, such as Donald Davidson(1980) and Jerry Fodor(1968), who
maintain that while there is only one ontological category of substances
and properties of substances (usually physical), the predicates that we
use to describe mental events cannot be redescribed in terms of (or
reduced to) physical predicates of natural languages. If we characterize
predicate monism as the view subscribed to by eliminative materialists,
who maintain that such intentional predicates as believe, desire, think,
feel, etc., will eventually be eliminated from both the language of
science and from ordinary language because the entities to which they
refer do not exist, then predicate dualism is most easily defined as the
negation of this position. Predicate dualists believe that so-called
\"folk psychology\", with all of its propositional attitude ascriptions,
is an ineliminable part of the enterprise of describing, explaining and
understanding human mental states and behavior.
Davidson, for example, subscribes to Anomalous Monism, according to
which there can be no strict psycho-physical laws which connect mental
and physical events under their descriptions as mental and physical
events. However, all mental events also have physical descriptions. It
is in terms of the latter that such events can be connected in law-like
relations with other physical events. Mental predicates are irreducibly
different in character (rational, holistic and necessary) from physical
predicates (contingent, atomic and causal).
(Section based on Wikipedia article)
- Davidson, D (1980). Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford University
Press.
- Fodor,J. (1968) *Psychological Explanation*, Random House.
.
### The interaction between mind and brain in dualism
#### Interactionism
Interactionism is the view that mental states, such as beliefs and
desires, causally interact with physical states. This is a position
which is very appealing to common-sense intuitions, notwithstanding the
fact that it is very difficult to establish its validity or correctness
by way of logical argumentation or empirical proof. It is appealing to
common-sense because we are surrounded by such everyday occurrences as a
child\'s touching a hot stove (physical event) which causes him to feel
pain (mental event) and then yell and scream (physical event) which
causes his parents to experience a sensation of fear and protectiveness
(mental event) and so on.
#### Epiphenomalism
According to epiphenomenalism, all mental events are caused by a
physical event and have no physical consequences. So, a mental event of
deciding to pick up a rock (call it \"M\") is caused by the firing of
specific neurons in the brain (call it \"P\"), however when the arm and
hand move to pick up a rock (call it \"E\") this is only caused by P.
The physical causes are in principle reducible to fundamental physics,
and therefore mental causes are eliminated using this reductionist
explanation. If P causes M and E, there is no overdetermination in the
explanation for E.
#### Parallelism
Psycho-physical parallelism is a very unusual view about the interaction
between mental and physical events which was most prominently, and
perhaps only truly, advocated by Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz. Like
Malebranche and others before him, Leibniz recognized the weaknesses of
Descartes\' account of causal interaction taking place in a physical
location in the brain. Malebranche decided that such a material basis of
interaction between material and immaterial was impossible and therefore
formulated his doctrine of occasionalism, stating that the interactions
were really caused by the intervention of God on each individual
occasion. Leibniz idea is that God has created a pre-established harmony
such that it only seems as if physical and mental events cause, and are
caused by, one another. In reality, mental causes only have mental
effects and physical causes only have physical effects. Hence the term
parallelism is used to describe this view.
#### Occasionalism
Occasionalism argues that bodily events are the occasion of an act by
the Creator causing a corresponding mental event, and vice versa. Any
such view requires a theological structure as a premise.
#### Further reading
- Robinson, Howard, \"Dualism\", The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Fall 2003 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2003/entries/dualism/>
- Robinson, H. (2003) \"Dualism\", in S. Stich and T. Warfield (eds)
The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell, Oxford,
85-101.
- Amoroso, R.L. (2010) \"The complementarity of Mind and Body:
Realizing the Dream of Descartes, Einstein and Eccles\", New York:
Nova Science Publishers,
`, ``https://www.novapublishers.com/catalog/product_info.php?products_id=12759`
## Idealism
According to Idealism only the mental truly exists.
The form and content of personal conscious experience might be related
to the structure of the world and brain in several ways. It could be a
**solipsism** or be the mind of God.
*This is a **stub** and needs expansion*.
## Panpsychism
### Etymology
Ancient Greek *pan* (πᾶν : \"all, everything, whole\") and *psyche*
(ψυχή : \"soul, mind\").[^1] Psyche is the from
ψύχω (*psukhō*, \"I blow\") and means mind or \'life-breath\'.
Philip Goff, a proponent of panpsychism, carves out a distinction
between panexperientialism and pancognitivism. Panexperientialism is the
belief that *experience* is ubiquitous, while pancognitivism is the
belief that *cognition* is ubiquitous. Most modern purponents of
panpsychism, such as Annaka Harris and David Chalmers, are careful to
distance themselves from pancognitivism.
In some interpretations, such as monadism, Panpsychism and Idealism can
overlap because the universe is conceived as being composed of an
infinity of point consciousnesses that each contain information about
the whole universe.
The form and content of personal conscious experience might be related
to the structure of the world and brain in many ways.
*This is a **stub** and needs expansion*.
## References
Seager W. & Allen-Hermanson (2001). 'Panpsychism.' Online document:
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, \[online\],
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/panpsychism/>, \[accessed 10/2005\]
**Supervenience**
- Chalmers, D.J. (1996). The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press.
**The problem of regression**
- Ryle, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind. The University of Chicago
Press, 1949.
**The homunculus argument**
- Gregory, R.L. (1990) Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing, Oxford
University Press Inc. New York.
- Gregory, T.L. (1987). The Oxford Companion to Mind. Oxford
University Press.
**Subject-object paradox**
- James, W. (1904)Does \'Consciousness\' Exist? Journal of
Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1,
477-491.
- Hegel, G.W.F. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND: SECTION I. MIND SUBJECTIVE B.
PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND CONSCIOUSNESS Part Three of the Encyclopaedia
of the Philosophical
Sciences
- Velmans, M. (1996) Consciousness and the \"Casual Paradox\".
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 19 (3):
538-542.
- Bermudez, J.L. (1999) The Paradox of Self-Consciousness
(representation and Mind) Psycoloquy:
10,#35
**Ontological status**
- Bierman, D.J. (2004) Non Conscious Processes Preceding Intuitive
decisions
<http://m0134.fmg.uva.nl/~djb/publications/2004/Intuition_bialsymp2004.pdf>
- Damasio, A.R. (1994). Descartes\' error: Emotion, reason and the
human brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam Book.
- Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason
<http://www.arts.cuhk.edu.hk/Philosophy/Kant/cpr/>
**Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness**
Block, N. (1995) On a confusion about a function of consciousness.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 227-287.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/documents/a/00/00/04/31/bbs00000431-00/bbs.block.html>
Block, N. (2004). *The Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science*.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/ecs.pdf>
Dennett, D. (1978). Why You Can\'t Make a Computer that Feels Pain, in:
Brainstorms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 190-229.
Dennett, D. (1988). Quining Qualia. in A. Marcel and E. Bisiach, eds,
Consciousness in Modern Science, Oxford University Press 1988. Reprinted
in W. Lycan, ed., Mind and Cognition: A Reader, MIT Press, 1990, A.
Goldman, ed. Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science, MIT Press,
1993. <http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/quinqual.htm>
Edelman, G.M. (1993). Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the
Mind. New York:
Feyerabend, P. (1963). Mental Events and the Brain, Journal of
Philosophy 40:295-6.
Huxley, T. H. (1874). On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and
its History, The Fortnightly Review, n.s.16:555-580. Reprinted in Method
and Results: Essays by Thomas H. Huxley (New York: D. Appleton and
Company, 1898).
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review
LXXXIII, 4 (October 1974): 435-50.
<http://web.archive.org/19990218140703/members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html>
Rey, Georges, (1997). Contemporary Philosophy of Mind.Blackwell: Oxford
Sellars W. (1956). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, In: Feigl H
and Scriven M (eds) The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of
Psychology and Psychoanalysis: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of
Science, Vol. 1. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 253-329
Whitehead, A.N. (1920). The Concept of Nature. Chapter 3: Time.
<http://spartan.ac.brocku.ca/~lward/Whitehead/Whitehead_1920/White1_03.html>
**Direct Realism**
- Austin, J.L. (1962) Sense and Sensibilia, ed. by Geoffrey J. Warnock
(Oxford, 1962)
- Aydede, M. (2001) Naturalism, introspection, and direct realism
about pain. Consciousness and Emotion, Vol. 2, No. 1, 2001,
pp. 29--73.
<http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/maydede/pain.pdf>
- Chapman, C.R., and Y. Nakamura (1999). A Passion of the Soul: An
Introduction to Pain for Consciousness Researchers. Consciousness
and Cognition, 8: 391-422.
- Dennett, D. (1991a). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown
- Dennett, D. (1991b). Lovely and suspect qualities. Commentary on
David Rosenthal, \"The Independence of Consciousness and Sensory
Quality\" in E. Villanueva, ed., Consciousness, (SOFIA Conference,
Buenos Aires), Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview 1991.
<http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/lovely&s.htm>
- Fowler C A (1986): "An event approach to the study of speech
perception from a direct-realist perspective", J of Phonetics
14(1):3-28.
- Gibson, J. J. (1966) The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems.
Houghton Mifflin Company,Boston.
- Gibson, J. J. (1979) Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Hillsdate.
- Gregory, R.L. 1988. Consciousness in science and philosophy:
conscience and con-science. Chapter 12 in Consciousness in
Contemporary Science. (Editors: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E.).
Oxford Science Publications.
- Le Morvan, Pierre (2004). Arguments against direct realism and how
to counter them. *The American Philosophical Quarterly*, *41*(3),
221-234.\] (pdf) <http://www.tcnj.edu/~lemorvan/DR_web.pdf>
- Michaels, C. F. and Carello, C. (1981). Direct Perception. Century
Psychology Series. Prentice-Hall.
. 1981. Download this book at
<http://ione.psy.uconn.edu/~psy254/MC.pdf>
- Oliveira, André L. G. and Oliveira, Luis F. (2002) Toward an
ecological conception of timbre. In Proceedings Auditory Perception
Cognition and Action Meeting 2002, Kansas City.
<http://cogprints.org/2713/>
- Skinner, B. F. Science and Human Behavior . New York: Macmillan,
1953.
- Skinner, B. F. 1971. Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New York: Knopf.
- Skinner, B. F. 1948. Walden Two. New York: Macmillan.
- Tye, M. (2004). ANOTHER LOOK AT REPRESENTATIONALISM ABOUT PAIN.
Consciousness and Emotion 2004, special issue on pain, edited by
Murat Aydede (with replies by M. Aydede, N. Block, B. Maund, and P.
Noordhof
<http://sun.soci.niu.edu/~phildept/MT/RepresentationalismAndPain.pdf>
- Vygotsky, L.S.(1925) Consciousness as a problem in the psychology of
behavior. Undiscovered Vygotsky: Etudes on the pre-history of
cultural-historical psychology (European Studies in the History of
Science and Ideas. Vol. 8), pp. 251--281. Peter Lang Publishing.
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/1925/consciousness.htm>
- Ziff, Paul. \"About Behaviourism.\" Analysis 18 (1958): 132-136.
Quoted by Larry Hauser in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/b/behavior.htm#B>. F. Skinner:
Radical Behaviorism
**Indirect Realism**
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
- Rizzo, M., Nawrot, M. & Zihl, J. (1995). Motion and shape perception
in cerebral akinetopsia.Brain, 118. 1105-1127.
<http://nawrot.psych.ndsu.nodak.edu/Publications/Nawrot.pdf/RizzoNawrotZihl.1995.pdf>
- Russell, B. (1912). Problems of Philosophy. Home University Library.
<http://www.ditext.com/russell/rus1.html>
- Tye, M. (2003) Qualia. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia/#Repqualia>
Further reading:
- Hume, D. (1739). A Treatise of Human Nature.
<http://www.class.uidaho.edu/mickelsen/ToC/hume%20treatise%20ToC.htm>
- Firth, R. (1949) Sense Data and the Percept Theory, Mind, 58 (1949);
59 (1950). (Describes early reasons for rejecting Indirect Realism)
<http://www.ditext.com/firth/spt.html>
- Grush, R. (2000). Self, world and space: The meaning and mechanisms
of ego- and allocentric spatial representation. Brain and Mind
1(1):59-92.
<http://mind.ucsd.edu/papers/sws/sws.html>
[^1]: Clarke, D.S. *Panpsychism: Past and Recent Selected Readings*.
State University of New York Press, 2004. p.1
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Conflict2#Idealism
*This part of this section is about the where and when of the experience
called consciousness. Is it in the world, in the brain or are the world
and brain within it?*
## Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness
Block(1995) drew attention to the way that there appear to be two types
of consciousness: *phenomenal* consciousness and *access* consciousness:
`Phenomenal consciousness is experience; the phenomenally`\
`conscious aspect of a state is what it is like to be in that`\
`state. The mark of access-consciousness, by contrast, is `\
`availability for use in reasoning and rationally guiding speech `\
`and action. (Block 1995).`
*See the section on Ned Block\'s
ideas
for a deeper coverage of his approach to access and phenomenal
consciousness.*
Block uses Nagel\'s famous (1974) paper, \"What is it like to be a
bat?\" as an exemplary description of phenomenal consciousness.
Excellent descriptions have also been proffered by the empiricist
philosophers who gave lengthy descriptions of consciousness as partly
experience itself. Although Block has formalised the idea of phenomenal
and access consciousness similar ideas have also been put forward by
many philosophers including Kant and Whitehead.
Access consciousness has two interpretations, in the first, used by
Block, it applies to the functions that appear to operate on phenomenal
consciousness. In the second, used by the behaviourists and
eliminativists, it is some property of the functions of the brain that
can be called \'consciousness\'.
This division between phenomenal and functional aspects of consciousness
is useful because it emphasises the idea of phenomenal consciousness as
observation rather than action. Some philosophers such as Huxley in
1874, have taken the view that because phenomenal consciousness appears
to have no function it is of no importance or cannot exist. James (1879)
introduced the term \"epiphenomenalism\" to summarise the idea that
consciousness has no function.
The idea that phenomenal consciousness cannot exist is a type of
*Eliminativism* (also known as Eliminative Materialism). Eliminativism
owes much to the work of Sellars(1956) and Feyerbend (1963). Dennett
(1978) applied Eliminativism to phenomenal consciousness and denies that
pain is real. Others such as Rey(1997) have also applied eliminativism
to phenomenal consciousness.
Dennett (1988) redefines consciousness in terms of access consciousness
alone, he argues that \"Everything real has properties, and since I
don\'t deny the reality of conscious experience, I grant that conscious
experience has properties\". Having related all consciousness to
properties he then declares that these properties are actually
judgements of properties. He considers judgements of the properties of
consciousness to be identical to the properties themselves. He writes:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"The infallibilist line on qualia treats
them as properties of one\'s experience one cannot in principle
misdiscover, and this is a mysterious doctrine (at least as mysterious
as papal infallibility) unless we shift the emphasis a little and treat
qualia as logical constructs out of subjects\' qualia-judgments: a
subject\'s experience has the quale F if and only if the subject judges
his experience to have quale F. \"`</font>`{=html}
Having identified \"properties\" with \"judgement of properties\" he can
then show that the judgements are insubstantial, hence the properties
are insubstantial and hence the qualia are insubstantial or even
non-existent. Dennett concludes that qualia can be rejected as
non-existent:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"So when we look one last time at our
original characterization of qualia, as ineffable, intrinsic, private,
directly apprehensible properties of experience, we find that there is
nothing to fill the bill. In their place are relatively or practically
ineffable public properties we can refer to indirectly via reference to
our private property-detectors\-- private only in the sense of
idiosyncratic. And insofar as we wish to cling to our subjective
authority about the occurrence within us of states of certain types or
with certain properties, we can have some authority\--not infallibility
or incorrigibility, but something better than sheer guessing\--but only
if we restrict ourselves to relational, extrinsic properties like the
power of certain internal states of ours to provoke acts of apparent re-
identification. So contrary to what seems obvious at first blush, there
simply are no qualia at all. \" (Dennett 1988)`</font>`{=html}
Dennett\'s asserts that \"a subject\'s experience has the quale F if and
only if the subject judges his experience to have quale F\". This is a
statement of the belief that qualia are the same as processes such as
judgements. Processes such as judgements are flows of data where one
state examines a previous state in a succession over time and embody
what Whitehead called the \"materialist\" concept of time. Dennett does
not consider how a scientific concept of time might affect his argument.
Dennett\'s argument has been persuasive and there are now many
philosophers and neuroscientists who believe that the problem of
phenomenal consciousness does not exist. This means that, to them, what
we call \'consciousness\' can only be a property of the functions
performed by the brain and body. According to these philosophers only
access consciousness exists.
Those who support the idea of phenomenal consciousness also tend to
frame it in terms of nineteenth century theory where one state examines
a previous state in a succession over time, for instance Edelman(1993)
places the past in memories at an instant and time within experience is
explained as continuing modelling processes:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"Primary consciousness is the state of
being mentally aware of things in the world\--of having mental images in
the present. But it is not accompanied by any sense of a person with a
past and a future\.... In contrast, higher-order consciousness involves
the recognition by a thinking subject of his or her own acts or
affections. It embodies a model of the personal, and of the past and the
future as well as the present. It exhibits direct awareness\--the
noninferential or immediate awareness of mental episodes without the
involvement of sense organs or receptors. It is what we humans have in
addition to primary consciousness. We are conscious of being
conscious.\" `</font>`{=html}
Block(2004) also suggests this flow from state to state in his idea of
\"Reflexivity\" where our idea of familiarity with an object is due to
one state being analysed by another:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"Thus in the "conscious" case, the subject
must have a state that is about the subject's own perceptual experience
(looking familiar) and thus conscious in what might be termed a
"reflexive" sense. An experience is conscious in this sense just in case
it is the object of another of the subject's states; for example, one
has a thought to the effect that one has that experience. The reflexive
sense of \'consciousness\' contrasts with phenomenality, which perhaps
attaches to some states which are not the objects of other mental
states. Reflexive consciousness might better be called 'awareness' than
'consciousness'. Reflexivity is phenomenality plus something else
(reflection) and that opens up the possibility in principle for
phenomenality without reflection. For example, it is at least
conceptually possible for there to be two people in pain, one of whom is
introspecting the pain the other not. (Perhaps infants or animals can
have pain but don't introspect it.) The first is reflexively conscious
of the pain, but both have phenomenally conscious states, since pain is
by its very nature a phenomenally conscious state. \"`</font>`{=html}
Both Block and Edelman allow phenomenal consciousness, our experience,
as an unexplained phenomenon. Block, Edelman and also Dennett\'s ideas
of consciousness are shown in the illustration below:
![](Constudphen.gif "Constudphen.gif")
This model differs from the empirical reports of phenomenal
consciousness that were considered earlier. According to the empirical
reports the present moment in our experience is extended so the
succession of outputs or stages of access consciousness could constitute
the contents of phenomenal consciousness. In other words phenomenal
consciousness is composed of periods of access consciousness. This is
how it seems to the empiricist and in our own experience but how such a
state could be explained in terms of brain activity is highly
problematical. Given that nineteenth century ideas cannot explain such a
state a scientific explanation will be required.
The idea that phenomenal consciousness misrepresents or \"misdiscovers\"
itself (Dennett 1988) deserves further discussion. According to
materialism the present instant has no duration so can only be known in
succeeding instants as a report or memory and this could be wrong.
Whitehead considered that this viewpoint originates in an archaic view
of science, particularly the concept of time in science:
\"The eighteenth and nineteenth centuries accepted as their natural
philosophy a certain circle of concepts which were as rigid and definite
as those of the philosophy of the middle ages, and were accepted with as
little critical research. I will call this natural philosophy
\'materialism.\' Not only were men of science materialists, but also
adherents of all schools of philosophy. The idealists only differed from
the philosophic materialists on question of the alignment of nature in
reference to mind. But no one had any doubt that the philosophy of
nature considered in itself was of the type which I have called
materialism. It is the philosophy which I have already examined in my
two lectures of this course preceding the present one. It can be
summarised as the belief that nature is an aggregate of material and
that this material exists in some sense at each successive member of a
one-dimensional series of extensionless instants of time. Furthermore
the mutual relations of the material entities at each instant formed
these entities into a spatial configuration in an unbounded space. It
would seem that space\-\--on this theory-would be as instantaneous as
the instants, and that some explanation is required of the relations
between the successive instantaneous spaces. The materialistic theory is
however silent on this point; and the succession of instantaneous spaces
is tacitly combined into one persistent space. This theory is a purely
intellectual rendering of experience which has had the luck to get
itself formulated at the dawn of scientific thought. It has dominated
the language and the imagination of science since science flourished in
Alexandria, with the result that it is now hardly possible to speak
without appearing to assume its immediate obviousness.\" (Whitehead
1920).
## Direct Realism and Direct Perception
Direct Realism proposes that phenomenal experience is directly objects
in the world without any intervening representation. It is motivated by
the belief that the Problem of Regression, the Subject-Object Paradox
and the recursion form of the Homunculus arguments show that phenomenal
consciousness cannot occur in the brain alone. Direct Realists reason
that if phenomenal consciousness cannot be things in the brain then it
must be something outside the brain.
There are two principle types of Direct Realism: Natural Dualism and
Behaviourism (both Radical and Analytical). Some behaviourists use the
term "Direct Perception" rather than Direct Realism and consider that
only the invariant parts of perception are direct (see for instance
Michaels and Carello 1981). Thomas Reid is generally regarded as the
founder of Direct Realism. In his Natural Dualism he proposed that the
soul is in direct contact with the contents of experience and these
contents are things in the world beyond the body. The Direct Realism of
Reid is summarised in the statement of his famous disciple Sir William
Hamilton: \"In the simplest act of perception I am conscious of myself
as the perceiving subject and of an external reality as the object
perceived\". Reid\'s Natural Dualism has now been largely replaced by
radical and analytical behaviourism which eschew the idea of a soul and
propose that phenomenal consciousness, if it exists at all, is a
behavioural reflex.
The modern justification of Direct Realism mainly consists of arguments
against Indirect Realism or Representationalism. Philosophers such as
Austin (1962) and Le Morvan (2004) have summarised the Direct Realism
debate and have identified the following arguments in favour of Indirect
Realism and given rebuttals to each of them:
1\. The Causal Argument: perception involves a succession of causal
events such as the reflection of photons, bleaching of retinal pigments
etc. so perception must involve the end of this causal chain. The Direct
Realist response is that, although there may be a causal chain in
sensation this does not inevitably imply that the end of the chain is
the content of phenomenal experience.
2\. The Time Lag Argument: it takes time for light to travel from an
object to the senses, time for chemical changes in the retina etc\...
The Direct Realist response is that direct perception may be referred
back in time.
3\. The Partial Character of Perception Argument: we only perceive the
surface of objects, and then only a part of the surface. As the whole
object would be perceived directly perception must be indirect. The
Direct Realist response is that direct perception could occur even if
only parts of an object were perceived.
4\. The Perceptual Relativity Argument: things appear to be different
shapes depending upon the point of view. The Direct Realist response is
that if perception can occur backwards in time it should have no problem
occurring back down a line of sight. However, Le Morvan\'s argument does
not seem to encompass the geometrical nature of phenomenal experience,
seeking to explain geometry in terms of movement.
5\. The Argument from Perceptual Illusion: A stick may appear bent when
projecting from the surface of water. Direct Realists apply the argument
used in (4) to this problem. The bent stick illusion is a physical event
in the world beyond the eye rather than a normal optical illusion such
as the Muller-Lyer illusion etc., see (6) for a discussion of optical
illusions.
6\. The Argument from Hallucination: Hallucinations are not in the world
beyond the body. This is highly problematical for Direct Realists
especially when phenomena such as lucid dreams, dreams and visual
imaginations are included along with hallucinations. Direct Realists
classify these phenomena as not being perceptions or deny that they
actually exist as phenomena. Indirect Realists would maintain that all
of perception is a reconstruction and use optical illusions such as the
Muller-Lyer, Ames Room etc. to justify this contention so the Direct
Realist approach to hallucination, dreams etc. might seem like an
unwillingness to accept Indirect Realism rather than an argument.
7\. The Dubitability Argument (cf: Indubitability argument): we cannot
doubt current phenomenal experience but we can doubt the world beyond
the body therefore phenomenal experience is not the world beyond the
body. Direct Realists fall back on Presentism or functional Presentism
to defeat this argument. If phenomenal experience is instantaneous and
made anew at each instant then anything can be doubted.
The points above have summarised the Direct Realist stance on visual
perception. Other sensory modalities have also been considered in the
Direct Realism debate.
Fowler (1986) considered that sounds were attached to objects in the
world. This idea is strange because sounds only seem to be closely
attached to objects in the world when these objects are seen as well as
heard. For example, when a subject is blindfolded it is found that there
can be a large error in locating the position of a sound in the world,
this is especially true for low frequency sounds. The Direct Realist
approach has difficulty explaining the transition from sounds with an
indefinite location when a subject is blindfolded to sounds that are
bound to visual events when the blindfold is removed. It also runs into
problems explaining how the sound of speech from a single loudspeaker
can become bound to lip movements on a cinema screen. If the binding
does not occur in the brain then where does it occur?
Pain is particularly problematic for Direct Realism because, unlike
colour vision where \'red\' is inferred to be a property of electrons or
light, pain is an inner experience that is not a property of tissue
damage. Tissue damage has properties such as bleeding, wheal formation
etc. but pain seems to be phenomenal experience in the brain and
\'phantom pain\' can occur without tissue damage (see Aydede (2001), Tye
(2004) and Chapman, and Nakamura (1999) for further analysis). On closer
inspection other sensations also appear to be inner experiences rather
than direct sensations. For instance, the red crosses of different hues
in the illustration below are all due to the same physical wavelengths
of light. In this case the range of hues in experience is unrelated to
the actual physical red on the page or screen.
Another problem for Direct Realism is that it does not overcome the
problems that it is supposed to solve. The argument for Direct Realism
begins with the idea that there are severe problems with
representationalism (the idea that phenomenal experience is in the
brain) and that direct perception is an alternative that does not have
these problems. However on closer inspection Direct Realism suffers from
almost same problems as representationalism. If phenomenal experience is
the world itself then Ryle\'s regress applies to the world itself and
this can only be avoided by assuming that phenomenal experience is a
subset of the world (i.e.: a representation) that receives input from
other parts of the world that are not part of phenomenal experience.
It is also commonly assumed that Direct Realism avoids the recursion
argument because it is believed that the separation of the observer from
the things that are observed is simply due to the geometry of the world.
If such simple geometry is possible between the eye and the world then
it should also be possible in the brain and a similar geometrical
explanation could be invoked to avoid recursion in representations.
These points are shown in the illustration below:
image:Constuddir1.gif
Scientists have a further problem with Direct Realism. The illustration
below demonstrates that our scientific knowledge of the world differs
markedly from our phenomenal experience.
image:constuddirect.gif
It is difficult to see how the form and content of phenomenal experience
could supervene directly on the world beyond the body. The world
inferred from measurements beyond the body seems to be a nebulous set of
quantum phenomena that are arranged as probability fields in three
dimensions at any instant. The objects in this real world are mostly
space. The world of phenomenal experience on the other hand contains
objects that are one-sided, and are like a 2 dimensional field of
vectors directed simultaneously at an observation point which is
apparently separate from them. Phenomenal experience is not three
dimensional, the rear of objects is not available within it at any
instant. Visual phenomenal experience seems to be a geometrical
relationship between an abstract observation point and the reflection
properties of the part of the world external to the body. It is a form
that crudely overlies the angular separations in inferred reality,
providing approximate directional data. It is not like things in
themselves beyond the body, not even in type, being a set of directional
vectors. (See the module on the neuroscience of perception for a
discussion of depth perception).
If the form and content of visual phenomenal experience are abstractions
separated according to the angular positions of things in the world
beyond the body then theories which propose that phenomenal experience
is the world itself are problematical. It should be noted that things
arranged according to angular positions can appear to overlie any group
of similar things along a radius from the centre point.
![](Constuddirectangle.gif "Constuddirectangle.gif")
If Direct Realists admit that things are as they appear to be, observed
according to angular positions at a \'point eye\', then any
representation of things on the inside of a sphere of any radius would
appear similar. The geometry of the \'point eye\' is problematical
whether the view contains the world itself or a representation of the
world; it cannot be the movements of lumps of matter or energy and the
point observation cannot be due to lumps all landing at a point. In
other words the \'view\' is inconsistent with nineteenth century
materialism and will require a scientific explanation.
Radical and Analytical Behaviourism tackle the problem of the difference
between the world inferred from measurements beyond the body and the
phenomenal world by denying phenomenal consciousness and maintaining
that access and reflex consciousness are all that exists or is
necessary. Radical Behaviourism is an offshoot of psychological
behaviourism and was established as a philosophical adjunct to Marxism
by Vygotsky and popularised by Burrhus Frederic Skinner (see Skinner
1953). There is another movement in psychological behaviourism which is
similar to Radical Behaviourism called Ecological Psychology (see Gibson
1966, 1979 and also Michaels and Carello 1981). Analytical Behaviourism
is a philosophical movement established by Gilbert Ryle (see Ryle 1949).
The core of Analytical and Radical Behaviourism is the assumption that
consciousness exists for a durationless instant so that the Dubitability
Argument and the Regression and Recursion Arguments can be applied (Ryle
1949, Skinner 1971 and see the sections on Ryle\'s Regress and the
Subject-Object Paradox above). As a result the Direct Realist is able to
insinuate that subjects only think that they have had a particular
experience (cf: Dennett 1991a). It is intriguing that Eliminativists
also maintain that experience is the world itself, for instance an
insight into Dennett\'s idea of the mind is to be found on pages 407-408
of Consciousness Explained:
\"It seemed to him, according to the text, as if his mind - his visual
field - were filled with intricate details of gold-green buds an
wiggling branches, but although this is how it seemed this was an
illusion. No such \"plenum\" ever came into his mind; the plenum
remained out in the world where it is didn\'t have to be represented,
but could just be. When we marvel, in those moments of heightened
self-consciousness, at the glorious richness of our conscious
experience, the richness we marvel at is actually the richness of the
world outside, in all its ravishing detail. It does not \"enter\" our
conscious minds, but is simply available\"
This is a clear description of Direct Realism (although Dennett does not
describe himself as a direct realist).
Radical Behaviourism is sometimes described as the dictum that the only
psychological events that are of importance are those that occur outside
the head. The absurdity of this has led to jokes:
Q: What does one behaviorist say to another when they meet on the
street?
A: You\'re fine. How am I?
Q: What does one behaviorist say to another after sex?
A: That was great for you. How was it for me?
(Ziff 1958)
However Vygotsky, Skinner and other Radical Behaviourists hold that
inner behaviour is possible so that events within the brain can result
in reward or punishment. Vygotsky (1925) describes this approach:
\"Consciousness is wholly reduced to the transmitting mechanisms of
reflexes operating according to general laws, i.e., no processes other
than reactions can be admitted into the organism. The way is also paved
for the solution of the problem of self-awareness and self-observation.
Inner perception and introspection are possible only thanks to the
existence of a proprioceptive field and secondary reflexes, which are
connected with it. This is always the echo of a reaction.\"
Hence Radical Behaviourists are able to make the claim that what are
believed to be representations with phenomenal content are processes.
Even events such as pain can then be explained as reflexes involving
organs within the skin. However, by opening the possibility that such
reflexes could occur at any sense organ, including the eye, this makes
Radical Behaviourism a mixed Direct Realist/Indirect Realist philosophy
with consciousness as a process, not a separate thing such as phenomenal
consciousness (see the section on representationalism and intentionality
below).
But this raises a serious issue for science: can the phenomenal
consciousness that seems to contain our observations really be argued
out of existence on the basis of a theory? As Gregory (1988) put it: "
'If you can't explain it -- deny it' is one strategy for dealing with
embarrassing questions such as 'what is consciousness?' ". But is this
the right strategy?
Direct Realism fails to overcome the problems of regression and
recursion inherent in representations. It proposes that phenomenal
consciousness is identical to the physical world beyond the body but
must then use a plethora of arguments to explain why this is evidently
not so. When confronted with these problems its proponents resort to the
argument that everything can be doubted and can misrepresent itself. Yet
it is still widely believed.
It should be noted that Direct Realism is espoused in Religious Natural
Dualism, some forms of Augustinian theology, nineteenth century
materialism and its offspring such as Marxism, post-modernism,
post-Marxism, and various sociological movements. It is also necessary
for some forms of Strong AI to occur. Perhaps this explains why few
ideas have attracted as much attention and defence as Direct Realism.
It is interesting to compare the Direct Realist and Indirect Realist
interpretations of something as simple as a cartoon on television (such
as the image below). According to Indirect Realism the cartoon would be
a moving representation constructed in the brain using data from the
senses. This leads to the prediction of brain mechanisms for modelling
motions, combining colours, binding sound and vision etc., many of which
have been verified. Can you demonstrate how the theory of Direct Realism
could explain the phenomenal experience that contains the cartoon and
produce a list of the predictions made by the theory?
![](constudcartoon.gif "constudcartoon.gif")
In science a theory should be of predictive value, for instance,
information theory describes how the state of a thing can be impressed
on a carrier so that a signal can be transmitted from one place to
another. This theory predicts what will happen when the signal arrives
at its destination and how the state of the source can be inferred from
the events at the destination, the total amount of information that can
be transmitted etc. At the destination it is the form of the signal that
is directly known by interaction and measurement, the form of the source
is inferred. Direct Realism is a direct challenge to this information
theory but does it deliver a more powerful predictive description of
phenomenal consciousness or is experience always dependent on what
happens to the information flow between things in the world and
somewhere in the brain? Does direct realism have a physical theory?
Ultimately it appears as if Direct Realism is about various
understandings of Information Theory. For example, Austin (1962)
discusses what we see when we see a church camouflaged as a barn and
comments that: \"We see, of course, a church that now looks like a
barn.\". Do we see a church or a barn? Scientific information theory is
clear about this, the church is an entity composed of selected
information from the quantum state of its constituents, the optical
image of a camouflaged church is an arrangement of photons emanating
from a screen on which it is projected, the retina has an arrangement of
chemical and electrical events based on an optical image and conscious
visual experience correlates with the arrangement of things on the
retina. The fact that conscious experience also correlates with
classifications of the retinal image as a barn or a church suggests that
conscious experience is an arrangement of things in the brain based on
both the retinal arrangement and the contents of a relational database.
Austin\'s arguments have been mythologised as a final demonstration that
\"sense data\" theories are false. However, as will be seen below, sense
data theories merely claim that there is a succession of information
states between an information state outside the body and that reported
as conscious experience i.e.: subjects report that a church is
camouflaged when it is camouflaged.
## Indirect Realism
Indirect realism proposes that phenomenal consciousness exists and is a
set of signals or **sense data**, usually in the brain. This was
proposed by philosophers from Aristotle to Locke and was probably the
most widespread idea of conscious experience until the eighteenth
century.
The idea of sense data is discussed in depth by Russell (1912).
Russell\'s original definition is given below:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Let us give the name of
\'sense-data\' to the things that are immediately known in sensation:
such things as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and so
on. We shall give the name \'sensation\' to the experience of being
immediately aware of these things. Thus, whenever we see a colour, we
have a sensation of the colour, but the colour itself is a sense-datum,
not a sensation. The colour is that of which we are immediately aware,
and the awareness itself is the sensation. It is plain that if we are to
know anything about the table, it must be by means of the sense-data \--
brown colour, oblong shape, smoothness, etc. \-- which we associate with
the table; but, for the reasons which have been given, we cannot say
that the table is the sense-data, or even that the sense-data are
directly properties of the table.\"`</font>`{=html}
Russell\'s definition is a materialist concept in which experience is
always **of** something because the durationless instant of the present
has always gone. As such it differs from some empiricist ideas where
experience is not confined to the durationless instant.
Science is Indirect Realist because it holds that the scientist can only
make **measurements** of events in the world. These measurements give
rise to signals as a result of interaction with the event. According to
**decoherence theory** the signals are a state that is a mixture of the
state of the measuring instrument and the state of the thing being
measured. For example, the eyes are measuring instruments that are
sensitive to photons, photons are signals containing a state that is
based on the state of electrons in a surface and the state of electrons
is based on the state of the surface etc. Scientific inference allows
some aspects of the state of the surface to be inferred from the state
of the photons.
In modern Indirect Realism there is an attempt to distinguish the
phenomenal content of conscious experience from the processing involved
in accessing this phenomenal content. According to these theories
phenomenal experience is an arrangement of signals that are the content
of the experience. This arrangement forms a *representation* of things
in the world so this form of indirect realism is known as
**Representationalism**. Tye (2003) describes types of
representationalist theory:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Representationalism, as I have
presented it so far, is an identity thesis with respect to qualia:
qualia are supposedly one and the same as certain representational
contents.\"`</font>`{=html}
Tye also describes variants of this idea of representationalism:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Sometimes it is held instead
that qualia are one and the same as certain representational properties
of experiences; and sometimes it is is argued that these
representational properties are themselves irreducible (Siewert 1998).
There is also a weaker version of representationalism, according to
which it is metaphysically necessary that experiences exactly alike with
respect to their representational contents are exactly alike with
respect to their qualia. Obviously, this supervenience thesis leaves
open the further question as to the essential nature of
qualia.\"`</font>`{=html} (Tye 2003).
In a scientific sense Direct Realists believe that phenomenal experience
is the signals that occur next to things in the world beyond the body
(which they call \"things in themselves\") and Indirect Realists usually
believe that phenomenal experience is signals in the brain. It can be
seen from the pattern of signal flow that the signals travelling into
the brain preserve the spatial relationships of the original signals and
encode the properties in the original signals. This means that the
original signals next to the QM sources and the signals in the brain are
equivalent provided the latter are oriented appropriately relative to
signals from the body. Either set of signals could transmit or contain
the same information. Both Direct and Indirect Realism cannot, at
present, explain the physics of how a viewing point occurs in experience
i.e.: how we seem to see through an apparent space to the signals that
are the contents of experience. So the choice between Direct Realism and
Indirect Realism reduces to whether there is only one set of signals or
a chain of signals between the world and phenomenal experience.
The philosophical arguments for Indirect Realism are listed below:
1\. Variable perspective: when we see things the view changes so what we
see must be a different set of signals depending on the view rather than
a constant object.
2\. Illusions: we can see through fingers and see a variety of colours
where measurements tell us one exists. Direct Realists quote the \"bent
stick illusion\", which is not really an illusion at all, being a
physical event.
3\. Hallucinations: two people can have phenomenal experience containing
a table. The first may be viewing a real table whereas the second may be
hallucinating a table. If the tables are the same (phenomenally) then
experience is indirect.
4\. Double vision: press the side of one eye, two images appear (cf Hume
1739) yet there are not two things in the world.
5\. Time gap arguments: according to materialism the past has gone. The
things being seen no longer exist in the state that relates to the state
in experience. In the extreme case, some stars in the night sky no
longer exist but are still in experience so experience must be a derived
signal.
6\. Secondary qualities such as pain, colour and smell do not exist as
physical things in the source of signals and are likely to be properties
of signals in the brain.
![](constudindirect.gif "constudindirect.gif")
Indirect Realism has received strong support from recent discoveries in
neuroscience, for example, it is now clear that both the colour and
motion in phenomenal experience are added by cortical processes. In
Cerebral **Achromatopsia** patients have suffered trauma to area V4 of
the cerebral cortex and report seeing the world in greyscale with no
colour vision and in Congenital Achromatopsia people do not even
understand the meaning of \'colour\'. In an astonishing ailment called
**Akinetopsia** patients perceive movement as a succession of stationary
images (Rizzo *et al.* 1995). Akinetopsia is usually associated with
damage to cortical area V5. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) have demonstrated
that the addition of colour occurs more rapidly than the addition of
motion. The section on the Neuroscience of Consciousness describes these
discoveries and many other aspects of the creation of phenomenal
experience in the brain.
Unfortunately knowledge of the whereabouts of the signals that are the
content of conscious experience does not resolve the problem of
phenomenal consciousness. Whether these signals are next to objects in
the world or at the end of a chain of signals in the brain there still
remains the problem of how they become arranged in the form of
experience. If such a thing occurs at all.
### Intentionality and representation
There is a materialist interpretation of representationalism in which
representations are redefined as intentional states:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"One way of explaining what is
meant by 'intentionality' in the (more obscure) philosophical sense is
this: it is that aspect of mental states or events that consists in
their being of or about things (as pertains to the questions, 'What are
you thinking of?' and 'What are you thinking about?'). Intentionality is
the aboutness or directedness of mind (or states of mind) to things,
objects, states of affairs, events. So if you are thinking about San
Francisco, or about the increased cost of living there, or about your
meeting someone there at Union Square---your mind, your thinking, is
directed toward San Francisco, or the increased cost of living, or the
meeting in Union Square. To think at all is to think of or about
something in this sense. This 'directedness' conception of
intentionality plays a prominent role in the influential philosophical
writings of Franz Brentano and those whose views developed in response
to his (to be discussed further in Section 3).\"(Siewert
2003)`</font>`{=html}
This definition allows \"representation\" to be redefined as a data
stream rather than a set of things arranged in some mental or neural
state that represents things in space. Husserl thought this approach
would allow a description of consciousness that \"carefully abstains
from affirming the existence of anything in spatio-temporal reality\"
(Siewert 2003) although it could be argued that a data stream such as
any description can never escape the constraints of representation in
time at some place.
Unfortunately the concept of \"intentionality\" has become so diverse
that it could be applied to almost any aspect of the description of
consciousness. An interesting example of this is given by Loar (2001)
where \"intentionality\" is considered to overlap \"representing\" and
\"conceiving\":
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"A person\'s thoughts represent
things to her \-- conceive things \-- in many ways: perceptually,
memory-wise, descriptively, by naming, by analogy, by intuitive sorting,
theoretically, abstractly, implicitly and explicitly. These various
manners of conceiving have something in common: they have intentional
properties, and they have them essentially. `</font>`{=html}
The usage of the term \"intentional state\" has become so broad that it
now means little more than a state that is about another state.
References
Siewert, C. (2003). Consciousness and Intentionality. The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-intentionality/>
Also see Loar, B. (2001) "Phenomenal Intentionality as the Basis of
Mental Content", in Reflections and Replies, ed. M. Hahn and B.
Ramsberg, MIT.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/courses/concepts/loar.html>
Williford, K. (2002) The intentionality of consciousness and the
consciousness of intentionality. Intentionality: Past and Future, edited
by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis, Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi.
<http://web.stcloudstate.edu/kwwilliford/Intentionality%20of%20Consciousness.pdf>
Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism Defended. Philosophical Review 110
(April 2001):199-240. <http://stripe.colorado.edu/~leeds/byrne.pdf>
### Cartesian materialism
The term \"Cartesian materialism\" once meant the idea that the mind is
in the brain (see for instance Block 1995). The term had largely fallen
out of use in philosophy until revived by Daniel Dennett (1991) in the
book *Consciousness Explained*. Dennett uses a very particular
definition of the term in his discussions and also uses a particular
definition of the word \"mind\". See the section on Daniel
Dennett
for Dennett\'s critique. Philosophers who adhere to the idea that the
mind is in the brain tend to call themselves \"indirect realists\" or
\"representationalists\" where the substrate of conscious experience is
in the brain and would deny that Dennett\'s critique applies to their
proposals. Dennett\'s critique makes the materialist assumption that if
there is a representation in the brain then a further flow of material
out of this representation would be required for the representation to
become part of mind.
### Identity theories of mind
The idea that mental states are brain states is known as the **identity
theory of mind**. There are two sorts of identity theory, in **type**
identity theory it is held that mental states are identical to brain
states whereas in **token** identity theory it is held that mental
states correlate with brain states.
Type identity theory was attacked by Putnam in \"The Nature of Mental
States\" where he pointed out that if mental states are functions then
type identity theory would presuppose that animals that had the same
mental states would need to have identical brain structures. He
suggested that this is unlikely, it being more probable that animals
have functional systems that perform similar overall functions but which
are not identical. In other words, if it is assumed that conscious
experience is a set of functions then token identity theory is more
probable than type identity theory.
Putnam\'s critique does not preclude identity theories of mind that
involve \"passive ideas\" (i.e.: states that are not classical
functions).
Most identity theories of mind would be representational, the physical
states representing the world in some way. All identity theories of mind
involve Cartesian materialism in the sense of the mental states being
brain states. According to identity theories the mind is in the brain.
Putnam, H. (1967) The nature of mental states. In The Nature of Mind,
edited by Rosenthal, pp. 197--203. Originally published as
\"Psychological predicates in Art, Mind, and Religion\", edited by
Capitan and Merill, pp. 37--48.
## Dualism
Prior to considering the arguments surrounding dualism it is important
to have a clear idea of \"information\" because many of these arguments
have parallels with the difference between information as a set of
states that can be transmitted and the substrate on which this
information is expressed or from which the information is derived. See
Elementary information and information systems
theory.
### Cartesian dualism
Descartes, a philosopher, analysed his experience and developed an
empirical description of how it is arranged. He described mental images
and perceptions as extended in space and with a duration. He called
these extended things **ideas** (Cartesian ideas) and proposed that they
are patterns in the brain. Descartes thought the pineal gland was the
most likely location for these ideas because it is one of the few single
organs in the brain. He also proposed that there is a rational soul that
directly contacts these ideas:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Now among these figures, it is
not those imprinted on the external sense organs, or on the internal
surface of the brain, which should be taken to be ideas - but only those
which are traced in the spirits on the surface of gland H *(where the
seat of the imagination and the \'common sense\' is located)*. That is
to say, it is only the latter figures which should be taken to be the
forms or images which the rational soul united to this machine will
consider directly when it imagines some object or perceives it by the
senses.\" Descartes (1664)`</font>`{=html}
See section on
Descartes
for more information and references.
Descartes considered that the soul was a physical point, an unextended
entity that acts like a mind\'s eye. He called this unextended place the
*res cogitans* and concluded that it was a substance that differed from
that of material things:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\".. I thence concluded that I was
a substance whose whole essence or nature consists only in thinking, and
which, that it may exist, has need of no place, nor is dependent on any
material thing; so that \" I,\" that is to say, the mind by which I am
what I am, is wholly distinct from the body, and is even more easily
known than the latter, and is such, that although the latter were not,
it would still continue to be all that it is.\"Descartes
(1637)`</font>`{=html}
This unextended substance that is not material gives the word
\"substance\" a new meaning. It has been attacked as a concept by Locke,
Hume, Berkely and many other philosophers. The concept of there being
two substances, that which composes the physical world and that which
composes the soul, is the origin of the word **Dualism** but dualism, as
a concept, has been extended beyond this original meaning. Cartesian
dualism is a type of **substance dualism**.
Cartesian dualism is an attempt to explain our experience. According to
Descartes something supernatural would be needed for an unextended
viewing point to exist.
Reid\'s **Natural Dualism** also has a point soul looking at things but
proposes that the things in question are forms in the world rather than
in the brain.
### Property dualism
Another sort of dualism has arisen out of a particular interpretation of
the regress and homunculus arguments. These arguments show that
phenomenal experience is not due entirely to flows from place to place
(i.e.: it is not due to classical processes and functions). Property
dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the appropriate way
(i.e. in the way that living human bodies are organized), mental
properties emerge.
As Goldman (1993) pointed out, qualitative experience does not seem to
be needed in a functional description of a system:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"For any functional description
of a system that is in pain (or has an itch), it seems as if we can
imagine another system with the same functional description but lacking
the qualitative property of painfulness (or itchiness).\"
`</font>`{=html}
Certainly a functional system that merely reports the words \"I am in
pain\" when it is dropped on the floor does not require any qualitative
property of painfulness. The *absent qualia* arguments suggest that even
in a large system there would be no need for qualitative properties for
the performance of any classical function.
Chalmers (1993) commenting on Goldman\'s point, said that this implies
that **zombies** might exist, functional replicas of humans but without
qualia. He then denied that a complete functional replica of a human
could exist without also including qualia:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"It seems to me that the only way
to avoid this conclusion is to deny that Zombie Dave is a conceptual
possibility; and the only principled way to deny that Zombie Dave is a
conceptual possibility is to allow that functional organization is
conceptually constitutive of qualitative content.\" Chalmers
(1993).`</font>`{=html}
In other words he identifies qualia with function. According to Chalmers
(1996) qualia are a particular type of function:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"I claim that conscious
experience arises from fine-grained functional organization. More
specifically, I will argue for a principle of organizational invariance,
holding that given any system that has conscious experiences, then any
system that has the same fine-grained functional organization will have
qualitatively identical experiences. According to this principle,
consciousness is an organizational invariant: a property that remains
constant over all functional isomorphs of a given system. Whether the
organization is realized in silicon chips, in the population of China,
or in beer cans and ping-pong balls does not matter. As long as the
functional organisation is right, conscious experience will be
determined.\" p249`</font>`{=html}
Chalmers\' idea of functional organisation has within it a sometimes
vague implication that the functional units must have a particular form;
for instance, in the development of his argument, he refers to "fine
grained" replacement of organic functional units with inorganic units.
Chalmers is actually making two major points, firstly that qualia occur
during the motion of things (functions), secondly that qualia are
independent of any particular substrate.\*\* For the first point to be
consistent with materialism the qualia must have no effect on the
function, they must be **epiphenomenal**. Epiphenomenal qualia would not
be forbidden by the regress and homunculus arguments and would be akin
to Berkeley\'s \"passive ideas\".
Whether or not epiphenomenal qualia are physical depends upon the
definition of the word \"physical\". If physical functions cause qualia
but qualia cannot affect functions then the qualia are \"physical\" in
the sense of being caused by physical events but might be regarded as
non-physical in the sense of being isolated from further physical
events. In philosophical terms they violate the principle of **Causal
Closure**. However, there are other definitions of physicalism based on
arguments such as **Methodological Naturalism** which hold that anything
that can be investigated using the methods of natural science is a
physical thing (see Stoljar 2001). Thus, although epiphenomenal qualia
may not conform to materialism they may be encompassed by physicalism;
as events that are related to material events they are awaiting a
physical theory of how they emerge from a given function.
The reader might consider whether phenomenal consciousness is indeed
epiphenomenal. Empirical reports describe it as something that is
different from the world beyond the body (see direct
realism) -
could we generate empirical reports of an epiphenomenon?
The term **property dualism** describes how physical events might give
rise to a set of properties that cannot be predicted from the fine
structure of the physical system. The \"dualism\" is present because one
set of events is related to two sets of properties, one of which is not
related by materialism to the set of events. In the case of the proposal
about consciousness outlined above an extra assumption, beyond
materialism, would be needed to explain qualia. Property dualism might
be defined as a theory that there could be a theory of consciousness but
that this requires some new assumption.
As far as the \"when and where\" of consciousness are concerned,
property dualism states that it is somewhere in the processes performed
by the organism and the parts of the organism.
`<font size=1>`{=html} \*\* In terms of information processing, Chalmers
is proposing that qualia are the enactment of a particular information
processing structure.`</font>`{=html}
- Block, N. (2006). Max Black\'s objection to mind-body identity.
Oxford Review of Metaphysics No.3.
<http://philrsss.anu.edu.au/BlockFest/MaxBlack.rtf>
- Chalmers, D.J. (1993) Commentary on \"The Psychology of Folk
Psychology\". Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16:35-36, 1993
- Chalmers, D.J. (1996) \"The Conscious Mind: In Search of a
Fundamental Theory\". Oxford University Press. 1996.
- Goldman, A.I., (1993). The Psychology of Folk Psychology. Behavioral
and Brain Sciences 16: 15-28 (1993).
<http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Papers/Py104/goldman.psyc.html>
### Predicate dualism
Predicate dualism is the view espoused by most non-reductive
physicalists, such as Donald Davidson(1980) and Jerry Fodor(1968), who
maintain that while there is only one ontological category of substances
and properties of substances (usually physical), the predicates that we
use to describe mental events cannot be redescribed in terms of (or
reduced to) physical predicates of natural languages. If we characterize
predicate monism as the view subscribed to by eliminative materialists,
who maintain that such intentional predicates as believe, desire, think,
feel, etc., will eventually be eliminated from both the language of
science and from ordinary language because the entities to which they
refer do not exist, then predicate dualism is most easily defined as the
negation of this position. Predicate dualists believe that so-called
\"folk psychology\", with all of its propositional attitude ascriptions,
is an ineliminable part of the enterprise of describing, explaining and
understanding human mental states and behavior.
Davidson, for example, subscribes to Anomalous Monism, according to
which there can be no strict psycho-physical laws which connect mental
and physical events under their descriptions as mental and physical
events. However, all mental events also have physical descriptions. It
is in terms of the latter that such events can be connected in law-like
relations with other physical events. Mental predicates are irreducibly
different in character (rational, holistic and necessary) from physical
predicates (contingent, atomic and causal).
(Section based on Wikipedia article)
- Davidson, D (1980). Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford University
Press.
- Fodor,J. (1968) *Psychological Explanation*, Random House.
.
### The interaction between mind and brain in dualism
#### Interactionism
Interactionism is the view that mental states, such as beliefs and
desires, causally interact with physical states. This is a position
which is very appealing to common-sense intuitions, notwithstanding the
fact that it is very difficult to establish its validity or correctness
by way of logical argumentation or empirical proof. It is appealing to
common-sense because we are surrounded by such everyday occurrences as a
child\'s touching a hot stove (physical event) which causes him to feel
pain (mental event) and then yell and scream (physical event) which
causes his parents to experience a sensation of fear and protectiveness
(mental event) and so on.
#### Epiphenomalism
According to epiphenomenalism, all mental events are caused by a
physical event and have no physical consequences. So, a mental event of
deciding to pick up a rock (call it \"M\") is caused by the firing of
specific neurons in the brain (call it \"P\"), however when the arm and
hand move to pick up a rock (call it \"E\") this is only caused by P.
The physical causes are in principle reducible to fundamental physics,
and therefore mental causes are eliminated using this reductionist
explanation. If P causes M and E, there is no overdetermination in the
explanation for E.
#### Parallelism
Psycho-physical parallelism is a very unusual view about the interaction
between mental and physical events which was most prominently, and
perhaps only truly, advocated by Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz. Like
Malebranche and others before him, Leibniz recognized the weaknesses of
Descartes\' account of causal interaction taking place in a physical
location in the brain. Malebranche decided that such a material basis of
interaction between material and immaterial was impossible and therefore
formulated his doctrine of occasionalism, stating that the interactions
were really caused by the intervention of God on each individual
occasion. Leibniz idea is that God has created a pre-established harmony
such that it only seems as if physical and mental events cause, and are
caused by, one another. In reality, mental causes only have mental
effects and physical causes only have physical effects. Hence the term
parallelism is used to describe this view.
#### Occasionalism
Occasionalism argues that bodily events are the occasion of an act by
the Creator causing a corresponding mental event, and vice versa. Any
such view requires a theological structure as a premise.
#### Further reading
- Robinson, Howard, \"Dualism\", The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Fall 2003 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2003/entries/dualism/>
- Robinson, H. (2003) \"Dualism\", in S. Stich and T. Warfield (eds)
The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell, Oxford,
85-101.
- Amoroso, R.L. (2010) \"The complementarity of Mind and Body:
Realizing the Dream of Descartes, Einstein and Eccles\", New York:
Nova Science Publishers,
`, ``https://www.novapublishers.com/catalog/product_info.php?products_id=12759`
## Idealism
According to Idealism only the mental truly exists.
The form and content of personal conscious experience might be related
to the structure of the world and brain in several ways. It could be a
**solipsism** or be the mind of God.
*This is a **stub** and needs expansion*.
## Panpsychism
### Etymology
Ancient Greek *pan* (πᾶν : \"all, everything, whole\") and *psyche*
(ψυχή : \"soul, mind\").[^1] Psyche is the from
ψύχω (*psukhō*, \"I blow\") and means mind or \'life-breath\'.
Philip Goff, a proponent of panpsychism, carves out a distinction
between panexperientialism and pancognitivism. Panexperientialism is the
belief that *experience* is ubiquitous, while pancognitivism is the
belief that *cognition* is ubiquitous. Most modern purponents of
panpsychism, such as Annaka Harris and David Chalmers, are careful to
distance themselves from pancognitivism.
In some interpretations, such as monadism, Panpsychism and Idealism can
overlap because the universe is conceived as being composed of an
infinity of point consciousnesses that each contain information about
the whole universe.
The form and content of personal conscious experience might be related
to the structure of the world and brain in many ways.
*This is a **stub** and needs expansion*.
## References
Seager W. & Allen-Hermanson (2001). 'Panpsychism.' Online document:
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, \[online\],
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/panpsychism/>, \[accessed 10/2005\]
**Supervenience**
- Chalmers, D.J. (1996). The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press.
**The problem of regression**
- Ryle, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind. The University of Chicago
Press, 1949.
**The homunculus argument**
- Gregory, R.L. (1990) Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing, Oxford
University Press Inc. New York.
- Gregory, T.L. (1987). The Oxford Companion to Mind. Oxford
University Press.
**Subject-object paradox**
- James, W. (1904)Does \'Consciousness\' Exist? Journal of
Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1,
477-491.
- Hegel, G.W.F. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND: SECTION I. MIND SUBJECTIVE B.
PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND CONSCIOUSNESS Part Three of the Encyclopaedia
of the Philosophical
Sciences
- Velmans, M. (1996) Consciousness and the \"Casual Paradox\".
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 19 (3):
538-542.
- Bermudez, J.L. (1999) The Paradox of Self-Consciousness
(representation and Mind) Psycoloquy:
10,#35
**Ontological status**
- Bierman, D.J. (2004) Non Conscious Processes Preceding Intuitive
decisions
<http://m0134.fmg.uva.nl/~djb/publications/2004/Intuition_bialsymp2004.pdf>
- Damasio, A.R. (1994). Descartes\' error: Emotion, reason and the
human brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam Book.
- Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason
<http://www.arts.cuhk.edu.hk/Philosophy/Kant/cpr/>
**Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness**
Block, N. (1995) On a confusion about a function of consciousness.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 227-287.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/documents/a/00/00/04/31/bbs00000431-00/bbs.block.html>
Block, N. (2004). *The Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science*.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/ecs.pdf>
Dennett, D. (1978). Why You Can\'t Make a Computer that Feels Pain, in:
Brainstorms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 190-229.
Dennett, D. (1988). Quining Qualia. in A. Marcel and E. Bisiach, eds,
Consciousness in Modern Science, Oxford University Press 1988. Reprinted
in W. Lycan, ed., Mind and Cognition: A Reader, MIT Press, 1990, A.
Goldman, ed. Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science, MIT Press,
1993. <http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/quinqual.htm>
Edelman, G.M. (1993). Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the
Mind. New York:
Feyerabend, P. (1963). Mental Events and the Brain, Journal of
Philosophy 40:295-6.
Huxley, T. H. (1874). On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and
its History, The Fortnightly Review, n.s.16:555-580. Reprinted in Method
and Results: Essays by Thomas H. Huxley (New York: D. Appleton and
Company, 1898).
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review
LXXXIII, 4 (October 1974): 435-50.
<http://web.archive.org/19990218140703/members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html>
Rey, Georges, (1997). Contemporary Philosophy of Mind.Blackwell: Oxford
Sellars W. (1956). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, In: Feigl H
and Scriven M (eds) The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of
Psychology and Psychoanalysis: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of
Science, Vol. 1. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 253-329
Whitehead, A.N. (1920). The Concept of Nature. Chapter 3: Time.
<http://spartan.ac.brocku.ca/~lward/Whitehead/Whitehead_1920/White1_03.html>
**Direct Realism**
- Austin, J.L. (1962) Sense and Sensibilia, ed. by Geoffrey J. Warnock
(Oxford, 1962)
- Aydede, M. (2001) Naturalism, introspection, and direct realism
about pain. Consciousness and Emotion, Vol. 2, No. 1, 2001,
pp. 29--73.
<http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/maydede/pain.pdf>
- Chapman, C.R., and Y. Nakamura (1999). A Passion of the Soul: An
Introduction to Pain for Consciousness Researchers. Consciousness
and Cognition, 8: 391-422.
- Dennett, D. (1991a). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown
- Dennett, D. (1991b). Lovely and suspect qualities. Commentary on
David Rosenthal, \"The Independence of Consciousness and Sensory
Quality\" in E. Villanueva, ed., Consciousness, (SOFIA Conference,
Buenos Aires), Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview 1991.
<http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/lovely&s.htm>
- Fowler C A (1986): "An event approach to the study of speech
perception from a direct-realist perspective", J of Phonetics
14(1):3-28.
- Gibson, J. J. (1966) The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems.
Houghton Mifflin Company,Boston.
- Gibson, J. J. (1979) Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Hillsdate.
- Gregory, R.L. 1988. Consciousness in science and philosophy:
conscience and con-science. Chapter 12 in Consciousness in
Contemporary Science. (Editors: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E.).
Oxford Science Publications.
- Le Morvan, Pierre (2004). Arguments against direct realism and how
to counter them. *The American Philosophical Quarterly*, *41*(3),
221-234.\] (pdf) <http://www.tcnj.edu/~lemorvan/DR_web.pdf>
- Michaels, C. F. and Carello, C. (1981). Direct Perception. Century
Psychology Series. Prentice-Hall.
. 1981. Download this book at
<http://ione.psy.uconn.edu/~psy254/MC.pdf>
- Oliveira, André L. G. and Oliveira, Luis F. (2002) Toward an
ecological conception of timbre. In Proceedings Auditory Perception
Cognition and Action Meeting 2002, Kansas City.
<http://cogprints.org/2713/>
- Skinner, B. F. Science and Human Behavior . New York: Macmillan,
1953.
- Skinner, B. F. 1971. Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New York: Knopf.
- Skinner, B. F. 1948. Walden Two. New York: Macmillan.
- Tye, M. (2004). ANOTHER LOOK AT REPRESENTATIONALISM ABOUT PAIN.
Consciousness and Emotion 2004, special issue on pain, edited by
Murat Aydede (with replies by M. Aydede, N. Block, B. Maund, and P.
Noordhof
<http://sun.soci.niu.edu/~phildept/MT/RepresentationalismAndPain.pdf>
- Vygotsky, L.S.(1925) Consciousness as a problem in the psychology of
behavior. Undiscovered Vygotsky: Etudes on the pre-history of
cultural-historical psychology (European Studies in the History of
Science and Ideas. Vol. 8), pp. 251--281. Peter Lang Publishing.
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/1925/consciousness.htm>
- Ziff, Paul. \"About Behaviourism.\" Analysis 18 (1958): 132-136.
Quoted by Larry Hauser in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/b/behavior.htm#B>. F. Skinner:
Radical Behaviorism
**Indirect Realism**
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
- Rizzo, M., Nawrot, M. & Zihl, J. (1995). Motion and shape perception
in cerebral akinetopsia.Brain, 118. 1105-1127.
<http://nawrot.psych.ndsu.nodak.edu/Publications/Nawrot.pdf/RizzoNawrotZihl.1995.pdf>
- Russell, B. (1912). Problems of Philosophy. Home University Library.
<http://www.ditext.com/russell/rus1.html>
- Tye, M. (2003) Qualia. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia/#Repqualia>
Further reading:
- Hume, D. (1739). A Treatise of Human Nature.
<http://www.class.uidaho.edu/mickelsen/ToC/hume%20treatise%20ToC.htm>
- Firth, R. (1949) Sense Data and the Percept Theory, Mind, 58 (1949);
59 (1950). (Describes early reasons for rejecting Indirect Realism)
<http://www.ditext.com/firth/spt.html>
- Grush, R. (2000). Self, world and space: The meaning and mechanisms
of ego- and allocentric spatial representation. Brain and Mind
1(1):59-92.
<http://mind.ucsd.edu/papers/sws/sws.html>
[^1]: Clarke, D.S. *Panpsychism: Past and Recent Selected Readings*.
State University of New York Press, 2004. p.1
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Conflict2#Panpsychism
*This part of this section is about the where and when of the experience
called consciousness. Is it in the world, in the brain or are the world
and brain within it?*
## Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness
Block(1995) drew attention to the way that there appear to be two types
of consciousness: *phenomenal* consciousness and *access* consciousness:
`Phenomenal consciousness is experience; the phenomenally`\
`conscious aspect of a state is what it is like to be in that`\
`state. The mark of access-consciousness, by contrast, is `\
`availability for use in reasoning and rationally guiding speech `\
`and action. (Block 1995).`
*See the section on Ned Block\'s
ideas
for a deeper coverage of his approach to access and phenomenal
consciousness.*
Block uses Nagel\'s famous (1974) paper, \"What is it like to be a
bat?\" as an exemplary description of phenomenal consciousness.
Excellent descriptions have also been proffered by the empiricist
philosophers who gave lengthy descriptions of consciousness as partly
experience itself. Although Block has formalised the idea of phenomenal
and access consciousness similar ideas have also been put forward by
many philosophers including Kant and Whitehead.
Access consciousness has two interpretations, in the first, used by
Block, it applies to the functions that appear to operate on phenomenal
consciousness. In the second, used by the behaviourists and
eliminativists, it is some property of the functions of the brain that
can be called \'consciousness\'.
This division between phenomenal and functional aspects of consciousness
is useful because it emphasises the idea of phenomenal consciousness as
observation rather than action. Some philosophers such as Huxley in
1874, have taken the view that because phenomenal consciousness appears
to have no function it is of no importance or cannot exist. James (1879)
introduced the term \"epiphenomenalism\" to summarise the idea that
consciousness has no function.
The idea that phenomenal consciousness cannot exist is a type of
*Eliminativism* (also known as Eliminative Materialism). Eliminativism
owes much to the work of Sellars(1956) and Feyerbend (1963). Dennett
(1978) applied Eliminativism to phenomenal consciousness and denies that
pain is real. Others such as Rey(1997) have also applied eliminativism
to phenomenal consciousness.
Dennett (1988) redefines consciousness in terms of access consciousness
alone, he argues that \"Everything real has properties, and since I
don\'t deny the reality of conscious experience, I grant that conscious
experience has properties\". Having related all consciousness to
properties he then declares that these properties are actually
judgements of properties. He considers judgements of the properties of
consciousness to be identical to the properties themselves. He writes:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"The infallibilist line on qualia treats
them as properties of one\'s experience one cannot in principle
misdiscover, and this is a mysterious doctrine (at least as mysterious
as papal infallibility) unless we shift the emphasis a little and treat
qualia as logical constructs out of subjects\' qualia-judgments: a
subject\'s experience has the quale F if and only if the subject judges
his experience to have quale F. \"`</font>`{=html}
Having identified \"properties\" with \"judgement of properties\" he can
then show that the judgements are insubstantial, hence the properties
are insubstantial and hence the qualia are insubstantial or even
non-existent. Dennett concludes that qualia can be rejected as
non-existent:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"So when we look one last time at our
original characterization of qualia, as ineffable, intrinsic, private,
directly apprehensible properties of experience, we find that there is
nothing to fill the bill. In their place are relatively or practically
ineffable public properties we can refer to indirectly via reference to
our private property-detectors\-- private only in the sense of
idiosyncratic. And insofar as we wish to cling to our subjective
authority about the occurrence within us of states of certain types or
with certain properties, we can have some authority\--not infallibility
or incorrigibility, but something better than sheer guessing\--but only
if we restrict ourselves to relational, extrinsic properties like the
power of certain internal states of ours to provoke acts of apparent re-
identification. So contrary to what seems obvious at first blush, there
simply are no qualia at all. \" (Dennett 1988)`</font>`{=html}
Dennett\'s asserts that \"a subject\'s experience has the quale F if and
only if the subject judges his experience to have quale F\". This is a
statement of the belief that qualia are the same as processes such as
judgements. Processes such as judgements are flows of data where one
state examines a previous state in a succession over time and embody
what Whitehead called the \"materialist\" concept of time. Dennett does
not consider how a scientific concept of time might affect his argument.
Dennett\'s argument has been persuasive and there are now many
philosophers and neuroscientists who believe that the problem of
phenomenal consciousness does not exist. This means that, to them, what
we call \'consciousness\' can only be a property of the functions
performed by the brain and body. According to these philosophers only
access consciousness exists.
Those who support the idea of phenomenal consciousness also tend to
frame it in terms of nineteenth century theory where one state examines
a previous state in a succession over time, for instance Edelman(1993)
places the past in memories at an instant and time within experience is
explained as continuing modelling processes:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"Primary consciousness is the state of
being mentally aware of things in the world\--of having mental images in
the present. But it is not accompanied by any sense of a person with a
past and a future\.... In contrast, higher-order consciousness involves
the recognition by a thinking subject of his or her own acts or
affections. It embodies a model of the personal, and of the past and the
future as well as the present. It exhibits direct awareness\--the
noninferential or immediate awareness of mental episodes without the
involvement of sense organs or receptors. It is what we humans have in
addition to primary consciousness. We are conscious of being
conscious.\" `</font>`{=html}
Block(2004) also suggests this flow from state to state in his idea of
\"Reflexivity\" where our idea of familiarity with an object is due to
one state being analysed by another:
`<font face="times">`{=html}\"Thus in the "conscious" case, the subject
must have a state that is about the subject's own perceptual experience
(looking familiar) and thus conscious in what might be termed a
"reflexive" sense. An experience is conscious in this sense just in case
it is the object of another of the subject's states; for example, one
has a thought to the effect that one has that experience. The reflexive
sense of \'consciousness\' contrasts with phenomenality, which perhaps
attaches to some states which are not the objects of other mental
states. Reflexive consciousness might better be called 'awareness' than
'consciousness'. Reflexivity is phenomenality plus something else
(reflection) and that opens up the possibility in principle for
phenomenality without reflection. For example, it is at least
conceptually possible for there to be two people in pain, one of whom is
introspecting the pain the other not. (Perhaps infants or animals can
have pain but don't introspect it.) The first is reflexively conscious
of the pain, but both have phenomenally conscious states, since pain is
by its very nature a phenomenally conscious state. \"`</font>`{=html}
Both Block and Edelman allow phenomenal consciousness, our experience,
as an unexplained phenomenon. Block, Edelman and also Dennett\'s ideas
of consciousness are shown in the illustration below:
![](Constudphen.gif "Constudphen.gif")
This model differs from the empirical reports of phenomenal
consciousness that were considered earlier. According to the empirical
reports the present moment in our experience is extended so the
succession of outputs or stages of access consciousness could constitute
the contents of phenomenal consciousness. In other words phenomenal
consciousness is composed of periods of access consciousness. This is
how it seems to the empiricist and in our own experience but how such a
state could be explained in terms of brain activity is highly
problematical. Given that nineteenth century ideas cannot explain such a
state a scientific explanation will be required.
The idea that phenomenal consciousness misrepresents or \"misdiscovers\"
itself (Dennett 1988) deserves further discussion. According to
materialism the present instant has no duration so can only be known in
succeeding instants as a report or memory and this could be wrong.
Whitehead considered that this viewpoint originates in an archaic view
of science, particularly the concept of time in science:
\"The eighteenth and nineteenth centuries accepted as their natural
philosophy a certain circle of concepts which were as rigid and definite
as those of the philosophy of the middle ages, and were accepted with as
little critical research. I will call this natural philosophy
\'materialism.\' Not only were men of science materialists, but also
adherents of all schools of philosophy. The idealists only differed from
the philosophic materialists on question of the alignment of nature in
reference to mind. But no one had any doubt that the philosophy of
nature considered in itself was of the type which I have called
materialism. It is the philosophy which I have already examined in my
two lectures of this course preceding the present one. It can be
summarised as the belief that nature is an aggregate of material and
that this material exists in some sense at each successive member of a
one-dimensional series of extensionless instants of time. Furthermore
the mutual relations of the material entities at each instant formed
these entities into a spatial configuration in an unbounded space. It
would seem that space\-\--on this theory-would be as instantaneous as
the instants, and that some explanation is required of the relations
between the successive instantaneous spaces. The materialistic theory is
however silent on this point; and the succession of instantaneous spaces
is tacitly combined into one persistent space. This theory is a purely
intellectual rendering of experience which has had the luck to get
itself formulated at the dawn of scientific thought. It has dominated
the language and the imagination of science since science flourished in
Alexandria, with the result that it is now hardly possible to speak
without appearing to assume its immediate obviousness.\" (Whitehead
1920).
## Direct Realism and Direct Perception
Direct Realism proposes that phenomenal experience is directly objects
in the world without any intervening representation. It is motivated by
the belief that the Problem of Regression, the Subject-Object Paradox
and the recursion form of the Homunculus arguments show that phenomenal
consciousness cannot occur in the brain alone. Direct Realists reason
that if phenomenal consciousness cannot be things in the brain then it
must be something outside the brain.
There are two principle types of Direct Realism: Natural Dualism and
Behaviourism (both Radical and Analytical). Some behaviourists use the
term "Direct Perception" rather than Direct Realism and consider that
only the invariant parts of perception are direct (see for instance
Michaels and Carello 1981). Thomas Reid is generally regarded as the
founder of Direct Realism. In his Natural Dualism he proposed that the
soul is in direct contact with the contents of experience and these
contents are things in the world beyond the body. The Direct Realism of
Reid is summarised in the statement of his famous disciple Sir William
Hamilton: \"In the simplest act of perception I am conscious of myself
as the perceiving subject and of an external reality as the object
perceived\". Reid\'s Natural Dualism has now been largely replaced by
radical and analytical behaviourism which eschew the idea of a soul and
propose that phenomenal consciousness, if it exists at all, is a
behavioural reflex.
The modern justification of Direct Realism mainly consists of arguments
against Indirect Realism or Representationalism. Philosophers such as
Austin (1962) and Le Morvan (2004) have summarised the Direct Realism
debate and have identified the following arguments in favour of Indirect
Realism and given rebuttals to each of them:
1\. The Causal Argument: perception involves a succession of causal
events such as the reflection of photons, bleaching of retinal pigments
etc. so perception must involve the end of this causal chain. The Direct
Realist response is that, although there may be a causal chain in
sensation this does not inevitably imply that the end of the chain is
the content of phenomenal experience.
2\. The Time Lag Argument: it takes time for light to travel from an
object to the senses, time for chemical changes in the retina etc\...
The Direct Realist response is that direct perception may be referred
back in time.
3\. The Partial Character of Perception Argument: we only perceive the
surface of objects, and then only a part of the surface. As the whole
object would be perceived directly perception must be indirect. The
Direct Realist response is that direct perception could occur even if
only parts of an object were perceived.
4\. The Perceptual Relativity Argument: things appear to be different
shapes depending upon the point of view. The Direct Realist response is
that if perception can occur backwards in time it should have no problem
occurring back down a line of sight. However, Le Morvan\'s argument does
not seem to encompass the geometrical nature of phenomenal experience,
seeking to explain geometry in terms of movement.
5\. The Argument from Perceptual Illusion: A stick may appear bent when
projecting from the surface of water. Direct Realists apply the argument
used in (4) to this problem. The bent stick illusion is a physical event
in the world beyond the eye rather than a normal optical illusion such
as the Muller-Lyer illusion etc., see (6) for a discussion of optical
illusions.
6\. The Argument from Hallucination: Hallucinations are not in the world
beyond the body. This is highly problematical for Direct Realists
especially when phenomena such as lucid dreams, dreams and visual
imaginations are included along with hallucinations. Direct Realists
classify these phenomena as not being perceptions or deny that they
actually exist as phenomena. Indirect Realists would maintain that all
of perception is a reconstruction and use optical illusions such as the
Muller-Lyer, Ames Room etc. to justify this contention so the Direct
Realist approach to hallucination, dreams etc. might seem like an
unwillingness to accept Indirect Realism rather than an argument.
7\. The Dubitability Argument (cf: Indubitability argument): we cannot
doubt current phenomenal experience but we can doubt the world beyond
the body therefore phenomenal experience is not the world beyond the
body. Direct Realists fall back on Presentism or functional Presentism
to defeat this argument. If phenomenal experience is instantaneous and
made anew at each instant then anything can be doubted.
The points above have summarised the Direct Realist stance on visual
perception. Other sensory modalities have also been considered in the
Direct Realism debate.
Fowler (1986) considered that sounds were attached to objects in the
world. This idea is strange because sounds only seem to be closely
attached to objects in the world when these objects are seen as well as
heard. For example, when a subject is blindfolded it is found that there
can be a large error in locating the position of a sound in the world,
this is especially true for low frequency sounds. The Direct Realist
approach has difficulty explaining the transition from sounds with an
indefinite location when a subject is blindfolded to sounds that are
bound to visual events when the blindfold is removed. It also runs into
problems explaining how the sound of speech from a single loudspeaker
can become bound to lip movements on a cinema screen. If the binding
does not occur in the brain then where does it occur?
Pain is particularly problematic for Direct Realism because, unlike
colour vision where \'red\' is inferred to be a property of electrons or
light, pain is an inner experience that is not a property of tissue
damage. Tissue damage has properties such as bleeding, wheal formation
etc. but pain seems to be phenomenal experience in the brain and
\'phantom pain\' can occur without tissue damage (see Aydede (2001), Tye
(2004) and Chapman, and Nakamura (1999) for further analysis). On closer
inspection other sensations also appear to be inner experiences rather
than direct sensations. For instance, the red crosses of different hues
in the illustration below are all due to the same physical wavelengths
of light. In this case the range of hues in experience is unrelated to
the actual physical red on the page or screen.
Another problem for Direct Realism is that it does not overcome the
problems that it is supposed to solve. The argument for Direct Realism
begins with the idea that there are severe problems with
representationalism (the idea that phenomenal experience is in the
brain) and that direct perception is an alternative that does not have
these problems. However on closer inspection Direct Realism suffers from
almost same problems as representationalism. If phenomenal experience is
the world itself then Ryle\'s regress applies to the world itself and
this can only be avoided by assuming that phenomenal experience is a
subset of the world (i.e.: a representation) that receives input from
other parts of the world that are not part of phenomenal experience.
It is also commonly assumed that Direct Realism avoids the recursion
argument because it is believed that the separation of the observer from
the things that are observed is simply due to the geometry of the world.
If such simple geometry is possible between the eye and the world then
it should also be possible in the brain and a similar geometrical
explanation could be invoked to avoid recursion in representations.
These points are shown in the illustration below:
image:Constuddir1.gif
Scientists have a further problem with Direct Realism. The illustration
below demonstrates that our scientific knowledge of the world differs
markedly from our phenomenal experience.
image:constuddirect.gif
It is difficult to see how the form and content of phenomenal experience
could supervene directly on the world beyond the body. The world
inferred from measurements beyond the body seems to be a nebulous set of
quantum phenomena that are arranged as probability fields in three
dimensions at any instant. The objects in this real world are mostly
space. The world of phenomenal experience on the other hand contains
objects that are one-sided, and are like a 2 dimensional field of
vectors directed simultaneously at an observation point which is
apparently separate from them. Phenomenal experience is not three
dimensional, the rear of objects is not available within it at any
instant. Visual phenomenal experience seems to be a geometrical
relationship between an abstract observation point and the reflection
properties of the part of the world external to the body. It is a form
that crudely overlies the angular separations in inferred reality,
providing approximate directional data. It is not like things in
themselves beyond the body, not even in type, being a set of directional
vectors. (See the module on the neuroscience of perception for a
discussion of depth perception).
If the form and content of visual phenomenal experience are abstractions
separated according to the angular positions of things in the world
beyond the body then theories which propose that phenomenal experience
is the world itself are problematical. It should be noted that things
arranged according to angular positions can appear to overlie any group
of similar things along a radius from the centre point.
![](Constuddirectangle.gif "Constuddirectangle.gif")
If Direct Realists admit that things are as they appear to be, observed
according to angular positions at a \'point eye\', then any
representation of things on the inside of a sphere of any radius would
appear similar. The geometry of the \'point eye\' is problematical
whether the view contains the world itself or a representation of the
world; it cannot be the movements of lumps of matter or energy and the
point observation cannot be due to lumps all landing at a point. In
other words the \'view\' is inconsistent with nineteenth century
materialism and will require a scientific explanation.
Radical and Analytical Behaviourism tackle the problem of the difference
between the world inferred from measurements beyond the body and the
phenomenal world by denying phenomenal consciousness and maintaining
that access and reflex consciousness are all that exists or is
necessary. Radical Behaviourism is an offshoot of psychological
behaviourism and was established as a philosophical adjunct to Marxism
by Vygotsky and popularised by Burrhus Frederic Skinner (see Skinner
1953). There is another movement in psychological behaviourism which is
similar to Radical Behaviourism called Ecological Psychology (see Gibson
1966, 1979 and also Michaels and Carello 1981). Analytical Behaviourism
is a philosophical movement established by Gilbert Ryle (see Ryle 1949).
The core of Analytical and Radical Behaviourism is the assumption that
consciousness exists for a durationless instant so that the Dubitability
Argument and the Regression and Recursion Arguments can be applied (Ryle
1949, Skinner 1971 and see the sections on Ryle\'s Regress and the
Subject-Object Paradox above). As a result the Direct Realist is able to
insinuate that subjects only think that they have had a particular
experience (cf: Dennett 1991a). It is intriguing that Eliminativists
also maintain that experience is the world itself, for instance an
insight into Dennett\'s idea of the mind is to be found on pages 407-408
of Consciousness Explained:
\"It seemed to him, according to the text, as if his mind - his visual
field - were filled with intricate details of gold-green buds an
wiggling branches, but although this is how it seemed this was an
illusion. No such \"plenum\" ever came into his mind; the plenum
remained out in the world where it is didn\'t have to be represented,
but could just be. When we marvel, in those moments of heightened
self-consciousness, at the glorious richness of our conscious
experience, the richness we marvel at is actually the richness of the
world outside, in all its ravishing detail. It does not \"enter\" our
conscious minds, but is simply available\"
This is a clear description of Direct Realism (although Dennett does not
describe himself as a direct realist).
Radical Behaviourism is sometimes described as the dictum that the only
psychological events that are of importance are those that occur outside
the head. The absurdity of this has led to jokes:
Q: What does one behaviorist say to another when they meet on the
street?
A: You\'re fine. How am I?
Q: What does one behaviorist say to another after sex?
A: That was great for you. How was it for me?
(Ziff 1958)
However Vygotsky, Skinner and other Radical Behaviourists hold that
inner behaviour is possible so that events within the brain can result
in reward or punishment. Vygotsky (1925) describes this approach:
\"Consciousness is wholly reduced to the transmitting mechanisms of
reflexes operating according to general laws, i.e., no processes other
than reactions can be admitted into the organism. The way is also paved
for the solution of the problem of self-awareness and self-observation.
Inner perception and introspection are possible only thanks to the
existence of a proprioceptive field and secondary reflexes, which are
connected with it. This is always the echo of a reaction.\"
Hence Radical Behaviourists are able to make the claim that what are
believed to be representations with phenomenal content are processes.
Even events such as pain can then be explained as reflexes involving
organs within the skin. However, by opening the possibility that such
reflexes could occur at any sense organ, including the eye, this makes
Radical Behaviourism a mixed Direct Realist/Indirect Realist philosophy
with consciousness as a process, not a separate thing such as phenomenal
consciousness (see the section on representationalism and intentionality
below).
But this raises a serious issue for science: can the phenomenal
consciousness that seems to contain our observations really be argued
out of existence on the basis of a theory? As Gregory (1988) put it: "
'If you can't explain it -- deny it' is one strategy for dealing with
embarrassing questions such as 'what is consciousness?' ". But is this
the right strategy?
Direct Realism fails to overcome the problems of regression and
recursion inherent in representations. It proposes that phenomenal
consciousness is identical to the physical world beyond the body but
must then use a plethora of arguments to explain why this is evidently
not so. When confronted with these problems its proponents resort to the
argument that everything can be doubted and can misrepresent itself. Yet
it is still widely believed.
It should be noted that Direct Realism is espoused in Religious Natural
Dualism, some forms of Augustinian theology, nineteenth century
materialism and its offspring such as Marxism, post-modernism,
post-Marxism, and various sociological movements. It is also necessary
for some forms of Strong AI to occur. Perhaps this explains why few
ideas have attracted as much attention and defence as Direct Realism.
It is interesting to compare the Direct Realist and Indirect Realist
interpretations of something as simple as a cartoon on television (such
as the image below). According to Indirect Realism the cartoon would be
a moving representation constructed in the brain using data from the
senses. This leads to the prediction of brain mechanisms for modelling
motions, combining colours, binding sound and vision etc., many of which
have been verified. Can you demonstrate how the theory of Direct Realism
could explain the phenomenal experience that contains the cartoon and
produce a list of the predictions made by the theory?
![](constudcartoon.gif "constudcartoon.gif")
In science a theory should be of predictive value, for instance,
information theory describes how the state of a thing can be impressed
on a carrier so that a signal can be transmitted from one place to
another. This theory predicts what will happen when the signal arrives
at its destination and how the state of the source can be inferred from
the events at the destination, the total amount of information that can
be transmitted etc. At the destination it is the form of the signal that
is directly known by interaction and measurement, the form of the source
is inferred. Direct Realism is a direct challenge to this information
theory but does it deliver a more powerful predictive description of
phenomenal consciousness or is experience always dependent on what
happens to the information flow between things in the world and
somewhere in the brain? Does direct realism have a physical theory?
Ultimately it appears as if Direct Realism is about various
understandings of Information Theory. For example, Austin (1962)
discusses what we see when we see a church camouflaged as a barn and
comments that: \"We see, of course, a church that now looks like a
barn.\". Do we see a church or a barn? Scientific information theory is
clear about this, the church is an entity composed of selected
information from the quantum state of its constituents, the optical
image of a camouflaged church is an arrangement of photons emanating
from a screen on which it is projected, the retina has an arrangement of
chemical and electrical events based on an optical image and conscious
visual experience correlates with the arrangement of things on the
retina. The fact that conscious experience also correlates with
classifications of the retinal image as a barn or a church suggests that
conscious experience is an arrangement of things in the brain based on
both the retinal arrangement and the contents of a relational database.
Austin\'s arguments have been mythologised as a final demonstration that
\"sense data\" theories are false. However, as will be seen below, sense
data theories merely claim that there is a succession of information
states between an information state outside the body and that reported
as conscious experience i.e.: subjects report that a church is
camouflaged when it is camouflaged.
## Indirect Realism
Indirect realism proposes that phenomenal consciousness exists and is a
set of signals or **sense data**, usually in the brain. This was
proposed by philosophers from Aristotle to Locke and was probably the
most widespread idea of conscious experience until the eighteenth
century.
The idea of sense data is discussed in depth by Russell (1912).
Russell\'s original definition is given below:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Let us give the name of
\'sense-data\' to the things that are immediately known in sensation:
such things as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and so
on. We shall give the name \'sensation\' to the experience of being
immediately aware of these things. Thus, whenever we see a colour, we
have a sensation of the colour, but the colour itself is a sense-datum,
not a sensation. The colour is that of which we are immediately aware,
and the awareness itself is the sensation. It is plain that if we are to
know anything about the table, it must be by means of the sense-data \--
brown colour, oblong shape, smoothness, etc. \-- which we associate with
the table; but, for the reasons which have been given, we cannot say
that the table is the sense-data, or even that the sense-data are
directly properties of the table.\"`</font>`{=html}
Russell\'s definition is a materialist concept in which experience is
always **of** something because the durationless instant of the present
has always gone. As such it differs from some empiricist ideas where
experience is not confined to the durationless instant.
Science is Indirect Realist because it holds that the scientist can only
make **measurements** of events in the world. These measurements give
rise to signals as a result of interaction with the event. According to
**decoherence theory** the signals are a state that is a mixture of the
state of the measuring instrument and the state of the thing being
measured. For example, the eyes are measuring instruments that are
sensitive to photons, photons are signals containing a state that is
based on the state of electrons in a surface and the state of electrons
is based on the state of the surface etc. Scientific inference allows
some aspects of the state of the surface to be inferred from the state
of the photons.
In modern Indirect Realism there is an attempt to distinguish the
phenomenal content of conscious experience from the processing involved
in accessing this phenomenal content. According to these theories
phenomenal experience is an arrangement of signals that are the content
of the experience. This arrangement forms a *representation* of things
in the world so this form of indirect realism is known as
**Representationalism**. Tye (2003) describes types of
representationalist theory:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Representationalism, as I have
presented it so far, is an identity thesis with respect to qualia:
qualia are supposedly one and the same as certain representational
contents.\"`</font>`{=html}
Tye also describes variants of this idea of representationalism:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Sometimes it is held instead
that qualia are one and the same as certain representational properties
of experiences; and sometimes it is is argued that these
representational properties are themselves irreducible (Siewert 1998).
There is also a weaker version of representationalism, according to
which it is metaphysically necessary that experiences exactly alike with
respect to their representational contents are exactly alike with
respect to their qualia. Obviously, this supervenience thesis leaves
open the further question as to the essential nature of
qualia.\"`</font>`{=html} (Tye 2003).
In a scientific sense Direct Realists believe that phenomenal experience
is the signals that occur next to things in the world beyond the body
(which they call \"things in themselves\") and Indirect Realists usually
believe that phenomenal experience is signals in the brain. It can be
seen from the pattern of signal flow that the signals travelling into
the brain preserve the spatial relationships of the original signals and
encode the properties in the original signals. This means that the
original signals next to the QM sources and the signals in the brain are
equivalent provided the latter are oriented appropriately relative to
signals from the body. Either set of signals could transmit or contain
the same information. Both Direct and Indirect Realism cannot, at
present, explain the physics of how a viewing point occurs in experience
i.e.: how we seem to see through an apparent space to the signals that
are the contents of experience. So the choice between Direct Realism and
Indirect Realism reduces to whether there is only one set of signals or
a chain of signals between the world and phenomenal experience.
The philosophical arguments for Indirect Realism are listed below:
1\. Variable perspective: when we see things the view changes so what we
see must be a different set of signals depending on the view rather than
a constant object.
2\. Illusions: we can see through fingers and see a variety of colours
where measurements tell us one exists. Direct Realists quote the \"bent
stick illusion\", which is not really an illusion at all, being a
physical event.
3\. Hallucinations: two people can have phenomenal experience containing
a table. The first may be viewing a real table whereas the second may be
hallucinating a table. If the tables are the same (phenomenally) then
experience is indirect.
4\. Double vision: press the side of one eye, two images appear (cf Hume
1739) yet there are not two things in the world.
5\. Time gap arguments: according to materialism the past has gone. The
things being seen no longer exist in the state that relates to the state
in experience. In the extreme case, some stars in the night sky no
longer exist but are still in experience so experience must be a derived
signal.
6\. Secondary qualities such as pain, colour and smell do not exist as
physical things in the source of signals and are likely to be properties
of signals in the brain.
![](constudindirect.gif "constudindirect.gif")
Indirect Realism has received strong support from recent discoveries in
neuroscience, for example, it is now clear that both the colour and
motion in phenomenal experience are added by cortical processes. In
Cerebral **Achromatopsia** patients have suffered trauma to area V4 of
the cerebral cortex and report seeing the world in greyscale with no
colour vision and in Congenital Achromatopsia people do not even
understand the meaning of \'colour\'. In an astonishing ailment called
**Akinetopsia** patients perceive movement as a succession of stationary
images (Rizzo *et al.* 1995). Akinetopsia is usually associated with
damage to cortical area V5. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) have demonstrated
that the addition of colour occurs more rapidly than the addition of
motion. The section on the Neuroscience of Consciousness describes these
discoveries and many other aspects of the creation of phenomenal
experience in the brain.
Unfortunately knowledge of the whereabouts of the signals that are the
content of conscious experience does not resolve the problem of
phenomenal consciousness. Whether these signals are next to objects in
the world or at the end of a chain of signals in the brain there still
remains the problem of how they become arranged in the form of
experience. If such a thing occurs at all.
### Intentionality and representation
There is a materialist interpretation of representationalism in which
representations are redefined as intentional states:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"One way of explaining what is
meant by 'intentionality' in the (more obscure) philosophical sense is
this: it is that aspect of mental states or events that consists in
their being of or about things (as pertains to the questions, 'What are
you thinking of?' and 'What are you thinking about?'). Intentionality is
the aboutness or directedness of mind (or states of mind) to things,
objects, states of affairs, events. So if you are thinking about San
Francisco, or about the increased cost of living there, or about your
meeting someone there at Union Square---your mind, your thinking, is
directed toward San Francisco, or the increased cost of living, or the
meeting in Union Square. To think at all is to think of or about
something in this sense. This 'directedness' conception of
intentionality plays a prominent role in the influential philosophical
writings of Franz Brentano and those whose views developed in response
to his (to be discussed further in Section 3).\"(Siewert
2003)`</font>`{=html}
This definition allows \"representation\" to be redefined as a data
stream rather than a set of things arranged in some mental or neural
state that represents things in space. Husserl thought this approach
would allow a description of consciousness that \"carefully abstains
from affirming the existence of anything in spatio-temporal reality\"
(Siewert 2003) although it could be argued that a data stream such as
any description can never escape the constraints of representation in
time at some place.
Unfortunately the concept of \"intentionality\" has become so diverse
that it could be applied to almost any aspect of the description of
consciousness. An interesting example of this is given by Loar (2001)
where \"intentionality\" is considered to overlap \"representing\" and
\"conceiving\":
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"A person\'s thoughts represent
things to her \-- conceive things \-- in many ways: perceptually,
memory-wise, descriptively, by naming, by analogy, by intuitive sorting,
theoretically, abstractly, implicitly and explicitly. These various
manners of conceiving have something in common: they have intentional
properties, and they have them essentially. `</font>`{=html}
The usage of the term \"intentional state\" has become so broad that it
now means little more than a state that is about another state.
References
Siewert, C. (2003). Consciousness and Intentionality. The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-intentionality/>
Also see Loar, B. (2001) "Phenomenal Intentionality as the Basis of
Mental Content", in Reflections and Replies, ed. M. Hahn and B.
Ramsberg, MIT.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/courses/concepts/loar.html>
Williford, K. (2002) The intentionality of consciousness and the
consciousness of intentionality. Intentionality: Past and Future, edited
by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis, Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi.
<http://web.stcloudstate.edu/kwwilliford/Intentionality%20of%20Consciousness.pdf>
Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism Defended. Philosophical Review 110
(April 2001):199-240. <http://stripe.colorado.edu/~leeds/byrne.pdf>
### Cartesian materialism
The term \"Cartesian materialism\" once meant the idea that the mind is
in the brain (see for instance Block 1995). The term had largely fallen
out of use in philosophy until revived by Daniel Dennett (1991) in the
book *Consciousness Explained*. Dennett uses a very particular
definition of the term in his discussions and also uses a particular
definition of the word \"mind\". See the section on Daniel
Dennett
for Dennett\'s critique. Philosophers who adhere to the idea that the
mind is in the brain tend to call themselves \"indirect realists\" or
\"representationalists\" where the substrate of conscious experience is
in the brain and would deny that Dennett\'s critique applies to their
proposals. Dennett\'s critique makes the materialist assumption that if
there is a representation in the brain then a further flow of material
out of this representation would be required for the representation to
become part of mind.
### Identity theories of mind
The idea that mental states are brain states is known as the **identity
theory of mind**. There are two sorts of identity theory, in **type**
identity theory it is held that mental states are identical to brain
states whereas in **token** identity theory it is held that mental
states correlate with brain states.
Type identity theory was attacked by Putnam in \"The Nature of Mental
States\" where he pointed out that if mental states are functions then
type identity theory would presuppose that animals that had the same
mental states would need to have identical brain structures. He
suggested that this is unlikely, it being more probable that animals
have functional systems that perform similar overall functions but which
are not identical. In other words, if it is assumed that conscious
experience is a set of functions then token identity theory is more
probable than type identity theory.
Putnam\'s critique does not preclude identity theories of mind that
involve \"passive ideas\" (i.e.: states that are not classical
functions).
Most identity theories of mind would be representational, the physical
states representing the world in some way. All identity theories of mind
involve Cartesian materialism in the sense of the mental states being
brain states. According to identity theories the mind is in the brain.
Putnam, H. (1967) The nature of mental states. In The Nature of Mind,
edited by Rosenthal, pp. 197--203. Originally published as
\"Psychological predicates in Art, Mind, and Religion\", edited by
Capitan and Merill, pp. 37--48.
## Dualism
Prior to considering the arguments surrounding dualism it is important
to have a clear idea of \"information\" because many of these arguments
have parallels with the difference between information as a set of
states that can be transmitted and the substrate on which this
information is expressed or from which the information is derived. See
Elementary information and information systems
theory.
### Cartesian dualism
Descartes, a philosopher, analysed his experience and developed an
empirical description of how it is arranged. He described mental images
and perceptions as extended in space and with a duration. He called
these extended things **ideas** (Cartesian ideas) and proposed that they
are patterns in the brain. Descartes thought the pineal gland was the
most likely location for these ideas because it is one of the few single
organs in the brain. He also proposed that there is a rational soul that
directly contacts these ideas:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Now among these figures, it is
not those imprinted on the external sense organs, or on the internal
surface of the brain, which should be taken to be ideas - but only those
which are traced in the spirits on the surface of gland H *(where the
seat of the imagination and the \'common sense\' is located)*. That is
to say, it is only the latter figures which should be taken to be the
forms or images which the rational soul united to this machine will
consider directly when it imagines some object or perceives it by the
senses.\" Descartes (1664)`</font>`{=html}
See section on
Descartes
for more information and references.
Descartes considered that the soul was a physical point, an unextended
entity that acts like a mind\'s eye. He called this unextended place the
*res cogitans* and concluded that it was a substance that differed from
that of material things:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\".. I thence concluded that I was
a substance whose whole essence or nature consists only in thinking, and
which, that it may exist, has need of no place, nor is dependent on any
material thing; so that \" I,\" that is to say, the mind by which I am
what I am, is wholly distinct from the body, and is even more easily
known than the latter, and is such, that although the latter were not,
it would still continue to be all that it is.\"Descartes
(1637)`</font>`{=html}
This unextended substance that is not material gives the word
\"substance\" a new meaning. It has been attacked as a concept by Locke,
Hume, Berkely and many other philosophers. The concept of there being
two substances, that which composes the physical world and that which
composes the soul, is the origin of the word **Dualism** but dualism, as
a concept, has been extended beyond this original meaning. Cartesian
dualism is a type of **substance dualism**.
Cartesian dualism is an attempt to explain our experience. According to
Descartes something supernatural would be needed for an unextended
viewing point to exist.
Reid\'s **Natural Dualism** also has a point soul looking at things but
proposes that the things in question are forms in the world rather than
in the brain.
### Property dualism
Another sort of dualism has arisen out of a particular interpretation of
the regress and homunculus arguments. These arguments show that
phenomenal experience is not due entirely to flows from place to place
(i.e.: it is not due to classical processes and functions). Property
dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the appropriate way
(i.e. in the way that living human bodies are organized), mental
properties emerge.
As Goldman (1993) pointed out, qualitative experience does not seem to
be needed in a functional description of a system:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"For any functional description
of a system that is in pain (or has an itch), it seems as if we can
imagine another system with the same functional description but lacking
the qualitative property of painfulness (or itchiness).\"
`</font>`{=html}
Certainly a functional system that merely reports the words \"I am in
pain\" when it is dropped on the floor does not require any qualitative
property of painfulness. The *absent qualia* arguments suggest that even
in a large system there would be no need for qualitative properties for
the performance of any classical function.
Chalmers (1993) commenting on Goldman\'s point, said that this implies
that **zombies** might exist, functional replicas of humans but without
qualia. He then denied that a complete functional replica of a human
could exist without also including qualia:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"It seems to me that the only way
to avoid this conclusion is to deny that Zombie Dave is a conceptual
possibility; and the only principled way to deny that Zombie Dave is a
conceptual possibility is to allow that functional organization is
conceptually constitutive of qualitative content.\" Chalmers
(1993).`</font>`{=html}
In other words he identifies qualia with function. According to Chalmers
(1996) qualia are a particular type of function:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"I claim that conscious
experience arises from fine-grained functional organization. More
specifically, I will argue for a principle of organizational invariance,
holding that given any system that has conscious experiences, then any
system that has the same fine-grained functional organization will have
qualitatively identical experiences. According to this principle,
consciousness is an organizational invariant: a property that remains
constant over all functional isomorphs of a given system. Whether the
organization is realized in silicon chips, in the population of China,
or in beer cans and ping-pong balls does not matter. As long as the
functional organisation is right, conscious experience will be
determined.\" p249`</font>`{=html}
Chalmers\' idea of functional organisation has within it a sometimes
vague implication that the functional units must have a particular form;
for instance, in the development of his argument, he refers to "fine
grained" replacement of organic functional units with inorganic units.
Chalmers is actually making two major points, firstly that qualia occur
during the motion of things (functions), secondly that qualia are
independent of any particular substrate.\*\* For the first point to be
consistent with materialism the qualia must have no effect on the
function, they must be **epiphenomenal**. Epiphenomenal qualia would not
be forbidden by the regress and homunculus arguments and would be akin
to Berkeley\'s \"passive ideas\".
Whether or not epiphenomenal qualia are physical depends upon the
definition of the word \"physical\". If physical functions cause qualia
but qualia cannot affect functions then the qualia are \"physical\" in
the sense of being caused by physical events but might be regarded as
non-physical in the sense of being isolated from further physical
events. In philosophical terms they violate the principle of **Causal
Closure**. However, there are other definitions of physicalism based on
arguments such as **Methodological Naturalism** which hold that anything
that can be investigated using the methods of natural science is a
physical thing (see Stoljar 2001). Thus, although epiphenomenal qualia
may not conform to materialism they may be encompassed by physicalism;
as events that are related to material events they are awaiting a
physical theory of how they emerge from a given function.
The reader might consider whether phenomenal consciousness is indeed
epiphenomenal. Empirical reports describe it as something that is
different from the world beyond the body (see direct
realism) -
could we generate empirical reports of an epiphenomenon?
The term **property dualism** describes how physical events might give
rise to a set of properties that cannot be predicted from the fine
structure of the physical system. The \"dualism\" is present because one
set of events is related to two sets of properties, one of which is not
related by materialism to the set of events. In the case of the proposal
about consciousness outlined above an extra assumption, beyond
materialism, would be needed to explain qualia. Property dualism might
be defined as a theory that there could be a theory of consciousness but
that this requires some new assumption.
As far as the \"when and where\" of consciousness are concerned,
property dualism states that it is somewhere in the processes performed
by the organism and the parts of the organism.
`<font size=1>`{=html} \*\* In terms of information processing, Chalmers
is proposing that qualia are the enactment of a particular information
processing structure.`</font>`{=html}
- Block, N. (2006). Max Black\'s objection to mind-body identity.
Oxford Review of Metaphysics No.3.
<http://philrsss.anu.edu.au/BlockFest/MaxBlack.rtf>
- Chalmers, D.J. (1993) Commentary on \"The Psychology of Folk
Psychology\". Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16:35-36, 1993
- Chalmers, D.J. (1996) \"The Conscious Mind: In Search of a
Fundamental Theory\". Oxford University Press. 1996.
- Goldman, A.I., (1993). The Psychology of Folk Psychology. Behavioral
and Brain Sciences 16: 15-28 (1993).
<http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Papers/Py104/goldman.psyc.html>
### Predicate dualism
Predicate dualism is the view espoused by most non-reductive
physicalists, such as Donald Davidson(1980) and Jerry Fodor(1968), who
maintain that while there is only one ontological category of substances
and properties of substances (usually physical), the predicates that we
use to describe mental events cannot be redescribed in terms of (or
reduced to) physical predicates of natural languages. If we characterize
predicate monism as the view subscribed to by eliminative materialists,
who maintain that such intentional predicates as believe, desire, think,
feel, etc., will eventually be eliminated from both the language of
science and from ordinary language because the entities to which they
refer do not exist, then predicate dualism is most easily defined as the
negation of this position. Predicate dualists believe that so-called
\"folk psychology\", with all of its propositional attitude ascriptions,
is an ineliminable part of the enterprise of describing, explaining and
understanding human mental states and behavior.
Davidson, for example, subscribes to Anomalous Monism, according to
which there can be no strict psycho-physical laws which connect mental
and physical events under their descriptions as mental and physical
events. However, all mental events also have physical descriptions. It
is in terms of the latter that such events can be connected in law-like
relations with other physical events. Mental predicates are irreducibly
different in character (rational, holistic and necessary) from physical
predicates (contingent, atomic and causal).
(Section based on Wikipedia article)
- Davidson, D (1980). Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford University
Press.
- Fodor,J. (1968) *Psychological Explanation*, Random House.
.
### The interaction between mind and brain in dualism
#### Interactionism
Interactionism is the view that mental states, such as beliefs and
desires, causally interact with physical states. This is a position
which is very appealing to common-sense intuitions, notwithstanding the
fact that it is very difficult to establish its validity or correctness
by way of logical argumentation or empirical proof. It is appealing to
common-sense because we are surrounded by such everyday occurrences as a
child\'s touching a hot stove (physical event) which causes him to feel
pain (mental event) and then yell and scream (physical event) which
causes his parents to experience a sensation of fear and protectiveness
(mental event) and so on.
#### Epiphenomalism
According to epiphenomenalism, all mental events are caused by a
physical event and have no physical consequences. So, a mental event of
deciding to pick up a rock (call it \"M\") is caused by the firing of
specific neurons in the brain (call it \"P\"), however when the arm and
hand move to pick up a rock (call it \"E\") this is only caused by P.
The physical causes are in principle reducible to fundamental physics,
and therefore mental causes are eliminated using this reductionist
explanation. If P causes M and E, there is no overdetermination in the
explanation for E.
#### Parallelism
Psycho-physical parallelism is a very unusual view about the interaction
between mental and physical events which was most prominently, and
perhaps only truly, advocated by Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz. Like
Malebranche and others before him, Leibniz recognized the weaknesses of
Descartes\' account of causal interaction taking place in a physical
location in the brain. Malebranche decided that such a material basis of
interaction between material and immaterial was impossible and therefore
formulated his doctrine of occasionalism, stating that the interactions
were really caused by the intervention of God on each individual
occasion. Leibniz idea is that God has created a pre-established harmony
such that it only seems as if physical and mental events cause, and are
caused by, one another. In reality, mental causes only have mental
effects and physical causes only have physical effects. Hence the term
parallelism is used to describe this view.
#### Occasionalism
Occasionalism argues that bodily events are the occasion of an act by
the Creator causing a corresponding mental event, and vice versa. Any
such view requires a theological structure as a premise.
#### Further reading
- Robinson, Howard, \"Dualism\", The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Fall 2003 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2003/entries/dualism/>
- Robinson, H. (2003) \"Dualism\", in S. Stich and T. Warfield (eds)
The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell, Oxford,
85-101.
- Amoroso, R.L. (2010) \"The complementarity of Mind and Body:
Realizing the Dream of Descartes, Einstein and Eccles\", New York:
Nova Science Publishers,
`, ``https://www.novapublishers.com/catalog/product_info.php?products_id=12759`
## Idealism
According to Idealism only the mental truly exists.
The form and content of personal conscious experience might be related
to the structure of the world and brain in several ways. It could be a
**solipsism** or be the mind of God.
*This is a **stub** and needs expansion*.
## Panpsychism
### Etymology
Ancient Greek *pan* (πᾶν : \"all, everything, whole\") and *psyche*
(ψυχή : \"soul, mind\").[^1] Psyche is the from
ψύχω (*psukhō*, \"I blow\") and means mind or \'life-breath\'.
Philip Goff, a proponent of panpsychism, carves out a distinction
between panexperientialism and pancognitivism. Panexperientialism is the
belief that *experience* is ubiquitous, while pancognitivism is the
belief that *cognition* is ubiquitous. Most modern purponents of
panpsychism, such as Annaka Harris and David Chalmers, are careful to
distance themselves from pancognitivism.
In some interpretations, such as monadism, Panpsychism and Idealism can
overlap because the universe is conceived as being composed of an
infinity of point consciousnesses that each contain information about
the whole universe.
The form and content of personal conscious experience might be related
to the structure of the world and brain in many ways.
*This is a **stub** and needs expansion*.
## References
Seager W. & Allen-Hermanson (2001). 'Panpsychism.' Online document:
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, \[online\],
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/panpsychism/>, \[accessed 10/2005\]
**Supervenience**
- Chalmers, D.J. (1996). The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press.
**The problem of regression**
- Ryle, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind. The University of Chicago
Press, 1949.
**The homunculus argument**
- Gregory, R.L. (1990) Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing, Oxford
University Press Inc. New York.
- Gregory, T.L. (1987). The Oxford Companion to Mind. Oxford
University Press.
**Subject-object paradox**
- James, W. (1904)Does \'Consciousness\' Exist? Journal of
Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1,
477-491.
- Hegel, G.W.F. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND: SECTION I. MIND SUBJECTIVE B.
PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND CONSCIOUSNESS Part Three of the Encyclopaedia
of the Philosophical
Sciences
- Velmans, M. (1996) Consciousness and the \"Casual Paradox\".
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 19 (3):
538-542.
- Bermudez, J.L. (1999) The Paradox of Self-Consciousness
(representation and Mind) Psycoloquy:
10,#35
**Ontological status**
- Bierman, D.J. (2004) Non Conscious Processes Preceding Intuitive
decisions
<http://m0134.fmg.uva.nl/~djb/publications/2004/Intuition_bialsymp2004.pdf>
- Damasio, A.R. (1994). Descartes\' error: Emotion, reason and the
human brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam Book.
- Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason
<http://www.arts.cuhk.edu.hk/Philosophy/Kant/cpr/>
**Phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness**
Block, N. (1995) On a confusion about a function of consciousness.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 227-287.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/documents/a/00/00/04/31/bbs00000431-00/bbs.block.html>
Block, N. (2004). *The Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science*.
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/ecs.pdf>
Dennett, D. (1978). Why You Can\'t Make a Computer that Feels Pain, in:
Brainstorms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 190-229.
Dennett, D. (1988). Quining Qualia. in A. Marcel and E. Bisiach, eds,
Consciousness in Modern Science, Oxford University Press 1988. Reprinted
in W. Lycan, ed., Mind and Cognition: A Reader, MIT Press, 1990, A.
Goldman, ed. Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science, MIT Press,
1993. <http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/quinqual.htm>
Edelman, G.M. (1993). Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the
Mind. New York:
Feyerabend, P. (1963). Mental Events and the Brain, Journal of
Philosophy 40:295-6.
Huxley, T. H. (1874). On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and
its History, The Fortnightly Review, n.s.16:555-580. Reprinted in Method
and Results: Essays by Thomas H. Huxley (New York: D. Appleton and
Company, 1898).
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review
LXXXIII, 4 (October 1974): 435-50.
<http://web.archive.org/19990218140703/members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html>
Rey, Georges, (1997). Contemporary Philosophy of Mind.Blackwell: Oxford
Sellars W. (1956). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, In: Feigl H
and Scriven M (eds) The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of
Psychology and Psychoanalysis: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of
Science, Vol. 1. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 253-329
Whitehead, A.N. (1920). The Concept of Nature. Chapter 3: Time.
<http://spartan.ac.brocku.ca/~lward/Whitehead/Whitehead_1920/White1_03.html>
**Direct Realism**
- Austin, J.L. (1962) Sense and Sensibilia, ed. by Geoffrey J. Warnock
(Oxford, 1962)
- Aydede, M. (2001) Naturalism, introspection, and direct realism
about pain. Consciousness and Emotion, Vol. 2, No. 1, 2001,
pp. 29--73.
<http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/maydede/pain.pdf>
- Chapman, C.R., and Y. Nakamura (1999). A Passion of the Soul: An
Introduction to Pain for Consciousness Researchers. Consciousness
and Cognition, 8: 391-422.
- Dennett, D. (1991a). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown
- Dennett, D. (1991b). Lovely and suspect qualities. Commentary on
David Rosenthal, \"The Independence of Consciousness and Sensory
Quality\" in E. Villanueva, ed., Consciousness, (SOFIA Conference,
Buenos Aires), Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview 1991.
<http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/lovely&s.htm>
- Fowler C A (1986): "An event approach to the study of speech
perception from a direct-realist perspective", J of Phonetics
14(1):3-28.
- Gibson, J. J. (1966) The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems.
Houghton Mifflin Company,Boston.
- Gibson, J. J. (1979) Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Hillsdate.
- Gregory, R.L. 1988. Consciousness in science and philosophy:
conscience and con-science. Chapter 12 in Consciousness in
Contemporary Science. (Editors: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E.).
Oxford Science Publications.
- Le Morvan, Pierre (2004). Arguments against direct realism and how
to counter them. *The American Philosophical Quarterly*, *41*(3),
221-234.\] (pdf) <http://www.tcnj.edu/~lemorvan/DR_web.pdf>
- Michaels, C. F. and Carello, C. (1981). Direct Perception. Century
Psychology Series. Prentice-Hall.
. 1981. Download this book at
<http://ione.psy.uconn.edu/~psy254/MC.pdf>
- Oliveira, André L. G. and Oliveira, Luis F. (2002) Toward an
ecological conception of timbre. In Proceedings Auditory Perception
Cognition and Action Meeting 2002, Kansas City.
<http://cogprints.org/2713/>
- Skinner, B. F. Science and Human Behavior . New York: Macmillan,
1953.
- Skinner, B. F. 1971. Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New York: Knopf.
- Skinner, B. F. 1948. Walden Two. New York: Macmillan.
- Tye, M. (2004). ANOTHER LOOK AT REPRESENTATIONALISM ABOUT PAIN.
Consciousness and Emotion 2004, special issue on pain, edited by
Murat Aydede (with replies by M. Aydede, N. Block, B. Maund, and P.
Noordhof
<http://sun.soci.niu.edu/~phildept/MT/RepresentationalismAndPain.pdf>
- Vygotsky, L.S.(1925) Consciousness as a problem in the psychology of
behavior. Undiscovered Vygotsky: Etudes on the pre-history of
cultural-historical psychology (European Studies in the History of
Science and Ideas. Vol. 8), pp. 251--281. Peter Lang Publishing.
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/1925/consciousness.htm>
- Ziff, Paul. \"About Behaviourism.\" Analysis 18 (1958): 132-136.
Quoted by Larry Hauser in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/b/behavior.htm#B>. F. Skinner:
Radical Behaviorism
**Indirect Realism**
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
- Rizzo, M., Nawrot, M. & Zihl, J. (1995). Motion and shape perception
in cerebral akinetopsia.Brain, 118. 1105-1127.
<http://nawrot.psych.ndsu.nodak.edu/Publications/Nawrot.pdf/RizzoNawrotZihl.1995.pdf>
- Russell, B. (1912). Problems of Philosophy. Home University Library.
<http://www.ditext.com/russell/rus1.html>
- Tye, M. (2003) Qualia. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia/#Repqualia>
Further reading:
- Hume, D. (1739). A Treatise of Human Nature.
<http://www.class.uidaho.edu/mickelsen/ToC/hume%20treatise%20ToC.htm>
- Firth, R. (1949) Sense Data and the Percept Theory, Mind, 58 (1949);
59 (1950). (Describes early reasons for rejecting Indirect Realism)
<http://www.ditext.com/firth/spt.html>
- Grush, R. (2000). Self, world and space: The meaning and mechanisms
of ego- and allocentric spatial representation. Brain and Mind
1(1):59-92.
<http://mind.ucsd.edu/papers/sws/sws.html>
[^1]: Clarke, D.S. *Panpsychism: Past and Recent Selected Readings*.
State University of New York Press, 2004. p.1
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Philosophical Problem
## The philosophical problem of phenomenal consciousness
Chalmers (1996) encapsulated the philosophical problem of phenomenal
consciousness, describing it as the *Hard Problem*. The Hard Problem can
be concisely defined as \"how to explain a state of consciousness in
terms of its neurological basis\" Block (2004). A state is an
arrangement of things in space over a period of time. It is possible
that the Hard Problem has not been solved because the concepts of
\"space\", \"time\" and \"things\" are intensely problematic in both
science and philosophy.
Some philosophers have argued that *changes* in state are equivalent to
\"mental states\". That consciousness experience always involves acts,
such as acts of acquaintance (Russell 1912). But what is a succession of
states in the brain or the physical world?
As an extension of the idea of \"acts\" as mental states many
philosophers have argued that the functional description of a system
does not need to contain any reference to qualia within that system.
Such ideas, based on nineteenth century materialism, have been expressed
by Huxley, Ryle, Smart, Goldman and many others. However, although
qualia are not required for classical functions, such as most
computations or servo-control, it is far from clear whether this is true
for all functions. If a function is described as any thing that mediates
a change in state it should be realised that \"change\" itself is not
fully understood in philosophy or science and that some systems, such as
quantum mechanical systems, contain state changes that are far from
understood. It will be seen below that our scientific knowledge is not
yet sufficiently complete to allow the claim that all, or even any,
changes can occur without qualia.
Whether a philosopher or scientist is dualist, materialist or
physicalist they should have some insight into current theories about
the physical world. Certainly, if they are considering the problem of
\"how to explain a state of consciousness in terms of its neurological
basis\" then some idea of a \"neurological basis\" is essential.
The objective of this section is to give an account of the problems of
space, time and content and to describe how these affect the problem of
consciousness.
## Epiphenomenalism and the problem of change
Philosophers have noticed since the time of Leibniz that phenomenal
consciousness does not seem to be required for the brain to produce
action. As an example there are numerous reflexes that can occur without
any awareness that they are happening. In fact it is difficult to think
of any response to a stimulus that requires phenomenal consciousness and
could not, in principle, be performed in the absence of conscious
intervention. T.H. Huxley is often regarded as the originator of the
term **epiphenomenalism** to describe how consciousness seems extraneous
to processes in the materialist interpretation of the world although the
term may have originated in James\' description of Huxley\'s (1874)
ideas.
According to nineteenth century science changes in state cannot explain
the existence of phenomenal consciousness so superficially it may appear
as if phenomenal consciousness is unnecessary. However, it may come as a
shock to the reader to discover that nineteenth century science is also
unable to account for any change in state. In the materialist paradigm
time is construed to be a succession of instants of no duration, each of
which is entirely separate from the others. As a result no instant can
cause a change in another instant. It is not only conscious experience
that is epiphenomenal, each instant of the nineteenth century concept of
the world is epiphenomenal because it cannot give rise to the next
instant.
On the one hand it seems that conscious experience is not required for a
nineteenth century model of behaviour and on the other hand nineteenth
century science seems to be impossible without extraneous input from a
conscious observer who contains the idea of change.
The problem of change is closely related to the problem of time which is
discussed in depth below. (See Change and Inconsistency, Stanford
Encyclopedia of
Philosophy).
The reader might consider whether phenomenal consciousness is indeed
epiphenomenal. Empirical reports describe it as something that is
different from the world beyond the body (see direct
realism) -
but could we generate empirical reports of an epiphenomenon? If we do
indeed generate empirical reports of phenomenal consciousness is there
some non-materialist, physical\*\* connection between phenomenal
consciousness and the functional state?
In the analysis that follows it is essential that the reader does not
dismiss the possibility that conscious experience is largely
non-functional in a classical sense. The idea that observation is not
action should not be dismissed out of hand. Indeed the claim that
something cannot be true if it is \"epiphenomenal\" in a classical sense
is astonishing in the context of modern quantum physics. Everettian
approaches (and offshoots like the Bohmian, Consistent Histories and
operational (decoherence) approaches) to quantum physics all allow that
the classical world is epiphenomenal (cf: Page 1997, Stapp 1998). The
Copenhagen Interpretation, however, was less clear on this issue.
It is curious that problems with the nature of phenomenal consciousness
are also problems with nineteenth century science - Aristotlean regress
in the mind is part of the wider problem of epistemological regress and
epiphenomenalism is part of the wider problem of change. Perhaps
nineteenth century science is not an appropriate foundation for
understanding consciousness.
Recommended reading:
Mortensen, C. (2002) Change. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/change/>
Page, D.N. (1997). Sensible Quantum Mechanics: Are Only Perceptions
Probabilistic? <http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9506010>
Rivas, T., & Dongen, H. van (2003). Exit Epiphenomenalism: The
Demolition of a Refuge
Stapp, (1998). Quantum Ontology and Mind-Matter Synthesis.\[Appeared in
proceedings of X-th Max Born Symposium, eds, Blanchard and Jadczyk, Vol
517 Lecture notes in Physics series, Springer-Verlag, 1999 (Quantum
Future:from Volta and Como to the present and beyond) \]
<http://arxiv.org/PS_cache/quant-ph/pdf/9905/9905053.pdf>
(\*\*) cf: gravity may affect the rate at which clocks tick without the
occurrence of any collisions between particles or anything that can be
called a \"process\".
## The problem of time
*This section should be read after reading a quick introduction to
special
relativity*
### The past century of ideas about time
McTaggart in 1908 set out some of the problems with our idea of time in
his classic paper *The Unreality of Time*. He drew attention to the way
that a sequence of things in a list does not describe time because a
sequence of things is constant yet events are always changing. These
considerations led him to propose that there are three different
sequences of things, or series, that are commonly used to describe
events. McTaggart\'s three different time series are summarized in the
illustration below.
![](constudseries.gif "constudseries.gif")
He argued that only the \'A Series\' is a temporal series because it is
only in the A Series that change occurs so that events can be given the
labels \'future\', \'present\' and \'past\'. He pointed out that
although the A Series is used for determining the direction and sequence
of events it is not itself \'in time\' because it contains relations
that are neither a part of the C Series nor the B Series. This led him
to propose that time is unreal because change involves a movement along
the time series so cannot be fixed within it.
Franck (1994) argued on the basis of Atmanspacher\'s models of universes
with real and imaginary geometries that McTaggart\'s \'unreality\' of
time could be avoided by proposing a second, imaginary, time dimension.
`"What McTaggart in fact demonstrates is that it is impossible to `\
`account for temporality within a strictly one-dimensional concept `\
`of time."(Franck 1994).`
This idea is illustrated below:
![](constudseries2.gif "constudseries2.gif")
This idea of time being two dimensional is not new and has also been
advanced by such luminaries as Hermann Weyl and CD Broad. Weyl (1920)
made the following statement that is extremely apposite to consciousness
studies, he wrote that reality is a:
`"...four-dimensional continuum which is neither 'time' nor 'space'. `\
`Only the consciousness that passes on in one portion of this world `\
`experiences the detached piece which comes to meet it and passes `\
`behind it, as history, that is, as a process that is going forward `\
`in time and takes place in space." (Weyl 1920).`
McTaggart\'s objection to time is felt intuitively by anyone who has
contemplated the *Block Universe* of Relativity Theory. If the universe
is four dimensional with three space dimensions and one time dimension
it would be fixed forever and the observer would be frozen within it.
This would occur whether the time dimension was arranged according to
Galilean Relativity or Modern Relativity.
Peter Lynds in 2003 has drawn attention to the \'frozen\' nature of the
observer in a four dimensional universe. He proposes, like Kevin Brown
in his popular mathpages,
that time must be approached from the viewpoint of quantum physics
because simple four dimensional universes would give rise to \'frozen,
static\' instants and hence no change could occur. Lynds argues that if
quantum physics is introduced then no event can have a definite moment
of occurrence and that change occurs because of this quantum
indeterminacy:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}I would suggest that there is
possibly much more to be gleaned from the connection between quantum
physics and the inherent need for physical continuity, and even go as
far to speculate that the dependent relationship may be the underlying
explanation for quantum jumping and with static indivisible mathematical
time values directly related to the process of quantum collapse. Time
will tell.\"`</font>`{=html}(Lynds 2003).
Our knowledge of quantum uncertainty can be traced back to De Broglie\'s
highly successful model of individual particle motions. This model was
based on Special Relativity theory and it predicted a wave nature for
particles. The Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle can be shown to be a
consequence of this wave nature. See the illustration below:
![](constuddebroglie.gif "constuddebroglie.gif")
The illustration is based on de Broglie (1925) and Pollock (2004).
So Lynds\' argument that change is due to the uncertainty principle is
actually an argument that change is due to differing planes of
simultaneity between systems that are in relative motion. Kevin Brown is
aware of this; he summarises the effect of uncertainty due to special
relativity and points out that it provides a resolution of Zeno\'s arrow
paradox:
`"The theory of special relativity answers Zeno's concern over the `\
`lack of an instantaneous difference between a moving and a non-moving `\
`arrow by positing a fundamental re-structuring the basic way in which `\
`space and time fit together, such that there really is an instantaneous `\
`difference between a moving and a non-moving object, insofar as it `\
`makes sense to speak of "an instant" of a physical system with mutually `\
`moving elements. Objects in relative motion have different planes of `\
`simultaneity, with all the familiar relativistic consequences, so not `\
`only does a moving object look different to the world, but the world `\
`looks different to a moving object." (Brown 19??)`
Another approach to the way that time has a direction is to suggest that
the possible outcomes in quantum mechanics are located in \"disjoint
space-time regions which exclude one another\" (McCall 2000). This does
not explain the A Series however because the observer would not have any
sense of \'becoming\' or temporality as a result of the existence of
regions that could not be observed.
### Presentism and Four-Dimensionalism
In the past century the philosophical battle lines have been drawn
between the Presentists, who believe that only the durationless instant
of the present exists and the Four Dimensionalists who consider that
things are extended in both space and time (see Rea (2004)). There are
two types of Presentism, in its extreme form it is the belief that the
past and future are truly non-existent, that what we call time is not an
axis for arranging things but a series of changes and records in an
*enduring* present. In its less extreme form, which might be called
*functional presentism*, the present is a durationless instant that can
never be connected to the future or past except through predictions and
records.
In consciousness studies it is the conventional theory that brain
activity occurs in the present instant and that the past can only occur
as memories retrieved into this durationless present. So, in
consciousness studies functional Presentism seems to be the accepted
paradigm.
Presentism cannot explain change. Each instant is durationless and
frozen. That said, as seen above, four dimensionalism cannot explain the
observation of change although it can explain the difference between
moving and stationary objects. Fortunately the debate has been largely
resolved by recent scientific experiments which show that time exists
and hence Presentism is unlikely.
### The existence of time
The issue of whether or not time exists is critical to consciousness
studies. If we exist at an instant without duration then how can we know
we exist? Clay (1882) coined the term \'specious present\' to describe
how we seem to exist for a short period containing the immediate past:
\"All the notes of a bar of a song seem to the listener to be contained
in the present. All the changes of place of a meteor seem to the
beholder to be contained in the present. At the instant of the
termination of such series, no part of the time measured by them seems
to be a past. Time, then, considered relatively to human apprehension,
consists of four parts, viz., the obvious past, the specious present,
the real present, and the future.\"
So conscious, phenomenal experience has things that are apparently
extended in time. But does time exist?
Recent experiments in quantum physics should change our view of time
forever. Lindner *et al.* (2005) have explored the problem of time by
investigating quantum interference between interferometer slits that are
separated by time rather than space.
In the famous, spatial \'double slit experiment\' in quantum physics
single electrons are directed at an apparatus that has the equivalent of
two tiny slits separated by a small gap. The electrons pass through the
apparatus one at a time and produce flashes of light on a screen or
changes in a photographic plate. The electrons produce series of bands
on the screen that are typical of interference effects. So each electron
is deflected as if it has passed through both slits and interfered with
itself.
![](constudtwinslit.gif "constudtwinslit.gif")
This experiment provided some of the earliest evidence for the
wave-packet nature of the electron.
In an amazing technical tour de force Lindner *et al.* (2005) have
extended the idea of the spatial double slit experiment to an
investigation of time. In the double slit experiment in time electrons
are produced in an inert gas by extremely short laser pulses. The pulses
stimulate a single atom and there is a probability of this atom
releasing an electron at each oscillation of the pulse. The apparatus is
described by Paulus *et al.* (2003). The probability (see note 1) of an
electron being ejected to the left or right of the apparatus can be
adjusted by adjusting the optical pulse. Pulses can be applied with a
duration of a few femtoseconds and these create \'slits\' extending over
an interval of about 500 attoseconds (500 x 10-18 seconds). A single
electron has a probability of being emitted at each of the slits. The
probability of the single electron going in a particular direction after
both slits have been created depends upon the interaction of the
probabilities of being emitted in a particular direction at each single
slit. As expected, an interference pattern was generated as a result of
single electrons interfering with themselves across different times.
![](constudtimeslit.gif "constudtimeslit.gif")
This experiment is remarkable because it provides direct evidence that
time exists in a similar fashion to the way that space exists. It is
consistent with Feynman\'s theory of Quantum Electrodynamics where all
possible paths, both in time and space, interact to produce the final
trajectory of a particle and consistent with modern Special Relativity,
on which QED is based, where the trajectories of particles occur in an
extended four dimensional space-time.
The experiment has not attracted as much attention as it might have done
because most physicists are not Presentists. To physicists the
experiment is yet another confirmation of modern physics. However it has
impressed many:
\"This experiment should be included in every textbook on quantum
mechanics,\" says Wolfgang Schleich, a quantum physicist at the
University of Ulm in Germany. \"It certainly will be in mine.\"
(PhysicsWeb)
Why should a concrete demonstration that time exists affect
consciousness studies? The simple answer is that, as Kant, Gombrich,
Clay, James and many others have spotted, there can be no conscious,
phenomenal experience without time. The fact that time exists should
provide new insights and liberate theorists in the field of
consciousness studies from the problems of recursion and regression that
are inherent in Presentism.
Meanwhile Quantum Theorists are pressing on with the problem of how an
organised spacetime could emerge from quantum chaos (cf: Ambjorn *et
al.* (2004)) and even how mind might be involved in the emergence of
time itself (cf: Romer (2004)).
### The nature of time
#### The nature of classical time
In the eighteenth century it became apparent that Euclid\'s parallel
postulate could not be explained in terms of the other postulates. The
parallel postulate is equivalent to the statement that exactly one line
can be drawn through any point not on a given line in such a way that it
is parallel to the given line (this is Playfair\'s simple version). It
is also known as the fifth postulate.
The attempts to prove the parallel postulate led to the development of
non-Euclidean geometry. It was then possible to show that the parallel
postulate is a special case within a range of geometrical forms from
spherical geometry, through Euclidean geometry to the hyperbolic
geometry of Bolyai and Lobatschefsky. Furthermore it was shown by
Taurinus that the axioms of Euclidean geometry, with the exception of
the fifth postulate, applied on the surface of a sphere with an
imaginary radius. This motivated Hermann Minkowski to propose that
Einstein\'s new theory of relativity was in fact due to the universe
being a \'space-time\' with four dimensions rather than just a space in
which things change (see Walter 1999). In 1909 Minkowski said that:
`"Henceforth space by itself and time by itself, are doomed to fade `\
`away into mere shadows, and only a kind of union of the two will `\
`preserve an independent reality". (Minkowski 1909).`
The earliest idea of the four dimensional universe involved time as an
axis with displacements measured in units of the square root of minus
one (cf: Einstein (1920)): time was considered to be displacements along
the imaginary plane. However, from the moment of Minkowski\'s proposal
mathematicians were aware that other interpretations of time could give
almost identical physical results.
According to the differential geometry developed during the nineteenth
century a space is defined in terms of a *metric tensor* which is a
matrix of factors that determine how displacements in each independent
direction vary with displacements in the other directions. The metric
tensor then specifies a *metric* which is an equation that describes the
length of a displacement in any direction in terms of the independent
directions, or *dimensions*.
A derivation of the metric tensor and how it can be used to calculate
the metric is given in the /Appendix/.
The metric of the space considered by Euclid is Pythagoras\' theorem
where the length of any displacement is given in terms of the
displacements along the three independent axes, or dimensions:
$s^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2$
It is interesting to explore *imaginary time* from the point of view of
consciousness studies. Minkowski\'s original idea for the geometry of
the world proposed that any displacement was a displacement in both time
and space given by a four dimensional version of Pythagoras\' theorem:
$s^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2 + (ict)^2$
which, given that $i^2 = -1$ equals:
$s^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2 - (ct)^2$
Where *i* is the square root of minus one, *c* is a constant for
converting metres to seconds and t is the displacement in time. The
space-time is considered to be flat and all displacements are measured
from the origin.
The interesting feature of Minkowski space-time with imaginary time is
that displacements in time can *subtract* from displacements in space.
If we set $r^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2$ (where *r* is the radius of a sphere
around the origin then:
$s^2 = r^2 - (ct)^2$
Notice that $s^2 = 0$ when $r^2 = (ct)^2$ so if imaginary time existed
there would be times and separations within a spherical volume of things
where **everything is at a point as well as distributed in space**. This
idea has distinct similarites with the *res cogitans* mentioned by
Descartes, and the *point soul* of Reid and Malebranche etc., however,
this feature of Minkowski\'s space-time has not been popular with
physicists for some good reasons. Blandford and Thorne point out some of
the problems:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html} One approach, often used in
elementary textbooks \[and also used in Goldstein\'s (1980) Classical
Mechanics and in the first edition of Jackson\'s Classical
Electrodynamics\], is to set $x^0 = it$, where $i = \sqrt{-1}$ and
correspondingly make the time basis vector be imaginary,\... When this
approach is adopted, the resulting formalism does not care whether
indices are placed up or down; one can place them wherever one\'s
stomach or liver dictate without asking one\'s brain. However, this
$x^0 = it$ approach has severe disadvantages: (i) it hides the true
physical geometry of Minkowski spacetime, (ii) it cannot be extended in
any reasonable manner to non-orthonormal bases in flat spacetime, and
(iii) it cannot be extended in any reasonable manner to the curvilinear
coordinates that one must use in general relativity. For this reason,
most advanced texts \[including the second and third editions of Jackson
(1999)\] and all general relativity texts take an alternative approach,
which we also adopt in this book. This alternative approach requires
introducing two different types of components for vectors, and
analogously for tensors: contravariant components denoted by
superscripts, and covariant components denoted by
subscripts.\"`</font>`{=html} Blandford & Thorne (2004).
What Blandford and Thorne are saying is that the metric of space-time
appears to be the result of the interaction of two coordinate systems
and cannot be explained by a single coordinate system with imaginary
time. When a more complicated geometrical analysis is applied it is
evident that there are two possibilities for the time coordinate. In the
first the metric can be **assumed** from the outset to be
$s^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2 - (ct)^2$
and the metric tensor simply adjusted by inserting -1 in the principle
diagonal so that the negative sign in front of the time coordinate
occurs. With this assumption and adjustment the time coordinate can be
assumed to be *real*. In the second possibility the time coordinate in
the world can be assumed to be imaginary and the time coordinate of the
observer can be assumed to be real. This gives rise to the same metric
tensor and metric as the first possibility but does not assume the
resulting metric from the outset.
The three ideas of classical time (imaginary, real and mixed) are shown
in the illustration below:
![](constudclasstime.gif "constudclasstime.gif")
The light cone is divided into three regions: events on the surface of
the light cone, such as photons converging on the observer, are said to
be *lightlike* separated from the observer, events inside the future or
past light cones are said to be *timelike separated* and events outside
the lightcone are said to be *spacelike* separated from the observer.
The physical **theory of relativity** consists of four dimensional
geometry plus the assumption of causality and the assumption that
physical laws are invariant between observers. It should be noted that
space-time could contain preferred frames of reference and is not, by
itself, a theory of relativity. The assumption that physical laws are
invariant between observers leads to the postulate that nothing can
travel faster than *c* metres per second. This means that the constant
*c*, which in Minkowski space-time is the conversion factor from seconds
to metres then has a new significance as the maximum velocity.
A result of *c* being a maximum velocity is that nothing can travel from
regions of the light cone that are spacelike separated to the observer
at coordinates (0,0,0,0). This is problematic for observers if time is
real because, as Stein (1968) wrote:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}"in Einstein-Minkowski space-time
an event\'s present is constituted by itself alone." `</font>`{=html}
(Stein 1968).
However, to each of us it seems that the present is characterised by
*many* things simultaneously. As will be discussed below, this
simultaneity of present things also results in the appearance of
phenomenal space. But in Minkowski space-time with real time the plane
of simultaneity is entirely space-like separated from the observation
point. If real time is accepted it would appear that we cannot have the
space of phenomenal experience. The regions of the light-cone and the
spacelike separation of present events are shown in the illustration
below:
![](Constudcone.gif "Constudcone.gif")
So can the time in Minkowski space-time be real? If time were in some
way related to the imaginary plane then all the content of the surface
of the light cone could be simultaneously at the position of the
observer and phenomenal experience containing space is possible, but
then general relativity may be problematic. So can the time in Minkowski
space-time be imaginary?
There is another problem with Minkowski space-time known as the
\"Rietdijk-Putnam-Penrose\" argument or the Andromeda paradox (Penrose
1989). Moving observers have different planes of simultaneity. The plane
of simultaneity of an observer moving towards you slopes upward relative
to your plane of simultaneity (see the illustration on \"De Broglie
waves\" above). Suppose an alien civilisation in the Andromeda galaxy
decided to launch a fleet of spacecraft intent on the invasion of earth
just as you passed Jim in your car. Your plane of simultaneity would
slope upwards ever so slightly compared with Jim\'s, Jim\'s plane of
simultaneity could contain earlier events on Andromeda than yours. At
the distance of the Andromeda galaxy it could be another week or two for
the Andromedean\'s to launch their invasion fleet in Jim\'s slice of the
universe. Penrose considers that this example shows that the events in
the universe must be fixed:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Two people pass each other on
the street; and according to one of the two people, an Andromedean space
fleet has already set off on its journey, while to the other, the
decision as to whether or not the journey will actually take place has
not yet been made. How can there still be some uncertainty as to the
outcome of that decision? If to either person the decision has already
been made, then surely there cannot be any uncertainty. The launching of
the space fleet is an inevitability.\"`</font>`{=html} (Penrose 1989).
If the decision to invade and a time previous to this decision are both
part of the present instant on earth then, in a 4D classical universe,
the decision to invade must be inevitable. This lack of free will in a
4D universe is known as chronogeometrical determinism (Toretti 1983).
However, as de Broglie demonstrated, it is sloping planes of
simultaneity that do indeed introduce uncertainty into our universe. It
should also be noted that nothing on the plane of simultaneity is
observable to the owner of that plane because, to observe it would
involve the transmission of data at velocities greater than the speed of
light.
Petkov (2002)considers a version of the Andromeda paradox in depth. He
concludes that:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"If the relativity of
simultaneity is explicitly discussed in terms of the dimensionality of
reality, the fact that observers in relative motion have different sets
of simultaneous events can be explained either by assuming that
existence is also relativized (preserving the views of the present and
objective becoming) or by considering existence absolute which means
that reality is a 4D world. Although the option of relativizing
existence appears completely unacceptable from a philosophical point of
view, that option is eliminated within the framework of SR by
demonstrating that the twin paradox would not be possible if existence
were not absolute.\"`</font>`{=html}
According to Petkov Special Relativity describes the universe as a
frozen space-time where things are eternally arranged in four
dimensions. Petkov introduces the possibility of change as a feature of
consciousness and in support of this quotes Weyl\'s intuition that only
the conscious observer moves in time.
## Relationalism, Substantivalism, the Hole Argument and General Covariance
### Relationalism and Substantivalism
The view that the universe could be an extended space and time with
things in it, a sort of unbounded container, is known as
**substantivalism**. It was championed by Newton and Clarke in the
seventeenth century. The view that the space and time in the universe
depends upon the relations between the objects in the universe is known
as **relationalism** and was championed by Leibniz.
Leibniz attacked substantivalism by arguing that if there were two
universes which only differed by things in one universe being displaced
by five feet compared with things in the other universe then there is no
reason why the two universes should be discernably different.
Newton supported substantivalism by arguing that when the water in a
bucket rotates it adopts a concave surface that is independent of other
motions and provides evidence of the possibility of absolute motion.
This argument is called the *bucket argument*. Newton also introduces
the *globe argument* in which he proposes that the state of motion of
two globes connected by a taut thread can be gauged from the tension in
the thread alone. When the globes are stationary with respect to each
other there is no tension in the thread.
Ernst Mach in 1893 introduced a relationalist account of the bucket
argument by claiming that the water rotates in relation to the fixed
stars. He stated this in what has become known as Mach\'s principle:
\"The inertia of any system is the result of the interaction of that
system and the rest of the universe. In other words, every particle in
the universe ultimately has an effect on every other particle.\"
The relationalist position is interesting from the viewpoint of
consciousness studies because phenomenal consciousness appears as a
projection that overlies physical space. As an example, the stars on the
ceiling of a planetarium appear to be at huge distances from the
observer even though they are reflected lights that are only a few
metres away. In general a projection where positions depend upon angular
separations will be subject to relationalism. It is also probable that
the space of phenomenal consciousness is a continuum of some field in
the brain, if this is the case then the way we conceive of space as an
existent entity is actually a conception involving the angular relations
between the perturbations of the substance that is the field.
Substantivalism would then literally be space as a substance. It is
intriguing in this respect that Kant believed that space was a form of
intuition and hence a property of mind.
Kant raised another type of argument for the justification of absolute
space. He asked whether *handedness* was due to relations or a property
of space. The right and left hands are enantiomorphs (mirror images).
The relations within the right and left hands are identical but they
still differ, for instance a right hand cannot be moved on to a left
hand so that it exactly overlies it. Kant proposed that handedness was
property inherent in space itself rather than a set of relations.
Gardner introduced a version of Kant\'s problem with the \"Ozma\"
argument: \"Is there any way to communicate the meaning of the word
\"left\" by a language transmitted in the form of pulsating signals? By
the terms of the problem we may say anything we please to our listeners,
ask them to perform any experiment whatever, with one proviso: there is
to be no asymmetric object or structure that we and they can observe in
common.\" (Gardner 1990).
Although it is probably impossible to provide an answer to the Ozma
argument it is possible to relate handedness to a conceptual point
observer who spans more than an instant of time. If a point observer is
at the centre of a field of inward pointing space-time vectors then
relative to any given vector there are positive and negative angular
separations. The body is asymmetric and the point observer would lie
within this so always have available a \'head\' direction or a \'foot
direction\' and hence a left and right. Unlike the time extended
observer an instantaneous observer would not contain vectors that
contained directional information and would be no more than a collection
of points in space.
Pooley (2002) discusses handedness in depth and introduces the problem
of parity violation in the Weak Interaction.
### General Covariance and the Hole Argument
The proposal that the universe is four dimensional does not in itself
produce a full physical theory. The assumptions of causality and the
invariance of physical laws between observers are also required to
create modern Relativity Theory. The second assumption, that the laws of
physics are the same for all observers is closely related to the
requirement of **general covariance**.
The principle of general covariance requires that a manifold of events
can be smoothly mapped to another manifold of the same dimension and
back again. This mapping should always give the same result. General
covariance is assumed in General Relativity.
Einstein realised that there was an apparent problem with this
assumption in certain circumstances. In his **hole argument** he
considers a special region of space-time that is devoid of matter and
where the stress-energy tensor vanishes. He then labels the same events
outside the hole with two different coordinate systems. These coordinate
systems could differ by something as simple as having origins that are
separate so the difference is entirely passive. Both systems will give
the same values for the gravitational field outside the hole. It turns
out however that that the systems predict different fields within the
hole (see MacDonald (2001) for the calculation and Norton (1993), (1999)
for a discussion). Einstein overcame this problem by considering active
mappings where particles are actually transferred through the hole. He
concluded that the points where particles meet can be transformed
according to general covariance and hence a relativistic theory could
indeed be constructed. Solutions to the field equations that were
inconsistent with the points defined by interacting particles were
discarded as non-physical.
The hole argument led Einstein to abandon the idea of space and time as
something separate from the material content of the universe. The
General Theory of Relativity becomes a theory of **observables**. He
wrote that:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"That the requirement of general
covariance, which takes away from space and time the last remnant of
physical objectivity, is a natural one, will be seen from the following
reflection. All our space-time verifications invariably amount to a
determination of space-time coincidences. If, for example, events
consisted merely in the motion of material points, then ultimately
nothing would be observable but the meetings of two or more of these
points. Moreover, the results of our measurings are nothing but
verifications of such meetings of the material points of our measuring
instruments with other material points, coincidences between the hands
of the a clock and points on the clock dial, and observed point-events
happening at the same place at the same time. The introduction of a
system of reference serves no other purpose than to facilitate the
description of the totality of such coincidences\".`</font>`{=html}
(Einstein 1916).
This is what would be expected from a four dimensional block universe
with real time. It is a frozen universe of the type discussed earlier.
As Earman (2002) puts it when discussing change:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"First, the roots of the problem
lie in classical GTR, and even if it was decided that it is a mistake to
quantize GTR, there would remain the problem of reconciling the frozen
dynamics of GTR with the B-series notion of change that is supported not
only by common sense but by every physical theory prior to GTR. Second,
although the aspect of the problem that grabs attention is that of time
and change, no solution will be forthcoming without tackling the more
general issue of what an "observable" of classical GTR
is.\"`</font>`{=html}
In such a universe action at a distance is not possible. From the
viewpoint of consciousness studies the limitation of physical concepts
to interactions between particles is a restatement of Ryle\'s regress
and the recursion version of the homunculus problem. If events are no
more than space-time coincidences then we are doomed to the endless
transfer of data from point to point without any conscious observation.
This seems to forbid any true simultaneity in experience and means that
only measurements are possible.
The reduction of physics to the study of particle interactions is fully
relationalist and allows space-time to become a property of these
interactions rather than vice-versa. Once it becomes possible to
consider space-time as a dependent property it is then feasible to
equate *observation* with *measurement*. Observation is normally the
representation of an event in an observer\'s space-time coordinate
system. Measurement is the change in state of a system in response to an
encounter with an event. If we maintain that space-time does not exist
and can be replaced by encounters between particles then observation can
be replaced by measurement. This may well be a way forward for some
approximations to physical reality and may allow us to understand how a
space-time is selected within an observer. As part of this approach the
word \"observable\" is often used interchangeably with \"measurable\".
## Quantum theory and time
### The general problem of QM and time
Quantum physics provides many fundamental insights into the nature of
time. At the simplest level the energy-time version of the Heisenberg
Uncertainty Principle predicts that Quantum Mechanical (QM) interference
should occur between a particle and earlier versions of itself. Such
interference has been observed (see \"The existence of time\" above).
Two of the most complete reviews of the problem of time in quantum
theory available at present are Zeh (2001) and Isham (1993).
Perhaps the most interesting aspect of QM and time is that it can
provide an argument that time does not exist in the universe as a whole.
The argument can be approached from many directions (See Rovelli 2003)
but is clear in the Wheeler-de Witt equation which describes the
wavefunction of the entire universe. This wavefunction has no reference
to time. De Witt explained the emergence of time by proposing that the
universe can be divided into an observer with measuring instruments and
the rest of the universe so that the rest of the universe changes with
respect to the observer.
Rovelli (2003) supports this idea of partition, he considers in depth
the problems of the \"hole argument\" and quantum physics and notes
that, given the assumption that events are just successions of
relations:
\"`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}The unique account of the state
of the world of the classical theory is thus shattered into a
multiplicity of accounts, one for each possible \"observing\" physical
system. Quantum mechanics is a theory about the physical description of
physical systems relative to other systems, and this is a complete
description of the world.`</font>`{=html} (Rovelli 2003).
Barbour (1997) and Hartle and Gell-Mann have both proposed that an
observer is a partition or region with memories that contain the trace
of histories. The histories would represent a B Series. Unfortunately
this leaves the A Series unexplained so time would have a direction but
there would be no \'becoming\'.
Hawking introduces the observer into the problem of time by asking what
sort of universe is compatible with human life. This application of the
**Anthropic Principle** leads to constraints on the form of the
universe, for instance the universe should have galaxies and last for
more than a few million years. The Anthropic Principle is actually a
restatement of the observer problem - if being an observer leads to a
certain division of the universe into observer and observed then the
observed part will have the form given by the Anthropic Principle.
Hartle and Hawking () also tackled the \"boundary problem\" of cosmology
by proposing that there is no boundary. This proposal involves adding a
fifth, time-like, dimension on the imaginary plane so that the universe
at its beginning is a **de Sitter** or **anti de Sitter** space-time.
A de Sitter space-time is characterised by the metric:
$ds^2 = dx^2 + dy^2 + dz^2 + (idt)^2 + du^2$
An anti de Sitter space time has the metric:
$ds^2 = dx^2 + dy^2 + dz^2 + (idt)^2 - du^2$
A de Sitter space time is fascinating from the view point of
consciousness studies because it contains three space-like dimensions,
one real, time-like dimension (u) and one imaginary time-like dimension.
This might give the real and imaginary time-like axes that Franck
proposed were needed to produce the McTaggart A Series. However, the
extra dimension could only be related to the observer in the universe as
it is at present because the extra dimension does not appear to be
required to explain measurables.
### The interpretation of QM
Time is also of interest in the interpretation of quantum mechanics and
entanglement. There are many interpretations of QM such as the
**Operational Interpretation** (Decoherence Theory), the **Transactional
Interpretation**, the **Relational Interpretation**, the **Many Worlds
Interpretation**, the **Copenhagen Interpretation**, the **Bohm
Interpretation**, the **Many Minds Interpretation** etc.
Some of these interpretations, such as the Transactional Interpretation,
allow the connection of entangled quantum states backwards in time along
the path of particles.
Decoherence theory is of particular interest because it allows the
calculation of how long an entangled state can persist. Tegmark (2000)
and Hagan *et al.* (2002) have used this technique to calculate the
decoherence time of entanglement in microtubules and have differed by a
factor of $10^{10}$ because of differing assumptions about the
biophysics of microtubules in the brain.
## Time and conscious experience
In a four dimensional universe time is an independent direction for
arranging things. As an independent direction things arranged in time do
not overlie things arranged in space. This also appears to be the case
in conscious experience where whole words or \"bars of a tune\" can be
experienced arranged in time. This extension in time is easy to
experience but the independence of the time dimension is difficult to
conceive, for instance Le Poidevin (2000) reflects that:
> \"If events e1 and e2 are registered in a single specious present,
> then we perceive them both as present, and so as simultaneous. But we
> do not see, e.g., the successive positions of a moving object as
> simultaneous, for if we did we would see a blurred object and not a
> moving one.\"
This assumes that arrangements in time do not occur in an independent
direction for arranging things and hence would overlay space. In fact
the mystery of conscious experience is deeply related to how we can
experience many things as events that are separate from each other. Our
experience of two dimensional patterns containing many things is as much
a mystery as how we experience temporal patterns extended in time. The
problem is illustrated below:
![](constudsimevent.gif "constudsimevent.gif")
It is as if patterns in conscious experience are being viewed from a
point in at least four dimensions. How our experience can be like the
\'view\' of a conceptual point observer at the apex of a light cone
without the data being overlaid and obscured is a profound mystery,
obviously the data cannot be transferred into the apparent observation
point and appears as nebulous vectors directed at the point. Some
philosophers have noticed this problem.
(*This is a stub, requires an elaboration of Specious Present Theory and
Husserl\'s ideas*)
Le Poidevin (2000). The experience and perception of time. Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu//archives/spr2001/entries/time-experience/#4>
Readers who are unfamiliar with the developments to Newtonian mechanics
that occurred in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries should read
Consciousness Studies/The Philosophical
Problem/Appendixs
See
overleaf
for the philosophical problem continued..:
## The problems of space, qualia, machine and digital consciousness
Click on the above link.
## Notes and References
More\...
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Philosophical Problem#The philosophical problem
## The philosophical problem of phenomenal consciousness
Chalmers (1996) encapsulated the philosophical problem of phenomenal
consciousness, describing it as the *Hard Problem*. The Hard Problem can
be concisely defined as \"how to explain a state of consciousness in
terms of its neurological basis\" Block (2004). A state is an
arrangement of things in space over a period of time. It is possible
that the Hard Problem has not been solved because the concepts of
\"space\", \"time\" and \"things\" are intensely problematic in both
science and philosophy.
Some philosophers have argued that *changes* in state are equivalent to
\"mental states\". That consciousness experience always involves acts,
such as acts of acquaintance (Russell 1912). But what is a succession of
states in the brain or the physical world?
As an extension of the idea of \"acts\" as mental states many
philosophers have argued that the functional description of a system
does not need to contain any reference to qualia within that system.
Such ideas, based on nineteenth century materialism, have been expressed
by Huxley, Ryle, Smart, Goldman and many others. However, although
qualia are not required for classical functions, such as most
computations or servo-control, it is far from clear whether this is true
for all functions. If a function is described as any thing that mediates
a change in state it should be realised that \"change\" itself is not
fully understood in philosophy or science and that some systems, such as
quantum mechanical systems, contain state changes that are far from
understood. It will be seen below that our scientific knowledge is not
yet sufficiently complete to allow the claim that all, or even any,
changes can occur without qualia.
Whether a philosopher or scientist is dualist, materialist or
physicalist they should have some insight into current theories about
the physical world. Certainly, if they are considering the problem of
\"how to explain a state of consciousness in terms of its neurological
basis\" then some idea of a \"neurological basis\" is essential.
The objective of this section is to give an account of the problems of
space, time and content and to describe how these affect the problem of
consciousness.
## Epiphenomenalism and the problem of change
Philosophers have noticed since the time of Leibniz that phenomenal
consciousness does not seem to be required for the brain to produce
action. As an example there are numerous reflexes that can occur without
any awareness that they are happening. In fact it is difficult to think
of any response to a stimulus that requires phenomenal consciousness and
could not, in principle, be performed in the absence of conscious
intervention. T.H. Huxley is often regarded as the originator of the
term **epiphenomenalism** to describe how consciousness seems extraneous
to processes in the materialist interpretation of the world although the
term may have originated in James\' description of Huxley\'s (1874)
ideas.
According to nineteenth century science changes in state cannot explain
the existence of phenomenal consciousness so superficially it may appear
as if phenomenal consciousness is unnecessary. However, it may come as a
shock to the reader to discover that nineteenth century science is also
unable to account for any change in state. In the materialist paradigm
time is construed to be a succession of instants of no duration, each of
which is entirely separate from the others. As a result no instant can
cause a change in another instant. It is not only conscious experience
that is epiphenomenal, each instant of the nineteenth century concept of
the world is epiphenomenal because it cannot give rise to the next
instant.
On the one hand it seems that conscious experience is not required for a
nineteenth century model of behaviour and on the other hand nineteenth
century science seems to be impossible without extraneous input from a
conscious observer who contains the idea of change.
The problem of change is closely related to the problem of time which is
discussed in depth below. (See Change and Inconsistency, Stanford
Encyclopedia of
Philosophy).
The reader might consider whether phenomenal consciousness is indeed
epiphenomenal. Empirical reports describe it as something that is
different from the world beyond the body (see direct
realism) -
but could we generate empirical reports of an epiphenomenon? If we do
indeed generate empirical reports of phenomenal consciousness is there
some non-materialist, physical\*\* connection between phenomenal
consciousness and the functional state?
In the analysis that follows it is essential that the reader does not
dismiss the possibility that conscious experience is largely
non-functional in a classical sense. The idea that observation is not
action should not be dismissed out of hand. Indeed the claim that
something cannot be true if it is \"epiphenomenal\" in a classical sense
is astonishing in the context of modern quantum physics. Everettian
approaches (and offshoots like the Bohmian, Consistent Histories and
operational (decoherence) approaches) to quantum physics all allow that
the classical world is epiphenomenal (cf: Page 1997, Stapp 1998). The
Copenhagen Interpretation, however, was less clear on this issue.
It is curious that problems with the nature of phenomenal consciousness
are also problems with nineteenth century science - Aristotlean regress
in the mind is part of the wider problem of epistemological regress and
epiphenomenalism is part of the wider problem of change. Perhaps
nineteenth century science is not an appropriate foundation for
understanding consciousness.
Recommended reading:
Mortensen, C. (2002) Change. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/change/>
Page, D.N. (1997). Sensible Quantum Mechanics: Are Only Perceptions
Probabilistic? <http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9506010>
Rivas, T., & Dongen, H. van (2003). Exit Epiphenomenalism: The
Demolition of a Refuge
Stapp, (1998). Quantum Ontology and Mind-Matter Synthesis.\[Appeared in
proceedings of X-th Max Born Symposium, eds, Blanchard and Jadczyk, Vol
517 Lecture notes in Physics series, Springer-Verlag, 1999 (Quantum
Future:from Volta and Como to the present and beyond) \]
<http://arxiv.org/PS_cache/quant-ph/pdf/9905/9905053.pdf>
(\*\*) cf: gravity may affect the rate at which clocks tick without the
occurrence of any collisions between particles or anything that can be
called a \"process\".
## The problem of time
*This section should be read after reading a quick introduction to
special
relativity*
### The past century of ideas about time
McTaggart in 1908 set out some of the problems with our idea of time in
his classic paper *The Unreality of Time*. He drew attention to the way
that a sequence of things in a list does not describe time because a
sequence of things is constant yet events are always changing. These
considerations led him to propose that there are three different
sequences of things, or series, that are commonly used to describe
events. McTaggart\'s three different time series are summarized in the
illustration below.
![](constudseries.gif "constudseries.gif")
He argued that only the \'A Series\' is a temporal series because it is
only in the A Series that change occurs so that events can be given the
labels \'future\', \'present\' and \'past\'. He pointed out that
although the A Series is used for determining the direction and sequence
of events it is not itself \'in time\' because it contains relations
that are neither a part of the C Series nor the B Series. This led him
to propose that time is unreal because change involves a movement along
the time series so cannot be fixed within it.
Franck (1994) argued on the basis of Atmanspacher\'s models of universes
with real and imaginary geometries that McTaggart\'s \'unreality\' of
time could be avoided by proposing a second, imaginary, time dimension.
`"What McTaggart in fact demonstrates is that it is impossible to `\
`account for temporality within a strictly one-dimensional concept `\
`of time."(Franck 1994).`
This idea is illustrated below:
![](constudseries2.gif "constudseries2.gif")
This idea of time being two dimensional is not new and has also been
advanced by such luminaries as Hermann Weyl and CD Broad. Weyl (1920)
made the following statement that is extremely apposite to consciousness
studies, he wrote that reality is a:
`"...four-dimensional continuum which is neither 'time' nor 'space'. `\
`Only the consciousness that passes on in one portion of this world `\
`experiences the detached piece which comes to meet it and passes `\
`behind it, as history, that is, as a process that is going forward `\
`in time and takes place in space." (Weyl 1920).`
McTaggart\'s objection to time is felt intuitively by anyone who has
contemplated the *Block Universe* of Relativity Theory. If the universe
is four dimensional with three space dimensions and one time dimension
it would be fixed forever and the observer would be frozen within it.
This would occur whether the time dimension was arranged according to
Galilean Relativity or Modern Relativity.
Peter Lynds in 2003 has drawn attention to the \'frozen\' nature of the
observer in a four dimensional universe. He proposes, like Kevin Brown
in his popular mathpages,
that time must be approached from the viewpoint of quantum physics
because simple four dimensional universes would give rise to \'frozen,
static\' instants and hence no change could occur. Lynds argues that if
quantum physics is introduced then no event can have a definite moment
of occurrence and that change occurs because of this quantum
indeterminacy:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}I would suggest that there is
possibly much more to be gleaned from the connection between quantum
physics and the inherent need for physical continuity, and even go as
far to speculate that the dependent relationship may be the underlying
explanation for quantum jumping and with static indivisible mathematical
time values directly related to the process of quantum collapse. Time
will tell.\"`</font>`{=html}(Lynds 2003).
Our knowledge of quantum uncertainty can be traced back to De Broglie\'s
highly successful model of individual particle motions. This model was
based on Special Relativity theory and it predicted a wave nature for
particles. The Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle can be shown to be a
consequence of this wave nature. See the illustration below:
![](constuddebroglie.gif "constuddebroglie.gif")
The illustration is based on de Broglie (1925) and Pollock (2004).
So Lynds\' argument that change is due to the uncertainty principle is
actually an argument that change is due to differing planes of
simultaneity between systems that are in relative motion. Kevin Brown is
aware of this; he summarises the effect of uncertainty due to special
relativity and points out that it provides a resolution of Zeno\'s arrow
paradox:
`"The theory of special relativity answers Zeno's concern over the `\
`lack of an instantaneous difference between a moving and a non-moving `\
`arrow by positing a fundamental re-structuring the basic way in which `\
`space and time fit together, such that there really is an instantaneous `\
`difference between a moving and a non-moving object, insofar as it `\
`makes sense to speak of "an instant" of a physical system with mutually `\
`moving elements. Objects in relative motion have different planes of `\
`simultaneity, with all the familiar relativistic consequences, so not `\
`only does a moving object look different to the world, but the world `\
`looks different to a moving object." (Brown 19??)`
Another approach to the way that time has a direction is to suggest that
the possible outcomes in quantum mechanics are located in \"disjoint
space-time regions which exclude one another\" (McCall 2000). This does
not explain the A Series however because the observer would not have any
sense of \'becoming\' or temporality as a result of the existence of
regions that could not be observed.
### Presentism and Four-Dimensionalism
In the past century the philosophical battle lines have been drawn
between the Presentists, who believe that only the durationless instant
of the present exists and the Four Dimensionalists who consider that
things are extended in both space and time (see Rea (2004)). There are
two types of Presentism, in its extreme form it is the belief that the
past and future are truly non-existent, that what we call time is not an
axis for arranging things but a series of changes and records in an
*enduring* present. In its less extreme form, which might be called
*functional presentism*, the present is a durationless instant that can
never be connected to the future or past except through predictions and
records.
In consciousness studies it is the conventional theory that brain
activity occurs in the present instant and that the past can only occur
as memories retrieved into this durationless present. So, in
consciousness studies functional Presentism seems to be the accepted
paradigm.
Presentism cannot explain change. Each instant is durationless and
frozen. That said, as seen above, four dimensionalism cannot explain the
observation of change although it can explain the difference between
moving and stationary objects. Fortunately the debate has been largely
resolved by recent scientific experiments which show that time exists
and hence Presentism is unlikely.
### The existence of time
The issue of whether or not time exists is critical to consciousness
studies. If we exist at an instant without duration then how can we know
we exist? Clay (1882) coined the term \'specious present\' to describe
how we seem to exist for a short period containing the immediate past:
\"All the notes of a bar of a song seem to the listener to be contained
in the present. All the changes of place of a meteor seem to the
beholder to be contained in the present. At the instant of the
termination of such series, no part of the time measured by them seems
to be a past. Time, then, considered relatively to human apprehension,
consists of four parts, viz., the obvious past, the specious present,
the real present, and the future.\"
So conscious, phenomenal experience has things that are apparently
extended in time. But does time exist?
Recent experiments in quantum physics should change our view of time
forever. Lindner *et al.* (2005) have explored the problem of time by
investigating quantum interference between interferometer slits that are
separated by time rather than space.
In the famous, spatial \'double slit experiment\' in quantum physics
single electrons are directed at an apparatus that has the equivalent of
two tiny slits separated by a small gap. The electrons pass through the
apparatus one at a time and produce flashes of light on a screen or
changes in a photographic plate. The electrons produce series of bands
on the screen that are typical of interference effects. So each electron
is deflected as if it has passed through both slits and interfered with
itself.
![](constudtwinslit.gif "constudtwinslit.gif")
This experiment provided some of the earliest evidence for the
wave-packet nature of the electron.
In an amazing technical tour de force Lindner *et al.* (2005) have
extended the idea of the spatial double slit experiment to an
investigation of time. In the double slit experiment in time electrons
are produced in an inert gas by extremely short laser pulses. The pulses
stimulate a single atom and there is a probability of this atom
releasing an electron at each oscillation of the pulse. The apparatus is
described by Paulus *et al.* (2003). The probability (see note 1) of an
electron being ejected to the left or right of the apparatus can be
adjusted by adjusting the optical pulse. Pulses can be applied with a
duration of a few femtoseconds and these create \'slits\' extending over
an interval of about 500 attoseconds (500 x 10-18 seconds). A single
electron has a probability of being emitted at each of the slits. The
probability of the single electron going in a particular direction after
both slits have been created depends upon the interaction of the
probabilities of being emitted in a particular direction at each single
slit. As expected, an interference pattern was generated as a result of
single electrons interfering with themselves across different times.
![](constudtimeslit.gif "constudtimeslit.gif")
This experiment is remarkable because it provides direct evidence that
time exists in a similar fashion to the way that space exists. It is
consistent with Feynman\'s theory of Quantum Electrodynamics where all
possible paths, both in time and space, interact to produce the final
trajectory of a particle and consistent with modern Special Relativity,
on which QED is based, where the trajectories of particles occur in an
extended four dimensional space-time.
The experiment has not attracted as much attention as it might have done
because most physicists are not Presentists. To physicists the
experiment is yet another confirmation of modern physics. However it has
impressed many:
\"This experiment should be included in every textbook on quantum
mechanics,\" says Wolfgang Schleich, a quantum physicist at the
University of Ulm in Germany. \"It certainly will be in mine.\"
(PhysicsWeb)
Why should a concrete demonstration that time exists affect
consciousness studies? The simple answer is that, as Kant, Gombrich,
Clay, James and many others have spotted, there can be no conscious,
phenomenal experience without time. The fact that time exists should
provide new insights and liberate theorists in the field of
consciousness studies from the problems of recursion and regression that
are inherent in Presentism.
Meanwhile Quantum Theorists are pressing on with the problem of how an
organised spacetime could emerge from quantum chaos (cf: Ambjorn *et
al.* (2004)) and even how mind might be involved in the emergence of
time itself (cf: Romer (2004)).
### The nature of time
#### The nature of classical time
In the eighteenth century it became apparent that Euclid\'s parallel
postulate could not be explained in terms of the other postulates. The
parallel postulate is equivalent to the statement that exactly one line
can be drawn through any point not on a given line in such a way that it
is parallel to the given line (this is Playfair\'s simple version). It
is also known as the fifth postulate.
The attempts to prove the parallel postulate led to the development of
non-Euclidean geometry. It was then possible to show that the parallel
postulate is a special case within a range of geometrical forms from
spherical geometry, through Euclidean geometry to the hyperbolic
geometry of Bolyai and Lobatschefsky. Furthermore it was shown by
Taurinus that the axioms of Euclidean geometry, with the exception of
the fifth postulate, applied on the surface of a sphere with an
imaginary radius. This motivated Hermann Minkowski to propose that
Einstein\'s new theory of relativity was in fact due to the universe
being a \'space-time\' with four dimensions rather than just a space in
which things change (see Walter 1999). In 1909 Minkowski said that:
`"Henceforth space by itself and time by itself, are doomed to fade `\
`away into mere shadows, and only a kind of union of the two will `\
`preserve an independent reality". (Minkowski 1909).`
The earliest idea of the four dimensional universe involved time as an
axis with displacements measured in units of the square root of minus
one (cf: Einstein (1920)): time was considered to be displacements along
the imaginary plane. However, from the moment of Minkowski\'s proposal
mathematicians were aware that other interpretations of time could give
almost identical physical results.
According to the differential geometry developed during the nineteenth
century a space is defined in terms of a *metric tensor* which is a
matrix of factors that determine how displacements in each independent
direction vary with displacements in the other directions. The metric
tensor then specifies a *metric* which is an equation that describes the
length of a displacement in any direction in terms of the independent
directions, or *dimensions*.
A derivation of the metric tensor and how it can be used to calculate
the metric is given in the /Appendix/.
The metric of the space considered by Euclid is Pythagoras\' theorem
where the length of any displacement is given in terms of the
displacements along the three independent axes, or dimensions:
$s^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2$
It is interesting to explore *imaginary time* from the point of view of
consciousness studies. Minkowski\'s original idea for the geometry of
the world proposed that any displacement was a displacement in both time
and space given by a four dimensional version of Pythagoras\' theorem:
$s^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2 + (ict)^2$
which, given that $i^2 = -1$ equals:
$s^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2 - (ct)^2$
Where *i* is the square root of minus one, *c* is a constant for
converting metres to seconds and t is the displacement in time. The
space-time is considered to be flat and all displacements are measured
from the origin.
The interesting feature of Minkowski space-time with imaginary time is
that displacements in time can *subtract* from displacements in space.
If we set $r^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2$ (where *r* is the radius of a sphere
around the origin then:
$s^2 = r^2 - (ct)^2$
Notice that $s^2 = 0$ when $r^2 = (ct)^2$ so if imaginary time existed
there would be times and separations within a spherical volume of things
where **everything is at a point as well as distributed in space**. This
idea has distinct similarites with the *res cogitans* mentioned by
Descartes, and the *point soul* of Reid and Malebranche etc., however,
this feature of Minkowski\'s space-time has not been popular with
physicists for some good reasons. Blandford and Thorne point out some of
the problems:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html} One approach, often used in
elementary textbooks \[and also used in Goldstein\'s (1980) Classical
Mechanics and in the first edition of Jackson\'s Classical
Electrodynamics\], is to set $x^0 = it$, where $i = \sqrt{-1}$ and
correspondingly make the time basis vector be imaginary,\... When this
approach is adopted, the resulting formalism does not care whether
indices are placed up or down; one can place them wherever one\'s
stomach or liver dictate without asking one\'s brain. However, this
$x^0 = it$ approach has severe disadvantages: (i) it hides the true
physical geometry of Minkowski spacetime, (ii) it cannot be extended in
any reasonable manner to non-orthonormal bases in flat spacetime, and
(iii) it cannot be extended in any reasonable manner to the curvilinear
coordinates that one must use in general relativity. For this reason,
most advanced texts \[including the second and third editions of Jackson
(1999)\] and all general relativity texts take an alternative approach,
which we also adopt in this book. This alternative approach requires
introducing two different types of components for vectors, and
analogously for tensors: contravariant components denoted by
superscripts, and covariant components denoted by
subscripts.\"`</font>`{=html} Blandford & Thorne (2004).
What Blandford and Thorne are saying is that the metric of space-time
appears to be the result of the interaction of two coordinate systems
and cannot be explained by a single coordinate system with imaginary
time. When a more complicated geometrical analysis is applied it is
evident that there are two possibilities for the time coordinate. In the
first the metric can be **assumed** from the outset to be
$s^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2 - (ct)^2$
and the metric tensor simply adjusted by inserting -1 in the principle
diagonal so that the negative sign in front of the time coordinate
occurs. With this assumption and adjustment the time coordinate can be
assumed to be *real*. In the second possibility the time coordinate in
the world can be assumed to be imaginary and the time coordinate of the
observer can be assumed to be real. This gives rise to the same metric
tensor and metric as the first possibility but does not assume the
resulting metric from the outset.
The three ideas of classical time (imaginary, real and mixed) are shown
in the illustration below:
![](constudclasstime.gif "constudclasstime.gif")
The light cone is divided into three regions: events on the surface of
the light cone, such as photons converging on the observer, are said to
be *lightlike* separated from the observer, events inside the future or
past light cones are said to be *timelike separated* and events outside
the lightcone are said to be *spacelike* separated from the observer.
The physical **theory of relativity** consists of four dimensional
geometry plus the assumption of causality and the assumption that
physical laws are invariant between observers. It should be noted that
space-time could contain preferred frames of reference and is not, by
itself, a theory of relativity. The assumption that physical laws are
invariant between observers leads to the postulate that nothing can
travel faster than *c* metres per second. This means that the constant
*c*, which in Minkowski space-time is the conversion factor from seconds
to metres then has a new significance as the maximum velocity.
A result of *c* being a maximum velocity is that nothing can travel from
regions of the light cone that are spacelike separated to the observer
at coordinates (0,0,0,0). This is problematic for observers if time is
real because, as Stein (1968) wrote:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}"in Einstein-Minkowski space-time
an event\'s present is constituted by itself alone." `</font>`{=html}
(Stein 1968).
However, to each of us it seems that the present is characterised by
*many* things simultaneously. As will be discussed below, this
simultaneity of present things also results in the appearance of
phenomenal space. But in Minkowski space-time with real time the plane
of simultaneity is entirely space-like separated from the observation
point. If real time is accepted it would appear that we cannot have the
space of phenomenal experience. The regions of the light-cone and the
spacelike separation of present events are shown in the illustration
below:
![](Constudcone.gif "Constudcone.gif")
So can the time in Minkowski space-time be real? If time were in some
way related to the imaginary plane then all the content of the surface
of the light cone could be simultaneously at the position of the
observer and phenomenal experience containing space is possible, but
then general relativity may be problematic. So can the time in Minkowski
space-time be imaginary?
There is another problem with Minkowski space-time known as the
\"Rietdijk-Putnam-Penrose\" argument or the Andromeda paradox (Penrose
1989). Moving observers have different planes of simultaneity. The plane
of simultaneity of an observer moving towards you slopes upward relative
to your plane of simultaneity (see the illustration on \"De Broglie
waves\" above). Suppose an alien civilisation in the Andromeda galaxy
decided to launch a fleet of spacecraft intent on the invasion of earth
just as you passed Jim in your car. Your plane of simultaneity would
slope upwards ever so slightly compared with Jim\'s, Jim\'s plane of
simultaneity could contain earlier events on Andromeda than yours. At
the distance of the Andromeda galaxy it could be another week or two for
the Andromedean\'s to launch their invasion fleet in Jim\'s slice of the
universe. Penrose considers that this example shows that the events in
the universe must be fixed:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Two people pass each other on
the street; and according to one of the two people, an Andromedean space
fleet has already set off on its journey, while to the other, the
decision as to whether or not the journey will actually take place has
not yet been made. How can there still be some uncertainty as to the
outcome of that decision? If to either person the decision has already
been made, then surely there cannot be any uncertainty. The launching of
the space fleet is an inevitability.\"`</font>`{=html} (Penrose 1989).
If the decision to invade and a time previous to this decision are both
part of the present instant on earth then, in a 4D classical universe,
the decision to invade must be inevitable. This lack of free will in a
4D universe is known as chronogeometrical determinism (Toretti 1983).
However, as de Broglie demonstrated, it is sloping planes of
simultaneity that do indeed introduce uncertainty into our universe. It
should also be noted that nothing on the plane of simultaneity is
observable to the owner of that plane because, to observe it would
involve the transmission of data at velocities greater than the speed of
light.
Petkov (2002)considers a version of the Andromeda paradox in depth. He
concludes that:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"If the relativity of
simultaneity is explicitly discussed in terms of the dimensionality of
reality, the fact that observers in relative motion have different sets
of simultaneous events can be explained either by assuming that
existence is also relativized (preserving the views of the present and
objective becoming) or by considering existence absolute which means
that reality is a 4D world. Although the option of relativizing
existence appears completely unacceptable from a philosophical point of
view, that option is eliminated within the framework of SR by
demonstrating that the twin paradox would not be possible if existence
were not absolute.\"`</font>`{=html}
According to Petkov Special Relativity describes the universe as a
frozen space-time where things are eternally arranged in four
dimensions. Petkov introduces the possibility of change as a feature of
consciousness and in support of this quotes Weyl\'s intuition that only
the conscious observer moves in time.
## Relationalism, Substantivalism, the Hole Argument and General Covariance
### Relationalism and Substantivalism
The view that the universe could be an extended space and time with
things in it, a sort of unbounded container, is known as
**substantivalism**. It was championed by Newton and Clarke in the
seventeenth century. The view that the space and time in the universe
depends upon the relations between the objects in the universe is known
as **relationalism** and was championed by Leibniz.
Leibniz attacked substantivalism by arguing that if there were two
universes which only differed by things in one universe being displaced
by five feet compared with things in the other universe then there is no
reason why the two universes should be discernably different.
Newton supported substantivalism by arguing that when the water in a
bucket rotates it adopts a concave surface that is independent of other
motions and provides evidence of the possibility of absolute motion.
This argument is called the *bucket argument*. Newton also introduces
the *globe argument* in which he proposes that the state of motion of
two globes connected by a taut thread can be gauged from the tension in
the thread alone. When the globes are stationary with respect to each
other there is no tension in the thread.
Ernst Mach in 1893 introduced a relationalist account of the bucket
argument by claiming that the water rotates in relation to the fixed
stars. He stated this in what has become known as Mach\'s principle:
\"The inertia of any system is the result of the interaction of that
system and the rest of the universe. In other words, every particle in
the universe ultimately has an effect on every other particle.\"
The relationalist position is interesting from the viewpoint of
consciousness studies because phenomenal consciousness appears as a
projection that overlies physical space. As an example, the stars on the
ceiling of a planetarium appear to be at huge distances from the
observer even though they are reflected lights that are only a few
metres away. In general a projection where positions depend upon angular
separations will be subject to relationalism. It is also probable that
the space of phenomenal consciousness is a continuum of some field in
the brain, if this is the case then the way we conceive of space as an
existent entity is actually a conception involving the angular relations
between the perturbations of the substance that is the field.
Substantivalism would then literally be space as a substance. It is
intriguing in this respect that Kant believed that space was a form of
intuition and hence a property of mind.
Kant raised another type of argument for the justification of absolute
space. He asked whether *handedness* was due to relations or a property
of space. The right and left hands are enantiomorphs (mirror images).
The relations within the right and left hands are identical but they
still differ, for instance a right hand cannot be moved on to a left
hand so that it exactly overlies it. Kant proposed that handedness was
property inherent in space itself rather than a set of relations.
Gardner introduced a version of Kant\'s problem with the \"Ozma\"
argument: \"Is there any way to communicate the meaning of the word
\"left\" by a language transmitted in the form of pulsating signals? By
the terms of the problem we may say anything we please to our listeners,
ask them to perform any experiment whatever, with one proviso: there is
to be no asymmetric object or structure that we and they can observe in
common.\" (Gardner 1990).
Although it is probably impossible to provide an answer to the Ozma
argument it is possible to relate handedness to a conceptual point
observer who spans more than an instant of time. If a point observer is
at the centre of a field of inward pointing space-time vectors then
relative to any given vector there are positive and negative angular
separations. The body is asymmetric and the point observer would lie
within this so always have available a \'head\' direction or a \'foot
direction\' and hence a left and right. Unlike the time extended
observer an instantaneous observer would not contain vectors that
contained directional information and would be no more than a collection
of points in space.
Pooley (2002) discusses handedness in depth and introduces the problem
of parity violation in the Weak Interaction.
### General Covariance and the Hole Argument
The proposal that the universe is four dimensional does not in itself
produce a full physical theory. The assumptions of causality and the
invariance of physical laws between observers are also required to
create modern Relativity Theory. The second assumption, that the laws of
physics are the same for all observers is closely related to the
requirement of **general covariance**.
The principle of general covariance requires that a manifold of events
can be smoothly mapped to another manifold of the same dimension and
back again. This mapping should always give the same result. General
covariance is assumed in General Relativity.
Einstein realised that there was an apparent problem with this
assumption in certain circumstances. In his **hole argument** he
considers a special region of space-time that is devoid of matter and
where the stress-energy tensor vanishes. He then labels the same events
outside the hole with two different coordinate systems. These coordinate
systems could differ by something as simple as having origins that are
separate so the difference is entirely passive. Both systems will give
the same values for the gravitational field outside the hole. It turns
out however that that the systems predict different fields within the
hole (see MacDonald (2001) for the calculation and Norton (1993), (1999)
for a discussion). Einstein overcame this problem by considering active
mappings where particles are actually transferred through the hole. He
concluded that the points where particles meet can be transformed
according to general covariance and hence a relativistic theory could
indeed be constructed. Solutions to the field equations that were
inconsistent with the points defined by interacting particles were
discarded as non-physical.
The hole argument led Einstein to abandon the idea of space and time as
something separate from the material content of the universe. The
General Theory of Relativity becomes a theory of **observables**. He
wrote that:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"That the requirement of general
covariance, which takes away from space and time the last remnant of
physical objectivity, is a natural one, will be seen from the following
reflection. All our space-time verifications invariably amount to a
determination of space-time coincidences. If, for example, events
consisted merely in the motion of material points, then ultimately
nothing would be observable but the meetings of two or more of these
points. Moreover, the results of our measurings are nothing but
verifications of such meetings of the material points of our measuring
instruments with other material points, coincidences between the hands
of the a clock and points on the clock dial, and observed point-events
happening at the same place at the same time. The introduction of a
system of reference serves no other purpose than to facilitate the
description of the totality of such coincidences\".`</font>`{=html}
(Einstein 1916).
This is what would be expected from a four dimensional block universe
with real time. It is a frozen universe of the type discussed earlier.
As Earman (2002) puts it when discussing change:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"First, the roots of the problem
lie in classical GTR, and even if it was decided that it is a mistake to
quantize GTR, there would remain the problem of reconciling the frozen
dynamics of GTR with the B-series notion of change that is supported not
only by common sense but by every physical theory prior to GTR. Second,
although the aspect of the problem that grabs attention is that of time
and change, no solution will be forthcoming without tackling the more
general issue of what an "observable" of classical GTR
is.\"`</font>`{=html}
In such a universe action at a distance is not possible. From the
viewpoint of consciousness studies the limitation of physical concepts
to interactions between particles is a restatement of Ryle\'s regress
and the recursion version of the homunculus problem. If events are no
more than space-time coincidences then we are doomed to the endless
transfer of data from point to point without any conscious observation.
This seems to forbid any true simultaneity in experience and means that
only measurements are possible.
The reduction of physics to the study of particle interactions is fully
relationalist and allows space-time to become a property of these
interactions rather than vice-versa. Once it becomes possible to
consider space-time as a dependent property it is then feasible to
equate *observation* with *measurement*. Observation is normally the
representation of an event in an observer\'s space-time coordinate
system. Measurement is the change in state of a system in response to an
encounter with an event. If we maintain that space-time does not exist
and can be replaced by encounters between particles then observation can
be replaced by measurement. This may well be a way forward for some
approximations to physical reality and may allow us to understand how a
space-time is selected within an observer. As part of this approach the
word \"observable\" is often used interchangeably with \"measurable\".
## Quantum theory and time
### The general problem of QM and time
Quantum physics provides many fundamental insights into the nature of
time. At the simplest level the energy-time version of the Heisenberg
Uncertainty Principle predicts that Quantum Mechanical (QM) interference
should occur between a particle and earlier versions of itself. Such
interference has been observed (see \"The existence of time\" above).
Two of the most complete reviews of the problem of time in quantum
theory available at present are Zeh (2001) and Isham (1993).
Perhaps the most interesting aspect of QM and time is that it can
provide an argument that time does not exist in the universe as a whole.
The argument can be approached from many directions (See Rovelli 2003)
but is clear in the Wheeler-de Witt equation which describes the
wavefunction of the entire universe. This wavefunction has no reference
to time. De Witt explained the emergence of time by proposing that the
universe can be divided into an observer with measuring instruments and
the rest of the universe so that the rest of the universe changes with
respect to the observer.
Rovelli (2003) supports this idea of partition, he considers in depth
the problems of the \"hole argument\" and quantum physics and notes
that, given the assumption that events are just successions of
relations:
\"`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}The unique account of the state
of the world of the classical theory is thus shattered into a
multiplicity of accounts, one for each possible \"observing\" physical
system. Quantum mechanics is a theory about the physical description of
physical systems relative to other systems, and this is a complete
description of the world.`</font>`{=html} (Rovelli 2003).
Barbour (1997) and Hartle and Gell-Mann have both proposed that an
observer is a partition or region with memories that contain the trace
of histories. The histories would represent a B Series. Unfortunately
this leaves the A Series unexplained so time would have a direction but
there would be no \'becoming\'.
Hawking introduces the observer into the problem of time by asking what
sort of universe is compatible with human life. This application of the
**Anthropic Principle** leads to constraints on the form of the
universe, for instance the universe should have galaxies and last for
more than a few million years. The Anthropic Principle is actually a
restatement of the observer problem - if being an observer leads to a
certain division of the universe into observer and observed then the
observed part will have the form given by the Anthropic Principle.
Hartle and Hawking () also tackled the \"boundary problem\" of cosmology
by proposing that there is no boundary. This proposal involves adding a
fifth, time-like, dimension on the imaginary plane so that the universe
at its beginning is a **de Sitter** or **anti de Sitter** space-time.
A de Sitter space-time is characterised by the metric:
$ds^2 = dx^2 + dy^2 + dz^2 + (idt)^2 + du^2$
An anti de Sitter space time has the metric:
$ds^2 = dx^2 + dy^2 + dz^2 + (idt)^2 - du^2$
A de Sitter space time is fascinating from the view point of
consciousness studies because it contains three space-like dimensions,
one real, time-like dimension (u) and one imaginary time-like dimension.
This might give the real and imaginary time-like axes that Franck
proposed were needed to produce the McTaggart A Series. However, the
extra dimension could only be related to the observer in the universe as
it is at present because the extra dimension does not appear to be
required to explain measurables.
### The interpretation of QM
Time is also of interest in the interpretation of quantum mechanics and
entanglement. There are many interpretations of QM such as the
**Operational Interpretation** (Decoherence Theory), the **Transactional
Interpretation**, the **Relational Interpretation**, the **Many Worlds
Interpretation**, the **Copenhagen Interpretation**, the **Bohm
Interpretation**, the **Many Minds Interpretation** etc.
Some of these interpretations, such as the Transactional Interpretation,
allow the connection of entangled quantum states backwards in time along
the path of particles.
Decoherence theory is of particular interest because it allows the
calculation of how long an entangled state can persist. Tegmark (2000)
and Hagan *et al.* (2002) have used this technique to calculate the
decoherence time of entanglement in microtubules and have differed by a
factor of $10^{10}$ because of differing assumptions about the
biophysics of microtubules in the brain.
## Time and conscious experience
In a four dimensional universe time is an independent direction for
arranging things. As an independent direction things arranged in time do
not overlie things arranged in space. This also appears to be the case
in conscious experience where whole words or \"bars of a tune\" can be
experienced arranged in time. This extension in time is easy to
experience but the independence of the time dimension is difficult to
conceive, for instance Le Poidevin (2000) reflects that:
> \"If events e1 and e2 are registered in a single specious present,
> then we perceive them both as present, and so as simultaneous. But we
> do not see, e.g., the successive positions of a moving object as
> simultaneous, for if we did we would see a blurred object and not a
> moving one.\"
This assumes that arrangements in time do not occur in an independent
direction for arranging things and hence would overlay space. In fact
the mystery of conscious experience is deeply related to how we can
experience many things as events that are separate from each other. Our
experience of two dimensional patterns containing many things is as much
a mystery as how we experience temporal patterns extended in time. The
problem is illustrated below:
![](constudsimevent.gif "constudsimevent.gif")
It is as if patterns in conscious experience are being viewed from a
point in at least four dimensions. How our experience can be like the
\'view\' of a conceptual point observer at the apex of a light cone
without the data being overlaid and obscured is a profound mystery,
obviously the data cannot be transferred into the apparent observation
point and appears as nebulous vectors directed at the point. Some
philosophers have noticed this problem.
(*This is a stub, requires an elaboration of Specious Present Theory and
Husserl\'s ideas*)
Le Poidevin (2000). The experience and perception of time. Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu//archives/spr2001/entries/time-experience/#4>
Readers who are unfamiliar with the developments to Newtonian mechanics
that occurred in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries should read
Consciousness Studies/The Philosophical
Problem/Appendixs
See
overleaf
for the philosophical problem continued..:
## The problems of space, qualia, machine and digital consciousness
Click on the above link.
## Notes and References
More\...
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Philosophical Problem#The problem of time
## The philosophical problem of phenomenal consciousness
Chalmers (1996) encapsulated the philosophical problem of phenomenal
consciousness, describing it as the *Hard Problem*. The Hard Problem can
be concisely defined as \"how to explain a state of consciousness in
terms of its neurological basis\" Block (2004). A state is an
arrangement of things in space over a period of time. It is possible
that the Hard Problem has not been solved because the concepts of
\"space\", \"time\" and \"things\" are intensely problematic in both
science and philosophy.
Some philosophers have argued that *changes* in state are equivalent to
\"mental states\". That consciousness experience always involves acts,
such as acts of acquaintance (Russell 1912). But what is a succession of
states in the brain or the physical world?
As an extension of the idea of \"acts\" as mental states many
philosophers have argued that the functional description of a system
does not need to contain any reference to qualia within that system.
Such ideas, based on nineteenth century materialism, have been expressed
by Huxley, Ryle, Smart, Goldman and many others. However, although
qualia are not required for classical functions, such as most
computations or servo-control, it is far from clear whether this is true
for all functions. If a function is described as any thing that mediates
a change in state it should be realised that \"change\" itself is not
fully understood in philosophy or science and that some systems, such as
quantum mechanical systems, contain state changes that are far from
understood. It will be seen below that our scientific knowledge is not
yet sufficiently complete to allow the claim that all, or even any,
changes can occur without qualia.
Whether a philosopher or scientist is dualist, materialist or
physicalist they should have some insight into current theories about
the physical world. Certainly, if they are considering the problem of
\"how to explain a state of consciousness in terms of its neurological
basis\" then some idea of a \"neurological basis\" is essential.
The objective of this section is to give an account of the problems of
space, time and content and to describe how these affect the problem of
consciousness.
## Epiphenomenalism and the problem of change
Philosophers have noticed since the time of Leibniz that phenomenal
consciousness does not seem to be required for the brain to produce
action. As an example there are numerous reflexes that can occur without
any awareness that they are happening. In fact it is difficult to think
of any response to a stimulus that requires phenomenal consciousness and
could not, in principle, be performed in the absence of conscious
intervention. T.H. Huxley is often regarded as the originator of the
term **epiphenomenalism** to describe how consciousness seems extraneous
to processes in the materialist interpretation of the world although the
term may have originated in James\' description of Huxley\'s (1874)
ideas.
According to nineteenth century science changes in state cannot explain
the existence of phenomenal consciousness so superficially it may appear
as if phenomenal consciousness is unnecessary. However, it may come as a
shock to the reader to discover that nineteenth century science is also
unable to account for any change in state. In the materialist paradigm
time is construed to be a succession of instants of no duration, each of
which is entirely separate from the others. As a result no instant can
cause a change in another instant. It is not only conscious experience
that is epiphenomenal, each instant of the nineteenth century concept of
the world is epiphenomenal because it cannot give rise to the next
instant.
On the one hand it seems that conscious experience is not required for a
nineteenth century model of behaviour and on the other hand nineteenth
century science seems to be impossible without extraneous input from a
conscious observer who contains the idea of change.
The problem of change is closely related to the problem of time which is
discussed in depth below. (See Change and Inconsistency, Stanford
Encyclopedia of
Philosophy).
The reader might consider whether phenomenal consciousness is indeed
epiphenomenal. Empirical reports describe it as something that is
different from the world beyond the body (see direct
realism) -
but could we generate empirical reports of an epiphenomenon? If we do
indeed generate empirical reports of phenomenal consciousness is there
some non-materialist, physical\*\* connection between phenomenal
consciousness and the functional state?
In the analysis that follows it is essential that the reader does not
dismiss the possibility that conscious experience is largely
non-functional in a classical sense. The idea that observation is not
action should not be dismissed out of hand. Indeed the claim that
something cannot be true if it is \"epiphenomenal\" in a classical sense
is astonishing in the context of modern quantum physics. Everettian
approaches (and offshoots like the Bohmian, Consistent Histories and
operational (decoherence) approaches) to quantum physics all allow that
the classical world is epiphenomenal (cf: Page 1997, Stapp 1998). The
Copenhagen Interpretation, however, was less clear on this issue.
It is curious that problems with the nature of phenomenal consciousness
are also problems with nineteenth century science - Aristotlean regress
in the mind is part of the wider problem of epistemological regress and
epiphenomenalism is part of the wider problem of change. Perhaps
nineteenth century science is not an appropriate foundation for
understanding consciousness.
Recommended reading:
Mortensen, C. (2002) Change. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/change/>
Page, D.N. (1997). Sensible Quantum Mechanics: Are Only Perceptions
Probabilistic? <http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9506010>
Rivas, T., & Dongen, H. van (2003). Exit Epiphenomenalism: The
Demolition of a Refuge
Stapp, (1998). Quantum Ontology and Mind-Matter Synthesis.\[Appeared in
proceedings of X-th Max Born Symposium, eds, Blanchard and Jadczyk, Vol
517 Lecture notes in Physics series, Springer-Verlag, 1999 (Quantum
Future:from Volta and Como to the present and beyond) \]
<http://arxiv.org/PS_cache/quant-ph/pdf/9905/9905053.pdf>
(\*\*) cf: gravity may affect the rate at which clocks tick without the
occurrence of any collisions between particles or anything that can be
called a \"process\".
## The problem of time
*This section should be read after reading a quick introduction to
special
relativity*
### The past century of ideas about time
McTaggart in 1908 set out some of the problems with our idea of time in
his classic paper *The Unreality of Time*. He drew attention to the way
that a sequence of things in a list does not describe time because a
sequence of things is constant yet events are always changing. These
considerations led him to propose that there are three different
sequences of things, or series, that are commonly used to describe
events. McTaggart\'s three different time series are summarized in the
illustration below.
![](constudseries.gif "constudseries.gif")
He argued that only the \'A Series\' is a temporal series because it is
only in the A Series that change occurs so that events can be given the
labels \'future\', \'present\' and \'past\'. He pointed out that
although the A Series is used for determining the direction and sequence
of events it is not itself \'in time\' because it contains relations
that are neither a part of the C Series nor the B Series. This led him
to propose that time is unreal because change involves a movement along
the time series so cannot be fixed within it.
Franck (1994) argued on the basis of Atmanspacher\'s models of universes
with real and imaginary geometries that McTaggart\'s \'unreality\' of
time could be avoided by proposing a second, imaginary, time dimension.
`"What McTaggart in fact demonstrates is that it is impossible to `\
`account for temporality within a strictly one-dimensional concept `\
`of time."(Franck 1994).`
This idea is illustrated below:
![](constudseries2.gif "constudseries2.gif")
This idea of time being two dimensional is not new and has also been
advanced by such luminaries as Hermann Weyl and CD Broad. Weyl (1920)
made the following statement that is extremely apposite to consciousness
studies, he wrote that reality is a:
`"...four-dimensional continuum which is neither 'time' nor 'space'. `\
`Only the consciousness that passes on in one portion of this world `\
`experiences the detached piece which comes to meet it and passes `\
`behind it, as history, that is, as a process that is going forward `\
`in time and takes place in space." (Weyl 1920).`
McTaggart\'s objection to time is felt intuitively by anyone who has
contemplated the *Block Universe* of Relativity Theory. If the universe
is four dimensional with three space dimensions and one time dimension
it would be fixed forever and the observer would be frozen within it.
This would occur whether the time dimension was arranged according to
Galilean Relativity or Modern Relativity.
Peter Lynds in 2003 has drawn attention to the \'frozen\' nature of the
observer in a four dimensional universe. He proposes, like Kevin Brown
in his popular mathpages,
that time must be approached from the viewpoint of quantum physics
because simple four dimensional universes would give rise to \'frozen,
static\' instants and hence no change could occur. Lynds argues that if
quantum physics is introduced then no event can have a definite moment
of occurrence and that change occurs because of this quantum
indeterminacy:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}I would suggest that there is
possibly much more to be gleaned from the connection between quantum
physics and the inherent need for physical continuity, and even go as
far to speculate that the dependent relationship may be the underlying
explanation for quantum jumping and with static indivisible mathematical
time values directly related to the process of quantum collapse. Time
will tell.\"`</font>`{=html}(Lynds 2003).
Our knowledge of quantum uncertainty can be traced back to De Broglie\'s
highly successful model of individual particle motions. This model was
based on Special Relativity theory and it predicted a wave nature for
particles. The Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle can be shown to be a
consequence of this wave nature. See the illustration below:
![](constuddebroglie.gif "constuddebroglie.gif")
The illustration is based on de Broglie (1925) and Pollock (2004).
So Lynds\' argument that change is due to the uncertainty principle is
actually an argument that change is due to differing planes of
simultaneity between systems that are in relative motion. Kevin Brown is
aware of this; he summarises the effect of uncertainty due to special
relativity and points out that it provides a resolution of Zeno\'s arrow
paradox:
`"The theory of special relativity answers Zeno's concern over the `\
`lack of an instantaneous difference between a moving and a non-moving `\
`arrow by positing a fundamental re-structuring the basic way in which `\
`space and time fit together, such that there really is an instantaneous `\
`difference between a moving and a non-moving object, insofar as it `\
`makes sense to speak of "an instant" of a physical system with mutually `\
`moving elements. Objects in relative motion have different planes of `\
`simultaneity, with all the familiar relativistic consequences, so not `\
`only does a moving object look different to the world, but the world `\
`looks different to a moving object." (Brown 19??)`
Another approach to the way that time has a direction is to suggest that
the possible outcomes in quantum mechanics are located in \"disjoint
space-time regions which exclude one another\" (McCall 2000). This does
not explain the A Series however because the observer would not have any
sense of \'becoming\' or temporality as a result of the existence of
regions that could not be observed.
### Presentism and Four-Dimensionalism
In the past century the philosophical battle lines have been drawn
between the Presentists, who believe that only the durationless instant
of the present exists and the Four Dimensionalists who consider that
things are extended in both space and time (see Rea (2004)). There are
two types of Presentism, in its extreme form it is the belief that the
past and future are truly non-existent, that what we call time is not an
axis for arranging things but a series of changes and records in an
*enduring* present. In its less extreme form, which might be called
*functional presentism*, the present is a durationless instant that can
never be connected to the future or past except through predictions and
records.
In consciousness studies it is the conventional theory that brain
activity occurs in the present instant and that the past can only occur
as memories retrieved into this durationless present. So, in
consciousness studies functional Presentism seems to be the accepted
paradigm.
Presentism cannot explain change. Each instant is durationless and
frozen. That said, as seen above, four dimensionalism cannot explain the
observation of change although it can explain the difference between
moving and stationary objects. Fortunately the debate has been largely
resolved by recent scientific experiments which show that time exists
and hence Presentism is unlikely.
### The existence of time
The issue of whether or not time exists is critical to consciousness
studies. If we exist at an instant without duration then how can we know
we exist? Clay (1882) coined the term \'specious present\' to describe
how we seem to exist for a short period containing the immediate past:
\"All the notes of a bar of a song seem to the listener to be contained
in the present. All the changes of place of a meteor seem to the
beholder to be contained in the present. At the instant of the
termination of such series, no part of the time measured by them seems
to be a past. Time, then, considered relatively to human apprehension,
consists of four parts, viz., the obvious past, the specious present,
the real present, and the future.\"
So conscious, phenomenal experience has things that are apparently
extended in time. But does time exist?
Recent experiments in quantum physics should change our view of time
forever. Lindner *et al.* (2005) have explored the problem of time by
investigating quantum interference between interferometer slits that are
separated by time rather than space.
In the famous, spatial \'double slit experiment\' in quantum physics
single electrons are directed at an apparatus that has the equivalent of
two tiny slits separated by a small gap. The electrons pass through the
apparatus one at a time and produce flashes of light on a screen or
changes in a photographic plate. The electrons produce series of bands
on the screen that are typical of interference effects. So each electron
is deflected as if it has passed through both slits and interfered with
itself.
![](constudtwinslit.gif "constudtwinslit.gif")
This experiment provided some of the earliest evidence for the
wave-packet nature of the electron.
In an amazing technical tour de force Lindner *et al.* (2005) have
extended the idea of the spatial double slit experiment to an
investigation of time. In the double slit experiment in time electrons
are produced in an inert gas by extremely short laser pulses. The pulses
stimulate a single atom and there is a probability of this atom
releasing an electron at each oscillation of the pulse. The apparatus is
described by Paulus *et al.* (2003). The probability (see note 1) of an
electron being ejected to the left or right of the apparatus can be
adjusted by adjusting the optical pulse. Pulses can be applied with a
duration of a few femtoseconds and these create \'slits\' extending over
an interval of about 500 attoseconds (500 x 10-18 seconds). A single
electron has a probability of being emitted at each of the slits. The
probability of the single electron going in a particular direction after
both slits have been created depends upon the interaction of the
probabilities of being emitted in a particular direction at each single
slit. As expected, an interference pattern was generated as a result of
single electrons interfering with themselves across different times.
![](constudtimeslit.gif "constudtimeslit.gif")
This experiment is remarkable because it provides direct evidence that
time exists in a similar fashion to the way that space exists. It is
consistent with Feynman\'s theory of Quantum Electrodynamics where all
possible paths, both in time and space, interact to produce the final
trajectory of a particle and consistent with modern Special Relativity,
on which QED is based, where the trajectories of particles occur in an
extended four dimensional space-time.
The experiment has not attracted as much attention as it might have done
because most physicists are not Presentists. To physicists the
experiment is yet another confirmation of modern physics. However it has
impressed many:
\"This experiment should be included in every textbook on quantum
mechanics,\" says Wolfgang Schleich, a quantum physicist at the
University of Ulm in Germany. \"It certainly will be in mine.\"
(PhysicsWeb)
Why should a concrete demonstration that time exists affect
consciousness studies? The simple answer is that, as Kant, Gombrich,
Clay, James and many others have spotted, there can be no conscious,
phenomenal experience without time. The fact that time exists should
provide new insights and liberate theorists in the field of
consciousness studies from the problems of recursion and regression that
are inherent in Presentism.
Meanwhile Quantum Theorists are pressing on with the problem of how an
organised spacetime could emerge from quantum chaos (cf: Ambjorn *et
al.* (2004)) and even how mind might be involved in the emergence of
time itself (cf: Romer (2004)).
### The nature of time
#### The nature of classical time
In the eighteenth century it became apparent that Euclid\'s parallel
postulate could not be explained in terms of the other postulates. The
parallel postulate is equivalent to the statement that exactly one line
can be drawn through any point not on a given line in such a way that it
is parallel to the given line (this is Playfair\'s simple version). It
is also known as the fifth postulate.
The attempts to prove the parallel postulate led to the development of
non-Euclidean geometry. It was then possible to show that the parallel
postulate is a special case within a range of geometrical forms from
spherical geometry, through Euclidean geometry to the hyperbolic
geometry of Bolyai and Lobatschefsky. Furthermore it was shown by
Taurinus that the axioms of Euclidean geometry, with the exception of
the fifth postulate, applied on the surface of a sphere with an
imaginary radius. This motivated Hermann Minkowski to propose that
Einstein\'s new theory of relativity was in fact due to the universe
being a \'space-time\' with four dimensions rather than just a space in
which things change (see Walter 1999). In 1909 Minkowski said that:
`"Henceforth space by itself and time by itself, are doomed to fade `\
`away into mere shadows, and only a kind of union of the two will `\
`preserve an independent reality". (Minkowski 1909).`
The earliest idea of the four dimensional universe involved time as an
axis with displacements measured in units of the square root of minus
one (cf: Einstein (1920)): time was considered to be displacements along
the imaginary plane. However, from the moment of Minkowski\'s proposal
mathematicians were aware that other interpretations of time could give
almost identical physical results.
According to the differential geometry developed during the nineteenth
century a space is defined in terms of a *metric tensor* which is a
matrix of factors that determine how displacements in each independent
direction vary with displacements in the other directions. The metric
tensor then specifies a *metric* which is an equation that describes the
length of a displacement in any direction in terms of the independent
directions, or *dimensions*.
A derivation of the metric tensor and how it can be used to calculate
the metric is given in the /Appendix/.
The metric of the space considered by Euclid is Pythagoras\' theorem
where the length of any displacement is given in terms of the
displacements along the three independent axes, or dimensions:
$s^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2$
It is interesting to explore *imaginary time* from the point of view of
consciousness studies. Minkowski\'s original idea for the geometry of
the world proposed that any displacement was a displacement in both time
and space given by a four dimensional version of Pythagoras\' theorem:
$s^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2 + (ict)^2$
which, given that $i^2 = -1$ equals:
$s^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2 - (ct)^2$
Where *i* is the square root of minus one, *c* is a constant for
converting metres to seconds and t is the displacement in time. The
space-time is considered to be flat and all displacements are measured
from the origin.
The interesting feature of Minkowski space-time with imaginary time is
that displacements in time can *subtract* from displacements in space.
If we set $r^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2$ (where *r* is the radius of a sphere
around the origin then:
$s^2 = r^2 - (ct)^2$
Notice that $s^2 = 0$ when $r^2 = (ct)^2$ so if imaginary time existed
there would be times and separations within a spherical volume of things
where **everything is at a point as well as distributed in space**. This
idea has distinct similarites with the *res cogitans* mentioned by
Descartes, and the *point soul* of Reid and Malebranche etc., however,
this feature of Minkowski\'s space-time has not been popular with
physicists for some good reasons. Blandford and Thorne point out some of
the problems:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html} One approach, often used in
elementary textbooks \[and also used in Goldstein\'s (1980) Classical
Mechanics and in the first edition of Jackson\'s Classical
Electrodynamics\], is to set $x^0 = it$, where $i = \sqrt{-1}$ and
correspondingly make the time basis vector be imaginary,\... When this
approach is adopted, the resulting formalism does not care whether
indices are placed up or down; one can place them wherever one\'s
stomach or liver dictate without asking one\'s brain. However, this
$x^0 = it$ approach has severe disadvantages: (i) it hides the true
physical geometry of Minkowski spacetime, (ii) it cannot be extended in
any reasonable manner to non-orthonormal bases in flat spacetime, and
(iii) it cannot be extended in any reasonable manner to the curvilinear
coordinates that one must use in general relativity. For this reason,
most advanced texts \[including the second and third editions of Jackson
(1999)\] and all general relativity texts take an alternative approach,
which we also adopt in this book. This alternative approach requires
introducing two different types of components for vectors, and
analogously for tensors: contravariant components denoted by
superscripts, and covariant components denoted by
subscripts.\"`</font>`{=html} Blandford & Thorne (2004).
What Blandford and Thorne are saying is that the metric of space-time
appears to be the result of the interaction of two coordinate systems
and cannot be explained by a single coordinate system with imaginary
time. When a more complicated geometrical analysis is applied it is
evident that there are two possibilities for the time coordinate. In the
first the metric can be **assumed** from the outset to be
$s^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2 - (ct)^2$
and the metric tensor simply adjusted by inserting -1 in the principle
diagonal so that the negative sign in front of the time coordinate
occurs. With this assumption and adjustment the time coordinate can be
assumed to be *real*. In the second possibility the time coordinate in
the world can be assumed to be imaginary and the time coordinate of the
observer can be assumed to be real. This gives rise to the same metric
tensor and metric as the first possibility but does not assume the
resulting metric from the outset.
The three ideas of classical time (imaginary, real and mixed) are shown
in the illustration below:
![](constudclasstime.gif "constudclasstime.gif")
The light cone is divided into three regions: events on the surface of
the light cone, such as photons converging on the observer, are said to
be *lightlike* separated from the observer, events inside the future or
past light cones are said to be *timelike separated* and events outside
the lightcone are said to be *spacelike* separated from the observer.
The physical **theory of relativity** consists of four dimensional
geometry plus the assumption of causality and the assumption that
physical laws are invariant between observers. It should be noted that
space-time could contain preferred frames of reference and is not, by
itself, a theory of relativity. The assumption that physical laws are
invariant between observers leads to the postulate that nothing can
travel faster than *c* metres per second. This means that the constant
*c*, which in Minkowski space-time is the conversion factor from seconds
to metres then has a new significance as the maximum velocity.
A result of *c* being a maximum velocity is that nothing can travel from
regions of the light cone that are spacelike separated to the observer
at coordinates (0,0,0,0). This is problematic for observers if time is
real because, as Stein (1968) wrote:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}"in Einstein-Minkowski space-time
an event\'s present is constituted by itself alone." `</font>`{=html}
(Stein 1968).
However, to each of us it seems that the present is characterised by
*many* things simultaneously. As will be discussed below, this
simultaneity of present things also results in the appearance of
phenomenal space. But in Minkowski space-time with real time the plane
of simultaneity is entirely space-like separated from the observation
point. If real time is accepted it would appear that we cannot have the
space of phenomenal experience. The regions of the light-cone and the
spacelike separation of present events are shown in the illustration
below:
![](Constudcone.gif "Constudcone.gif")
So can the time in Minkowski space-time be real? If time were in some
way related to the imaginary plane then all the content of the surface
of the light cone could be simultaneously at the position of the
observer and phenomenal experience containing space is possible, but
then general relativity may be problematic. So can the time in Minkowski
space-time be imaginary?
There is another problem with Minkowski space-time known as the
\"Rietdijk-Putnam-Penrose\" argument or the Andromeda paradox (Penrose
1989). Moving observers have different planes of simultaneity. The plane
of simultaneity of an observer moving towards you slopes upward relative
to your plane of simultaneity (see the illustration on \"De Broglie
waves\" above). Suppose an alien civilisation in the Andromeda galaxy
decided to launch a fleet of spacecraft intent on the invasion of earth
just as you passed Jim in your car. Your plane of simultaneity would
slope upwards ever so slightly compared with Jim\'s, Jim\'s plane of
simultaneity could contain earlier events on Andromeda than yours. At
the distance of the Andromeda galaxy it could be another week or two for
the Andromedean\'s to launch their invasion fleet in Jim\'s slice of the
universe. Penrose considers that this example shows that the events in
the universe must be fixed:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Two people pass each other on
the street; and according to one of the two people, an Andromedean space
fleet has already set off on its journey, while to the other, the
decision as to whether or not the journey will actually take place has
not yet been made. How can there still be some uncertainty as to the
outcome of that decision? If to either person the decision has already
been made, then surely there cannot be any uncertainty. The launching of
the space fleet is an inevitability.\"`</font>`{=html} (Penrose 1989).
If the decision to invade and a time previous to this decision are both
part of the present instant on earth then, in a 4D classical universe,
the decision to invade must be inevitable. This lack of free will in a
4D universe is known as chronogeometrical determinism (Toretti 1983).
However, as de Broglie demonstrated, it is sloping planes of
simultaneity that do indeed introduce uncertainty into our universe. It
should also be noted that nothing on the plane of simultaneity is
observable to the owner of that plane because, to observe it would
involve the transmission of data at velocities greater than the speed of
light.
Petkov (2002)considers a version of the Andromeda paradox in depth. He
concludes that:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"If the relativity of
simultaneity is explicitly discussed in terms of the dimensionality of
reality, the fact that observers in relative motion have different sets
of simultaneous events can be explained either by assuming that
existence is also relativized (preserving the views of the present and
objective becoming) or by considering existence absolute which means
that reality is a 4D world. Although the option of relativizing
existence appears completely unacceptable from a philosophical point of
view, that option is eliminated within the framework of SR by
demonstrating that the twin paradox would not be possible if existence
were not absolute.\"`</font>`{=html}
According to Petkov Special Relativity describes the universe as a
frozen space-time where things are eternally arranged in four
dimensions. Petkov introduces the possibility of change as a feature of
consciousness and in support of this quotes Weyl\'s intuition that only
the conscious observer moves in time.
## Relationalism, Substantivalism, the Hole Argument and General Covariance
### Relationalism and Substantivalism
The view that the universe could be an extended space and time with
things in it, a sort of unbounded container, is known as
**substantivalism**. It was championed by Newton and Clarke in the
seventeenth century. The view that the space and time in the universe
depends upon the relations between the objects in the universe is known
as **relationalism** and was championed by Leibniz.
Leibniz attacked substantivalism by arguing that if there were two
universes which only differed by things in one universe being displaced
by five feet compared with things in the other universe then there is no
reason why the two universes should be discernably different.
Newton supported substantivalism by arguing that when the water in a
bucket rotates it adopts a concave surface that is independent of other
motions and provides evidence of the possibility of absolute motion.
This argument is called the *bucket argument*. Newton also introduces
the *globe argument* in which he proposes that the state of motion of
two globes connected by a taut thread can be gauged from the tension in
the thread alone. When the globes are stationary with respect to each
other there is no tension in the thread.
Ernst Mach in 1893 introduced a relationalist account of the bucket
argument by claiming that the water rotates in relation to the fixed
stars. He stated this in what has become known as Mach\'s principle:
\"The inertia of any system is the result of the interaction of that
system and the rest of the universe. In other words, every particle in
the universe ultimately has an effect on every other particle.\"
The relationalist position is interesting from the viewpoint of
consciousness studies because phenomenal consciousness appears as a
projection that overlies physical space. As an example, the stars on the
ceiling of a planetarium appear to be at huge distances from the
observer even though they are reflected lights that are only a few
metres away. In general a projection where positions depend upon angular
separations will be subject to relationalism. It is also probable that
the space of phenomenal consciousness is a continuum of some field in
the brain, if this is the case then the way we conceive of space as an
existent entity is actually a conception involving the angular relations
between the perturbations of the substance that is the field.
Substantivalism would then literally be space as a substance. It is
intriguing in this respect that Kant believed that space was a form of
intuition and hence a property of mind.
Kant raised another type of argument for the justification of absolute
space. He asked whether *handedness* was due to relations or a property
of space. The right and left hands are enantiomorphs (mirror images).
The relations within the right and left hands are identical but they
still differ, for instance a right hand cannot be moved on to a left
hand so that it exactly overlies it. Kant proposed that handedness was
property inherent in space itself rather than a set of relations.
Gardner introduced a version of Kant\'s problem with the \"Ozma\"
argument: \"Is there any way to communicate the meaning of the word
\"left\" by a language transmitted in the form of pulsating signals? By
the terms of the problem we may say anything we please to our listeners,
ask them to perform any experiment whatever, with one proviso: there is
to be no asymmetric object or structure that we and they can observe in
common.\" (Gardner 1990).
Although it is probably impossible to provide an answer to the Ozma
argument it is possible to relate handedness to a conceptual point
observer who spans more than an instant of time. If a point observer is
at the centre of a field of inward pointing space-time vectors then
relative to any given vector there are positive and negative angular
separations. The body is asymmetric and the point observer would lie
within this so always have available a \'head\' direction or a \'foot
direction\' and hence a left and right. Unlike the time extended
observer an instantaneous observer would not contain vectors that
contained directional information and would be no more than a collection
of points in space.
Pooley (2002) discusses handedness in depth and introduces the problem
of parity violation in the Weak Interaction.
### General Covariance and the Hole Argument
The proposal that the universe is four dimensional does not in itself
produce a full physical theory. The assumptions of causality and the
invariance of physical laws between observers are also required to
create modern Relativity Theory. The second assumption, that the laws of
physics are the same for all observers is closely related to the
requirement of **general covariance**.
The principle of general covariance requires that a manifold of events
can be smoothly mapped to another manifold of the same dimension and
back again. This mapping should always give the same result. General
covariance is assumed in General Relativity.
Einstein realised that there was an apparent problem with this
assumption in certain circumstances. In his **hole argument** he
considers a special region of space-time that is devoid of matter and
where the stress-energy tensor vanishes. He then labels the same events
outside the hole with two different coordinate systems. These coordinate
systems could differ by something as simple as having origins that are
separate so the difference is entirely passive. Both systems will give
the same values for the gravitational field outside the hole. It turns
out however that that the systems predict different fields within the
hole (see MacDonald (2001) for the calculation and Norton (1993), (1999)
for a discussion). Einstein overcame this problem by considering active
mappings where particles are actually transferred through the hole. He
concluded that the points where particles meet can be transformed
according to general covariance and hence a relativistic theory could
indeed be constructed. Solutions to the field equations that were
inconsistent with the points defined by interacting particles were
discarded as non-physical.
The hole argument led Einstein to abandon the idea of space and time as
something separate from the material content of the universe. The
General Theory of Relativity becomes a theory of **observables**. He
wrote that:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"That the requirement of general
covariance, which takes away from space and time the last remnant of
physical objectivity, is a natural one, will be seen from the following
reflection. All our space-time verifications invariably amount to a
determination of space-time coincidences. If, for example, events
consisted merely in the motion of material points, then ultimately
nothing would be observable but the meetings of two or more of these
points. Moreover, the results of our measurings are nothing but
verifications of such meetings of the material points of our measuring
instruments with other material points, coincidences between the hands
of the a clock and points on the clock dial, and observed point-events
happening at the same place at the same time. The introduction of a
system of reference serves no other purpose than to facilitate the
description of the totality of such coincidences\".`</font>`{=html}
(Einstein 1916).
This is what would be expected from a four dimensional block universe
with real time. It is a frozen universe of the type discussed earlier.
As Earman (2002) puts it when discussing change:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"First, the roots of the problem
lie in classical GTR, and even if it was decided that it is a mistake to
quantize GTR, there would remain the problem of reconciling the frozen
dynamics of GTR with the B-series notion of change that is supported not
only by common sense but by every physical theory prior to GTR. Second,
although the aspect of the problem that grabs attention is that of time
and change, no solution will be forthcoming without tackling the more
general issue of what an "observable" of classical GTR
is.\"`</font>`{=html}
In such a universe action at a distance is not possible. From the
viewpoint of consciousness studies the limitation of physical concepts
to interactions between particles is a restatement of Ryle\'s regress
and the recursion version of the homunculus problem. If events are no
more than space-time coincidences then we are doomed to the endless
transfer of data from point to point without any conscious observation.
This seems to forbid any true simultaneity in experience and means that
only measurements are possible.
The reduction of physics to the study of particle interactions is fully
relationalist and allows space-time to become a property of these
interactions rather than vice-versa. Once it becomes possible to
consider space-time as a dependent property it is then feasible to
equate *observation* with *measurement*. Observation is normally the
representation of an event in an observer\'s space-time coordinate
system. Measurement is the change in state of a system in response to an
encounter with an event. If we maintain that space-time does not exist
and can be replaced by encounters between particles then observation can
be replaced by measurement. This may well be a way forward for some
approximations to physical reality and may allow us to understand how a
space-time is selected within an observer. As part of this approach the
word \"observable\" is often used interchangeably with \"measurable\".
## Quantum theory and time
### The general problem of QM and time
Quantum physics provides many fundamental insights into the nature of
time. At the simplest level the energy-time version of the Heisenberg
Uncertainty Principle predicts that Quantum Mechanical (QM) interference
should occur between a particle and earlier versions of itself. Such
interference has been observed (see \"The existence of time\" above).
Two of the most complete reviews of the problem of time in quantum
theory available at present are Zeh (2001) and Isham (1993).
Perhaps the most interesting aspect of QM and time is that it can
provide an argument that time does not exist in the universe as a whole.
The argument can be approached from many directions (See Rovelli 2003)
but is clear in the Wheeler-de Witt equation which describes the
wavefunction of the entire universe. This wavefunction has no reference
to time. De Witt explained the emergence of time by proposing that the
universe can be divided into an observer with measuring instruments and
the rest of the universe so that the rest of the universe changes with
respect to the observer.
Rovelli (2003) supports this idea of partition, he considers in depth
the problems of the \"hole argument\" and quantum physics and notes
that, given the assumption that events are just successions of
relations:
\"`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}The unique account of the state
of the world of the classical theory is thus shattered into a
multiplicity of accounts, one for each possible \"observing\" physical
system. Quantum mechanics is a theory about the physical description of
physical systems relative to other systems, and this is a complete
description of the world.`</font>`{=html} (Rovelli 2003).
Barbour (1997) and Hartle and Gell-Mann have both proposed that an
observer is a partition or region with memories that contain the trace
of histories. The histories would represent a B Series. Unfortunately
this leaves the A Series unexplained so time would have a direction but
there would be no \'becoming\'.
Hawking introduces the observer into the problem of time by asking what
sort of universe is compatible with human life. This application of the
**Anthropic Principle** leads to constraints on the form of the
universe, for instance the universe should have galaxies and last for
more than a few million years. The Anthropic Principle is actually a
restatement of the observer problem - if being an observer leads to a
certain division of the universe into observer and observed then the
observed part will have the form given by the Anthropic Principle.
Hartle and Hawking () also tackled the \"boundary problem\" of cosmology
by proposing that there is no boundary. This proposal involves adding a
fifth, time-like, dimension on the imaginary plane so that the universe
at its beginning is a **de Sitter** or **anti de Sitter** space-time.
A de Sitter space-time is characterised by the metric:
$ds^2 = dx^2 + dy^2 + dz^2 + (idt)^2 + du^2$
An anti de Sitter space time has the metric:
$ds^2 = dx^2 + dy^2 + dz^2 + (idt)^2 - du^2$
A de Sitter space time is fascinating from the view point of
consciousness studies because it contains three space-like dimensions,
one real, time-like dimension (u) and one imaginary time-like dimension.
This might give the real and imaginary time-like axes that Franck
proposed were needed to produce the McTaggart A Series. However, the
extra dimension could only be related to the observer in the universe as
it is at present because the extra dimension does not appear to be
required to explain measurables.
### The interpretation of QM
Time is also of interest in the interpretation of quantum mechanics and
entanglement. There are many interpretations of QM such as the
**Operational Interpretation** (Decoherence Theory), the **Transactional
Interpretation**, the **Relational Interpretation**, the **Many Worlds
Interpretation**, the **Copenhagen Interpretation**, the **Bohm
Interpretation**, the **Many Minds Interpretation** etc.
Some of these interpretations, such as the Transactional Interpretation,
allow the connection of entangled quantum states backwards in time along
the path of particles.
Decoherence theory is of particular interest because it allows the
calculation of how long an entangled state can persist. Tegmark (2000)
and Hagan *et al.* (2002) have used this technique to calculate the
decoherence time of entanglement in microtubules and have differed by a
factor of $10^{10}$ because of differing assumptions about the
biophysics of microtubules in the brain.
## Time and conscious experience
In a four dimensional universe time is an independent direction for
arranging things. As an independent direction things arranged in time do
not overlie things arranged in space. This also appears to be the case
in conscious experience where whole words or \"bars of a tune\" can be
experienced arranged in time. This extension in time is easy to
experience but the independence of the time dimension is difficult to
conceive, for instance Le Poidevin (2000) reflects that:
> \"If events e1 and e2 are registered in a single specious present,
> then we perceive them both as present, and so as simultaneous. But we
> do not see, e.g., the successive positions of a moving object as
> simultaneous, for if we did we would see a blurred object and not a
> moving one.\"
This assumes that arrangements in time do not occur in an independent
direction for arranging things and hence would overlay space. In fact
the mystery of conscious experience is deeply related to how we can
experience many things as events that are separate from each other. Our
experience of two dimensional patterns containing many things is as much
a mystery as how we experience temporal patterns extended in time. The
problem is illustrated below:
![](constudsimevent.gif "constudsimevent.gif")
It is as if patterns in conscious experience are being viewed from a
point in at least four dimensions. How our experience can be like the
\'view\' of a conceptual point observer at the apex of a light cone
without the data being overlaid and obscured is a profound mystery,
obviously the data cannot be transferred into the apparent observation
point and appears as nebulous vectors directed at the point. Some
philosophers have noticed this problem.
(*This is a stub, requires an elaboration of Specious Present Theory and
Husserl\'s ideas*)
Le Poidevin (2000). The experience and perception of time. Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
<http://plato.stanford.edu//archives/spr2001/entries/time-experience/#4>
Readers who are unfamiliar with the developments to Newtonian mechanics
that occurred in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries should read
Consciousness Studies/The Philosophical
Problem/Appendixs
See
overleaf
for the philosophical problem continued..:
## The problems of space, qualia, machine and digital consciousness
Click on the above link.
## Notes and References
More\...
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Philosophical Problem Continued#The problem of space
## The problem of space
The problem of Relationalism and Substantivalism has been discussed
earlier. In this section the concept of space will be explored in more
depth.
Space is apparent to us all. It is the existence of many simultaneous
things at an instant. If we see a ship and hear a dog barking on our
left there is space. If we look at a checkerboard there is space. This
occurrence of space in phenomenal experience is similar to the
measurement of space in the world: things that are simultaneously at the
ends of a metre rule are a metre apart; if there is more than one object
at a given instant the objects are separated by space.
Physicists have found that the mathematics of **vector spaces**
describes much of the arrangement of things in the world. In a vector
space the independent directions for arranging things are called
**dimensions**. At any instant physical space has three clearly
observable dimensions.
It has been known for millennia that the three dimensions observable at
an instant are interrelated by **Pythagoras\' Theorem**:
Pythagoras\' theorem on a plane shows that the length of any
displacement is related to the sum of the squares of the displacements
in the independent directions (x and y):
$h^2 = x^2 + y^2$
Pythagoras\' theorem in three dimensions is:
$h^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2$
The advances in geometry in the nineteenth century showed that
Pythagoras\' theorem was a special case of a **metric**, an equation
that describes displacements in terms of the dimensions available. In
the twentieth century it was realised that time was another independent
direction for arranging things that was interrelated to the other three
dimensions. The world is now described as a **four dimensional
manifold**.
The illustration below shows how different numbers of dimensions affect
the arrangement of things.
![](constudspace2.gif "constudspace2.gif")
It is sometimes suggested that our idea of space is due to some sort of
memory that is read out sequentially. This is unlikely because, at any
instant a one dimensional form cannot be made to overlie a two
dimensional form and a two dimensional form cannot overlie a three
dimensional form etc. One dimensional forms are not *congruent* with two
dimensional forms. This means that a one dimensional form such as
*virtual memory* cannot, at any instant, overlie two dimensional forms
such as occur in phenomenal experience and hence experience does not
supervene on the idea of virtual memory (See section on functionalism
as a one dimensional Turing
Machine).
Curiously the idea of *mental space* is often denied. McGinn(1995) gives
such a denial:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}We perceive, by our various sense
organs, a variety of material objects laid out in space, taking up
certain volumes and separated by certain distances. We thus conceive of
these perceptual objects as spatial entities; perception informs us
directly of their spatiality. But conscious subjects and their mental
states are not in this way perceptual objects. We do not see or hear or
smell or touch them, and a fortiori do not perceive them as spatially
individuated.(2) This holds both for the first- and third-person
perspectives. Since we do not observe our own states of consciousness,
nor those of others, we do not apprehend these states as spatial.
`</font>`{=html} McGinn(1995).
This denial is strange because it begins by describing phenomenal
experience as clearly spatial and then proceeds to argue that there is
some other thing, the \"mental state\", which is non-spatial. This seems
to contradict our everday life where our experience is our experience,
there is no other experience. The issue is whether this experience is
things in themselves (Direct Realism) or some other form in the brain
(Indirect Realism). The illustration below shows how space occurs in
phenomenal experience; it sidesteps the issue of the location of the
contents of phenomenal consciousness.
![](constudspace.gif "constudspace.gif")
McGinn (1995) gives a description of how phenomenal experience cannot be
overlaid by a 3D model of events in the brain:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Consider a visual experience, E,
as of a yellow flash. Associated with E in the cortex is a complex of
neural structures and events, N, which does admit of spatial
description. N occurs, say, an inch from the back of the head; it
extends over some specific area of the cortex; it has some kind of
configuration or contour; it is composed of spatial parts that aggregate
into a structured whole; it exists in three spatial dimensions; it
excludes other neural complexes from its spatial location. N is a
regular denizen of space, as much as any other physical entity. But E
seems not to have any of these spatial characteristics: it is not
located at any specific place; it takes up no particular volume of
space; it has no shape; it is not made up of spatially distributed
parts; it has no spatial dimensionality; it is not solid. Even to ask
for its spatial properties is to commit some sort of category mistake,
analogous to asking for the spatial properties of numbers. E seems not
to be the kind of thing that falls under spatial predicates. It falls
under temporal predicates\... `</font>`{=html}McGinn(1995)
He concludes that a 3D form can only be rearranged into the form of the
things in experience over a succession of instants (\"It falls under
temporal predicates\"). This is highly suggestive of phenomenal
experience having more than three dimensions in the same way as an
ordinary physical thing or field has more than three dimensions.
## The problem of qualia
A quality of an object such as its colour, roughness, temperature etc.
is known as a **quale**, the plural of quale is **qualia**. Qualia are
the contents of phenomenal consciousness. The term \"qualia\" is
sometimes extended to all mental aspects of an object such as roundness,
size and even relative position.
### The physics of qualia
According to physicalism qualia must be things in the universe. But what
are \"things in the universe\" and which of these are qualia?
If we wish to explain phenomenal experience we must first decide whether
experience is a measurement or things themselves. Measurement begins
with a quantum mechanical interaction between an instrument and a set of
particles, this then creates a *signal* which is a change in the state
of the instrument. As an example, a mercury thermometer interacts with
the fluid around it which results in a signal in the form of a moving
column of mercury in the thermometer. As another example, a measuring
rule is aligned with the two ends of an object by a servomechanism that
interacts with photons from the rule and the object, the signal being
the markings that align with the end of the object.
The signal can be a flow of charge or photons or a chemical change etc.
Sensory experience begins with the interaction between an object that
acts as a measuring instrument and a set of particles such as photons or
scent molecules etc. In the Direct Realist case the signal would be the
change at the interface between the bulk of a material (a crude
measuring device) and a set of particles such as photons, in the
Indirect Realist case it would be some signal in the brain derived from
the initial signal. In either case phenomenal consciousness would be
some form, an arrangement of the set of signals themselves.
The signals in measuring events arise as a result of interactions
between QM phenomena and a measuring apparatus composed of relatively
large structures. These structures (called *the environment*) produce
signals at definite locations. This chain of fixing positions is known
as **decoherence** (see Zurek (2003) or Bacciagaluppi (2004) for a
review). This means that measuring events fix the positions of signals
and these represent the positions of QM events. (Some physical particles
such as photons are subject to little decoherence during propagation,
even in water (cf: Anglin & Zurek (1996)).)
So signals in measuring devices usually have highly restrained
positions. Now consider the final signals, the one\'s in phenomenal
consciousness. To an observer of the brain they should be, very nearly,
in their classical positions within the brain unless they consist of
photons or are subject to some special effect such as has been proposed
for microtubules. The brain acts as a measuring device causing
decoherence. But despite this even signals composed of sodium ions,
which should decohere rapidly in water, have a tiny, but finite,
probability of remaining in a coherent state.
If your conscious experience is the signals and not the fabric of the
brain are you the set of signals that interacts with the brain fabric
almost immediately, the set that interacts after a minute or the set
that almost never interacts? To an outside observer you must be the main
chance, the rapidly interacting signals, but to the signals themselves
all possibilities exist. Which one are you? Certainly any interaction
between the signals and the mutually observed world must involve
decoherence but the external observer would find it difficult to
determine whether a particular interaction was due to signals that had
interacted immediately or ones that were delayed (or delayed in an
alternate QM reality). This problem is part of the *preferred basis
problem* that will be discussed later.
Zurek (2003)assumes that phenomenal experience is identical to
measurements. The observer is then both the signal and the apparatus
that encloses the signal. He summarises the resultant idea of the
completely determined observer who is fully integrated into the measured
world:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}The 'higher functions' of
observers - e.g., consciousness, etc. - may be at present poorly
understood, but it is safe to assume that they reflect physical
processes in the information processing hardware of the brain. Hence,
mental processes are in effect objective, as they leave an indelible
imprint on the environment: The observer has no chance of perceiving
either his memory, or any other macroscopic part of the Universe in some
arbitrary superposition. \"`</font>`{=html} Zurek (2003)
Notice the phrase \"perceiving .. his memory\" - as neuroscientists we
must ask \"how\"? By more measurements? There are no more measurements
when things are arranged in phenomenal consciousness, the information
has nowhere else to go. However, according to the empiricist
philosophers the arrangements of the signals in phenomenal consciousness
do extend through time in a definite order at any instant. Is it this
order that determines the positions of signals in the brain or is it the
brain that determines this order?
Physicalism leads us to an idea of the content of consciousness as an
arrangement of quantum fields like the content of the brain or the
content of the world. The arrangement of the quantum fields at an
instant in experience is probably related to the arrangement of measured
events at a succession of instants in the world.
According to the account given above, the contents of conscious
experience, the qualia, are signals derived from the world that compose
conscious experience with the interesting problem that they are
themselves the experience and are not fixed in space and time by further
measurement.
### The philosophy of qualia
The term \"qualia\" was introduced by C.I. Lewis in 1929:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}This given element in a single
experience of an object is what will be meant by \"a presentation.\"
Such a presentation is, obviously, an event and historically unique. But
for most of the purposes of analyzing knowledge one presentation of a
half-dollar held at right angles to the line of vision, etc., will be as
good as another. If, then, I speak of \" the presentation\" of this or
that, it will be on the supposition that the reader can provide his own
illustration. No identification of the event itself with the repeatable
content of it is intended.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}In any presentation, this content
is either a specific quale (such as the immediacy of redness or
loudness) or something analyzable into a complex of such. The
presentation as an event is, of course, unique, but the qualia which
make it up are not. They are recognizable from one to another
experience.(CI Lewis, *Mind and the World Order*, 1941 edition Chapter
2)`</font>`{=html}
Tye (2003) gives the following definition of qualia:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Experiences vary widely. For
example, I run my fingers over sandpaper, smell a skunk, feel a sharp
pain in my finger, seem to see bright purple, become extremely angry. In
each of these cases, I am the subject of a mental state with a very
distinctive subjective character. There is something it is like for me
to undergo each state, some phenomenology that it has. Philosophers
often use the term \'qualia\' to refer to the introspectively accessible
properties of experiences that characterize what it is like to have
them. In this standard, broad sense of the term, it is very difficult to
deny that there are qualia.\"`</font>`{=html} Tye(2003).
In philosophy objects are considered to have perceived features such as
shape and colour, weight and texture which are called sensible
qualities. Sensible qualities are divided into intrinsic, or primary,
qualities that are properties of the object itself and extrinsic, or
secondary, qualities which are related to the sensations produced in the
observer. Shape is generally considered to be a primary quality whereas
colour is often considered to be a secondary quality. It is generally
considered that secondary qualities correspond to qualia (Smith 1990,
Shoemaker 1990) and the two terms are often used synonymously. Although
secondary qualities may be qualia, the term \"qualia\" may include
things other than perceptions such as pain etc. that are, arguably, not
secondary qualities. Primary qualities might also give rise to
experience that is distinct from, say, the shape of an object itself.
Although \"qualia\" is a recent term, the philosophical debate about the
nature of secondary qualities, such as colours, and the nature of
conscious experience itself has been around for millennia.
It seems that the visual system gives rise to experience even in the
absence of previous visual stimulation. For example, when someone
recovers from blindness they have an experience that contains shapes and
colours even though these have little meaning:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"When he first saw, he was so far
from making any judgement of distances, that he thought all object
whatever touched his eyes\.... he knew not the shape of anything, nor
any one thing from another, however different in shape and magnitude..
We thought he soon knew what pictures represented, which were shewed to
him, but we found afterwards we were mistaken; for about two months
after he was couched, he discovered at once they represented solid
bodiess, when to that time he considered them only as party-coloured
panes, or surfaces diversified with variety of paint.\"`</font>`{=html}
William Cheselden (1728)
Qualia are the components of experience, whatever the mode of input to
that experience. Strawson (1994) includes content such as accompanies
suddenly remembering or thinking of something as examples of qualia.
There is thought to be an *explanatory gap* associated with qualia
(Levine 1983), as an example it is hard to imagine how the experience
called pain could be a set of impulses in the brain.
Some philosophers have attempted to bridge this gap by invoking Direct
Realism, proposing that our experience is in some way \'transparent\' so
that we experience the world or the injured limb directly (i.e.: there
is an assumption that things flow within phenomenal experience into a
centre point and we see right through this flow!). This idea has led to
a deduction that phenomenal experience is a set of things and qualities
are these things, not deductions about or experiences based on these
things. As Tye (2003) puts it:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}These observations suggest that
qualia, conceived of as the immediately \'felt\' qualities of
experiences of which we are cognizant when we attend to them
introspectively, do not really exist. The qualities of which we are
aware are not qualities of experiences at all, but rather qualities
that, if they are qualities of anything, are qualities of things in the
world (as in the case of perceptual experiences) or of regions of our
bodies (as in the case of bodily sensations). This is not to say that
experiences do not have qualia. The point is that qualia are not
qualities of experiences. `</font>`{=html}
However, the outstanding issue for Tye\'s analysis is where in the world
the thing that is called a quale exists - on a thing in the world beyond
the body, on the retina, in the cortex, in the thalamus? Tye seems to be
suggesting that \"in the world\" can only be beyond the retina but given
that a television can have a colour and a retina can have a colour why
should we insist that the colour in conscious experience is always *of*
the thing being represented via the DVD or videotape? That colour should
always be a property of an original coloured object seems strange, why
is it not a property of the pigment in a photo of the object, a property
of an led in a computer screen displaying an image of the photo, a
property of the pigments in the retina viewing the computer, the
impulses in the visual cortex etc.?
As was seen in the previous section, only signals are available in the
classical world of conscious observation. The \"reality\" of the things
that generate signals is not available. So whether experience is a
signal at the position of what we call an \"oak tree\" or a signal in
the eye due to photons reflected from the tree or a signal in the brain
the same sort of phenomena would apply. Qualia would be a field, an
arrangement of signals, not processes based on these signals.
Some philosophers hold that qualia are a field of signals derived from
the original signals that are next to the quantum phenomena that compose
an object. In other words they propose that qualia are not the first
signals in the chain from whatever composes an object to the observer.
These philosophers are known as Representationalists and the emphasis on
secondary signals allows a contribution from the brain etc. to the field
of signals that is conscious experience. Modern representationalists
such as Tye (1995), Lehar(2003) and Dretske(2003) emphasise the idea
that qualia are actual things that represent objects rather than
concepts or experiences of things. As Dretske puts it:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"..the features that define what
it is like to have an experience are properties that the objects we
experience (not our experience of them) have.`</font>`{=html}(Dretske
2003).
Lehar(2003) uses modern language to express the empiricist notion that
the signals that comprise qualia are more likely to be in our brains
than elsewhere, according to Lehar the objects we experience must be
informational replicas in our heads:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"The central message of Gestalt
theory therefore is that the primary function of perceptual processing
is the generation of a miniature, virtual-reality replica of the
external world inside our head, and that the world we see around us is
not the real external world, but is exactly that miniature internal
replica\" (Lehar 2003).`</font>`{=html}
Direct Realists and Representationalists share the same view that qualia
are an actual, physical field of things somewhere in the world. Some
functionalists and eliminativists take a different view, believing that
qualia do not exist except as judgements of properties that are used in
interactions (i.e.: as disembodied information - see the section on
Direct Realism).
Lewis, C.I. (1929) Mind and the World-Order.
<http://www.ditext.com/lewis/mwo2.html> Smith, A.D. (1990) Of Primary
and Secondary Qualities, Philosophical Review 99 (1990).
### More about qualia
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Philosophical Problem Continued#The problem of qualia
## The problem of space
The problem of Relationalism and Substantivalism has been discussed
earlier. In this section the concept of space will be explored in more
depth.
Space is apparent to us all. It is the existence of many simultaneous
things at an instant. If we see a ship and hear a dog barking on our
left there is space. If we look at a checkerboard there is space. This
occurrence of space in phenomenal experience is similar to the
measurement of space in the world: things that are simultaneously at the
ends of a metre rule are a metre apart; if there is more than one object
at a given instant the objects are separated by space.
Physicists have found that the mathematics of **vector spaces**
describes much of the arrangement of things in the world. In a vector
space the independent directions for arranging things are called
**dimensions**. At any instant physical space has three clearly
observable dimensions.
It has been known for millennia that the three dimensions observable at
an instant are interrelated by **Pythagoras\' Theorem**:
Pythagoras\' theorem on a plane shows that the length of any
displacement is related to the sum of the squares of the displacements
in the independent directions (x and y):
$h^2 = x^2 + y^2$
Pythagoras\' theorem in three dimensions is:
$h^2 = x^2 + y^2 + z^2$
The advances in geometry in the nineteenth century showed that
Pythagoras\' theorem was a special case of a **metric**, an equation
that describes displacements in terms of the dimensions available. In
the twentieth century it was realised that time was another independent
direction for arranging things that was interrelated to the other three
dimensions. The world is now described as a **four dimensional
manifold**.
The illustration below shows how different numbers of dimensions affect
the arrangement of things.
![](constudspace2.gif "constudspace2.gif")
It is sometimes suggested that our idea of space is due to some sort of
memory that is read out sequentially. This is unlikely because, at any
instant a one dimensional form cannot be made to overlie a two
dimensional form and a two dimensional form cannot overlie a three
dimensional form etc. One dimensional forms are not *congruent* with two
dimensional forms. This means that a one dimensional form such as
*virtual memory* cannot, at any instant, overlie two dimensional forms
such as occur in phenomenal experience and hence experience does not
supervene on the idea of virtual memory (See section on functionalism
as a one dimensional Turing
Machine).
Curiously the idea of *mental space* is often denied. McGinn(1995) gives
such a denial:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}We perceive, by our various sense
organs, a variety of material objects laid out in space, taking up
certain volumes and separated by certain distances. We thus conceive of
these perceptual objects as spatial entities; perception informs us
directly of their spatiality. But conscious subjects and their mental
states are not in this way perceptual objects. We do not see or hear or
smell or touch them, and a fortiori do not perceive them as spatially
individuated.(2) This holds both for the first- and third-person
perspectives. Since we do not observe our own states of consciousness,
nor those of others, we do not apprehend these states as spatial.
`</font>`{=html} McGinn(1995).
This denial is strange because it begins by describing phenomenal
experience as clearly spatial and then proceeds to argue that there is
some other thing, the \"mental state\", which is non-spatial. This seems
to contradict our everday life where our experience is our experience,
there is no other experience. The issue is whether this experience is
things in themselves (Direct Realism) or some other form in the brain
(Indirect Realism). The illustration below shows how space occurs in
phenomenal experience; it sidesteps the issue of the location of the
contents of phenomenal consciousness.
![](constudspace.gif "constudspace.gif")
McGinn (1995) gives a description of how phenomenal experience cannot be
overlaid by a 3D model of events in the brain:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Consider a visual experience, E,
as of a yellow flash. Associated with E in the cortex is a complex of
neural structures and events, N, which does admit of spatial
description. N occurs, say, an inch from the back of the head; it
extends over some specific area of the cortex; it has some kind of
configuration or contour; it is composed of spatial parts that aggregate
into a structured whole; it exists in three spatial dimensions; it
excludes other neural complexes from its spatial location. N is a
regular denizen of space, as much as any other physical entity. But E
seems not to have any of these spatial characteristics: it is not
located at any specific place; it takes up no particular volume of
space; it has no shape; it is not made up of spatially distributed
parts; it has no spatial dimensionality; it is not solid. Even to ask
for its spatial properties is to commit some sort of category mistake,
analogous to asking for the spatial properties of numbers. E seems not
to be the kind of thing that falls under spatial predicates. It falls
under temporal predicates\... `</font>`{=html}McGinn(1995)
He concludes that a 3D form can only be rearranged into the form of the
things in experience over a succession of instants (\"It falls under
temporal predicates\"). This is highly suggestive of phenomenal
experience having more than three dimensions in the same way as an
ordinary physical thing or field has more than three dimensions.
## The problem of qualia
A quality of an object such as its colour, roughness, temperature etc.
is known as a **quale**, the plural of quale is **qualia**. Qualia are
the contents of phenomenal consciousness. The term \"qualia\" is
sometimes extended to all mental aspects of an object such as roundness,
size and even relative position.
### The physics of qualia
According to physicalism qualia must be things in the universe. But what
are \"things in the universe\" and which of these are qualia?
If we wish to explain phenomenal experience we must first decide whether
experience is a measurement or things themselves. Measurement begins
with a quantum mechanical interaction between an instrument and a set of
particles, this then creates a *signal* which is a change in the state
of the instrument. As an example, a mercury thermometer interacts with
the fluid around it which results in a signal in the form of a moving
column of mercury in the thermometer. As another example, a measuring
rule is aligned with the two ends of an object by a servomechanism that
interacts with photons from the rule and the object, the signal being
the markings that align with the end of the object.
The signal can be a flow of charge or photons or a chemical change etc.
Sensory experience begins with the interaction between an object that
acts as a measuring instrument and a set of particles such as photons or
scent molecules etc. In the Direct Realist case the signal would be the
change at the interface between the bulk of a material (a crude
measuring device) and a set of particles such as photons, in the
Indirect Realist case it would be some signal in the brain derived from
the initial signal. In either case phenomenal consciousness would be
some form, an arrangement of the set of signals themselves.
The signals in measuring events arise as a result of interactions
between QM phenomena and a measuring apparatus composed of relatively
large structures. These structures (called *the environment*) produce
signals at definite locations. This chain of fixing positions is known
as **decoherence** (see Zurek (2003) or Bacciagaluppi (2004) for a
review). This means that measuring events fix the positions of signals
and these represent the positions of QM events. (Some physical particles
such as photons are subject to little decoherence during propagation,
even in water (cf: Anglin & Zurek (1996)).)
So signals in measuring devices usually have highly restrained
positions. Now consider the final signals, the one\'s in phenomenal
consciousness. To an observer of the brain they should be, very nearly,
in their classical positions within the brain unless they consist of
photons or are subject to some special effect such as has been proposed
for microtubules. The brain acts as a measuring device causing
decoherence. But despite this even signals composed of sodium ions,
which should decohere rapidly in water, have a tiny, but finite,
probability of remaining in a coherent state.
If your conscious experience is the signals and not the fabric of the
brain are you the set of signals that interacts with the brain fabric
almost immediately, the set that interacts after a minute or the set
that almost never interacts? To an outside observer you must be the main
chance, the rapidly interacting signals, but to the signals themselves
all possibilities exist. Which one are you? Certainly any interaction
between the signals and the mutually observed world must involve
decoherence but the external observer would find it difficult to
determine whether a particular interaction was due to signals that had
interacted immediately or ones that were delayed (or delayed in an
alternate QM reality). This problem is part of the *preferred basis
problem* that will be discussed later.
Zurek (2003)assumes that phenomenal experience is identical to
measurements. The observer is then both the signal and the apparatus
that encloses the signal. He summarises the resultant idea of the
completely determined observer who is fully integrated into the measured
world:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}The 'higher functions' of
observers - e.g., consciousness, etc. - may be at present poorly
understood, but it is safe to assume that they reflect physical
processes in the information processing hardware of the brain. Hence,
mental processes are in effect objective, as they leave an indelible
imprint on the environment: The observer has no chance of perceiving
either his memory, or any other macroscopic part of the Universe in some
arbitrary superposition. \"`</font>`{=html} Zurek (2003)
Notice the phrase \"perceiving .. his memory\" - as neuroscientists we
must ask \"how\"? By more measurements? There are no more measurements
when things are arranged in phenomenal consciousness, the information
has nowhere else to go. However, according to the empiricist
philosophers the arrangements of the signals in phenomenal consciousness
do extend through time in a definite order at any instant. Is it this
order that determines the positions of signals in the brain or is it the
brain that determines this order?
Physicalism leads us to an idea of the content of consciousness as an
arrangement of quantum fields like the content of the brain or the
content of the world. The arrangement of the quantum fields at an
instant in experience is probably related to the arrangement of measured
events at a succession of instants in the world.
According to the account given above, the contents of conscious
experience, the qualia, are signals derived from the world that compose
conscious experience with the interesting problem that they are
themselves the experience and are not fixed in space and time by further
measurement.
### The philosophy of qualia
The term \"qualia\" was introduced by C.I. Lewis in 1929:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}This given element in a single
experience of an object is what will be meant by \"a presentation.\"
Such a presentation is, obviously, an event and historically unique. But
for most of the purposes of analyzing knowledge one presentation of a
half-dollar held at right angles to the line of vision, etc., will be as
good as another. If, then, I speak of \" the presentation\" of this or
that, it will be on the supposition that the reader can provide his own
illustration. No identification of the event itself with the repeatable
content of it is intended.`</font>`{=html}
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}In any presentation, this content
is either a specific quale (such as the immediacy of redness or
loudness) or something analyzable into a complex of such. The
presentation as an event is, of course, unique, but the qualia which
make it up are not. They are recognizable from one to another
experience.(CI Lewis, *Mind and the World Order*, 1941 edition Chapter
2)`</font>`{=html}
Tye (2003) gives the following definition of qualia:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Experiences vary widely. For
example, I run my fingers over sandpaper, smell a skunk, feel a sharp
pain in my finger, seem to see bright purple, become extremely angry. In
each of these cases, I am the subject of a mental state with a very
distinctive subjective character. There is something it is like for me
to undergo each state, some phenomenology that it has. Philosophers
often use the term \'qualia\' to refer to the introspectively accessible
properties of experiences that characterize what it is like to have
them. In this standard, broad sense of the term, it is very difficult to
deny that there are qualia.\"`</font>`{=html} Tye(2003).
In philosophy objects are considered to have perceived features such as
shape and colour, weight and texture which are called sensible
qualities. Sensible qualities are divided into intrinsic, or primary,
qualities that are properties of the object itself and extrinsic, or
secondary, qualities which are related to the sensations produced in the
observer. Shape is generally considered to be a primary quality whereas
colour is often considered to be a secondary quality. It is generally
considered that secondary qualities correspond to qualia (Smith 1990,
Shoemaker 1990) and the two terms are often used synonymously. Although
secondary qualities may be qualia, the term \"qualia\" may include
things other than perceptions such as pain etc. that are, arguably, not
secondary qualities. Primary qualities might also give rise to
experience that is distinct from, say, the shape of an object itself.
Although \"qualia\" is a recent term, the philosophical debate about the
nature of secondary qualities, such as colours, and the nature of
conscious experience itself has been around for millennia.
It seems that the visual system gives rise to experience even in the
absence of previous visual stimulation. For example, when someone
recovers from blindness they have an experience that contains shapes and
colours even though these have little meaning:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"When he first saw, he was so far
from making any judgement of distances, that he thought all object
whatever touched his eyes\.... he knew not the shape of anything, nor
any one thing from another, however different in shape and magnitude..
We thought he soon knew what pictures represented, which were shewed to
him, but we found afterwards we were mistaken; for about two months
after he was couched, he discovered at once they represented solid
bodiess, when to that time he considered them only as party-coloured
panes, or surfaces diversified with variety of paint.\"`</font>`{=html}
William Cheselden (1728)
Qualia are the components of experience, whatever the mode of input to
that experience. Strawson (1994) includes content such as accompanies
suddenly remembering or thinking of something as examples of qualia.
There is thought to be an *explanatory gap* associated with qualia
(Levine 1983), as an example it is hard to imagine how the experience
called pain could be a set of impulses in the brain.
Some philosophers have attempted to bridge this gap by invoking Direct
Realism, proposing that our experience is in some way \'transparent\' so
that we experience the world or the injured limb directly (i.e.: there
is an assumption that things flow within phenomenal experience into a
centre point and we see right through this flow!). This idea has led to
a deduction that phenomenal experience is a set of things and qualities
are these things, not deductions about or experiences based on these
things. As Tye (2003) puts it:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}These observations suggest that
qualia, conceived of as the immediately \'felt\' qualities of
experiences of which we are cognizant when we attend to them
introspectively, do not really exist. The qualities of which we are
aware are not qualities of experiences at all, but rather qualities
that, if they are qualities of anything, are qualities of things in the
world (as in the case of perceptual experiences) or of regions of our
bodies (as in the case of bodily sensations). This is not to say that
experiences do not have qualia. The point is that qualia are not
qualities of experiences. `</font>`{=html}
However, the outstanding issue for Tye\'s analysis is where in the world
the thing that is called a quale exists - on a thing in the world beyond
the body, on the retina, in the cortex, in the thalamus? Tye seems to be
suggesting that \"in the world\" can only be beyond the retina but given
that a television can have a colour and a retina can have a colour why
should we insist that the colour in conscious experience is always *of*
the thing being represented via the DVD or videotape? That colour should
always be a property of an original coloured object seems strange, why
is it not a property of the pigment in a photo of the object, a property
of an led in a computer screen displaying an image of the photo, a
property of the pigments in the retina viewing the computer, the
impulses in the visual cortex etc.?
As was seen in the previous section, only signals are available in the
classical world of conscious observation. The \"reality\" of the things
that generate signals is not available. So whether experience is a
signal at the position of what we call an \"oak tree\" or a signal in
the eye due to photons reflected from the tree or a signal in the brain
the same sort of phenomena would apply. Qualia would be a field, an
arrangement of signals, not processes based on these signals.
Some philosophers hold that qualia are a field of signals derived from
the original signals that are next to the quantum phenomena that compose
an object. In other words they propose that qualia are not the first
signals in the chain from whatever composes an object to the observer.
These philosophers are known as Representationalists and the emphasis on
secondary signals allows a contribution from the brain etc. to the field
of signals that is conscious experience. Modern representationalists
such as Tye (1995), Lehar(2003) and Dretske(2003) emphasise the idea
that qualia are actual things that represent objects rather than
concepts or experiences of things. As Dretske puts it:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"..the features that define what
it is like to have an experience are properties that the objects we
experience (not our experience of them) have.`</font>`{=html}(Dretske
2003).
Lehar(2003) uses modern language to express the empiricist notion that
the signals that comprise qualia are more likely to be in our brains
than elsewhere, according to Lehar the objects we experience must be
informational replicas in our heads:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"The central message of Gestalt
theory therefore is that the primary function of perceptual processing
is the generation of a miniature, virtual-reality replica of the
external world inside our head, and that the world we see around us is
not the real external world, but is exactly that miniature internal
replica\" (Lehar 2003).`</font>`{=html}
Direct Realists and Representationalists share the same view that qualia
are an actual, physical field of things somewhere in the world. Some
functionalists and eliminativists take a different view, believing that
qualia do not exist except as judgements of properties that are used in
interactions (i.e.: as disembodied information - see the section on
Direct Realism).
Lewis, C.I. (1929) Mind and the World-Order.
<http://www.ditext.com/lewis/mwo2.html> Smith, A.D. (1990) Of Primary
and Secondary Qualities, Philosophical Review 99 (1990).
### More about qualia
|
# Consciousness Studies/Measurement In Quantum Physics And The Preferred Basis Problem
## The Measurement Problem
In quantum physics the probability of an event is deduced by taking the
square of the **amplitude** for an event to happen. The term \"amplitude
for an event\" arises because of the way that the Schrödinger equation
is derived using the mathematics of ordinary, classical waves where the
amplitude over a small area is related to the number of photons hitting
the area. In the case of light, the probability of a photon hitting that
area will be related to the ratio of the number of photons hitting the
area divided by the total number of photons released. The number of
photons hitting an area per second is the intensity or amplitude of the
light on the area, hence the probability of finding a photon is related
to \"amplitude\".
However, the Schrödinger equation is not a classical wave equation. It
does not determine events, it simply tells us the probability of an
event. In fact the Schrödinger equation in itself does not tell us that
an event occurs at all, it is only when a measurement is made that an
event occurs. The measurement is said to cause *state vector reduction*.
This role of measurement in quantum theory is known as the **measurement
problem**. The measurement problem asks how a definite event can arise
out of a theory that only predicts a continuous probability for events.
Two broad classes of theory have been advanced to explain the
measurement problem. In the first it is proposed that observation
produces a sudden change in the quantum system so that a particle
becomes localised or has a definite momentum. This type of explanation
is known as *collapse of the wavefunction*. In the second it is proposed
that the probabilistic Schrödinger equation is always correct and that,
for some reason, the observer only observes one particular outcome for
an event. This type of explanation is known as the *relative state
interpretation*. In the past thirty years relative state
interpretations, especially Everett\'s relative state interpretation
have become favoured amongst quantum physicists.
## The quantum probability problem
The measurement problem is particularly problematical when a single
particle is considered. Quantum theory differs from classical theory
because it is found that a single photon seems to be able to interfere
with itself. If there are many photons then probabilities can be
expressed in terms of the ratio of the number hitting a particular place
to the total number released but if there is only one photon then this
does not make sense. When only one photon is released from a light
source quantum theory still gives us a probability for a photon to hit a
particular area but what does this mean at any instant if there is
indeed only one photon?
If the Everettian interpretation of quantum mechanics is invoked then it
might seem that the probability of the photon hitting an area in your
particular universe is related to the occurrences of the photon in all
the other universes. But in the Everrettian interpretation even the
improbable universes occur. This leads to a problem known as the quantum
**probability problem**:
`If the universe splits after a measurement, with every possible `\
`measurement outcome realised in some branch, then how can it make `\
`sense to talk about the probabilities of each outcome? Each `\
`outcome occurs.`
This means that if our phenomenal consciousness is a set of events then
there would be endless copies of these sets of events, almost all of
which are almost entirely improbable to an observer outside the brain
but all of which exist according to an Everrettian Interpretation. Which
set is you? Why should \'you\' conform to what happens in the
environment around you?
## The preferred basis problem
It could be held that you assess probabilities in terms of the branch of
the universe in which you find yourself but then why do you find
yourself in a particular branch? Decoherence Theory is one approach to
these questions. In decoherence theory the environment is a complex form
that can only interact with particles in particular ways. As a result
quantum phenomena are rapidly smoothed out in a series of
micro-measurements so that the macro-scale universe appears
quasi-classical. The form of the environment is known as the preferred
basis for quantum decoherence. This then leads to the **preferred basis
problem** in which it is asked how the environment occurs or whether the
state of the environment depends on any other system.
According to most forms of decoherence theory \'you\' are a part of the
environment and hence determined by the preferred basis. From the
viewpoint of phenomenal consciousness this does not seem unreasonable
because it has always been understood that the conscious observer does
not observe things as quantum superpositions. The conscious observation
is a classical observation.
However, the arguments that are used to derive this idea of the
classical, conscious observer contain dubious assumptions that may be
hindering the progress of quantum physics. The assumption that the
conscious observer is simply an information system is particularly
dubious:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"Here we are using aware in a
down - to - earth sense: Quite simply, observers know what they know.
Their information processing machinery (that must underlie higher
functions of the mind such as \"consciousness\") can readily consult the
content of their memory. `</font>`{=html}(Zurek 2003).
This assumption is the same as assuming that the conscious observer is a
set of measurements rather than an observation. It makes the rest of
Zurek\'s argument about decoherence and the observer into a tautology -
given that observations are measurements then observations will be like
measurements. However, conscious observation is not simply a change of
state in a neuron, a \"measurement\", it is the entire manifold of
conscious experience.
In his 2003 review of this topic Zurek makes clear an important feature
of information theory when he states that:
`There is no information without representation.`
So the contents of conscious observation are states that correspond to
states of the environment in the brain (i.e.: measurements). But how do
these states in the brain arise? The issue that arises here is whether
the representation, the contents of consciousness, is entirely due to
the environment or due to some degree to the form of conscious
observation. Suppose we make the reasonable assumption that conscious
observation is due to some physical field in the dendrites of neurons
rather than in the action potentials that transmit the state of the
neurons from place to place. This field would not necessarily be
constrained by decoherence; there are many possibilities for the field,
for instance, it could be a radio frequency field due to impulses or
some other electromagnetic field (cf: Anglin & Zurek (1996)) or some
quantum state of macromolecules etc.. Such a field might contain many
superposed possibilities for the state of the underlying neurons and
although these would not affect sensations, they could affect the firing
patterns of neurons and create actions in the world that are not
determined by the environmental \"preferred basis\".
Zeh (2000) provides a mature review of the problem of conscious
observation. For example he realises that memory is not the same as
consciousness:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"The genuine carriers of
consciousness \... must not in general be expected to represent memory
states, as there do not seem to be permanent contents of
consciousness.\"`</font>`{=html}
and notes of memory states that they must enter some other system to
become part of observation:
`<font face="times new roman">`{=html}\"To most of these states,
however, the true physical carrier of consciousness somewhere in the
brain may still represent an external observer system, with whom they
have to interact in order to be perceived. Regardless of whether the
ultimate observer systems are quasi-classical or possess essential
quantum aspects, consciousness can only be related to factor states (of
systems assumed to be localized in the brain) that appear in branches
(robust components) of the global wave function --- provided the
Schrodinger equation is exact. Environmental decoherence represents
entanglement (but not any "distortion" --- of the brain, in this case),
while ensembles of wave functions, representing various potential
(unpredictable) outcomes, would require a dynamical collapse (that has
never been observed).\"`</font>`{=html}
However, Zeh (2003) points out that events may be irreversibly
determined by decoherence before information from them reaches the
observer. This might give rise to a multiple worlds and multiple minds
mixture for the universe, the multiple minds being superposed states of
the part of the world that is the mind. Such an interpretation would be
consistent with the *apparently* epiphenomenal nature of mind. A mind
that interacts only weakly with the consensus physical world, perhaps
only approving or rejecting passing actions would be an ideal candidate
for a QM multiple minds hypothesis.
## Further reading and references
- Anglin, J.R. & Zurek, J.H. (1996). Decoherence of quantum fields:
decoherence and predictability. Phys.Rev. D53 (1996) 7327-7335
<http://arxiv.org/PS_cache/quant-ph/pdf/9510/9510021.pdf>
- Baker, D.J. (2004). Lingering Problems with Probability in
Everettian Quantum Mechanics
<http://www.princeton.edu/~hhalvors/teaching/phi538_f2004/LingeringProbsEverett.pdf>
- Lockwood, M. (1996) Many Minds Interpretations of quantum mechanics.
The British Journal of the Philosophy of Science. 47: 2 (159-188).
<http://www.ibiblio.org/weidai/Many_Minds.pdf>
- Pearl, P. (1997). True collapse and false collapse. Published in
Quantum Classical Correspondence: Proceedings of the 4th Drexel
Symposium on Quantum Nonintegrability, Philadelphia, PA, USA,
September 8--11, 1994, pp. 51--68. Edited by Da Hsuan Feng and Bei
Lok Hu. Cambridge, MA: International Press, 1997.
<http://arxiv.org/PS_cache/quant-ph/pdf/9805/9805049.pdf>
- Squires, E.J. (1996). What are quantum theorists doing at a
conference on consciousness?
<http://arxiv.org/PS_cache/quant-ph/pdf/9602/9602006.pdf>
- Zeh, H. D. (1979). Quantum Theory and Time Asymmetry. Foundations of
Physics, Vol 9, pp 803--818 (1979).
- Zeh, H.D. (2000) THE PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUS OBSERVATION IN QUANTUM
MECHANICAL DESCRIPTION. Epistemological Letters of the
Ferdinand-Gonseth Association in Biel (Switzerland) Letter No
63.0.1981, updated 2000. <http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9908084>
- Zeh, H.D. (2003). Decoherence and the Appearance of a Classical
World in Quantum Theory, second edition, Authors:. E. Joos, H.D.
Zeh, C. Kiefer D. Giulini, J. Kupsch, and I.-O. Stamatescu. Chapter
2: Basic Concepts and their Interpretation.
<http://www.rzuser.uni-heidelberg.de/~as3/index.html>
- Zurek, W.H. (2003). Decoherence, einselection and the quantum
origins of the classical. Rev. Mod. Phys. 75, 715 (2003)
<http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0105127>
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Neuroscience Of Consciousness
*\"All parts of the brain may well be involved in normal conscious
processes but the indispensable substratum of consciousness lies outside
the cerebral cortex, probably in the diencephalon\" Penfield 1937.*
*\"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not the
detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\" Baars
et al 1998.*
## Introduction
*It is recommended that readers review ../The Philosophical
Problem/ before reading the
sections on the neuroscience of consciousness.*
One of the most exciting discoveries of neuroscience is that nearly all
of the brain performs functions that are not part of conscious
experience. In everyday life we are usually unaware of breathing or
heartbeats yet there are parts of the brain dedicated to these
functions. When we pick up a pencil we have no experience of the fine
control of individual muscles yet large areas of cortex and cerebellum
implement this. Things do not appear as greyscale and then have the
colour poured into them although this strange colour addition is done in
the visual cortex. Most of the brain is non-conscious but how is the
\"ghost in the machine\", the mind, created by and linked into the
mostly non-conscious brain?
Although most of the processes in the brain are non-conscious there can
be little doubt that the output of sensory processes contribute to
experience. For example, although we do not experience the process of
adding colour to visual data in cortical area V4 we do experience
coloured forms and although we have little inkling of the hugely complex
creation of words in the temporal/frontal lobes we do experience verbal
thoughts. Our experience is an integrated output of most of the brain
processes that deal with sensation as well as dreams, thoughts and
emotions. But how and where does this experience occur?
The signals that compose phenomenal consciousness have not been
elucidated. Perhaps the least likely signals for this role are
electrical impulses in nerve fibres because they are distributed
unevenly in time and space and can even be absent for relatively long
periods. Furthermore, electrical impulses across the membranes of
neurons have an all or nothing character; they cannot be easily
superimposed on one another. There are many other possibilities however,
such as: the electrical fields on the dendrites of neurons, the fields
of chemicals spreading out from synapses, the radio-frequency emissions
of action potentials, events in the microtubules in cells, the
depolarisations of glia, the varying fields measured by EEG devices, the
quantum superposition of brain states etc\...
Phenomenal consciousness could exist in the dendritic field of ten
neurons receiving 100,000 synapses or as an oscillation of fields over
the whole brain. The substrate of phenomenal consciousness could be
staring us in the face as a state of the whole brain or be like a needle
in a haystack, lurking in a tiny region of brain, unsuspected and
undiscovered.
Given that there is no widely accepted theory of phenomenal
consciousness Crick (1994) and Crick and Koch (1998) approached the
problem of the location of the substrate of consciousness by proposing
that scientists search for the **Neural Correlates of Consciousness**.
These neural correlates consist of events in the brain that accompany
events in conscious experience.
References:
Crick, F. (1994). The Astonishing Hypothesis. New York: Scribners.
Crick, F. & Koch, C. (1998).Consciousness and Neuroscience. Cerebral
Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
## Neuroanatomy
### General layout of the CNS
The Central Nervous System (CNS) consists of the spinal cord, the brain
and the retina.
The CNS consists of two major groups of active cells, the **neurons**
and the **glia**. The neurons conduct short impulses of electricity
along their membranes called **\'action potentials** and encode data as
frequency modulated signals (i.e.: different intensities of stimulation
are converted into different rates of firing). The glia modify the
connections between neurons and can respond to neuron activity by a
change of voltage across their membranes. Glia also have many other
roles such as sustaining neurons and providing electrical insulation.
Neurons have three principal parts: the **cell body**, the **dendrites**
and the **axon**. Impulses flow from the cell body to the axon. The axon
can be over a metre long and bundles of axons form **nerve fibres**.
Where an axon makes contact with the dendrites or cell body of another
neuron there is a special sort of junction called a **synapse**.
Transmission of data across synapses is usually mediated by chemical
signals.
Areas of the brain where there are many cell bodies have a beige/grey
tinge and are called **grey matter**. Areas that contain mainly nerve
fibres are called **white matter**. Masses of grey matter outside of the
surface of the cerebral cortex or the cerebellum are called **nuclei**.
The brain is of central interest in consciousness studies because
consciousness persists even when the spinal cord is sectioned at the
neck.
The brain can be divided into five distinct divisions or *\'vesicles* on
the basis of embryological development. These are the myelencephalon,
metencephalon, mesencephalon, diencephalon and telencephalon (See the
illustration below).
![](Constuddivis.png "Constuddivis.png")
: Myelencephalon: Medulla oblongata.
: Metencephalon: pons and cerebellum.
: Mesencephalon: midbrain (tectum containing the superior colliculus
and inferior colliculus, red nucleus, substantia nigra, cerebellar
peduncles.
: Diencephalon: thalamus, epithalamus, hypothalamus, subthalamus.
: Telencephalon: corpus striatum, cerebral hemispheres.
These divisions tend to obscure the physical anatomy of the brain which
looks like a rod of spinal cord with a swelling at the top due to the
thalamus and corpus striatum. Around the top of the rod is a globe of
deeply indented cerebral cortex and at the back there is the puckered
mass of cerebellum. The physical anatomy is shown in greater detail in
the illustration below where the thalamus and corpus striatum have been
splayed out to show more detail.
![](Constudoverbrain_-_2.png "Constudoverbrain_-_2.png")
The thalamus is a complex organ with numerous nuclei. These are listed
below:
```{=html}
<TABLE BORDER CELLSPACING=1 BORDERCOLOR="#000080" CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=590>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Type
of Nucleus`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Name`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Abbrev`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Function`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1>`{=html}Reticular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Reticular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}R`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Arousal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1>`{=html}Intralaminar
`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Centromedian`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}CM`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Arousal, attention, motivation,
pain`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Parafascicular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pf`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Central lateral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}CL`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Paracentral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pcn`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Intralaminar Midline`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Reunions`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Re`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Paraventricular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pv`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Rhomboid`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Nonspecific`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pulvinar`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}P`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Association`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral dorsal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anteromedial`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AM`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anteroventral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AV`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral posterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LP`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Medial Dorsal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}MD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Specific Thalamic Nuclei `</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral geniculate`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LGN`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Vision`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}(Sensory Relays)`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Medial geniculate`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}MGN`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Auditory`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral posterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VP`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}General sensation`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Specific Thalamic Nuclei `</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral anterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VA`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Motor`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}(motor)`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral lateral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VL`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Motor`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
The location of these nuclei is shown in the illustration below:
![](constudthal.gif "constudthal.gif")
The cerebral hemispheres consist of a thin layer of nerve cell bodies on
the surface (the cerebral cortex) with a mass of white, interconnecting
fibres below (the cerebral medulla). Each hemisphere is divided into
four principle **lobes** as shown in the illustration below:
![](Main_brain_lobes.gif "Main_brain_lobes.gif")
The cortex is a set of interconnected processors. The general layout of
the cortex with the location of the processors is shown in the
illustration below:
![](Constudproc.png "Constudproc.png")
The pathways in the brain tend to preserve the **topography** of the
sense organs so that particular groups of cells on the retina, cochlear
or body have corresponding groups of cells in the thalamus or cortex.
The retina is said to have a topological mapping onto the thalamus so
that the projection of the optic nerve is said to be **retinotopic**.
Nerve fibres that go to a part of the brain are called **afferents** and
fibres that come from a part of the brain are called **efferents**.
The cortex and thalamus/striatum are intimately linked by millions of
connecting fibres and there is also a direct connection from the motor
cortex to the spinal cord.
### Sensory pathways
Information from the sense organs travels along the appropriate sensory
nerve (optic, auditory, spinal etc.) and once in the brain is divided
into three principal paths that connect either with the thalamus, the
cerebellum or the reticular formation.
There are thalamic nuclei for each broad type of sensation and these
have reciprocal connections with specific areas of cortex that deal with
the appropriate mode of sensation. The large mass of nerve fibres that
mediate the connection between the thalamus and cortex are known as the
thalamo-cortical and cortico-thalamic tracts. There tend to be more
sensory nerve fibres returning from the cortex to the thalamus than
connect from the thalamus to the cortex so it is difficult to determine
whether the cortex is the destination of sensory data or a region that
supplies extra processing power to thalamic nuclei.
The cerebellum mediates reflex control of complex movements and receives
input from most of the sense organs.
The reticular formation is a group of loosely distributed neurons in the
medulla, pons and mesencephalon. It receives a large amount of autonomic
input and also input from all the sense organs. The intralaminar nuclei
of the thalamus are the principal destination of reticular output to
higher centres. In the most primitive vertebrates the reticular
formation performs most of the higher control functions of the animal.
The reticular formation is implicated in the maintenance of sleep-wake
cycles and activates the higher centres. This activity has attracted the
label **ascending reticular activating system** (ARAS) to describe how
the activity of higher centres is controlled by reticular input. This
title is unfortunate from the point of view of consciousness studies
because it implies that conscious experience is a result of activating
the cortex when it could be due to turning on or off particular systems
all the way from the reticular formation to the cortex. Destruction of
the reticular formation leads to coma.
### Motor and output pathways
Motor control of the body below the skull is accomplished by three
principle routes.
The motor cortex of the frontal lobes and related cortex in the parietal
lobes can control movement directly via nerves known as the
cortico-spinal tract (also called the pyramidal tract). The activity of
the motor cortex is modified and controlled by a loop that passes
through the corpus striatum, the substantia nigra and the subthalamic
nucleus and returns to the cortex. These controlling nuclei are, along
with the amygdala, known as the **basal ganglia**.
The cerebellum and the corpus striatum provide complex reflex control of
the body through nerves that travel through the red nucleus and form the
rubro-spinal tract.
The vestibular nucleus, which processes signals related to balance and
posture, has direct connections with the periphery via the
vestibulo-spinal tract.
Apart from the routes for controlling motor activity there are also
other outputs from the brain, for instance the autonomic nervous system
is intimately linked with the reticular formation which has areas that
control blood pressure, respiratory rhythm etc.
## Topological mapping and cortical columns
!Sensorimotor
homunculus{width="400"}The
cerebral cortex has a highly convoluted surface that provides a large
area of tissue. The parts of the cortex that are used for motor and
sensory functions are organised so that different areas correspond to
different zones of the body. This **topological** organisation is shown
classically by a drawing of the *sensorimotor homunculus* such as that
shown on the right.
Within a given area of the cortex there are further subdivisions. For
example, the occipital cortex corresponds to the eyes of the
sensorimotor homunculus and it is further organised so that areas of the
retina have corresponding areas on the cortex. This mapping of the
layout of the retina onto the cortex is known as **topological
mapping**. It results in a corresponding mapping of the receptive field
of the eye onto the cortex. The mapping is like an image on the surface
of the brain tissue and the visual scene that is presented to a subject
can be recovered by using fMRI along with computer analysis (Miyawaki
*et al.* 2008).
The human cortex is fairly deep, containing 100-200 neurons from the
surface to the white matter. It is divided into six histological and
functional layers. These layers can be further subdivided. In 1957
Mountcastle used microelectrode measurements to show that activity of
small zones of cortex about 0.1 to 1 mm in diameter corresponded to
particular points in the receptive field. These functional columns of
cortical tissue are called **cortical columns**.
![](Corticalcol.png "Corticalcol.png")
The diagram above shows the organisation of **ocular dominance
columns**. Each column represents a particular part of the receptive
field of a single eye. The columns for left and right eyes are linked
together in lines. The lines of ocular dominance form a pattern like a
fingerprint on the surface of the cortex.
The same part of cortex can have overlapping columns for different
functions. For instance there are columns that react to particular
orientations of edges at particular places in the visual field. These
columns tend to be located together on the cortex forming a **pinwheel**
of columns that cover all orientations at a particular receptive field
position.
![](Corticalorient.GIF "Corticalorient.GIF")
There are also topologically arranged columns for colour, spatial
frequency etc.
Yoichi Miyawaki, Hajime Uchida, Okito Yamashita, Masa-aki Sato, Yusuke
Morito, Hiroki C. Tanabe, Norihiro Sadato and Yukiyasu Kamitani. (2008).
Visual Image Reconstruction from Human Brain Activity using a
Combination of Multiscale Local Image Decoders. Neuron, Volume 60, Issue
5, 10 December 2008, Pages 915-929
**Modules**
- The neurophysiology of sensation and
perception
- The cortex and
thalamus
- Rivalries and
synchronisation
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Neuroscience Of Consciousness#Introduction
*\"All parts of the brain may well be involved in normal conscious
processes but the indispensable substratum of consciousness lies outside
the cerebral cortex, probably in the diencephalon\" Penfield 1937.*
*\"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not the
detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\" Baars
et al 1998.*
## Introduction
*It is recommended that readers review ../The Philosophical
Problem/ before reading the
sections on the neuroscience of consciousness.*
One of the most exciting discoveries of neuroscience is that nearly all
of the brain performs functions that are not part of conscious
experience. In everyday life we are usually unaware of breathing or
heartbeats yet there are parts of the brain dedicated to these
functions. When we pick up a pencil we have no experience of the fine
control of individual muscles yet large areas of cortex and cerebellum
implement this. Things do not appear as greyscale and then have the
colour poured into them although this strange colour addition is done in
the visual cortex. Most of the brain is non-conscious but how is the
\"ghost in the machine\", the mind, created by and linked into the
mostly non-conscious brain?
Although most of the processes in the brain are non-conscious there can
be little doubt that the output of sensory processes contribute to
experience. For example, although we do not experience the process of
adding colour to visual data in cortical area V4 we do experience
coloured forms and although we have little inkling of the hugely complex
creation of words in the temporal/frontal lobes we do experience verbal
thoughts. Our experience is an integrated output of most of the brain
processes that deal with sensation as well as dreams, thoughts and
emotions. But how and where does this experience occur?
The signals that compose phenomenal consciousness have not been
elucidated. Perhaps the least likely signals for this role are
electrical impulses in nerve fibres because they are distributed
unevenly in time and space and can even be absent for relatively long
periods. Furthermore, electrical impulses across the membranes of
neurons have an all or nothing character; they cannot be easily
superimposed on one another. There are many other possibilities however,
such as: the electrical fields on the dendrites of neurons, the fields
of chemicals spreading out from synapses, the radio-frequency emissions
of action potentials, events in the microtubules in cells, the
depolarisations of glia, the varying fields measured by EEG devices, the
quantum superposition of brain states etc\...
Phenomenal consciousness could exist in the dendritic field of ten
neurons receiving 100,000 synapses or as an oscillation of fields over
the whole brain. The substrate of phenomenal consciousness could be
staring us in the face as a state of the whole brain or be like a needle
in a haystack, lurking in a tiny region of brain, unsuspected and
undiscovered.
Given that there is no widely accepted theory of phenomenal
consciousness Crick (1994) and Crick and Koch (1998) approached the
problem of the location of the substrate of consciousness by proposing
that scientists search for the **Neural Correlates of Consciousness**.
These neural correlates consist of events in the brain that accompany
events in conscious experience.
References:
Crick, F. (1994). The Astonishing Hypothesis. New York: Scribners.
Crick, F. & Koch, C. (1998).Consciousness and Neuroscience. Cerebral
Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
## Neuroanatomy
### General layout of the CNS
The Central Nervous System (CNS) consists of the spinal cord, the brain
and the retina.
The CNS consists of two major groups of active cells, the **neurons**
and the **glia**. The neurons conduct short impulses of electricity
along their membranes called **\'action potentials** and encode data as
frequency modulated signals (i.e.: different intensities of stimulation
are converted into different rates of firing). The glia modify the
connections between neurons and can respond to neuron activity by a
change of voltage across their membranes. Glia also have many other
roles such as sustaining neurons and providing electrical insulation.
Neurons have three principal parts: the **cell body**, the **dendrites**
and the **axon**. Impulses flow from the cell body to the axon. The axon
can be over a metre long and bundles of axons form **nerve fibres**.
Where an axon makes contact with the dendrites or cell body of another
neuron there is a special sort of junction called a **synapse**.
Transmission of data across synapses is usually mediated by chemical
signals.
Areas of the brain where there are many cell bodies have a beige/grey
tinge and are called **grey matter**. Areas that contain mainly nerve
fibres are called **white matter**. Masses of grey matter outside of the
surface of the cerebral cortex or the cerebellum are called **nuclei**.
The brain is of central interest in consciousness studies because
consciousness persists even when the spinal cord is sectioned at the
neck.
The brain can be divided into five distinct divisions or *\'vesicles* on
the basis of embryological development. These are the myelencephalon,
metencephalon, mesencephalon, diencephalon and telencephalon (See the
illustration below).
![](Constuddivis.png "Constuddivis.png")
: Myelencephalon: Medulla oblongata.
: Metencephalon: pons and cerebellum.
: Mesencephalon: midbrain (tectum containing the superior colliculus
and inferior colliculus, red nucleus, substantia nigra, cerebellar
peduncles.
: Diencephalon: thalamus, epithalamus, hypothalamus, subthalamus.
: Telencephalon: corpus striatum, cerebral hemispheres.
These divisions tend to obscure the physical anatomy of the brain which
looks like a rod of spinal cord with a swelling at the top due to the
thalamus and corpus striatum. Around the top of the rod is a globe of
deeply indented cerebral cortex and at the back there is the puckered
mass of cerebellum. The physical anatomy is shown in greater detail in
the illustration below where the thalamus and corpus striatum have been
splayed out to show more detail.
![](Constudoverbrain_-_2.png "Constudoverbrain_-_2.png")
The thalamus is a complex organ with numerous nuclei. These are listed
below:
```{=html}
<TABLE BORDER CELLSPACING=1 BORDERCOLOR="#000080" CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=590>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Type
of Nucleus`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Name`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Abbrev`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Function`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1>`{=html}Reticular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Reticular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}R`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Arousal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1>`{=html}Intralaminar
`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Centromedian`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}CM`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Arousal, attention, motivation,
pain`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Parafascicular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pf`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Central lateral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}CL`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Paracentral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pcn`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Intralaminar Midline`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Reunions`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Re`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Paraventricular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pv`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Rhomboid`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Nonspecific`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pulvinar`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}P`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Association`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral dorsal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anteromedial`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AM`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anteroventral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AV`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral posterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LP`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Medial Dorsal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}MD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Specific Thalamic Nuclei `</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral geniculate`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LGN`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Vision`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}(Sensory Relays)`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Medial geniculate`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}MGN`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Auditory`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral posterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VP`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}General sensation`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Specific Thalamic Nuclei `</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral anterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VA`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Motor`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}(motor)`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral lateral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VL`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Motor`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
The location of these nuclei is shown in the illustration below:
![](constudthal.gif "constudthal.gif")
The cerebral hemispheres consist of a thin layer of nerve cell bodies on
the surface (the cerebral cortex) with a mass of white, interconnecting
fibres below (the cerebral medulla). Each hemisphere is divided into
four principle **lobes** as shown in the illustration below:
![](Main_brain_lobes.gif "Main_brain_lobes.gif")
The cortex is a set of interconnected processors. The general layout of
the cortex with the location of the processors is shown in the
illustration below:
![](Constudproc.png "Constudproc.png")
The pathways in the brain tend to preserve the **topography** of the
sense organs so that particular groups of cells on the retina, cochlear
or body have corresponding groups of cells in the thalamus or cortex.
The retina is said to have a topological mapping onto the thalamus so
that the projection of the optic nerve is said to be **retinotopic**.
Nerve fibres that go to a part of the brain are called **afferents** and
fibres that come from a part of the brain are called **efferents**.
The cortex and thalamus/striatum are intimately linked by millions of
connecting fibres and there is also a direct connection from the motor
cortex to the spinal cord.
### Sensory pathways
Information from the sense organs travels along the appropriate sensory
nerve (optic, auditory, spinal etc.) and once in the brain is divided
into three principal paths that connect either with the thalamus, the
cerebellum or the reticular formation.
There are thalamic nuclei for each broad type of sensation and these
have reciprocal connections with specific areas of cortex that deal with
the appropriate mode of sensation. The large mass of nerve fibres that
mediate the connection between the thalamus and cortex are known as the
thalamo-cortical and cortico-thalamic tracts. There tend to be more
sensory nerve fibres returning from the cortex to the thalamus than
connect from the thalamus to the cortex so it is difficult to determine
whether the cortex is the destination of sensory data or a region that
supplies extra processing power to thalamic nuclei.
The cerebellum mediates reflex control of complex movements and receives
input from most of the sense organs.
The reticular formation is a group of loosely distributed neurons in the
medulla, pons and mesencephalon. It receives a large amount of autonomic
input and also input from all the sense organs. The intralaminar nuclei
of the thalamus are the principal destination of reticular output to
higher centres. In the most primitive vertebrates the reticular
formation performs most of the higher control functions of the animal.
The reticular formation is implicated in the maintenance of sleep-wake
cycles and activates the higher centres. This activity has attracted the
label **ascending reticular activating system** (ARAS) to describe how
the activity of higher centres is controlled by reticular input. This
title is unfortunate from the point of view of consciousness studies
because it implies that conscious experience is a result of activating
the cortex when it could be due to turning on or off particular systems
all the way from the reticular formation to the cortex. Destruction of
the reticular formation leads to coma.
### Motor and output pathways
Motor control of the body below the skull is accomplished by three
principle routes.
The motor cortex of the frontal lobes and related cortex in the parietal
lobes can control movement directly via nerves known as the
cortico-spinal tract (also called the pyramidal tract). The activity of
the motor cortex is modified and controlled by a loop that passes
through the corpus striatum, the substantia nigra and the subthalamic
nucleus and returns to the cortex. These controlling nuclei are, along
with the amygdala, known as the **basal ganglia**.
The cerebellum and the corpus striatum provide complex reflex control of
the body through nerves that travel through the red nucleus and form the
rubro-spinal tract.
The vestibular nucleus, which processes signals related to balance and
posture, has direct connections with the periphery via the
vestibulo-spinal tract.
Apart from the routes for controlling motor activity there are also
other outputs from the brain, for instance the autonomic nervous system
is intimately linked with the reticular formation which has areas that
control blood pressure, respiratory rhythm etc.
## Topological mapping and cortical columns
!Sensorimotor
homunculus{width="400"}The
cerebral cortex has a highly convoluted surface that provides a large
area of tissue. The parts of the cortex that are used for motor and
sensory functions are organised so that different areas correspond to
different zones of the body. This **topological** organisation is shown
classically by a drawing of the *sensorimotor homunculus* such as that
shown on the right.
Within a given area of the cortex there are further subdivisions. For
example, the occipital cortex corresponds to the eyes of the
sensorimotor homunculus and it is further organised so that areas of the
retina have corresponding areas on the cortex. This mapping of the
layout of the retina onto the cortex is known as **topological
mapping**. It results in a corresponding mapping of the receptive field
of the eye onto the cortex. The mapping is like an image on the surface
of the brain tissue and the visual scene that is presented to a subject
can be recovered by using fMRI along with computer analysis (Miyawaki
*et al.* 2008).
The human cortex is fairly deep, containing 100-200 neurons from the
surface to the white matter. It is divided into six histological and
functional layers. These layers can be further subdivided. In 1957
Mountcastle used microelectrode measurements to show that activity of
small zones of cortex about 0.1 to 1 mm in diameter corresponded to
particular points in the receptive field. These functional columns of
cortical tissue are called **cortical columns**.
![](Corticalcol.png "Corticalcol.png")
The diagram above shows the organisation of **ocular dominance
columns**. Each column represents a particular part of the receptive
field of a single eye. The columns for left and right eyes are linked
together in lines. The lines of ocular dominance form a pattern like a
fingerprint on the surface of the cortex.
The same part of cortex can have overlapping columns for different
functions. For instance there are columns that react to particular
orientations of edges at particular places in the visual field. These
columns tend to be located together on the cortex forming a **pinwheel**
of columns that cover all orientations at a particular receptive field
position.
![](Corticalorient.GIF "Corticalorient.GIF")
There are also topologically arranged columns for colour, spatial
frequency etc.
Yoichi Miyawaki, Hajime Uchida, Okito Yamashita, Masa-aki Sato, Yusuke
Morito, Hiroki C. Tanabe, Norihiro Sadato and Yukiyasu Kamitani. (2008).
Visual Image Reconstruction from Human Brain Activity using a
Combination of Multiscale Local Image Decoders. Neuron, Volume 60, Issue
5, 10 December 2008, Pages 915-929
**Modules**
- The neurophysiology of sensation and
perception
- The cortex and
thalamus
- Rivalries and
synchronisation
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Neuroscience Of Consciousness#The substrate of experience
*\"All parts of the brain may well be involved in normal conscious
processes but the indispensable substratum of consciousness lies outside
the cerebral cortex, probably in the diencephalon\" Penfield 1937.*
*\"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not the
detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\" Baars
et al 1998.*
## Introduction
*It is recommended that readers review ../The Philosophical
Problem/ before reading the
sections on the neuroscience of consciousness.*
One of the most exciting discoveries of neuroscience is that nearly all
of the brain performs functions that are not part of conscious
experience. In everyday life we are usually unaware of breathing or
heartbeats yet there are parts of the brain dedicated to these
functions. When we pick up a pencil we have no experience of the fine
control of individual muscles yet large areas of cortex and cerebellum
implement this. Things do not appear as greyscale and then have the
colour poured into them although this strange colour addition is done in
the visual cortex. Most of the brain is non-conscious but how is the
\"ghost in the machine\", the mind, created by and linked into the
mostly non-conscious brain?
Although most of the processes in the brain are non-conscious there can
be little doubt that the output of sensory processes contribute to
experience. For example, although we do not experience the process of
adding colour to visual data in cortical area V4 we do experience
coloured forms and although we have little inkling of the hugely complex
creation of words in the temporal/frontal lobes we do experience verbal
thoughts. Our experience is an integrated output of most of the brain
processes that deal with sensation as well as dreams, thoughts and
emotions. But how and where does this experience occur?
The signals that compose phenomenal consciousness have not been
elucidated. Perhaps the least likely signals for this role are
electrical impulses in nerve fibres because they are distributed
unevenly in time and space and can even be absent for relatively long
periods. Furthermore, electrical impulses across the membranes of
neurons have an all or nothing character; they cannot be easily
superimposed on one another. There are many other possibilities however,
such as: the electrical fields on the dendrites of neurons, the fields
of chemicals spreading out from synapses, the radio-frequency emissions
of action potentials, events in the microtubules in cells, the
depolarisations of glia, the varying fields measured by EEG devices, the
quantum superposition of brain states etc\...
Phenomenal consciousness could exist in the dendritic field of ten
neurons receiving 100,000 synapses or as an oscillation of fields over
the whole brain. The substrate of phenomenal consciousness could be
staring us in the face as a state of the whole brain or be like a needle
in a haystack, lurking in a tiny region of brain, unsuspected and
undiscovered.
Given that there is no widely accepted theory of phenomenal
consciousness Crick (1994) and Crick and Koch (1998) approached the
problem of the location of the substrate of consciousness by proposing
that scientists search for the **Neural Correlates of Consciousness**.
These neural correlates consist of events in the brain that accompany
events in conscious experience.
References:
Crick, F. (1994). The Astonishing Hypothesis. New York: Scribners.
Crick, F. & Koch, C. (1998).Consciousness and Neuroscience. Cerebral
Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
## Neuroanatomy
### General layout of the CNS
The Central Nervous System (CNS) consists of the spinal cord, the brain
and the retina.
The CNS consists of two major groups of active cells, the **neurons**
and the **glia**. The neurons conduct short impulses of electricity
along their membranes called **\'action potentials** and encode data as
frequency modulated signals (i.e.: different intensities of stimulation
are converted into different rates of firing). The glia modify the
connections between neurons and can respond to neuron activity by a
change of voltage across their membranes. Glia also have many other
roles such as sustaining neurons and providing electrical insulation.
Neurons have three principal parts: the **cell body**, the **dendrites**
and the **axon**. Impulses flow from the cell body to the axon. The axon
can be over a metre long and bundles of axons form **nerve fibres**.
Where an axon makes contact with the dendrites or cell body of another
neuron there is a special sort of junction called a **synapse**.
Transmission of data across synapses is usually mediated by chemical
signals.
Areas of the brain where there are many cell bodies have a beige/grey
tinge and are called **grey matter**. Areas that contain mainly nerve
fibres are called **white matter**. Masses of grey matter outside of the
surface of the cerebral cortex or the cerebellum are called **nuclei**.
The brain is of central interest in consciousness studies because
consciousness persists even when the spinal cord is sectioned at the
neck.
The brain can be divided into five distinct divisions or *\'vesicles* on
the basis of embryological development. These are the myelencephalon,
metencephalon, mesencephalon, diencephalon and telencephalon (See the
illustration below).
![](Constuddivis.png "Constuddivis.png")
: Myelencephalon: Medulla oblongata.
: Metencephalon: pons and cerebellum.
: Mesencephalon: midbrain (tectum containing the superior colliculus
and inferior colliculus, red nucleus, substantia nigra, cerebellar
peduncles.
: Diencephalon: thalamus, epithalamus, hypothalamus, subthalamus.
: Telencephalon: corpus striatum, cerebral hemispheres.
These divisions tend to obscure the physical anatomy of the brain which
looks like a rod of spinal cord with a swelling at the top due to the
thalamus and corpus striatum. Around the top of the rod is a globe of
deeply indented cerebral cortex and at the back there is the puckered
mass of cerebellum. The physical anatomy is shown in greater detail in
the illustration below where the thalamus and corpus striatum have been
splayed out to show more detail.
![](Constudoverbrain_-_2.png "Constudoverbrain_-_2.png")
The thalamus is a complex organ with numerous nuclei. These are listed
below:
```{=html}
<TABLE BORDER CELLSPACING=1 BORDERCOLOR="#000080" CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=590>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Type
of Nucleus`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Name`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Abbrev`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Function`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1>`{=html}Reticular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Reticular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}R`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Arousal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1>`{=html}Intralaminar
`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Centromedian`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}CM`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Arousal, attention, motivation,
pain`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Parafascicular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pf`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Central lateral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}CL`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Paracentral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pcn`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Intralaminar Midline`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Reunions`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Re`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Paraventricular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pv`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Rhomboid`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Nonspecific`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pulvinar`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}P`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Association`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral dorsal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anteromedial`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AM`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anteroventral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AV`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral posterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LP`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Medial Dorsal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}MD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Specific Thalamic Nuclei `</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral geniculate`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LGN`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Vision`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}(Sensory Relays)`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Medial geniculate`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}MGN`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Auditory`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral posterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VP`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}General sensation`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Specific Thalamic Nuclei `</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral anterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VA`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Motor`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}(motor)`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral lateral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VL`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Motor`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
The location of these nuclei is shown in the illustration below:
![](constudthal.gif "constudthal.gif")
The cerebral hemispheres consist of a thin layer of nerve cell bodies on
the surface (the cerebral cortex) with a mass of white, interconnecting
fibres below (the cerebral medulla). Each hemisphere is divided into
four principle **lobes** as shown in the illustration below:
![](Main_brain_lobes.gif "Main_brain_lobes.gif")
The cortex is a set of interconnected processors. The general layout of
the cortex with the location of the processors is shown in the
illustration below:
![](Constudproc.png "Constudproc.png")
The pathways in the brain tend to preserve the **topography** of the
sense organs so that particular groups of cells on the retina, cochlear
or body have corresponding groups of cells in the thalamus or cortex.
The retina is said to have a topological mapping onto the thalamus so
that the projection of the optic nerve is said to be **retinotopic**.
Nerve fibres that go to a part of the brain are called **afferents** and
fibres that come from a part of the brain are called **efferents**.
The cortex and thalamus/striatum are intimately linked by millions of
connecting fibres and there is also a direct connection from the motor
cortex to the spinal cord.
### Sensory pathways
Information from the sense organs travels along the appropriate sensory
nerve (optic, auditory, spinal etc.) and once in the brain is divided
into three principal paths that connect either with the thalamus, the
cerebellum or the reticular formation.
There are thalamic nuclei for each broad type of sensation and these
have reciprocal connections with specific areas of cortex that deal with
the appropriate mode of sensation. The large mass of nerve fibres that
mediate the connection between the thalamus and cortex are known as the
thalamo-cortical and cortico-thalamic tracts. There tend to be more
sensory nerve fibres returning from the cortex to the thalamus than
connect from the thalamus to the cortex so it is difficult to determine
whether the cortex is the destination of sensory data or a region that
supplies extra processing power to thalamic nuclei.
The cerebellum mediates reflex control of complex movements and receives
input from most of the sense organs.
The reticular formation is a group of loosely distributed neurons in the
medulla, pons and mesencephalon. It receives a large amount of autonomic
input and also input from all the sense organs. The intralaminar nuclei
of the thalamus are the principal destination of reticular output to
higher centres. In the most primitive vertebrates the reticular
formation performs most of the higher control functions of the animal.
The reticular formation is implicated in the maintenance of sleep-wake
cycles and activates the higher centres. This activity has attracted the
label **ascending reticular activating system** (ARAS) to describe how
the activity of higher centres is controlled by reticular input. This
title is unfortunate from the point of view of consciousness studies
because it implies that conscious experience is a result of activating
the cortex when it could be due to turning on or off particular systems
all the way from the reticular formation to the cortex. Destruction of
the reticular formation leads to coma.
### Motor and output pathways
Motor control of the body below the skull is accomplished by three
principle routes.
The motor cortex of the frontal lobes and related cortex in the parietal
lobes can control movement directly via nerves known as the
cortico-spinal tract (also called the pyramidal tract). The activity of
the motor cortex is modified and controlled by a loop that passes
through the corpus striatum, the substantia nigra and the subthalamic
nucleus and returns to the cortex. These controlling nuclei are, along
with the amygdala, known as the **basal ganglia**.
The cerebellum and the corpus striatum provide complex reflex control of
the body through nerves that travel through the red nucleus and form the
rubro-spinal tract.
The vestibular nucleus, which processes signals related to balance and
posture, has direct connections with the periphery via the
vestibulo-spinal tract.
Apart from the routes for controlling motor activity there are also
other outputs from the brain, for instance the autonomic nervous system
is intimately linked with the reticular formation which has areas that
control blood pressure, respiratory rhythm etc.
## Topological mapping and cortical columns
!Sensorimotor
homunculus{width="400"}The
cerebral cortex has a highly convoluted surface that provides a large
area of tissue. The parts of the cortex that are used for motor and
sensory functions are organised so that different areas correspond to
different zones of the body. This **topological** organisation is shown
classically by a drawing of the *sensorimotor homunculus* such as that
shown on the right.
Within a given area of the cortex there are further subdivisions. For
example, the occipital cortex corresponds to the eyes of the
sensorimotor homunculus and it is further organised so that areas of the
retina have corresponding areas on the cortex. This mapping of the
layout of the retina onto the cortex is known as **topological
mapping**. It results in a corresponding mapping of the receptive field
of the eye onto the cortex. The mapping is like an image on the surface
of the brain tissue and the visual scene that is presented to a subject
can be recovered by using fMRI along with computer analysis (Miyawaki
*et al.* 2008).
The human cortex is fairly deep, containing 100-200 neurons from the
surface to the white matter. It is divided into six histological and
functional layers. These layers can be further subdivided. In 1957
Mountcastle used microelectrode measurements to show that activity of
small zones of cortex about 0.1 to 1 mm in diameter corresponded to
particular points in the receptive field. These functional columns of
cortical tissue are called **cortical columns**.
![](Corticalcol.png "Corticalcol.png")
The diagram above shows the organisation of **ocular dominance
columns**. Each column represents a particular part of the receptive
field of a single eye. The columns for left and right eyes are linked
together in lines. The lines of ocular dominance form a pattern like a
fingerprint on the surface of the cortex.
The same part of cortex can have overlapping columns for different
functions. For instance there are columns that react to particular
orientations of edges at particular places in the visual field. These
columns tend to be located together on the cortex forming a **pinwheel**
of columns that cover all orientations at a particular receptive field
position.
![](Corticalorient.GIF "Corticalorient.GIF")
There are also topologically arranged columns for colour, spatial
frequency etc.
Yoichi Miyawaki, Hajime Uchida, Okito Yamashita, Masa-aki Sato, Yusuke
Morito, Hiroki C. Tanabe, Norihiro Sadato and Yukiyasu Kamitani. (2008).
Visual Image Reconstruction from Human Brain Activity using a
Combination of Multiscale Local Image Decoders. Neuron, Volume 60, Issue
5, 10 December 2008, Pages 915-929
**Modules**
- The neurophysiology of sensation and
perception
- The cortex and
thalamus
- Rivalries and
synchronisation
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Neuroscience Of Consciousness#Neuroanatomy
*\"All parts of the brain may well be involved in normal conscious
processes but the indispensable substratum of consciousness lies outside
the cerebral cortex, probably in the diencephalon\" Penfield 1937.*
*\"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not the
detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\" Baars
et al 1998.*
## Introduction
*It is recommended that readers review ../The Philosophical
Problem/ before reading the
sections on the neuroscience of consciousness.*
One of the most exciting discoveries of neuroscience is that nearly all
of the brain performs functions that are not part of conscious
experience. In everyday life we are usually unaware of breathing or
heartbeats yet there are parts of the brain dedicated to these
functions. When we pick up a pencil we have no experience of the fine
control of individual muscles yet large areas of cortex and cerebellum
implement this. Things do not appear as greyscale and then have the
colour poured into them although this strange colour addition is done in
the visual cortex. Most of the brain is non-conscious but how is the
\"ghost in the machine\", the mind, created by and linked into the
mostly non-conscious brain?
Although most of the processes in the brain are non-conscious there can
be little doubt that the output of sensory processes contribute to
experience. For example, although we do not experience the process of
adding colour to visual data in cortical area V4 we do experience
coloured forms and although we have little inkling of the hugely complex
creation of words in the temporal/frontal lobes we do experience verbal
thoughts. Our experience is an integrated output of most of the brain
processes that deal with sensation as well as dreams, thoughts and
emotions. But how and where does this experience occur?
The signals that compose phenomenal consciousness have not been
elucidated. Perhaps the least likely signals for this role are
electrical impulses in nerve fibres because they are distributed
unevenly in time and space and can even be absent for relatively long
periods. Furthermore, electrical impulses across the membranes of
neurons have an all or nothing character; they cannot be easily
superimposed on one another. There are many other possibilities however,
such as: the electrical fields on the dendrites of neurons, the fields
of chemicals spreading out from synapses, the radio-frequency emissions
of action potentials, events in the microtubules in cells, the
depolarisations of glia, the varying fields measured by EEG devices, the
quantum superposition of brain states etc\...
Phenomenal consciousness could exist in the dendritic field of ten
neurons receiving 100,000 synapses or as an oscillation of fields over
the whole brain. The substrate of phenomenal consciousness could be
staring us in the face as a state of the whole brain or be like a needle
in a haystack, lurking in a tiny region of brain, unsuspected and
undiscovered.
Given that there is no widely accepted theory of phenomenal
consciousness Crick (1994) and Crick and Koch (1998) approached the
problem of the location of the substrate of consciousness by proposing
that scientists search for the **Neural Correlates of Consciousness**.
These neural correlates consist of events in the brain that accompany
events in conscious experience.
References:
Crick, F. (1994). The Astonishing Hypothesis. New York: Scribners.
Crick, F. & Koch, C. (1998).Consciousness and Neuroscience. Cerebral
Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
## Neuroanatomy
### General layout of the CNS
The Central Nervous System (CNS) consists of the spinal cord, the brain
and the retina.
The CNS consists of two major groups of active cells, the **neurons**
and the **glia**. The neurons conduct short impulses of electricity
along their membranes called **\'action potentials** and encode data as
frequency modulated signals (i.e.: different intensities of stimulation
are converted into different rates of firing). The glia modify the
connections between neurons and can respond to neuron activity by a
change of voltage across their membranes. Glia also have many other
roles such as sustaining neurons and providing electrical insulation.
Neurons have three principal parts: the **cell body**, the **dendrites**
and the **axon**. Impulses flow from the cell body to the axon. The axon
can be over a metre long and bundles of axons form **nerve fibres**.
Where an axon makes contact with the dendrites or cell body of another
neuron there is a special sort of junction called a **synapse**.
Transmission of data across synapses is usually mediated by chemical
signals.
Areas of the brain where there are many cell bodies have a beige/grey
tinge and are called **grey matter**. Areas that contain mainly nerve
fibres are called **white matter**. Masses of grey matter outside of the
surface of the cerebral cortex or the cerebellum are called **nuclei**.
The brain is of central interest in consciousness studies because
consciousness persists even when the spinal cord is sectioned at the
neck.
The brain can be divided into five distinct divisions or *\'vesicles* on
the basis of embryological development. These are the myelencephalon,
metencephalon, mesencephalon, diencephalon and telencephalon (See the
illustration below).
![](Constuddivis.png "Constuddivis.png")
: Myelencephalon: Medulla oblongata.
: Metencephalon: pons and cerebellum.
: Mesencephalon: midbrain (tectum containing the superior colliculus
and inferior colliculus, red nucleus, substantia nigra, cerebellar
peduncles.
: Diencephalon: thalamus, epithalamus, hypothalamus, subthalamus.
: Telencephalon: corpus striatum, cerebral hemispheres.
These divisions tend to obscure the physical anatomy of the brain which
looks like a rod of spinal cord with a swelling at the top due to the
thalamus and corpus striatum. Around the top of the rod is a globe of
deeply indented cerebral cortex and at the back there is the puckered
mass of cerebellum. The physical anatomy is shown in greater detail in
the illustration below where the thalamus and corpus striatum have been
splayed out to show more detail.
![](Constudoverbrain_-_2.png "Constudoverbrain_-_2.png")
The thalamus is a complex organ with numerous nuclei. These are listed
below:
```{=html}
<TABLE BORDER CELLSPACING=1 BORDERCOLOR="#000080" CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=590>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Type
of Nucleus`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Name`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Abbrev`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Function`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1>`{=html}Reticular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Reticular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}R`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Arousal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1>`{=html}Intralaminar
`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Centromedian`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}CM`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Arousal, attention, motivation,
pain`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Parafascicular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pf`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Central lateral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}CL`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Paracentral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pcn`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Intralaminar Midline`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Reunions`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Re`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Paraventricular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pv`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Rhomboid`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Nonspecific`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pulvinar`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}P`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Association`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral dorsal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anteromedial`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AM`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anteroventral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AV`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral posterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LP`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Medial Dorsal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}MD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Specific Thalamic Nuclei `</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral geniculate`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LGN`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Vision`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}(Sensory Relays)`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Medial geniculate`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}MGN`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Auditory`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral posterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VP`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}General sensation`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Specific Thalamic Nuclei `</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral anterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VA`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Motor`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}(motor)`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral lateral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VL`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Motor`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
The location of these nuclei is shown in the illustration below:
![](constudthal.gif "constudthal.gif")
The cerebral hemispheres consist of a thin layer of nerve cell bodies on
the surface (the cerebral cortex) with a mass of white, interconnecting
fibres below (the cerebral medulla). Each hemisphere is divided into
four principle **lobes** as shown in the illustration below:
![](Main_brain_lobes.gif "Main_brain_lobes.gif")
The cortex is a set of interconnected processors. The general layout of
the cortex with the location of the processors is shown in the
illustration below:
![](Constudproc.png "Constudproc.png")
The pathways in the brain tend to preserve the **topography** of the
sense organs so that particular groups of cells on the retina, cochlear
or body have corresponding groups of cells in the thalamus or cortex.
The retina is said to have a topological mapping onto the thalamus so
that the projection of the optic nerve is said to be **retinotopic**.
Nerve fibres that go to a part of the brain are called **afferents** and
fibres that come from a part of the brain are called **efferents**.
The cortex and thalamus/striatum are intimately linked by millions of
connecting fibres and there is also a direct connection from the motor
cortex to the spinal cord.
### Sensory pathways
Information from the sense organs travels along the appropriate sensory
nerve (optic, auditory, spinal etc.) and once in the brain is divided
into three principal paths that connect either with the thalamus, the
cerebellum or the reticular formation.
There are thalamic nuclei for each broad type of sensation and these
have reciprocal connections with specific areas of cortex that deal with
the appropriate mode of sensation. The large mass of nerve fibres that
mediate the connection between the thalamus and cortex are known as the
thalamo-cortical and cortico-thalamic tracts. There tend to be more
sensory nerve fibres returning from the cortex to the thalamus than
connect from the thalamus to the cortex so it is difficult to determine
whether the cortex is the destination of sensory data or a region that
supplies extra processing power to thalamic nuclei.
The cerebellum mediates reflex control of complex movements and receives
input from most of the sense organs.
The reticular formation is a group of loosely distributed neurons in the
medulla, pons and mesencephalon. It receives a large amount of autonomic
input and also input from all the sense organs. The intralaminar nuclei
of the thalamus are the principal destination of reticular output to
higher centres. In the most primitive vertebrates the reticular
formation performs most of the higher control functions of the animal.
The reticular formation is implicated in the maintenance of sleep-wake
cycles and activates the higher centres. This activity has attracted the
label **ascending reticular activating system** (ARAS) to describe how
the activity of higher centres is controlled by reticular input. This
title is unfortunate from the point of view of consciousness studies
because it implies that conscious experience is a result of activating
the cortex when it could be due to turning on or off particular systems
all the way from the reticular formation to the cortex. Destruction of
the reticular formation leads to coma.
### Motor and output pathways
Motor control of the body below the skull is accomplished by three
principle routes.
The motor cortex of the frontal lobes and related cortex in the parietal
lobes can control movement directly via nerves known as the
cortico-spinal tract (also called the pyramidal tract). The activity of
the motor cortex is modified and controlled by a loop that passes
through the corpus striatum, the substantia nigra and the subthalamic
nucleus and returns to the cortex. These controlling nuclei are, along
with the amygdala, known as the **basal ganglia**.
The cerebellum and the corpus striatum provide complex reflex control of
the body through nerves that travel through the red nucleus and form the
rubro-spinal tract.
The vestibular nucleus, which processes signals related to balance and
posture, has direct connections with the periphery via the
vestibulo-spinal tract.
Apart from the routes for controlling motor activity there are also
other outputs from the brain, for instance the autonomic nervous system
is intimately linked with the reticular formation which has areas that
control blood pressure, respiratory rhythm etc.
## Topological mapping and cortical columns
!Sensorimotor
homunculus{width="400"}The
cerebral cortex has a highly convoluted surface that provides a large
area of tissue. The parts of the cortex that are used for motor and
sensory functions are organised so that different areas correspond to
different zones of the body. This **topological** organisation is shown
classically by a drawing of the *sensorimotor homunculus* such as that
shown on the right.
Within a given area of the cortex there are further subdivisions. For
example, the occipital cortex corresponds to the eyes of the
sensorimotor homunculus and it is further organised so that areas of the
retina have corresponding areas on the cortex. This mapping of the
layout of the retina onto the cortex is known as **topological
mapping**. It results in a corresponding mapping of the receptive field
of the eye onto the cortex. The mapping is like an image on the surface
of the brain tissue and the visual scene that is presented to a subject
can be recovered by using fMRI along with computer analysis (Miyawaki
*et al.* 2008).
The human cortex is fairly deep, containing 100-200 neurons from the
surface to the white matter. It is divided into six histological and
functional layers. These layers can be further subdivided. In 1957
Mountcastle used microelectrode measurements to show that activity of
small zones of cortex about 0.1 to 1 mm in diameter corresponded to
particular points in the receptive field. These functional columns of
cortical tissue are called **cortical columns**.
![](Corticalcol.png "Corticalcol.png")
The diagram above shows the organisation of **ocular dominance
columns**. Each column represents a particular part of the receptive
field of a single eye. The columns for left and right eyes are linked
together in lines. The lines of ocular dominance form a pattern like a
fingerprint on the surface of the cortex.
The same part of cortex can have overlapping columns for different
functions. For instance there are columns that react to particular
orientations of edges at particular places in the visual field. These
columns tend to be located together on the cortex forming a **pinwheel**
of columns that cover all orientations at a particular receptive field
position.
![](Corticalorient.GIF "Corticalorient.GIF")
There are also topologically arranged columns for colour, spatial
frequency etc.
Yoichi Miyawaki, Hajime Uchida, Okito Yamashita, Masa-aki Sato, Yusuke
Morito, Hiroki C. Tanabe, Norihiro Sadato and Yukiyasu Kamitani. (2008).
Visual Image Reconstruction from Human Brain Activity using a
Combination of Multiscale Local Image Decoders. Neuron, Volume 60, Issue
5, 10 December 2008, Pages 915-929
**Modules**
- The neurophysiology of sensation and
perception
- The cortex and
thalamus
- Rivalries and
synchronisation
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Neuroscience Of Consciousness#Topological mapping and cortical columns
*\"All parts of the brain may well be involved in normal conscious
processes but the indispensable substratum of consciousness lies outside
the cerebral cortex, probably in the diencephalon\" Penfield 1937.*
*\"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not the
detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\" Baars
et al 1998.*
## Introduction
*It is recommended that readers review ../The Philosophical
Problem/ before reading the
sections on the neuroscience of consciousness.*
One of the most exciting discoveries of neuroscience is that nearly all
of the brain performs functions that are not part of conscious
experience. In everyday life we are usually unaware of breathing or
heartbeats yet there are parts of the brain dedicated to these
functions. When we pick up a pencil we have no experience of the fine
control of individual muscles yet large areas of cortex and cerebellum
implement this. Things do not appear as greyscale and then have the
colour poured into them although this strange colour addition is done in
the visual cortex. Most of the brain is non-conscious but how is the
\"ghost in the machine\", the mind, created by and linked into the
mostly non-conscious brain?
Although most of the processes in the brain are non-conscious there can
be little doubt that the output of sensory processes contribute to
experience. For example, although we do not experience the process of
adding colour to visual data in cortical area V4 we do experience
coloured forms and although we have little inkling of the hugely complex
creation of words in the temporal/frontal lobes we do experience verbal
thoughts. Our experience is an integrated output of most of the brain
processes that deal with sensation as well as dreams, thoughts and
emotions. But how and where does this experience occur?
The signals that compose phenomenal consciousness have not been
elucidated. Perhaps the least likely signals for this role are
electrical impulses in nerve fibres because they are distributed
unevenly in time and space and can even be absent for relatively long
periods. Furthermore, electrical impulses across the membranes of
neurons have an all or nothing character; they cannot be easily
superimposed on one another. There are many other possibilities however,
such as: the electrical fields on the dendrites of neurons, the fields
of chemicals spreading out from synapses, the radio-frequency emissions
of action potentials, events in the microtubules in cells, the
depolarisations of glia, the varying fields measured by EEG devices, the
quantum superposition of brain states etc\...
Phenomenal consciousness could exist in the dendritic field of ten
neurons receiving 100,000 synapses or as an oscillation of fields over
the whole brain. The substrate of phenomenal consciousness could be
staring us in the face as a state of the whole brain or be like a needle
in a haystack, lurking in a tiny region of brain, unsuspected and
undiscovered.
Given that there is no widely accepted theory of phenomenal
consciousness Crick (1994) and Crick and Koch (1998) approached the
problem of the location of the substrate of consciousness by proposing
that scientists search for the **Neural Correlates of Consciousness**.
These neural correlates consist of events in the brain that accompany
events in conscious experience.
References:
Crick, F. (1994). The Astonishing Hypothesis. New York: Scribners.
Crick, F. & Koch, C. (1998).Consciousness and Neuroscience. Cerebral
Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
## Neuroanatomy
### General layout of the CNS
The Central Nervous System (CNS) consists of the spinal cord, the brain
and the retina.
The CNS consists of two major groups of active cells, the **neurons**
and the **glia**. The neurons conduct short impulses of electricity
along their membranes called **\'action potentials** and encode data as
frequency modulated signals (i.e.: different intensities of stimulation
are converted into different rates of firing). The glia modify the
connections between neurons and can respond to neuron activity by a
change of voltage across their membranes. Glia also have many other
roles such as sustaining neurons and providing electrical insulation.
Neurons have three principal parts: the **cell body**, the **dendrites**
and the **axon**. Impulses flow from the cell body to the axon. The axon
can be over a metre long and bundles of axons form **nerve fibres**.
Where an axon makes contact with the dendrites or cell body of another
neuron there is a special sort of junction called a **synapse**.
Transmission of data across synapses is usually mediated by chemical
signals.
Areas of the brain where there are many cell bodies have a beige/grey
tinge and are called **grey matter**. Areas that contain mainly nerve
fibres are called **white matter**. Masses of grey matter outside of the
surface of the cerebral cortex or the cerebellum are called **nuclei**.
The brain is of central interest in consciousness studies because
consciousness persists even when the spinal cord is sectioned at the
neck.
The brain can be divided into five distinct divisions or *\'vesicles* on
the basis of embryological development. These are the myelencephalon,
metencephalon, mesencephalon, diencephalon and telencephalon (See the
illustration below).
![](Constuddivis.png "Constuddivis.png")
: Myelencephalon: Medulla oblongata.
: Metencephalon: pons and cerebellum.
: Mesencephalon: midbrain (tectum containing the superior colliculus
and inferior colliculus, red nucleus, substantia nigra, cerebellar
peduncles.
: Diencephalon: thalamus, epithalamus, hypothalamus, subthalamus.
: Telencephalon: corpus striatum, cerebral hemispheres.
These divisions tend to obscure the physical anatomy of the brain which
looks like a rod of spinal cord with a swelling at the top due to the
thalamus and corpus striatum. Around the top of the rod is a globe of
deeply indented cerebral cortex and at the back there is the puckered
mass of cerebellum. The physical anatomy is shown in greater detail in
the illustration below where the thalamus and corpus striatum have been
splayed out to show more detail.
![](Constudoverbrain_-_2.png "Constudoverbrain_-_2.png")
The thalamus is a complex organ with numerous nuclei. These are listed
below:
```{=html}
<TABLE BORDER CELLSPACING=1 BORDERCOLOR="#000080" CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=590>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Type
of Nucleus`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Name`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Abbrev`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP" BGCOLOR="#000080">
```
`<B>`{=html}`<FONT SIZE=2 COLOR="#ffffff">`{=html}Function`</FONT>`{=html}`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1>`{=html}Reticular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Reticular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}R`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Arousal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT FACE="HelveticaNeue-Condensed" SIZE=1>`{=html}Intralaminar
`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Centromedian`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}CM`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Arousal, attention, motivation,
pain`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Parafascicular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pf`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Central lateral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}CL`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Paracentral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pcn`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Intralaminar Midline`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Reunions`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Re`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Paraventricular`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pv`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Rhomboid`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Nonspecific`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Pulvinar`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}P`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Association`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral dorsal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anteromedial`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AM`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Anteroventral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}AV`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral posterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LP`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Medial Dorsal`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}MD`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Specific Thalamic Nuclei `</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Lateral geniculate`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}LGN`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Vision`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}(Sensory Relays)`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Medial geniculate`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}MGN`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Auditory`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral posterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VP`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}General sensation`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Specific Thalamic Nuclei `</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral anterior`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VA`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Motor`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}(motor)`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Ventral lateral`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}VL`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<FONT SIZE=2>`{=html}Motor`</FONT>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD VALIGN="TOP">
```
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
The location of these nuclei is shown in the illustration below:
![](constudthal.gif "constudthal.gif")
The cerebral hemispheres consist of a thin layer of nerve cell bodies on
the surface (the cerebral cortex) with a mass of white, interconnecting
fibres below (the cerebral medulla). Each hemisphere is divided into
four principle **lobes** as shown in the illustration below:
![](Main_brain_lobes.gif "Main_brain_lobes.gif")
The cortex is a set of interconnected processors. The general layout of
the cortex with the location of the processors is shown in the
illustration below:
![](Constudproc.png "Constudproc.png")
The pathways in the brain tend to preserve the **topography** of the
sense organs so that particular groups of cells on the retina, cochlear
or body have corresponding groups of cells in the thalamus or cortex.
The retina is said to have a topological mapping onto the thalamus so
that the projection of the optic nerve is said to be **retinotopic**.
Nerve fibres that go to a part of the brain are called **afferents** and
fibres that come from a part of the brain are called **efferents**.
The cortex and thalamus/striatum are intimately linked by millions of
connecting fibres and there is also a direct connection from the motor
cortex to the spinal cord.
### Sensory pathways
Information from the sense organs travels along the appropriate sensory
nerve (optic, auditory, spinal etc.) and once in the brain is divided
into three principal paths that connect either with the thalamus, the
cerebellum or the reticular formation.
There are thalamic nuclei for each broad type of sensation and these
have reciprocal connections with specific areas of cortex that deal with
the appropriate mode of sensation. The large mass of nerve fibres that
mediate the connection between the thalamus and cortex are known as the
thalamo-cortical and cortico-thalamic tracts. There tend to be more
sensory nerve fibres returning from the cortex to the thalamus than
connect from the thalamus to the cortex so it is difficult to determine
whether the cortex is the destination of sensory data or a region that
supplies extra processing power to thalamic nuclei.
The cerebellum mediates reflex control of complex movements and receives
input from most of the sense organs.
The reticular formation is a group of loosely distributed neurons in the
medulla, pons and mesencephalon. It receives a large amount of autonomic
input and also input from all the sense organs. The intralaminar nuclei
of the thalamus are the principal destination of reticular output to
higher centres. In the most primitive vertebrates the reticular
formation performs most of the higher control functions of the animal.
The reticular formation is implicated in the maintenance of sleep-wake
cycles and activates the higher centres. This activity has attracted the
label **ascending reticular activating system** (ARAS) to describe how
the activity of higher centres is controlled by reticular input. This
title is unfortunate from the point of view of consciousness studies
because it implies that conscious experience is a result of activating
the cortex when it could be due to turning on or off particular systems
all the way from the reticular formation to the cortex. Destruction of
the reticular formation leads to coma.
### Motor and output pathways
Motor control of the body below the skull is accomplished by three
principle routes.
The motor cortex of the frontal lobes and related cortex in the parietal
lobes can control movement directly via nerves known as the
cortico-spinal tract (also called the pyramidal tract). The activity of
the motor cortex is modified and controlled by a loop that passes
through the corpus striatum, the substantia nigra and the subthalamic
nucleus and returns to the cortex. These controlling nuclei are, along
with the amygdala, known as the **basal ganglia**.
The cerebellum and the corpus striatum provide complex reflex control of
the body through nerves that travel through the red nucleus and form the
rubro-spinal tract.
The vestibular nucleus, which processes signals related to balance and
posture, has direct connections with the periphery via the
vestibulo-spinal tract.
Apart from the routes for controlling motor activity there are also
other outputs from the brain, for instance the autonomic nervous system
is intimately linked with the reticular formation which has areas that
control blood pressure, respiratory rhythm etc.
## Topological mapping and cortical columns
!Sensorimotor
homunculus{width="400"}The
cerebral cortex has a highly convoluted surface that provides a large
area of tissue. The parts of the cortex that are used for motor and
sensory functions are organised so that different areas correspond to
different zones of the body. This **topological** organisation is shown
classically by a drawing of the *sensorimotor homunculus* such as that
shown on the right.
Within a given area of the cortex there are further subdivisions. For
example, the occipital cortex corresponds to the eyes of the
sensorimotor homunculus and it is further organised so that areas of the
retina have corresponding areas on the cortex. This mapping of the
layout of the retina onto the cortex is known as **topological
mapping**. It results in a corresponding mapping of the receptive field
of the eye onto the cortex. The mapping is like an image on the surface
of the brain tissue and the visual scene that is presented to a subject
can be recovered by using fMRI along with computer analysis (Miyawaki
*et al.* 2008).
The human cortex is fairly deep, containing 100-200 neurons from the
surface to the white matter. It is divided into six histological and
functional layers. These layers can be further subdivided. In 1957
Mountcastle used microelectrode measurements to show that activity of
small zones of cortex about 0.1 to 1 mm in diameter corresponded to
particular points in the receptive field. These functional columns of
cortical tissue are called **cortical columns**.
![](Corticalcol.png "Corticalcol.png")
The diagram above shows the organisation of **ocular dominance
columns**. Each column represents a particular part of the receptive
field of a single eye. The columns for left and right eyes are linked
together in lines. The lines of ocular dominance form a pattern like a
fingerprint on the surface of the cortex.
The same part of cortex can have overlapping columns for different
functions. For instance there are columns that react to particular
orientations of edges at particular places in the visual field. These
columns tend to be located together on the cortex forming a **pinwheel**
of columns that cover all orientations at a particular receptive field
position.
![](Corticalorient.GIF "Corticalorient.GIF")
There are also topologically arranged columns for colour, spatial
frequency etc.
Yoichi Miyawaki, Hajime Uchida, Okito Yamashita, Masa-aki Sato, Yusuke
Morito, Hiroki C. Tanabe, Norihiro Sadato and Yukiyasu Kamitani. (2008).
Visual Image Reconstruction from Human Brain Activity using a
Combination of Multiscale Local Image Decoders. Neuron, Volume 60, Issue
5, 10 December 2008, Pages 915-929
**Modules**
- The neurophysiology of sensation and
perception
- The cortex and
thalamus
- Rivalries and
synchronisation
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Neurophysiology Of Sensation And Perception
## Vision
### The human eye
The eye is a remarkable optical instrument that is often poorly
understood by students of consciousness. The most popular misconception
is that there is a \'focus\' within the eye through which all the light
rays pass! The purpose of this article is to describe our knowledge of
the optics of the eye so that such misconceptions can be avoided.
![](Constudtheeye.png "Constudtheeye.png")
The eye consists of several surfaces at which refraction occurs:
air-cornea, cornea-aqueous humour, aqueous humour-lens, lens-vitreous
humour. The crude image forming capability of the eye can be represented
quite accurately by the *reduced eye* model which involves a single
optical surface (air-cornea). Optometrists use more accurate models such
as the Gullstrand Schematic Eye, the Le Grand Theoretical and the
LeGrand Simplified Eye.
The lens system at the front of the eye forms an inverted image on the
retina.
The eye is about 23 mm deep from the front of the cornea to the back of
the retina. The refractive index of the components of the lens system
varies from about 1.33 to 1.39.
Light from every point of a field of view falls all over the surface of
the eye. There is no \'point eye\' and there is no ordered image between
objects in the view and the retina except on the retina. The image on
the eye has the form of an inverted mapping of 3D objects to a 2D
surface. This is also the form of conscious experience so the images on
the retinas are the closest physical analogues of phenomenal, visual,
conscious experience (see Perspective below).
### Perspective
Perspective describes how light from three dimensional objects is mapped
onto a two dimensional surface as a result of the action of lenses of
the type found in the eye.
![](Constudperspective.png "Constudperspective.png")
Perspective is used by artists to create the impression of viewing a 3D
scene. To do this they create a 2D image that is similar to the image on
the retina that would be created by the 3D scene.
![](Constudperspective2.png "Constudperspective2.png")
Naive Realists and many Direct Realists believe that the 2D perspective
view is the way things are actually arranged in the world. Of course,
things in the world differ from images because they are arranged in
three dimensions.
### Colour
The colour of an object can be represented by its **spectral power
distribution** which is a plot of the power available at each
wavelength. The unit of light power is the watt but the unit that is
used to measure subjective illumination is the **candela**. One candela
is the illumination due to light of a wavelength of 555 nanometres and a
radiant intensity of 1/683 watts per steradian in the direction being
measured. A steradian is a solid angle at the centre of sphere of one
metre radius that is subtended by one square metre of the surface. The
curious number 1/683 occurs because the unit was originally based on
light emitted from a square centimetre of molten platinum. The
wavelength of 555 nm is chosen because this is the wavelength of peak
sensitivity for light adapted (photopic) vision over a large group of
subjects. Light adapted vision is largely due to photosensitive cells in
the retina called **cones**. The candela is fixed as a standard SI Unit
for light at a wavelength of 555 nanometres.
The **lumen** is a subjective measure of the flux of light energy
passing through a solid angle (a steradian). 683 lumens of light at 555
nm are equivalent to a watt passing through the solid angle. At a
wavelength of about 520 nm only 500 lumens of luminous flux occur per
watt because the visual system is less sensitive at this wavelength. The
curve of sensitivity of the visual system to light is known as the
**V-lambda Curve**. At a wavelength of about 510 nm the same radiant
intensity is seen as being half as bright as at a wavelength of 555 nm.
![](Constudluminance.png "Constudluminance.png")
Dark adapted (scotopic) vision has a peak sensitivity at a wavelength of
507 nm and is largely due to photosensitive cells called **rods** in the
retina. Spectral Luminous Efficacy Curves are also used to express how
the sensitivity to light varies with wavelength.
Phenomenal colours are due to mixtures of **spectral colours** of
varying intensities. A **spectral colour** corresponds to a wavelength
of light found on the electromagnetic spectrum of visible light. Colours
have three attributes: **brightness**, **saturation** and **hue**. The
brightness of a colour depends on the illuminance and the reflectivity
of the surface. The saturation depends on the amount of white present,
for instance white and red make pink. The hue is similar to spectral
colour but can consist of some combinations - for instance magenta is a
hue but combines two spectral colours: red and blue. It should be noted
that experiences that contain colour are dependent on the properties of
the visual system as much as on the wavelengths of light being
reflected.
Any set of three colours that can be added together to give white are
known as **primary colours**. There are a large number of colours that
can be combined to make white, or almost any other colour. This means
that a set of surfaces that all appear white could reflect a wide range
of different wavelengths of light.
There are numerous systems for predicting how colours will combine to
make other colours; the CIE Chromaticity Diagram, the Munsell Colour
System and the Ostwald Colour System have all been used. The 1931 CIE
Chromaticity Diagram is shown below:
![](CIExy1931.png "CIExy1931.png"){width="400"}
See Chromaticity diagram for more
information.
### The retina
The retina contains photoreceptive cells called rods and cones and
several types of neurons. The rods are generally sensitive to light and
there are three varieties of cones sensitive to long, medium and short
wavelengths of light (L, M and S type cones). Some of the ganglion cells
in the retina (about 2%) are also slightly light sensitive and provide
input for the control of circadian rhythms. A schematic diagram of the
retina is shown below.
![](Constudretina.png "Constudretina.png")
The photoreceptors hyperpolarise (their membrane potential becomes more
negative) in response to illumination. Bipolar cells make direct contact
with the photoreceptors and come in two types, *on* and *off*. The
on-bipolar cells are also known as *invaginating* bipolars and the
off-bipolars as *flat bipolars*. On-bipolars depolarise when light falls
on the photoreceptors and off-bipolars hyperpolarise. Action potentials
do not occur in the bipolar or photoreceptor cells.
The retinal neurons perform considerable preprocessing before submitting
information to the brain. The network of horizontal and ganglion neurons
act to produce an output of action potentials that is sensitive to
boundaries between areas of differing illumination (edge detection) and
to motion.
Kuffler in 1953 discovered that many retinal ganglion cells are
responsive to differences in illumination on the retina. This
**centre-surround** processing is shown in the illustration below.
![](Constudcentresurr.png "Constudcentresurr.png")
The centre-surround effect is due to **lateral inhibition** by
horizontally arranged cells in the retina.
The structure of the response fields of ganglion cells is important in
everyday processing and increases the definition of boundaries in the
visual field. Sometimes it gives rise to effects that are not directly
related to the physical content of the visual field. The most famous of
these effects is the Hermann Illusion. The Hermann Grid Illusion is a
set of black squares separated by white lines. Where the white lines
cross it appears as if there are grey dots.
![](Hermann_grid.jpg "Hermann_grid.jpg")
The grey dots are due to the relative suppression of on-centre ganglion
cells where the white lines cross. This is explained in the illustration
below.
![](Constudillfld.png "Constudillfld.png")
Notice how the grey dots disappear when the crossed white lines are at
the centre of the visual field. This is due to way that ganglion cell
fields are much smaller in the fovea.
There are many other retinal illusions. White\'s illusion is
particularly strong and was believed to be due to centre-surround
activity but is now thought to have a complex origin.
![](constudwhites.gif "constudwhites.gif")
The grey lines really are the same shade of grey in the illustration.
Mach\'s Illusion is another example of a centre-surround effect.
Centre-surround effects can also occur with colour fields, red/green and
yellow/blue contrasts having a similar effect to light/dark contrasts.
Lateral inhibition and the resultant centre-surround effect increases
the number of cells that respond to boundaries and edges in the visual
field. If it did not occur then small boundaries might be missed
entirely if these fell on areas of the retina outside of the fovea. The
result of this effect is everywhere in our normal visual phenomenal
experience so not only is visual experience a mapping of 3D on to a 2D
surface, it also contains shading and brightening at edges that will not
be found by photometers that measure objective light intensities.
Photoreceptors become less responsive after continuous exposure to
bright light. This gives rise to **afterimages**. Afterimages are
usually of the opponent colour (white light gives a dark afterimage,
yellow light gives a blue afterimage, red gives a green afterimage
etc.). Afterimages when the eyes are open are generally due to a lack of
response to a particular frequency of light within the white light that
bathes the retina.
It is clear that visual phenomenal experience is related more directly
to the layout and type of activity in the retinal cells than to things
in the visual field beyond the eye.
### Visual pathways
![](Constudeyepath.png "Constudeyepath.png")
### The lateral geniculate nucleus
Retinal ganglion cells project to the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei which
are small bumps on the back of the thalamus. (Only 10-15% of the input
to the LGN comes from the retina, most (c.80%) comes from the visual
cortex). The neurons in the LGN are arranged retinotopically so preserve
the layout of events on the surface of the retina.
The LGN are arranged in 6 layers. The top two are known as Magnocellular
layers (about 100,000 neurons with large cell bodies) and the bottom
four are called Parvocellular layers (about 1,000,000 neurons with small
cell bodies). Between the main layers are the Koniocellular layers that
consist of large numbers of tiny neurons.
The left Lateral Geniculate Nucleus receives input from the right visual
field and the right LGN receives input from the left visual field. Each
nucleus receives input from both eyes but this input is segregated so
that input from the eye on the same side goes to layers 1, 3, 5 and from
the other side to layers 2,4, 6.
The magnocellular layers contain neurons that have a large receptive
field, are sensitive to contrast, a transient response and are not
colour sensitive. The parvocellular layers contains neurons that have
small receptive fields, are colour sensitive, have a prolonged response
and are less sensitive to contrast.
The LGN pathway from the retina is largely connected to the striate part
of the visual cortex (cortical area V1) via a set of fibres called the
optic radiation. There are reciprocal connections between the Thalamic
Reticular Nucleus and the LGN. The LGN are also interconnected with the
Superior Colliculus and brainstem.
The LGN may be involved in controlling which areas of the visual field
are subjected to attention (O\'Connor *et al.* 2002).
### The visual cortex
The input from the LGN goes mainly to area V1 of the cortex. The cortex
is arranged in six layers and divided up into **columns**. Each column
in the visual cortex corresponds to a particular area of the retina in
one eye. The columns are arranged in rows called **hypercolumns**. Each
column within a hypercolumn responds to a different orientation of an
optical stimulus at a given location (so responds to edges/boundaries
that are oriented in the visual field). Hypercolumns from each eye are
arranged alternately and form a small block of cortex called a
**pinwheel**. At the centre of each pinwheel are colour sensitive cells
that are usually not orientation sensitive. These coincide with the
\"blobs\" that are seen when visual cortex is viewed using cytochrome
oxidase dependent stains. It is important to note that the
\"hypercolumns\" merge into one another and respond to line stimuli that
cover an area of retina so they may be physiological rather than
anatomical entities.
The blind spot in each eye is represented by an area of visual cortex
that only receives monocular input from the other eye (Tong & Engel
2001). The effect of the blind spot is illustrated below:
![](constudblindspot.gif "constudblindspot.gif")
Normally it seems that the blindspot is \'filled in\' with background
when one eye is used. However, Lou & Chen (2003) demonstrated that
subjects could respond to quite complex figures in the blind spot,
although how far they were investigating \'blindsight\' rather than
visual experience in the blind spot is difficult to determine.
Different layers in the visual cortex have outputs that go to different
locations. Layer 6 sends nerve fibres to the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei
and thalamus, layer 5 to superior colliculus and pons, layer 2 & 3 to
other cortical areas.
There are two important outputs to other cortical areas, the **ventral
stream** and the **dorsal stream**. The ventral stream processes colour,
form and objects. It proceeds to the inferior (lower) temporal cortex.
The dorsal stream processes motion, position and spatial relationships.
It proceeds towards the parietal cortex. Lesions in the ventral stream
can result in patients knowing where an object is located but being
unable to enumerate its properties, on the other hand, lesions to the
dorsal stream can result in patients being able to label an object but
unable to tell exactly where it is located.
There is also a large output from the visual cortex back to the
thalamus, this output contains more fibres than the thalamo-cortical
input.
### Depth perception
The world is three dimensional but the image on the back of the retinas
is two dimensional. How does the brain give the subject a perception of
depth?
Depth perception relies on **cues** which are data about the
displacement of things relative to the body. These cues consist of:
- the convergence of the eyes
- the accommodation of the lens
- binocular disparity -the difference between the images on the
retinas- this was first suggested by Wheatstone.
- motion parallax - distant objects move slower when the observer
moves - first suggested by Helmholtz.
- optical flow - the rate of expansion/contraction of a scene with
movement towards or away from it (Lee & Aronson 1974).
- binocular occlusion - parts of a scene are invisible to each eye.
- body motion provides cues about near objects.
- vanishing points - the convergence of parallel lines.
- numerous other cues such as size constancy, texture etc.
Binocular disparity has been most extensively studied as a source of
depth cues. When the eyes converge to focus on an object in from of them
there is very little disparity in the images of that object on the two
retinas. The angle at the object formed between the lines that project
back to the pupils is known as the **vergence** at the object. The
sphere where all objects have the same vergence is known as the
**horopter**.
![](Constudverge.png "Constudverge.png")
When the disparity between the retinas is small a single image occurs in
phenomenal experience which is accompanied by a sensation of objects
with depth. This is known as **stereopsis**. If the disparity between
the retinas is large double vision ensues, this is known as
**diplopia**. The curious feature of stereopsis is that we can see no
more of the object than is visible on the retinas and certainly cannot
see behind the object. Stereopsis is more like a stretching of 2D space
than actual 3D.
The **empirical horopter** is a zone where things are seen without
diplopia. The empirical and **Veith Muller** (geometric) horopters are
different. This difference is the result of both processing by the CNS
and optical factors.
**Physiological diplopia** refers to the stimulation of receptors in
different parts of the retinas of the two eyes by the same object.
Physiological diplopia does not always give rise to subjective diplopia,
objects close to the empirical horopter do not give rise to double
vision and the zone in which this occurs is known as **Panum\'s Fusion
Area**. It is widest for objects that are distributed away from the nose
(with \'temporal\' locations) and for objects that are slow moving and
poorly focussed.
In the review by Cutting and Vishton (1995) the contributions of each
type of cue is discussed. Cutting and Vishton also present evidence that
there are several zones of depth perception that are informed by
different sets of cues. These are **personal space**, which is the zone
of things within arms reach, **action space**, which is the zone in
which we interact and where our motions have a large impact on the
perceived layout, and **vista space** which is the zone beyond about 30m
that is informed by long range cues.
The interesting feature of 3D perceptual space is that it is not seen.
The sides of a solid object appear as intrusions or lateral extensions
in 2D space, when we close an eye that has access to the side of the
object and then open it again the side grows out into 2D space. The lack
of \'seeing\' depth is also evident when we close one eye when looking
at a vista - nothing seems to change even though stereopsis has gone.
This leaves the problem of what it is that constitutes the \'feeling\'
of depth. We have feelings that we can fall into space or move into it
or around in it. Depth seems to be defined by premotor modelling and the
potential for occupancy by our bodies and limbs. As such it involves
qualia that are different from those of vision and more akin to those
that accompany movement, as an example, if you reach out to touch
something, move the hand back, then consider the distance to the object
it is evident that a feeling of the movement is still present. Is depth
a quale of movement modelled during the extended present of perception?
- Cutting, J.E. & Vishton, P.M. (1995) Perceiving layout and knowing
distances: The integration, relative potency, and contextual use of
different information about depth. In W. Epstein & S. Rogers (eds.)
Handbook of perception and cognition, Vol 5; Perception of space and
motion. (pp. 69-117). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
<http://pmvish.people.wm.edu/cutting&vishton1995.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gregory, R.L. (1997). Knowledge in perception and illusion. From:
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B (1997) 352, 1121--1128.
<http://www.richardgregory.org/papers/knowl_illusion/knowledge-in-perception.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Hubel, D.H. (1981). EVOLUTION OF IDEAS ON THE PRIMARY VISUAL CORTEX,
1955-1978: A BIASED HISTORICAL ACCOUNT.
<http://nobelprize.org/medicine/laureates/1981/hubel-lecture.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Lou, L. & Chen, J. (2003). Attention and Blind-Spot Phenomenology.
PSYCHE, 9(02), January 2003.
<http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v9/psyche-9-02-lou.html>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- O\'Connor, D.H., Fukui, M.M., Pinsk, M.A. & Kastner, S. (2002).
Attention modulates responses in the human lateral geniculate
nucleus. Nature Neuroscience 5, 1203 - 1209 (2002).
<http://www.nature.com/neuro/journal/v5/n11/full/nn957.html#B34>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tong, F., & Engel, S. A. (2001). Interocular rivalry revealed in the
human cortical blind-spot representation. Nature, 411, 195-199.
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong&Engel2001.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tong, F. (2003). PRIMARY VISUAL CORTEX AND VISUAL AWARENESS. Nature
Reviews of Neuroscience. 4:219-229.
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
**Modules**
- The cortex and
thalamus
- Rivalries and
synchronisation
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Neurophysiology Of Sensation And Perception#Vision
## Vision
### The human eye
The eye is a remarkable optical instrument that is often poorly
understood by students of consciousness. The most popular misconception
is that there is a \'focus\' within the eye through which all the light
rays pass! The purpose of this article is to describe our knowledge of
the optics of the eye so that such misconceptions can be avoided.
![](Constudtheeye.png "Constudtheeye.png")
The eye consists of several surfaces at which refraction occurs:
air-cornea, cornea-aqueous humour, aqueous humour-lens, lens-vitreous
humour. The crude image forming capability of the eye can be represented
quite accurately by the *reduced eye* model which involves a single
optical surface (air-cornea). Optometrists use more accurate models such
as the Gullstrand Schematic Eye, the Le Grand Theoretical and the
LeGrand Simplified Eye.
The lens system at the front of the eye forms an inverted image on the
retina.
The eye is about 23 mm deep from the front of the cornea to the back of
the retina. The refractive index of the components of the lens system
varies from about 1.33 to 1.39.
Light from every point of a field of view falls all over the surface of
the eye. There is no \'point eye\' and there is no ordered image between
objects in the view and the retina except on the retina. The image on
the eye has the form of an inverted mapping of 3D objects to a 2D
surface. This is also the form of conscious experience so the images on
the retinas are the closest physical analogues of phenomenal, visual,
conscious experience (see Perspective below).
### Perspective
Perspective describes how light from three dimensional objects is mapped
onto a two dimensional surface as a result of the action of lenses of
the type found in the eye.
![](Constudperspective.png "Constudperspective.png")
Perspective is used by artists to create the impression of viewing a 3D
scene. To do this they create a 2D image that is similar to the image on
the retina that would be created by the 3D scene.
![](Constudperspective2.png "Constudperspective2.png")
Naive Realists and many Direct Realists believe that the 2D perspective
view is the way things are actually arranged in the world. Of course,
things in the world differ from images because they are arranged in
three dimensions.
### Colour
The colour of an object can be represented by its **spectral power
distribution** which is a plot of the power available at each
wavelength. The unit of light power is the watt but the unit that is
used to measure subjective illumination is the **candela**. One candela
is the illumination due to light of a wavelength of 555 nanometres and a
radiant intensity of 1/683 watts per steradian in the direction being
measured. A steradian is a solid angle at the centre of sphere of one
metre radius that is subtended by one square metre of the surface. The
curious number 1/683 occurs because the unit was originally based on
light emitted from a square centimetre of molten platinum. The
wavelength of 555 nm is chosen because this is the wavelength of peak
sensitivity for light adapted (photopic) vision over a large group of
subjects. Light adapted vision is largely due to photosensitive cells in
the retina called **cones**. The candela is fixed as a standard SI Unit
for light at a wavelength of 555 nanometres.
The **lumen** is a subjective measure of the flux of light energy
passing through a solid angle (a steradian). 683 lumens of light at 555
nm are equivalent to a watt passing through the solid angle. At a
wavelength of about 520 nm only 500 lumens of luminous flux occur per
watt because the visual system is less sensitive at this wavelength. The
curve of sensitivity of the visual system to light is known as the
**V-lambda Curve**. At a wavelength of about 510 nm the same radiant
intensity is seen as being half as bright as at a wavelength of 555 nm.
![](Constudluminance.png "Constudluminance.png")
Dark adapted (scotopic) vision has a peak sensitivity at a wavelength of
507 nm and is largely due to photosensitive cells called **rods** in the
retina. Spectral Luminous Efficacy Curves are also used to express how
the sensitivity to light varies with wavelength.
Phenomenal colours are due to mixtures of **spectral colours** of
varying intensities. A **spectral colour** corresponds to a wavelength
of light found on the electromagnetic spectrum of visible light. Colours
have three attributes: **brightness**, **saturation** and **hue**. The
brightness of a colour depends on the illuminance and the reflectivity
of the surface. The saturation depends on the amount of white present,
for instance white and red make pink. The hue is similar to spectral
colour but can consist of some combinations - for instance magenta is a
hue but combines two spectral colours: red and blue. It should be noted
that experiences that contain colour are dependent on the properties of
the visual system as much as on the wavelengths of light being
reflected.
Any set of three colours that can be added together to give white are
known as **primary colours**. There are a large number of colours that
can be combined to make white, or almost any other colour. This means
that a set of surfaces that all appear white could reflect a wide range
of different wavelengths of light.
There are numerous systems for predicting how colours will combine to
make other colours; the CIE Chromaticity Diagram, the Munsell Colour
System and the Ostwald Colour System have all been used. The 1931 CIE
Chromaticity Diagram is shown below:
![](CIExy1931.png "CIExy1931.png"){width="400"}
See Chromaticity diagram for more
information.
### The retina
The retina contains photoreceptive cells called rods and cones and
several types of neurons. The rods are generally sensitive to light and
there are three varieties of cones sensitive to long, medium and short
wavelengths of light (L, M and S type cones). Some of the ganglion cells
in the retina (about 2%) are also slightly light sensitive and provide
input for the control of circadian rhythms. A schematic diagram of the
retina is shown below.
![](Constudretina.png "Constudretina.png")
The photoreceptors hyperpolarise (their membrane potential becomes more
negative) in response to illumination. Bipolar cells make direct contact
with the photoreceptors and come in two types, *on* and *off*. The
on-bipolar cells are also known as *invaginating* bipolars and the
off-bipolars as *flat bipolars*. On-bipolars depolarise when light falls
on the photoreceptors and off-bipolars hyperpolarise. Action potentials
do not occur in the bipolar or photoreceptor cells.
The retinal neurons perform considerable preprocessing before submitting
information to the brain. The network of horizontal and ganglion neurons
act to produce an output of action potentials that is sensitive to
boundaries between areas of differing illumination (edge detection) and
to motion.
Kuffler in 1953 discovered that many retinal ganglion cells are
responsive to differences in illumination on the retina. This
**centre-surround** processing is shown in the illustration below.
![](Constudcentresurr.png "Constudcentresurr.png")
The centre-surround effect is due to **lateral inhibition** by
horizontally arranged cells in the retina.
The structure of the response fields of ganglion cells is important in
everyday processing and increases the definition of boundaries in the
visual field. Sometimes it gives rise to effects that are not directly
related to the physical content of the visual field. The most famous of
these effects is the Hermann Illusion. The Hermann Grid Illusion is a
set of black squares separated by white lines. Where the white lines
cross it appears as if there are grey dots.
![](Hermann_grid.jpg "Hermann_grid.jpg")
The grey dots are due to the relative suppression of on-centre ganglion
cells where the white lines cross. This is explained in the illustration
below.
![](Constudillfld.png "Constudillfld.png")
Notice how the grey dots disappear when the crossed white lines are at
the centre of the visual field. This is due to way that ganglion cell
fields are much smaller in the fovea.
There are many other retinal illusions. White\'s illusion is
particularly strong and was believed to be due to centre-surround
activity but is now thought to have a complex origin.
![](constudwhites.gif "constudwhites.gif")
The grey lines really are the same shade of grey in the illustration.
Mach\'s Illusion is another example of a centre-surround effect.
Centre-surround effects can also occur with colour fields, red/green and
yellow/blue contrasts having a similar effect to light/dark contrasts.
Lateral inhibition and the resultant centre-surround effect increases
the number of cells that respond to boundaries and edges in the visual
field. If it did not occur then small boundaries might be missed
entirely if these fell on areas of the retina outside of the fovea. The
result of this effect is everywhere in our normal visual phenomenal
experience so not only is visual experience a mapping of 3D on to a 2D
surface, it also contains shading and brightening at edges that will not
be found by photometers that measure objective light intensities.
Photoreceptors become less responsive after continuous exposure to
bright light. This gives rise to **afterimages**. Afterimages are
usually of the opponent colour (white light gives a dark afterimage,
yellow light gives a blue afterimage, red gives a green afterimage
etc.). Afterimages when the eyes are open are generally due to a lack of
response to a particular frequency of light within the white light that
bathes the retina.
It is clear that visual phenomenal experience is related more directly
to the layout and type of activity in the retinal cells than to things
in the visual field beyond the eye.
### Visual pathways
![](Constudeyepath.png "Constudeyepath.png")
### The lateral geniculate nucleus
Retinal ganglion cells project to the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei which
are small bumps on the back of the thalamus. (Only 10-15% of the input
to the LGN comes from the retina, most (c.80%) comes from the visual
cortex). The neurons in the LGN are arranged retinotopically so preserve
the layout of events on the surface of the retina.
The LGN are arranged in 6 layers. The top two are known as Magnocellular
layers (about 100,000 neurons with large cell bodies) and the bottom
four are called Parvocellular layers (about 1,000,000 neurons with small
cell bodies). Between the main layers are the Koniocellular layers that
consist of large numbers of tiny neurons.
The left Lateral Geniculate Nucleus receives input from the right visual
field and the right LGN receives input from the left visual field. Each
nucleus receives input from both eyes but this input is segregated so
that input from the eye on the same side goes to layers 1, 3, 5 and from
the other side to layers 2,4, 6.
The magnocellular layers contain neurons that have a large receptive
field, are sensitive to contrast, a transient response and are not
colour sensitive. The parvocellular layers contains neurons that have
small receptive fields, are colour sensitive, have a prolonged response
and are less sensitive to contrast.
The LGN pathway from the retina is largely connected to the striate part
of the visual cortex (cortical area V1) via a set of fibres called the
optic radiation. There are reciprocal connections between the Thalamic
Reticular Nucleus and the LGN. The LGN are also interconnected with the
Superior Colliculus and brainstem.
The LGN may be involved in controlling which areas of the visual field
are subjected to attention (O\'Connor *et al.* 2002).
### The visual cortex
The input from the LGN goes mainly to area V1 of the cortex. The cortex
is arranged in six layers and divided up into **columns**. Each column
in the visual cortex corresponds to a particular area of the retina in
one eye. The columns are arranged in rows called **hypercolumns**. Each
column within a hypercolumn responds to a different orientation of an
optical stimulus at a given location (so responds to edges/boundaries
that are oriented in the visual field). Hypercolumns from each eye are
arranged alternately and form a small block of cortex called a
**pinwheel**. At the centre of each pinwheel are colour sensitive cells
that are usually not orientation sensitive. These coincide with the
\"blobs\" that are seen when visual cortex is viewed using cytochrome
oxidase dependent stains. It is important to note that the
\"hypercolumns\" merge into one another and respond to line stimuli that
cover an area of retina so they may be physiological rather than
anatomical entities.
The blind spot in each eye is represented by an area of visual cortex
that only receives monocular input from the other eye (Tong & Engel
2001). The effect of the blind spot is illustrated below:
![](constudblindspot.gif "constudblindspot.gif")
Normally it seems that the blindspot is \'filled in\' with background
when one eye is used. However, Lou & Chen (2003) demonstrated that
subjects could respond to quite complex figures in the blind spot,
although how far they were investigating \'blindsight\' rather than
visual experience in the blind spot is difficult to determine.
Different layers in the visual cortex have outputs that go to different
locations. Layer 6 sends nerve fibres to the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei
and thalamus, layer 5 to superior colliculus and pons, layer 2 & 3 to
other cortical areas.
There are two important outputs to other cortical areas, the **ventral
stream** and the **dorsal stream**. The ventral stream processes colour,
form and objects. It proceeds to the inferior (lower) temporal cortex.
The dorsal stream processes motion, position and spatial relationships.
It proceeds towards the parietal cortex. Lesions in the ventral stream
can result in patients knowing where an object is located but being
unable to enumerate its properties, on the other hand, lesions to the
dorsal stream can result in patients being able to label an object but
unable to tell exactly where it is located.
There is also a large output from the visual cortex back to the
thalamus, this output contains more fibres than the thalamo-cortical
input.
### Depth perception
The world is three dimensional but the image on the back of the retinas
is two dimensional. How does the brain give the subject a perception of
depth?
Depth perception relies on **cues** which are data about the
displacement of things relative to the body. These cues consist of:
- the convergence of the eyes
- the accommodation of the lens
- binocular disparity -the difference between the images on the
retinas- this was first suggested by Wheatstone.
- motion parallax - distant objects move slower when the observer
moves - first suggested by Helmholtz.
- optical flow - the rate of expansion/contraction of a scene with
movement towards or away from it (Lee & Aronson 1974).
- binocular occlusion - parts of a scene are invisible to each eye.
- body motion provides cues about near objects.
- vanishing points - the convergence of parallel lines.
- numerous other cues such as size constancy, texture etc.
Binocular disparity has been most extensively studied as a source of
depth cues. When the eyes converge to focus on an object in from of them
there is very little disparity in the images of that object on the two
retinas. The angle at the object formed between the lines that project
back to the pupils is known as the **vergence** at the object. The
sphere where all objects have the same vergence is known as the
**horopter**.
![](Constudverge.png "Constudverge.png")
When the disparity between the retinas is small a single image occurs in
phenomenal experience which is accompanied by a sensation of objects
with depth. This is known as **stereopsis**. If the disparity between
the retinas is large double vision ensues, this is known as
**diplopia**. The curious feature of stereopsis is that we can see no
more of the object than is visible on the retinas and certainly cannot
see behind the object. Stereopsis is more like a stretching of 2D space
than actual 3D.
The **empirical horopter** is a zone where things are seen without
diplopia. The empirical and **Veith Muller** (geometric) horopters are
different. This difference is the result of both processing by the CNS
and optical factors.
**Physiological diplopia** refers to the stimulation of receptors in
different parts of the retinas of the two eyes by the same object.
Physiological diplopia does not always give rise to subjective diplopia,
objects close to the empirical horopter do not give rise to double
vision and the zone in which this occurs is known as **Panum\'s Fusion
Area**. It is widest for objects that are distributed away from the nose
(with \'temporal\' locations) and for objects that are slow moving and
poorly focussed.
In the review by Cutting and Vishton (1995) the contributions of each
type of cue is discussed. Cutting and Vishton also present evidence that
there are several zones of depth perception that are informed by
different sets of cues. These are **personal space**, which is the zone
of things within arms reach, **action space**, which is the zone in
which we interact and where our motions have a large impact on the
perceived layout, and **vista space** which is the zone beyond about 30m
that is informed by long range cues.
The interesting feature of 3D perceptual space is that it is not seen.
The sides of a solid object appear as intrusions or lateral extensions
in 2D space, when we close an eye that has access to the side of the
object and then open it again the side grows out into 2D space. The lack
of \'seeing\' depth is also evident when we close one eye when looking
at a vista - nothing seems to change even though stereopsis has gone.
This leaves the problem of what it is that constitutes the \'feeling\'
of depth. We have feelings that we can fall into space or move into it
or around in it. Depth seems to be defined by premotor modelling and the
potential for occupancy by our bodies and limbs. As such it involves
qualia that are different from those of vision and more akin to those
that accompany movement, as an example, if you reach out to touch
something, move the hand back, then consider the distance to the object
it is evident that a feeling of the movement is still present. Is depth
a quale of movement modelled during the extended present of perception?
- Cutting, J.E. & Vishton, P.M. (1995) Perceiving layout and knowing
distances: The integration, relative potency, and contextual use of
different information about depth. In W. Epstein & S. Rogers (eds.)
Handbook of perception and cognition, Vol 5; Perception of space and
motion. (pp. 69-117). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
<http://pmvish.people.wm.edu/cutting&vishton1995.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gregory, R.L. (1997). Knowledge in perception and illusion. From:
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B (1997) 352, 1121--1128.
<http://www.richardgregory.org/papers/knowl_illusion/knowledge-in-perception.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Hubel, D.H. (1981). EVOLUTION OF IDEAS ON THE PRIMARY VISUAL CORTEX,
1955-1978: A BIASED HISTORICAL ACCOUNT.
<http://nobelprize.org/medicine/laureates/1981/hubel-lecture.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Lou, L. & Chen, J. (2003). Attention and Blind-Spot Phenomenology.
PSYCHE, 9(02), January 2003.
<http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v9/psyche-9-02-lou.html>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- O\'Connor, D.H., Fukui, M.M., Pinsk, M.A. & Kastner, S. (2002).
Attention modulates responses in the human lateral geniculate
nucleus. Nature Neuroscience 5, 1203 - 1209 (2002).
<http://www.nature.com/neuro/journal/v5/n11/full/nn957.html#B34>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tong, F., & Engel, S. A. (2001). Interocular rivalry revealed in the
human cortical blind-spot representation. Nature, 411, 195-199.
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong&Engel2001.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tong, F. (2003). PRIMARY VISUAL CORTEX AND VISUAL AWARENESS. Nature
Reviews of Neuroscience. 4:219-229.
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
**Modules**
- The cortex and
thalamus
- Rivalries and
synchronisation
|
# Consciousness Studies/The Neurophysiology Of Sensation And Perception#Depth perception
## Vision
### The human eye
The eye is a remarkable optical instrument that is often poorly
understood by students of consciousness. The most popular misconception
is that there is a \'focus\' within the eye through which all the light
rays pass! The purpose of this article is to describe our knowledge of
the optics of the eye so that such misconceptions can be avoided.
![](Constudtheeye.png "Constudtheeye.png")
The eye consists of several surfaces at which refraction occurs:
air-cornea, cornea-aqueous humour, aqueous humour-lens, lens-vitreous
humour. The crude image forming capability of the eye can be represented
quite accurately by the *reduced eye* model which involves a single
optical surface (air-cornea). Optometrists use more accurate models such
as the Gullstrand Schematic Eye, the Le Grand Theoretical and the
LeGrand Simplified Eye.
The lens system at the front of the eye forms an inverted image on the
retina.
The eye is about 23 mm deep from the front of the cornea to the back of
the retina. The refractive index of the components of the lens system
varies from about 1.33 to 1.39.
Light from every point of a field of view falls all over the surface of
the eye. There is no \'point eye\' and there is no ordered image between
objects in the view and the retina except on the retina. The image on
the eye has the form of an inverted mapping of 3D objects to a 2D
surface. This is also the form of conscious experience so the images on
the retinas are the closest physical analogues of phenomenal, visual,
conscious experience (see Perspective below).
### Perspective
Perspective describes how light from three dimensional objects is mapped
onto a two dimensional surface as a result of the action of lenses of
the type found in the eye.
![](Constudperspective.png "Constudperspective.png")
Perspective is used by artists to create the impression of viewing a 3D
scene. To do this they create a 2D image that is similar to the image on
the retina that would be created by the 3D scene.
![](Constudperspective2.png "Constudperspective2.png")
Naive Realists and many Direct Realists believe that the 2D perspective
view is the way things are actually arranged in the world. Of course,
things in the world differ from images because they are arranged in
three dimensions.
### Colour
The colour of an object can be represented by its **spectral power
distribution** which is a plot of the power available at each
wavelength. The unit of light power is the watt but the unit that is
used to measure subjective illumination is the **candela**. One candela
is the illumination due to light of a wavelength of 555 nanometres and a
radiant intensity of 1/683 watts per steradian in the direction being
measured. A steradian is a solid angle at the centre of sphere of one
metre radius that is subtended by one square metre of the surface. The
curious number 1/683 occurs because the unit was originally based on
light emitted from a square centimetre of molten platinum. The
wavelength of 555 nm is chosen because this is the wavelength of peak
sensitivity for light adapted (photopic) vision over a large group of
subjects. Light adapted vision is largely due to photosensitive cells in
the retina called **cones**. The candela is fixed as a standard SI Unit
for light at a wavelength of 555 nanometres.
The **lumen** is a subjective measure of the flux of light energy
passing through a solid angle (a steradian). 683 lumens of light at 555
nm are equivalent to a watt passing through the solid angle. At a
wavelength of about 520 nm only 500 lumens of luminous flux occur per
watt because the visual system is less sensitive at this wavelength. The
curve of sensitivity of the visual system to light is known as the
**V-lambda Curve**. At a wavelength of about 510 nm the same radiant
intensity is seen as being half as bright as at a wavelength of 555 nm.
![](Constudluminance.png "Constudluminance.png")
Dark adapted (scotopic) vision has a peak sensitivity at a wavelength of
507 nm and is largely due to photosensitive cells called **rods** in the
retina. Spectral Luminous Efficacy Curves are also used to express how
the sensitivity to light varies with wavelength.
Phenomenal colours are due to mixtures of **spectral colours** of
varying intensities. A **spectral colour** corresponds to a wavelength
of light found on the electromagnetic spectrum of visible light. Colours
have three attributes: **brightness**, **saturation** and **hue**. The
brightness of a colour depends on the illuminance and the reflectivity
of the surface. The saturation depends on the amount of white present,
for instance white and red make pink. The hue is similar to spectral
colour but can consist of some combinations - for instance magenta is a
hue but combines two spectral colours: red and blue. It should be noted
that experiences that contain colour are dependent on the properties of
the visual system as much as on the wavelengths of light being
reflected.
Any set of three colours that can be added together to give white are
known as **primary colours**. There are a large number of colours that
can be combined to make white, or almost any other colour. This means
that a set of surfaces that all appear white could reflect a wide range
of different wavelengths of light.
There are numerous systems for predicting how colours will combine to
make other colours; the CIE Chromaticity Diagram, the Munsell Colour
System and the Ostwald Colour System have all been used. The 1931 CIE
Chromaticity Diagram is shown below:
![](CIExy1931.png "CIExy1931.png"){width="400"}
See Chromaticity diagram for more
information.
### The retina
The retina contains photoreceptive cells called rods and cones and
several types of neurons. The rods are generally sensitive to light and
there are three varieties of cones sensitive to long, medium and short
wavelengths of light (L, M and S type cones). Some of the ganglion cells
in the retina (about 2%) are also slightly light sensitive and provide
input for the control of circadian rhythms. A schematic diagram of the
retina is shown below.
![](Constudretina.png "Constudretina.png")
The photoreceptors hyperpolarise (their membrane potential becomes more
negative) in response to illumination. Bipolar cells make direct contact
with the photoreceptors and come in two types, *on* and *off*. The
on-bipolar cells are also known as *invaginating* bipolars and the
off-bipolars as *flat bipolars*. On-bipolars depolarise when light falls
on the photoreceptors and off-bipolars hyperpolarise. Action potentials
do not occur in the bipolar or photoreceptor cells.
The retinal neurons perform considerable preprocessing before submitting
information to the brain. The network of horizontal and ganglion neurons
act to produce an output of action potentials that is sensitive to
boundaries between areas of differing illumination (edge detection) and
to motion.
Kuffler in 1953 discovered that many retinal ganglion cells are
responsive to differences in illumination on the retina. This
**centre-surround** processing is shown in the illustration below.
![](Constudcentresurr.png "Constudcentresurr.png")
The centre-surround effect is due to **lateral inhibition** by
horizontally arranged cells in the retina.
The structure of the response fields of ganglion cells is important in
everyday processing and increases the definition of boundaries in the
visual field. Sometimes it gives rise to effects that are not directly
related to the physical content of the visual field. The most famous of
these effects is the Hermann Illusion. The Hermann Grid Illusion is a
set of black squares separated by white lines. Where the white lines
cross it appears as if there are grey dots.
![](Hermann_grid.jpg "Hermann_grid.jpg")
The grey dots are due to the relative suppression of on-centre ganglion
cells where the white lines cross. This is explained in the illustration
below.
![](Constudillfld.png "Constudillfld.png")
Notice how the grey dots disappear when the crossed white lines are at
the centre of the visual field. This is due to way that ganglion cell
fields are much smaller in the fovea.
There are many other retinal illusions. White\'s illusion is
particularly strong and was believed to be due to centre-surround
activity but is now thought to have a complex origin.
![](constudwhites.gif "constudwhites.gif")
The grey lines really are the same shade of grey in the illustration.
Mach\'s Illusion is another example of a centre-surround effect.
Centre-surround effects can also occur with colour fields, red/green and
yellow/blue contrasts having a similar effect to light/dark contrasts.
Lateral inhibition and the resultant centre-surround effect increases
the number of cells that respond to boundaries and edges in the visual
field. If it did not occur then small boundaries might be missed
entirely if these fell on areas of the retina outside of the fovea. The
result of this effect is everywhere in our normal visual phenomenal
experience so not only is visual experience a mapping of 3D on to a 2D
surface, it also contains shading and brightening at edges that will not
be found by photometers that measure objective light intensities.
Photoreceptors become less responsive after continuous exposure to
bright light. This gives rise to **afterimages**. Afterimages are
usually of the opponent colour (white light gives a dark afterimage,
yellow light gives a blue afterimage, red gives a green afterimage
etc.). Afterimages when the eyes are open are generally due to a lack of
response to a particular frequency of light within the white light that
bathes the retina.
It is clear that visual phenomenal experience is related more directly
to the layout and type of activity in the retinal cells than to things
in the visual field beyond the eye.
### Visual pathways
![](Constudeyepath.png "Constudeyepath.png")
### The lateral geniculate nucleus
Retinal ganglion cells project to the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei which
are small bumps on the back of the thalamus. (Only 10-15% of the input
to the LGN comes from the retina, most (c.80%) comes from the visual
cortex). The neurons in the LGN are arranged retinotopically so preserve
the layout of events on the surface of the retina.
The LGN are arranged in 6 layers. The top two are known as Magnocellular
layers (about 100,000 neurons with large cell bodies) and the bottom
four are called Parvocellular layers (about 1,000,000 neurons with small
cell bodies). Between the main layers are the Koniocellular layers that
consist of large numbers of tiny neurons.
The left Lateral Geniculate Nucleus receives input from the right visual
field and the right LGN receives input from the left visual field. Each
nucleus receives input from both eyes but this input is segregated so
that input from the eye on the same side goes to layers 1, 3, 5 and from
the other side to layers 2,4, 6.
The magnocellular layers contain neurons that have a large receptive
field, are sensitive to contrast, a transient response and are not
colour sensitive. The parvocellular layers contains neurons that have
small receptive fields, are colour sensitive, have a prolonged response
and are less sensitive to contrast.
The LGN pathway from the retina is largely connected to the striate part
of the visual cortex (cortical area V1) via a set of fibres called the
optic radiation. There are reciprocal connections between the Thalamic
Reticular Nucleus and the LGN. The LGN are also interconnected with the
Superior Colliculus and brainstem.
The LGN may be involved in controlling which areas of the visual field
are subjected to attention (O\'Connor *et al.* 2002).
### The visual cortex
The input from the LGN goes mainly to area V1 of the cortex. The cortex
is arranged in six layers and divided up into **columns**. Each column
in the visual cortex corresponds to a particular area of the retina in
one eye. The columns are arranged in rows called **hypercolumns**. Each
column within a hypercolumn responds to a different orientation of an
optical stimulus at a given location (so responds to edges/boundaries
that are oriented in the visual field). Hypercolumns from each eye are
arranged alternately and form a small block of cortex called a
**pinwheel**. At the centre of each pinwheel are colour sensitive cells
that are usually not orientation sensitive. These coincide with the
\"blobs\" that are seen when visual cortex is viewed using cytochrome
oxidase dependent stains. It is important to note that the
\"hypercolumns\" merge into one another and respond to line stimuli that
cover an area of retina so they may be physiological rather than
anatomical entities.
The blind spot in each eye is represented by an area of visual cortex
that only receives monocular input from the other eye (Tong & Engel
2001). The effect of the blind spot is illustrated below:
![](constudblindspot.gif "constudblindspot.gif")
Normally it seems that the blindspot is \'filled in\' with background
when one eye is used. However, Lou & Chen (2003) demonstrated that
subjects could respond to quite complex figures in the blind spot,
although how far they were investigating \'blindsight\' rather than
visual experience in the blind spot is difficult to determine.
Different layers in the visual cortex have outputs that go to different
locations. Layer 6 sends nerve fibres to the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei
and thalamus, layer 5 to superior colliculus and pons, layer 2 & 3 to
other cortical areas.
There are two important outputs to other cortical areas, the **ventral
stream** and the **dorsal stream**. The ventral stream processes colour,
form and objects. It proceeds to the inferior (lower) temporal cortex.
The dorsal stream processes motion, position and spatial relationships.
It proceeds towards the parietal cortex. Lesions in the ventral stream
can result in patients knowing where an object is located but being
unable to enumerate its properties, on the other hand, lesions to the
dorsal stream can result in patients being able to label an object but
unable to tell exactly where it is located.
There is also a large output from the visual cortex back to the
thalamus, this output contains more fibres than the thalamo-cortical
input.
### Depth perception
The world is three dimensional but the image on the back of the retinas
is two dimensional. How does the brain give the subject a perception of
depth?
Depth perception relies on **cues** which are data about the
displacement of things relative to the body. These cues consist of:
- the convergence of the eyes
- the accommodation of the lens
- binocular disparity -the difference between the images on the
retinas- this was first suggested by Wheatstone.
- motion parallax - distant objects move slower when the observer
moves - first suggested by Helmholtz.
- optical flow - the rate of expansion/contraction of a scene with
movement towards or away from it (Lee & Aronson 1974).
- binocular occlusion - parts of a scene are invisible to each eye.
- body motion provides cues about near objects.
- vanishing points - the convergence of parallel lines.
- numerous other cues such as size constancy, texture etc.
Binocular disparity has been most extensively studied as a source of
depth cues. When the eyes converge to focus on an object in from of them
there is very little disparity in the images of that object on the two
retinas. The angle at the object formed between the lines that project
back to the pupils is known as the **vergence** at the object. The
sphere where all objects have the same vergence is known as the
**horopter**.
![](Constudverge.png "Constudverge.png")
When the disparity between the retinas is small a single image occurs in
phenomenal experience which is accompanied by a sensation of objects
with depth. This is known as **stereopsis**. If the disparity between
the retinas is large double vision ensues, this is known as
**diplopia**. The curious feature of stereopsis is that we can see no
more of the object than is visible on the retinas and certainly cannot
see behind the object. Stereopsis is more like a stretching of 2D space
than actual 3D.
The **empirical horopter** is a zone where things are seen without
diplopia. The empirical and **Veith Muller** (geometric) horopters are
different. This difference is the result of both processing by the CNS
and optical factors.
**Physiological diplopia** refers to the stimulation of receptors in
different parts of the retinas of the two eyes by the same object.
Physiological diplopia does not always give rise to subjective diplopia,
objects close to the empirical horopter do not give rise to double
vision and the zone in which this occurs is known as **Panum\'s Fusion
Area**. It is widest for objects that are distributed away from the nose
(with \'temporal\' locations) and for objects that are slow moving and
poorly focussed.
In the review by Cutting and Vishton (1995) the contributions of each
type of cue is discussed. Cutting and Vishton also present evidence that
there are several zones of depth perception that are informed by
different sets of cues. These are **personal space**, which is the zone
of things within arms reach, **action space**, which is the zone in
which we interact and where our motions have a large impact on the
perceived layout, and **vista space** which is the zone beyond about 30m
that is informed by long range cues.
The interesting feature of 3D perceptual space is that it is not seen.
The sides of a solid object appear as intrusions or lateral extensions
in 2D space, when we close an eye that has access to the side of the
object and then open it again the side grows out into 2D space. The lack
of \'seeing\' depth is also evident when we close one eye when looking
at a vista - nothing seems to change even though stereopsis has gone.
This leaves the problem of what it is that constitutes the \'feeling\'
of depth. We have feelings that we can fall into space or move into it
or around in it. Depth seems to be defined by premotor modelling and the
potential for occupancy by our bodies and limbs. As such it involves
qualia that are different from those of vision and more akin to those
that accompany movement, as an example, if you reach out to touch
something, move the hand back, then consider the distance to the object
it is evident that a feeling of the movement is still present. Is depth
a quale of movement modelled during the extended present of perception?
- Cutting, J.E. & Vishton, P.M. (1995) Perceiving layout and knowing
distances: The integration, relative potency, and contextual use of
different information about depth. In W. Epstein & S. Rogers (eds.)
Handbook of perception and cognition, Vol 5; Perception of space and
motion. (pp. 69-117). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
<http://pmvish.people.wm.edu/cutting&vishton1995.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Gregory, R.L. (1997). Knowledge in perception and illusion. From:
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B (1997) 352, 1121--1128.
<http://www.richardgregory.org/papers/knowl_illusion/knowledge-in-perception.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Hubel, D.H. (1981). EVOLUTION OF IDEAS ON THE PRIMARY VISUAL CORTEX,
1955-1978: A BIASED HISTORICAL ACCOUNT.
<http://nobelprize.org/medicine/laureates/1981/hubel-lecture.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Lou, L. & Chen, J. (2003). Attention and Blind-Spot Phenomenology.
PSYCHE, 9(02), January 2003.
<http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v9/psyche-9-02-lou.html>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- O\'Connor, D.H., Fukui, M.M., Pinsk, M.A. & Kastner, S. (2002).
Attention modulates responses in the human lateral geniculate
nucleus. Nature Neuroscience 5, 1203 - 1209 (2002).
<http://www.nature.com/neuro/journal/v5/n11/full/nn957.html#B34>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tong, F., & Engel, S. A. (2001). Interocular rivalry revealed in the
human cortical blind-spot representation. Nature, 411, 195-199.
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong&Engel2001.pdf>
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tong, F. (2003). PRIMARY VISUAL CORTEX AND VISUAL AWARENESS. Nature
Reviews of Neuroscience. 4:219-229.
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
**Modules**
- The cortex and
thalamus
- Rivalries and
synchronisation
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 1
## The cortex and consciousness
The cerebral cortex consists of a set of specialised areas that process
different aspects of sensation and motor control. There are about ten
times as many nerve fibres going from the cortex to the thalamus as
there are from the thalamus to the cortex (Destexhe 2000).
![](constudconn.gif "constudconn.gif")
Histologically the cerebral cortex is a layer of greyish neurons
overlying a huge mass of white nerve fibres, the cerebral medulla. The
cortex consists of six main layers. The upper layers receive input from
the relays in the thalamus such as the lateral geniculate, from the
thalamus in general and from other areas of cortex plus a few
specialised inputs from other locations. The lower layers give rise to
output fibres that largely connect with the thalamus and other areas of
cortex although particular specialised processors in the cortex may also
have direct connections elsewhere such as to motor nuclei.
![](Constudcortex2.png "Constudcortex2.png")
The cerebral cortex has many functions and is divided up into numerous
separate processors. The most important function of the cortex from the
point of view of consciousness studies is that it creates models. As was
seen in Part I, philosophers debate whether these models are actually
experienced consciously but in the neurophysiological literature it is
normally assumed that we do experience models and rehearsals such as
inner speech and imaginings. There is considerable evidence that the
parts of the brain that deal with imagining (modelling) things are also
the parts that deal with perception (i.e.: modelling the world). The
overlap between imagination and normal perception is not complete
because, as Tong(2003), in a review of visual consciousness, put it:
\"Internally generated experiences share some, but not all, of the
phenomenal properties of actual perception\". There is also considerable
overlap between the areas used for imaginary speech (thought) and actual
speech, areas dealing with the control of sensation and of the tongue
etc. being used in actual speech but not in imagined speech (Fu *et al.*
2002). Kreiman *et al.* (2000) investigated the activity of single
neurons in humans and also found that the brain activity evoked by
visual imagination overlapped that which occurs upon direct stimulation
by the same image.
Our conscious experience consists of the output of the cortical
modelling and perceptual processes. The cerebral cortex itself appears
to be non-conscious. The evidence for the non-conscious nature of the
cerebral cortex consists of lesion studies in which large amounts of
cortex can be removed without removing consciousness and physiological
studies in which it is demonstrated that the cerebral cortex can be
active without conscious experience.
Lesion studies have shown that up to 60% of the cerebral cortex can be
removed without abolishing consciousness (Austin and Grant 1958). An
entire hemisphere can be removed or much of the front or back of the
cerebral cortex can be cut off yet consciousness persists.
Fiset *et al.* (1999) and Cariani (2000) have shown that cortical
activity can be normal or even elevated during the unconscious state of
general anaesthesia. Alkire *et al.* (1996) also showed that cortical
activity related to word recognition occurred during general
anaesthesia.
Libet *et al.* (1967) found that there could be cerebral cortical
activity in response to weak stimulation of the skin without any
conscious awareness of the stimulus. This work provides a
neurophysiological basis for subliminal (non-conscious) perception and
also shows that large areas of the cerebral cortex can be active without
conscious experience. The insensitivity of experience to cortical
activity has been further confirmed by Libet *et al.* (1979). They
electrically stimulated the cerebral cortex of conscious patients and
discovered that the stimulus must be continued for about 0.5 seconds for
subjects to report a conscious experience of the stimulation. Libet\'s
findings have been analysed at length but there still appears to be a
0.25 to 0.5 secs delay (Klein 2002).
It has been demonstrated that cerebral cortical activity is not
synonymous with conscious experience but why should there be a delay of
up to 0.5 seconds or so between cortical stimulation and a conscious
percept? What is the cortex doing in the 0.5 seconds between the start
of stimulation and the report of awareness of the stimulation? It is
probably synchronising its various processors and creating a waking
dream, a structured set of events that accounts for the activity. The
synchronisation of cerebral cortical processes will be discussed later,
but what evidence is there for the cerebral cortex constructing a waking
dream, or model, to describe the world?
The \'Attentional Blink\' (Raymond *et al.* 1992) is consistent with the
concept of the cerebral cortex being a device that creates models. In
the \'Attentional Blink\' the identification of an object impairs the
identification of a second object that is presented within 0.5 seconds
of the first. Raymond *et al.* used a stream of letters (11 letters per
second) and the identification of a first letter impaired the
identification of a subsequent \'probe\' letter in the stream. If the
probe letter followed the first letter within about 180 msecs it could
easily be identified, suggesting that chunks of about 180 msecs of data
stream are modelled together. Christmann & Leuthold (2004) have
theorised that the \'Attentional Blink\' involves perceptual and central
components of visual processing. This is supported by the fMRI studies
of Marois *et al.* (2004) who presented subjects with faces mounted on
scenes of places. The scenes of places often went undetected by subjects
but they activated regions of the medial temporal cortex involved in
high-level scene representations, the parahippocampal place area (PPA).
When the scenes of places were detected by the subjects there was
activity in the frontal cortex and the PPA activity was increased. These
experiments are consistent with the idea of a cerebral cortex that is a
multiprocessor system that creates consistent models of the environment.
Bregman\'s (1990) auditory continuity illusion is another example of how
sensory events are modelled. If a pure tone is followed by broadband
noise and the noise followed by the same pure tone it seems as if the
tone occurs throughout the period of noise. If the noise is not followed
by the pure tone there is no sound of the tone during the period of
noise. This effect is similar to the results found by Libet because a
delay of several hundred milliseconds between sensory stimulation and
conscious experience is needed to account for the apparent rewriting of
history after the second tone appears.
Dennett and Kinsbourne (1992) argued strongly against modelling as the
source of conscious experience. They discussed two illusions, the
\"cutaneous rabbit illusion\", in which the subject is tapped
successively in such a way that some illusory taps appear and the \"phi
illusion\" in which successively illuminated lights appear as a motion
of the light. Dennett and Kinsbourne declared that there should be no
cerebral cortical filling in of the gaps in the these illusions. Both
these illusions have now been investigated. Blankenburg *et al.* (2006)
found that cerebral cortical activity occurred at the locations expected
for the missing taps in the \"cutaneous rabbit\" illusion and Larsen *et
al.* (2006) found that the areas of cerebral cortex that would be
stimulated by a moving light were active during the \"phi illusion\".
## The delay before consciousness of \"voluntary\" actions
The 0.5 second delay required for the cortex to model an event has
implications for the role of conscious experience in the control of our
lives. If experience is about 0.5 seconds behind the true present
instant then how can we be said to control anything? The brain must be
acting automatically whilst performing most tasks. The 0.5 second delay
also seems to contradict our everyday experience. We certainly feel like
we are aware of things in less than 0.5 seconds, for example, the direct
stimulation of sense organs seems to be experienced much more rapidly
than the delayed experience of cortical stimulation. In fact subjects
report that they are conscious of stimuli, such as being touched or
seeing flashing lights, within 0.1 to 0.2 seconds of the event. So how
can subjects report events within 0.2 seconds even though it seems to
take 0.5 seconds for the cortex to generate activity that can be
experienced? The simplest explanation is that the reaction occurs
automatically within 0.2 seconds and then the conscious experience of
this reaction occurs 0.3 seconds later. This gives a total 0.5 seconds
delay before conscious experience whilst allowing fast reactions.
Libet *et al.* extended their experiments by stimulating a \"relay
nucleus\" in the thalamus that intercepts signals from the senses before
they reach the somatosensory cortex. It was found that when this nucleus
was stimulated for 0.5 seconds the subjects reported that the stimulus
occurred 0.2 seconds after it had begun. When the nucleus was stimulated
for less than 0.5 seconds the subjects did not report any sensation.
This supports the concept of a 0.5 second delay whilst the cortex puts a
stimulus in context before it is experienced.
These experiments show that our experience is an output of cortical
processing rather than the processing itself. If our conscious
experience is non-cortical then this raises the possibility that the
non-conscious cerebral cortex can perform actions without conscious
control. Of course, the cortex does this all the time when we are
indulging in skilled or routine behaviour. The ability of the
non-conscious cortex is quite remarkable; for instance car drivers
sometimes discover that they have driven for several miles without
conscious experience of driving, even at the level of having no
recollection of the route.
!Typical recording of the readiness
potential.{width="150"}Although
it might be accepted that much of our everyday behaviour is automatic is
there any behaviour that is definitely initiated by conscious
experience? This is probably a pointless question because consciousness
is about observation, not action; however, despite this there have been
several experiments that have attempted to determine the relationship
between consciousness and action.
In 1964 Kornhuber and Deecke performed a series of experiments that
measured the electrical activity from the scalp (EEG) during voluntary
actions. They averaged many EEG\'s from subjects who were about to move
a finger and discovered that there is an increase in scalp potential
before the movement takes place. The increase in potential can start as
long as 2 seconds or so before the movement and is known as the
\"readiness potential\" (Bereitschaftspotential). The readiness
potential is strange because it seems to contradict our conscious
experience; we do not decide to move a hand and then wait 2 seconds
before the hand moves. It seems that the non-conscious brain may be
taking things into its own hands.
Libet *et al.* (1983) extended the readiness potential experiments by
asking subjects to observe a Wundt clock whilst flexing a finger. The
Wundt clock had a spot of light that moved around a circle every 2.56
seconds and allowed the subjects to obtain timings that were related to
their mental experiences. When the subjects flexed a finger it was found
that the readiness potential occurred about 0.5 seconds before the
finger moved and the subjects reported they were going to move the
finger about 0.2 seconds before the movement. This suggested that a
subject\'s cerebral cortex was preparing for the movement about 0.3
seconds before the subject was conscious of this. Libet\'s experiments
have been reproduced elsewhere (see Keller & Heckhausen 1990). (It is
important to note that the subjects in Libet\'s experiment were asked to
wait until they felt the urge to move the finger.) These results are
consistent with the idea of the cortex as a modelling system that
constructs a consistent model of events to pass on to whatever mediates
conscious experience.
More recently fMRI and direct electrode recording have borne out the
readiness potential experiments. Soon *et al.* (2008) allowed subjects
to decide to press either a left or right button. They used fMRI to show
that there was spatially organised activity in the polar frontal cortex
and parietal cortex (from precuneus into posterior cingulate cortex)
that predicted the conscious left/right decision and preceded it by
about **seven seconds**. Rektor *et al.* (2001) used direct electrode
recordings to show a 2 second latency. Haggard & Eimer (1999) and also
Trevena and Miller (2002, 2009) have identified a \"Lateralized
Readiness Potential\" that is correlated with the movement of a
particular hand (left or right) in their EEG experiments and Trevena and
Miller claim that this potential always follows the making of a
conscious decision and precedes the actions being studied. However, Soon
*et al.* (2008) showed that fMRI can predict which button will be used
well before any conscious decision is reported. (See Haggard (2008) for
a review of conscious volition).
## Perception, Imagination, Memory and Dreams
### More about Models
Our dreams are clearly models that form a \'dreamworld\' but the idea
that perception might be like a dream that is updated by sensation is
not so obvious. Experience seems to be an active model of the world
(virtual reality) based on sense data rather than a simple mapping of
retinal and other sensory data. This is demonstrated by visual illusions
such as the Ames Room, Spoke Illusion and Muller Lyer illusions shown
below:
![](Constudame.png "Constudame.png")
Notice how the circle is distorted without any distortion in the
\'spokes\', it is as if the circle has been treated as a separate object
by the processes in the brain that rearranged it. In all of these
illusions the brain has rearranged large areas of the visual field and
has managed the input as a collection of \'objects\' that are
manipulated separately. Even movement seems to occur in some figures
showing that the brain models the position of things:
![](Constudcafe.png "Constudcafe.png")
The creation of a model is also demonstrated by the illusion of movement
experienced when we watch the cinema or television. This is due to the
cortical modelling that is known as \'short-range apparent motion\'
rather than flicker fusion or persistence of vision. It is intriguing
that, although it has been known for decades that the joining together
of static images in our minds is due to modelling activity in the brain
the myth that it is due to persistence of vision or flicker fusion is
universal. As Anderson and Anderson (1993) noted:
`Indeed, in the past decade, psychoanalytic-Marxist film scholars `\
`have retained the model implied by persistence of vision: theirs `\
`is a passive viewer, a spectator who is "positioned," unwittingly `\
`"sutured" into the text, and victimized by excess ideology.`
Our experience of the cinema is like a dream updated by sensation rather
than sensation updated by interpretation. In fact the most compelling
evidence for the modelling power of the brain is the existence of
dreams; our dreams are often models of worlds that do not exist and
involve little or no sensory input yet can involve effects as powerful
as any television drama.
Short range apparent motion occurs when the interval between
presentations of an object is brief (c. 50-100 msecs). Motion modelling
in response to longer intervals is known as long range apparent motion.
There is evidence that the modelling in short range apparent motion is
enhanced if the moving patterns are similar to moving human forms (such
as patterns of dots outlining a person)(Thornton *et al.* 1998). The
accuracy of predicting movement can actually improve if the interval
between presentations is increased when human forms are used.
Motion modelling can also be seen in visual illusions such as the
*Waterfall Illusion* (motion aftereffect). The waterfall illusion is
commonly seen after viewing a sequence of scrolling credits on the
television; when the credits stop rolling it appears as if they briefly
move in the opposite direction. Tootel *et al.* (1995) have used fMRI to
show that this is correlated with activity in the motion modelling area
of visual cortex (area MT/V5). The waterfall illusion is also associated
with an intriguing aftereffect known as **storage of the motion
aftereffect**. Normal motion aftereffects last for up to about ten
seconds after the stimulus, however, if the subjects close their eyes
for the normal duration of the aftereffect then reopen them they see the
illusion for almost the normal duration. Culham *et al.* (1999) used
fMRI to show that activity in area MT/V5 was low during the period when
the eyes were closed then increased dramatically when the eyes were
opened. This is strongly suggestive of a modelling mechanism outside
MT/V5 that has adapted to motion and then models stationary data with
movement in the wrong direction.
Visual area MT/V5 is also involved in the separation of moving visual
scenes into *sprites* or objects that move together as a whole within a
scene (Muckli *et al.* 2002).
The way that mental models may be the basis of ordinary reasoning was
outlined by Johnson-Laird (1980), based on earlier work by Kenneth
Craik.
Studies of \'change blindness\' and \'inattentional blindness\', where
subjects fail to spot outrageous changes in their environment, also
demonstrate that we experience a model and suggest that the brain must
analyse an object to incorporate it fully into the model (See for
instance Rensink (2000), Simons & Rensink (2005)).
### Brain areas used in perception overlap those used in imagination and recall
Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI) has shown that similar
areas of brain are used during perception involving the senses as during
imagination (Tong 2003, Kosslyn and Thompson 2003). The substrate of the
mental images that occur in both modes of brain activity has not yet
been found. This overlap of the brain areas used in perception with
those used in imagination, memory and recall has been demonstrated in a
wide range of experiments.
Ganis *et al.* (2004) used fairly complex perceptual and imagination
tasks that activated large areas of the brain, they found an overlap
between the brain areas activated during perception and imagery. The
principle areas that were different in the two tasks were found in the
primary sensory areas of the visual cortex. Other areas in the visual
cortex and activity in the rest of the brain showed a remarkable degree
of overlap. The authors suggested that the differences in the activity
of primary visual cortex may have been due to differences between the
perceptual and imaginary stimuli such as speed of onset etc. The
hippocampus was not activated.
It is intriguing that, contrary to object imagery, spatial imagery such
as predicting when a cross on a screen would fall on an imaginary letter
actually seems to inhibit activity in sensory visual cortex (Aleman *et
al.*). Both fMRI and blocking with transcranial magnetic stimulation
(TMS) showed that the posterior parietal cortex was involved in the
spatial imagery.
Imagery involving places and faces activates the place and face areas
that are activated during perception (Ishai *et al.* 2000).
The recall and recognition of things also seems to involve very similar
brain areas to those used during perception. Wheeler and Buckner (2003)
showed that areas involved in perception were also involved in the
recall of the perceptual stimuli.
Recall causes activation of areas used in perception but also seems to
use areas that may be particularly related to the process of recall
iself, such as the left parietal cortex (Konishi *et al.* 2000)
(Brodmann\'s area 40/39). Frontal and parietal regions are involved in
the recognition of whether stimuli have been experienced before.
Image generation during sleep seems to differ from that during
imagination and recall. In particular it seems to involve a few well
defined areas of cortex and considerable activation of the posterior
thalamus.
Sleep studies have shown that people dream throughout sleep. However,
dreams are more frequent during the REM (rapid eye movement) periods of
sleep than the NREM (non-REM) periods. Dreams are reported after 70-95%
of awakenings in REM sleep and 5-10% of awakenings in NREM sleep. REM
dreams are more visual than NREM dreams which are more \'thoughtlike\'
(Solms 2000). Thoughtlike events (mentation) are reported after 43% of
awakenings from NREM sleep.
Solms (1997) found that patients who had lesions in the
parietal-temporo-occipital junction reported a cessation of visual
images in dreams. Solms also found that patients with lesions in the
white matter inferior to the frontal horns of the lateral ventricles, in
the ventromesial quadrant of the frontal lobes, also reported loss of
dreaming. Loss of dreaming is also reported by leucotomised patients
with frontal ventromesial damage. Damasio *et al.* (1985) and Solms
(1997) also reported that some patients with damage to the medial
prefrontal cortex, the anterior cingulate cortex, and the basal
forebrain became confused about what was real life and what was dreaming
(waking dreams occurred).
Studies using fMRI show that the sensory occipital lobe (BA 18) and
posterior thalamus, especially the lateral geniculate nuclei, are
activated in REM sleep, weaker activations of the posterior cingulate,
putamen and midbrain were also found (Wehrle *et al.* 2005, Loveblad *et
al.* 1999). These findings are consistent with activation of the
ponto-geniculo-occipital system (PGO) during REM.
So dreams may be more like primary activations of sensory cortex than
imagining or recall. This suggests that dreams have a thalamic origin or
are managed via connections from the cortex through the thalamus to the
visual cortex.
Hallucinations seem to differ from dreams. In Charles Bonnett Syndrome
patients can have clear hallucinations. These, like imaginations, seem
to involve areas of the visual cortex that deal with processed data, for
instance hallucinations of faces activate the \"face area\" rather than
visual cortical area V1 (Ffytche *et al.* 1998).
### Suppression of data acquisition during saccades - perception as a patchwork
If you look at yourself in the mirror you will not see your eyes moving
even though they will be darting all over the view of your face. Even
when you deliberately look from place to place your eyes will appear
steady. The natural darting of the eyes from place to place as you view
a scene is known as \"saccadic\" movement of the eyes. The suppression
of the visual image during the motion of the eyes is known as \"saccadic
suppression\" or \"saccadic masking\". The suppression of the
acquisition of image data extends to suppression of awareness of flashes
of light during saccades, this effect is known as \"flash suppression\",
however, flash suppression seems to apply only to rather dull flashes
(Volkman (1962). The suppression during saccades is probably due to
suppression of the magnocellular pathway (the motion sensitive pathway)
in the lateral geniculate nucleus (Burr *et al.* (1996).
The most intriguing feature of this suppression of data acquisition
during saccades is that each snapshot that is obtained between saccades
can only contain a relatively small amount of information. This is
because the fovea, which is the most sensitive area of the eye, is tiny
(about 1mm diameter) and only receives input from a few degrees of the
visual field. As a result what we consider to be a uniform scene in our
minds is actually a patchwork of intersaccade snapshots.
Another aspect of saccades is that the timing of events is referred back
to the beginning of the saccade. This effect is known as \"saccadic
chronostasis\". For example, if an object changes colour during a
saccade the observer feels as if the colour change occurred at the
beginning of the saccade, so extending the amount of time that the
object possesses the changed colour. This effect can extend apparent
durations by up to 500 ms and is consistent with the idea that the
visual system models events prior to perception (see Yarrow *et al.*
2006).
Burr D, Morrone M, Ross J. (1996) Selective suppression of the
magnocellular visual pathway during saccades\]\'\', Behavioral Brain
Research 80 1-8 (1996)
<http://www.pisavisionlab.org/downloads/BBRReview96.pdf>
Volkman, F. (1962). Vision during voluntary saccadic eye movements. J.
Opt Soc. Am. 52:571-578. 1962.
Yarrow, K, Whiteley, L, Rothwell, J.C & Haggard,P. (2006) Spatial
consequences of bridging the saccadic gap. Vision Res. 2006 February;
46(4): 545--555.
<http://www.hexicon.co.uk/Kielan/papers/Moving_chrono.pdf>
## Blindsight
Blindsight studies illuminate the relationship between the cerebral
cortex and our experience. When the visual cortex is removed subjects
become almost totally blind. If the visual cortex on one side is removed
subjects become relatively blind in the contra-lateral hemifield. One of
the most revealing studies of blindsight is Marcel\'s 1998 paper: \"
Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of visual consciousness or
visual function?\".
It is useful when considering blindsight to contemplate for a while the
appearance of the world with both eyes closed and then with one eye
closed. When both eyes are closed our experience is of a darkish space
radiating out from our heads, with one eye closed we tend to ignore the
darkish areas that cannot be seen even though they are still present.
Marcel notes that patients who have a right blind field still have an
underlying visual field on the right side and that this can even contain
conscious visual experience. This sounds a bit like the darkish space
that we all experience if deprived of visual input on one side. As
Marcel says: \"A question that naturally arises is whether the loss is a
\'total\' loss of visual consciousness in the blind field. It is often
assumed to be so, especially by those who discuss blindsight without
carefully reading the literature or working with the subjects. One can
immediately respond negatively to the question..\"
The consciousness of the completion of Kanizsa figures in blindsight
patients is particularly indicative of the preservation of the field
even though the content was largely missing. A Kanizsa figure is shown
below:
![](Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg "Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg")
If we put Marcel\'s observations together with cortical anatomy and
function it seems that the space of our experience is located outside of
the cerebral cortex. The cortex generates much of visual and other
content but it does not generate the space.
## The Role of the Thalamus
The thalamus is connected to the entire bottom layer of the cerebral
cortex. It is the nexus of the various cortical processors as well as a
recipient of independent input from most of the rest of the brain.
![](Constudbrain.png "Constudbrain.png")
The thalamus is subdivided into numerous small and medium sized nuclei
that between them receive inputs from every process in the nervous
system (the white fibres in the illustration above largely penetrate the
thalamus). The thalamic nuclei are interconnected which means that any
of them could, potentially host activity from anywhere in the body or
brain. Although the founders of neurology such as Hughlings Jackson and
Penfield & Jasper located conscious experience in the diencephalon,
including the thalamus, this is no longer the conventional wisdom. The
small size of the thalamic nuclei means that they cannot support the
processes that are assumed to compose access consciousness, however,
even some of the smallest thalamic nuclei host millions of synapses so
size would not be an obstacle if the thalamus contains the substrate of
phenomenal consciousness. Indeed, the diencephalon and the thalamus in
particular can be shown to be excellent candidates for a possible
location of phenomenal experience.
![](constudintralam.jpg "constudintralam.jpg")
`<font size=1>`{=html} The Intralaminar Nuclei of the thalamus. The
white space above and to the left of RN is the third ventricle.
MD=mediodorsal nucleus. CM=Centromedian nucleus, RN=red nucleus (not
part of thalamus) The black areas are stained white fibres. Picture
from: <http://www.neurophys.wisc.edu/> University of Wisconsin and
Michigan State Comparative Mammalian Brain Collections. Preparation of
image has been funded by the National Science Foundation, as well as by
the National Institutes of Health. May only be used with these
acknowledgements.`</font>`{=html}
If the thalamus contains a location for conscious experience then
lesions should abolish this experience. Unlike the cerebral hemispheres,
lesions of the thalamus do indeed seem to abolish consciousness. The
area that is most sensitive to lesions contains the Intralaminar Nuclei,
especially the Parafascicular and Centromedian Nuclei. If these are
damaged bilaterally patients suffer death, coma, akinetic mutism,
hypersomnia, dementia and other equally serious impairments of
consciousness that depend upon the size and placement of the lesions
(Bogen 1995, Schiff & Plum 1999). In cases of fatal familial insomnia,
in which patients exhibit many of these symptoms, there is marked neuron
loss in the Intralaminar Nuclei (Budka 1998).
The effect of interrupting the blood supply to the medial thalamus
depends upon the severity of the damage. There is frequently initial
coma. The recovery after coma is often incomplete, Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) described bilateral paramedian thalamic infarcts as normally
being \"followed by persisting dementia with severe mnemic disturbance,
global aspontaneity and apathy.\" The symptoms of bilateral damage to
the ILN can be so severe that it is possible that, even after recovery
from coma, some patients may cease to be conscious and are being
coordinated by automatic cortical processes.
Bjornstad *et al.* (2003) and Woernera *et al.* (2005) both reported
that the initial coma after bilateral paramedian infarct was accompanied
by a similar pattern of EEG activity to stage 2 sleep. Woernera *et al.*
(2005) also discovered that painful stimuli gave rise to a range of EEG
activity, transiently breaking the stage 2 sleep pattern but without
recovery of consciousness. Unfortunately even in those patients who
recover consciousness Kumral *et al.* (2001) report that \"Cognitive
functions in patients with bilateral paramedian infarction did not
change significantly during the follow-up, in contrast to those with
infarcts in varied arterial territories\" although Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) did report a single patient who made a total recovery.
Laureys *et al.* (2002) investigated recovery from \'persistent
vegetative state\' (wakefulness without awareness). They found that
overall cortical metabolism remained almost constant during recovery but
that the metabolism in the prefrontal and association cortices became
correlated with thalamic ILN and precuneus activity. Again confirming
that thalamo-cortico-thalamic activity is required for consciousness and
that cortical activity by itself is not conscious. Yamamoto *et al.*
(2005) investigated persistent vegetative state and found that deep
brain stimulation (25Hz) of the centromedian-parafascicular complex (19
cases) or mesencephalic reticular formation (2 cases) resulted in 8 of
the patients emerging from persistent vegetative state. It is
interesting that zolpidem, a GABA agonist, has recently been found to
reverse PVS in some patients (Claus & Nel 2006). The effect is rapid and
might be used to demonstrate the correlations that occur on recovery
from PVS.
As Bogen(1995) demonstrates, the ILN receive inputs, either directly or
indirectly, from every part of the CNS but what do they do?
Interest in the thalamus has recently been revived by the theories of
Newman & Baars (1993), Baars, Newman, & Taylor1998) and Crick & Koch
(1990). In Baars, Newman and Taylors\' (1998) theory it is suggested
that \"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not
the detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\".
They also propose that the \"nucleus reticularis thalami\" (Thalamic
Reticular Nucleus, TRN), which is a thin sheet of neurons that covers
the thalamus, is involved in a selective attention system. This concept
is reinforced by the way that point stimulation of the TRN causes focal
activity in the overlying cortex (MacDonald *et al.* 1998) and the way
the TRN is organised topographically (i.e.: has activity that is like an
electrical image of receptor fields).
The thalamus is ideally placed for integrating brain activity, if tiny
parts of the thalamus are removed consciousness is abolished and the
thalamus is involved in attention and the global integration of cortical
activity. Any impartial judge might pronounce that the site of conscious
experience has been found, possibly in the ILN of the thalamus, but no
one can say how it works.
## General Anaesthesia and the Thalamus
General anaesthesia should result in a profound depression of activity
in the ILN if these are indeed the sites of the conscious state. White &
Alkire (2003) administered halothane or isoflurane to volunteers and
used positron emission tomography (PET) to monitor brain activity. They
found severe depression of activity in the thalamus. The depression
appeared to be higher in the non-specific nuclei than in the relay
nuclei of the thalamus. In other words the anaesthesia is neither
turning off the cortex nor turning off the input to the cortex but it is
turning off an important part of the thalamus. Fiset *et al.* (1999)
have also demonstrated a similar pattern of medial thalamic inactivity
and cortical activity in propofol anaesthesia. Suppression of cortical
activity is not the cause of unconsciousness; for instance, the
anaesthetic agent chloralose leads to increased neural activity in the
cortex relative to conscious patients (Cariani 2000).
## The function of consciousness
When we walk our conscious experience does not contain data about the
control of the spinal, cerebellar and vestibular reflexes that keep us
on an even keel. When we reach out for a cup our conscious experience
only contains data related to the need for the cup, not data about the
elaborate control system that enables the action. When we talk the words
just come into mind, we do not painstakingly control the syntax and
vocal chords. When our attention shifts the conscious experience
containing the shift happens after the attention has shifted. This
passive nature of experience recurs throughout the neuroscience of
consciousness from the \"readiness potential\" to the \"auditory
continuity illusion\". So what does conscious observation do? The
medical evidence of the lack of consciousness in some forms of delirium,
mutism, PVS etc. suggest that the role of conscious observation is to
stabilise the brain so that it acts as a coordinated whole. Conscious
observation is an orderly arrangement of events, a stable groundform
that reflects the environment and composes the stage for action. It
could be speculated that if quantum events were prominent in brain
function then such a groundform would be essential but even a classical
brain might require a stabilising form that could be continuously
compared with the world beyond the body.
A stable form of neural information that contains bound data from the
senses and internal neural processes is likely to have a role in the
functioning of the organism. There is now an *integration consensus*
that proposes that phenomenal states somehow integrate neural activities
and information-processing that would otherwise be independent (see
review in Baars, 2002).
However, it has remained unspecified which kinds of information are
integrated in a conscious manner and which kinds can be integrated
without consciousness. Obviously not all kinds of information are
capable of being disseminated consciously (e.g., neural activity related
to vegetative functions, reflexes, unconscious motor programs, low-level
perceptual analyses, etc.) and many kinds can be disseminated and
combined with other kinds without consciousness, as in intersensory
interactions such as the ventriloquism effect.
Morsella (2005) proposed a *Supramodular Interaction Theory* (SIT) that
contrasts the task demands of consciously penetrable processes (e.g.:
those that can be part of conscious experience such as pain, conflicting
urges, and the delay of gratification) and consciously impenetrable
processes (e.g.: intersensory conflicts, peristalsis, and the pupillary
reflex). With this contrastive approach, SIT builds upon the integration
consensus by specifying which kinds of interaction require conscious
processing and which kinds do not (e.g., some intersensory processes).
SIT proposes that conscious processes are required to integrate
high-level systems in the brain that are vying for (specifically)
skeletomotor control, as described by the principle of *parallel
responses into skeletal muscle* (PRISM). Accordingly, regarding
processes such as digestion and excretion, one is conscious of only
those phases of the processes that require coordination with
skeletomotor plans (e.g., chewing or micturating) and none of those that
do not (e.g., peristalsis). From this standpoint, consciousness
functions above the level of the traditional module to "cross-talk"
among high-level, specialized and often multi-modal, systems.
**References**
Baars, B. J. (2002). The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent
evidence. *Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6,* 47 -- 52.
Morsella, E. (2005). The function of phenomenal states: Supramodular
interaction theory. *Psychological Review, 112,* 1000 - 1021.
More\... Click here for Rivalries and synchronisation, bibliography
and references
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 1#The cortex and consciousness
## The cortex and consciousness
The cerebral cortex consists of a set of specialised areas that process
different aspects of sensation and motor control. There are about ten
times as many nerve fibres going from the cortex to the thalamus as
there are from the thalamus to the cortex (Destexhe 2000).
![](constudconn.gif "constudconn.gif")
Histologically the cerebral cortex is a layer of greyish neurons
overlying a huge mass of white nerve fibres, the cerebral medulla. The
cortex consists of six main layers. The upper layers receive input from
the relays in the thalamus such as the lateral geniculate, from the
thalamus in general and from other areas of cortex plus a few
specialised inputs from other locations. The lower layers give rise to
output fibres that largely connect with the thalamus and other areas of
cortex although particular specialised processors in the cortex may also
have direct connections elsewhere such as to motor nuclei.
![](Constudcortex2.png "Constudcortex2.png")
The cerebral cortex has many functions and is divided up into numerous
separate processors. The most important function of the cortex from the
point of view of consciousness studies is that it creates models. As was
seen in Part I, philosophers debate whether these models are actually
experienced consciously but in the neurophysiological literature it is
normally assumed that we do experience models and rehearsals such as
inner speech and imaginings. There is considerable evidence that the
parts of the brain that deal with imagining (modelling) things are also
the parts that deal with perception (i.e.: modelling the world). The
overlap between imagination and normal perception is not complete
because, as Tong(2003), in a review of visual consciousness, put it:
\"Internally generated experiences share some, but not all, of the
phenomenal properties of actual perception\". There is also considerable
overlap between the areas used for imaginary speech (thought) and actual
speech, areas dealing with the control of sensation and of the tongue
etc. being used in actual speech but not in imagined speech (Fu *et al.*
2002). Kreiman *et al.* (2000) investigated the activity of single
neurons in humans and also found that the brain activity evoked by
visual imagination overlapped that which occurs upon direct stimulation
by the same image.
Our conscious experience consists of the output of the cortical
modelling and perceptual processes. The cerebral cortex itself appears
to be non-conscious. The evidence for the non-conscious nature of the
cerebral cortex consists of lesion studies in which large amounts of
cortex can be removed without removing consciousness and physiological
studies in which it is demonstrated that the cerebral cortex can be
active without conscious experience.
Lesion studies have shown that up to 60% of the cerebral cortex can be
removed without abolishing consciousness (Austin and Grant 1958). An
entire hemisphere can be removed or much of the front or back of the
cerebral cortex can be cut off yet consciousness persists.
Fiset *et al.* (1999) and Cariani (2000) have shown that cortical
activity can be normal or even elevated during the unconscious state of
general anaesthesia. Alkire *et al.* (1996) also showed that cortical
activity related to word recognition occurred during general
anaesthesia.
Libet *et al.* (1967) found that there could be cerebral cortical
activity in response to weak stimulation of the skin without any
conscious awareness of the stimulus. This work provides a
neurophysiological basis for subliminal (non-conscious) perception and
also shows that large areas of the cerebral cortex can be active without
conscious experience. The insensitivity of experience to cortical
activity has been further confirmed by Libet *et al.* (1979). They
electrically stimulated the cerebral cortex of conscious patients and
discovered that the stimulus must be continued for about 0.5 seconds for
subjects to report a conscious experience of the stimulation. Libet\'s
findings have been analysed at length but there still appears to be a
0.25 to 0.5 secs delay (Klein 2002).
It has been demonstrated that cerebral cortical activity is not
synonymous with conscious experience but why should there be a delay of
up to 0.5 seconds or so between cortical stimulation and a conscious
percept? What is the cortex doing in the 0.5 seconds between the start
of stimulation and the report of awareness of the stimulation? It is
probably synchronising its various processors and creating a waking
dream, a structured set of events that accounts for the activity. The
synchronisation of cerebral cortical processes will be discussed later,
but what evidence is there for the cerebral cortex constructing a waking
dream, or model, to describe the world?
The \'Attentional Blink\' (Raymond *et al.* 1992) is consistent with the
concept of the cerebral cortex being a device that creates models. In
the \'Attentional Blink\' the identification of an object impairs the
identification of a second object that is presented within 0.5 seconds
of the first. Raymond *et al.* used a stream of letters (11 letters per
second) and the identification of a first letter impaired the
identification of a subsequent \'probe\' letter in the stream. If the
probe letter followed the first letter within about 180 msecs it could
easily be identified, suggesting that chunks of about 180 msecs of data
stream are modelled together. Christmann & Leuthold (2004) have
theorised that the \'Attentional Blink\' involves perceptual and central
components of visual processing. This is supported by the fMRI studies
of Marois *et al.* (2004) who presented subjects with faces mounted on
scenes of places. The scenes of places often went undetected by subjects
but they activated regions of the medial temporal cortex involved in
high-level scene representations, the parahippocampal place area (PPA).
When the scenes of places were detected by the subjects there was
activity in the frontal cortex and the PPA activity was increased. These
experiments are consistent with the idea of a cerebral cortex that is a
multiprocessor system that creates consistent models of the environment.
Bregman\'s (1990) auditory continuity illusion is another example of how
sensory events are modelled. If a pure tone is followed by broadband
noise and the noise followed by the same pure tone it seems as if the
tone occurs throughout the period of noise. If the noise is not followed
by the pure tone there is no sound of the tone during the period of
noise. This effect is similar to the results found by Libet because a
delay of several hundred milliseconds between sensory stimulation and
conscious experience is needed to account for the apparent rewriting of
history after the second tone appears.
Dennett and Kinsbourne (1992) argued strongly against modelling as the
source of conscious experience. They discussed two illusions, the
\"cutaneous rabbit illusion\", in which the subject is tapped
successively in such a way that some illusory taps appear and the \"phi
illusion\" in which successively illuminated lights appear as a motion
of the light. Dennett and Kinsbourne declared that there should be no
cerebral cortical filling in of the gaps in the these illusions. Both
these illusions have now been investigated. Blankenburg *et al.* (2006)
found that cerebral cortical activity occurred at the locations expected
for the missing taps in the \"cutaneous rabbit\" illusion and Larsen *et
al.* (2006) found that the areas of cerebral cortex that would be
stimulated by a moving light were active during the \"phi illusion\".
## The delay before consciousness of \"voluntary\" actions
The 0.5 second delay required for the cortex to model an event has
implications for the role of conscious experience in the control of our
lives. If experience is about 0.5 seconds behind the true present
instant then how can we be said to control anything? The brain must be
acting automatically whilst performing most tasks. The 0.5 second delay
also seems to contradict our everyday experience. We certainly feel like
we are aware of things in less than 0.5 seconds, for example, the direct
stimulation of sense organs seems to be experienced much more rapidly
than the delayed experience of cortical stimulation. In fact subjects
report that they are conscious of stimuli, such as being touched or
seeing flashing lights, within 0.1 to 0.2 seconds of the event. So how
can subjects report events within 0.2 seconds even though it seems to
take 0.5 seconds for the cortex to generate activity that can be
experienced? The simplest explanation is that the reaction occurs
automatically within 0.2 seconds and then the conscious experience of
this reaction occurs 0.3 seconds later. This gives a total 0.5 seconds
delay before conscious experience whilst allowing fast reactions.
Libet *et al.* extended their experiments by stimulating a \"relay
nucleus\" in the thalamus that intercepts signals from the senses before
they reach the somatosensory cortex. It was found that when this nucleus
was stimulated for 0.5 seconds the subjects reported that the stimulus
occurred 0.2 seconds after it had begun. When the nucleus was stimulated
for less than 0.5 seconds the subjects did not report any sensation.
This supports the concept of a 0.5 second delay whilst the cortex puts a
stimulus in context before it is experienced.
These experiments show that our experience is an output of cortical
processing rather than the processing itself. If our conscious
experience is non-cortical then this raises the possibility that the
non-conscious cerebral cortex can perform actions without conscious
control. Of course, the cortex does this all the time when we are
indulging in skilled or routine behaviour. The ability of the
non-conscious cortex is quite remarkable; for instance car drivers
sometimes discover that they have driven for several miles without
conscious experience of driving, even at the level of having no
recollection of the route.
!Typical recording of the readiness
potential.{width="150"}Although
it might be accepted that much of our everyday behaviour is automatic is
there any behaviour that is definitely initiated by conscious
experience? This is probably a pointless question because consciousness
is about observation, not action; however, despite this there have been
several experiments that have attempted to determine the relationship
between consciousness and action.
In 1964 Kornhuber and Deecke performed a series of experiments that
measured the electrical activity from the scalp (EEG) during voluntary
actions. They averaged many EEG\'s from subjects who were about to move
a finger and discovered that there is an increase in scalp potential
before the movement takes place. The increase in potential can start as
long as 2 seconds or so before the movement and is known as the
\"readiness potential\" (Bereitschaftspotential). The readiness
potential is strange because it seems to contradict our conscious
experience; we do not decide to move a hand and then wait 2 seconds
before the hand moves. It seems that the non-conscious brain may be
taking things into its own hands.
Libet *et al.* (1983) extended the readiness potential experiments by
asking subjects to observe a Wundt clock whilst flexing a finger. The
Wundt clock had a spot of light that moved around a circle every 2.56
seconds and allowed the subjects to obtain timings that were related to
their mental experiences. When the subjects flexed a finger it was found
that the readiness potential occurred about 0.5 seconds before the
finger moved and the subjects reported they were going to move the
finger about 0.2 seconds before the movement. This suggested that a
subject\'s cerebral cortex was preparing for the movement about 0.3
seconds before the subject was conscious of this. Libet\'s experiments
have been reproduced elsewhere (see Keller & Heckhausen 1990). (It is
important to note that the subjects in Libet\'s experiment were asked to
wait until they felt the urge to move the finger.) These results are
consistent with the idea of the cortex as a modelling system that
constructs a consistent model of events to pass on to whatever mediates
conscious experience.
More recently fMRI and direct electrode recording have borne out the
readiness potential experiments. Soon *et al.* (2008) allowed subjects
to decide to press either a left or right button. They used fMRI to show
that there was spatially organised activity in the polar frontal cortex
and parietal cortex (from precuneus into posterior cingulate cortex)
that predicted the conscious left/right decision and preceded it by
about **seven seconds**. Rektor *et al.* (2001) used direct electrode
recordings to show a 2 second latency. Haggard & Eimer (1999) and also
Trevena and Miller (2002, 2009) have identified a \"Lateralized
Readiness Potential\" that is correlated with the movement of a
particular hand (left or right) in their EEG experiments and Trevena and
Miller claim that this potential always follows the making of a
conscious decision and precedes the actions being studied. However, Soon
*et al.* (2008) showed that fMRI can predict which button will be used
well before any conscious decision is reported. (See Haggard (2008) for
a review of conscious volition).
## Perception, Imagination, Memory and Dreams
### More about Models
Our dreams are clearly models that form a \'dreamworld\' but the idea
that perception might be like a dream that is updated by sensation is
not so obvious. Experience seems to be an active model of the world
(virtual reality) based on sense data rather than a simple mapping of
retinal and other sensory data. This is demonstrated by visual illusions
such as the Ames Room, Spoke Illusion and Muller Lyer illusions shown
below:
![](Constudame.png "Constudame.png")
Notice how the circle is distorted without any distortion in the
\'spokes\', it is as if the circle has been treated as a separate object
by the processes in the brain that rearranged it. In all of these
illusions the brain has rearranged large areas of the visual field and
has managed the input as a collection of \'objects\' that are
manipulated separately. Even movement seems to occur in some figures
showing that the brain models the position of things:
![](Constudcafe.png "Constudcafe.png")
The creation of a model is also demonstrated by the illusion of movement
experienced when we watch the cinema or television. This is due to the
cortical modelling that is known as \'short-range apparent motion\'
rather than flicker fusion or persistence of vision. It is intriguing
that, although it has been known for decades that the joining together
of static images in our minds is due to modelling activity in the brain
the myth that it is due to persistence of vision or flicker fusion is
universal. As Anderson and Anderson (1993) noted:
`Indeed, in the past decade, psychoanalytic-Marxist film scholars `\
`have retained the model implied by persistence of vision: theirs `\
`is a passive viewer, a spectator who is "positioned," unwittingly `\
`"sutured" into the text, and victimized by excess ideology.`
Our experience of the cinema is like a dream updated by sensation rather
than sensation updated by interpretation. In fact the most compelling
evidence for the modelling power of the brain is the existence of
dreams; our dreams are often models of worlds that do not exist and
involve little or no sensory input yet can involve effects as powerful
as any television drama.
Short range apparent motion occurs when the interval between
presentations of an object is brief (c. 50-100 msecs). Motion modelling
in response to longer intervals is known as long range apparent motion.
There is evidence that the modelling in short range apparent motion is
enhanced if the moving patterns are similar to moving human forms (such
as patterns of dots outlining a person)(Thornton *et al.* 1998). The
accuracy of predicting movement can actually improve if the interval
between presentations is increased when human forms are used.
Motion modelling can also be seen in visual illusions such as the
*Waterfall Illusion* (motion aftereffect). The waterfall illusion is
commonly seen after viewing a sequence of scrolling credits on the
television; when the credits stop rolling it appears as if they briefly
move in the opposite direction. Tootel *et al.* (1995) have used fMRI to
show that this is correlated with activity in the motion modelling area
of visual cortex (area MT/V5). The waterfall illusion is also associated
with an intriguing aftereffect known as **storage of the motion
aftereffect**. Normal motion aftereffects last for up to about ten
seconds after the stimulus, however, if the subjects close their eyes
for the normal duration of the aftereffect then reopen them they see the
illusion for almost the normal duration. Culham *et al.* (1999) used
fMRI to show that activity in area MT/V5 was low during the period when
the eyes were closed then increased dramatically when the eyes were
opened. This is strongly suggestive of a modelling mechanism outside
MT/V5 that has adapted to motion and then models stationary data with
movement in the wrong direction.
Visual area MT/V5 is also involved in the separation of moving visual
scenes into *sprites* or objects that move together as a whole within a
scene (Muckli *et al.* 2002).
The way that mental models may be the basis of ordinary reasoning was
outlined by Johnson-Laird (1980), based on earlier work by Kenneth
Craik.
Studies of \'change blindness\' and \'inattentional blindness\', where
subjects fail to spot outrageous changes in their environment, also
demonstrate that we experience a model and suggest that the brain must
analyse an object to incorporate it fully into the model (See for
instance Rensink (2000), Simons & Rensink (2005)).
### Brain areas used in perception overlap those used in imagination and recall
Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI) has shown that similar
areas of brain are used during perception involving the senses as during
imagination (Tong 2003, Kosslyn and Thompson 2003). The substrate of the
mental images that occur in both modes of brain activity has not yet
been found. This overlap of the brain areas used in perception with
those used in imagination, memory and recall has been demonstrated in a
wide range of experiments.
Ganis *et al.* (2004) used fairly complex perceptual and imagination
tasks that activated large areas of the brain, they found an overlap
between the brain areas activated during perception and imagery. The
principle areas that were different in the two tasks were found in the
primary sensory areas of the visual cortex. Other areas in the visual
cortex and activity in the rest of the brain showed a remarkable degree
of overlap. The authors suggested that the differences in the activity
of primary visual cortex may have been due to differences between the
perceptual and imaginary stimuli such as speed of onset etc. The
hippocampus was not activated.
It is intriguing that, contrary to object imagery, spatial imagery such
as predicting when a cross on a screen would fall on an imaginary letter
actually seems to inhibit activity in sensory visual cortex (Aleman *et
al.*). Both fMRI and blocking with transcranial magnetic stimulation
(TMS) showed that the posterior parietal cortex was involved in the
spatial imagery.
Imagery involving places and faces activates the place and face areas
that are activated during perception (Ishai *et al.* 2000).
The recall and recognition of things also seems to involve very similar
brain areas to those used during perception. Wheeler and Buckner (2003)
showed that areas involved in perception were also involved in the
recall of the perceptual stimuli.
Recall causes activation of areas used in perception but also seems to
use areas that may be particularly related to the process of recall
iself, such as the left parietal cortex (Konishi *et al.* 2000)
(Brodmann\'s area 40/39). Frontal and parietal regions are involved in
the recognition of whether stimuli have been experienced before.
Image generation during sleep seems to differ from that during
imagination and recall. In particular it seems to involve a few well
defined areas of cortex and considerable activation of the posterior
thalamus.
Sleep studies have shown that people dream throughout sleep. However,
dreams are more frequent during the REM (rapid eye movement) periods of
sleep than the NREM (non-REM) periods. Dreams are reported after 70-95%
of awakenings in REM sleep and 5-10% of awakenings in NREM sleep. REM
dreams are more visual than NREM dreams which are more \'thoughtlike\'
(Solms 2000). Thoughtlike events (mentation) are reported after 43% of
awakenings from NREM sleep.
Solms (1997) found that patients who had lesions in the
parietal-temporo-occipital junction reported a cessation of visual
images in dreams. Solms also found that patients with lesions in the
white matter inferior to the frontal horns of the lateral ventricles, in
the ventromesial quadrant of the frontal lobes, also reported loss of
dreaming. Loss of dreaming is also reported by leucotomised patients
with frontal ventromesial damage. Damasio *et al.* (1985) and Solms
(1997) also reported that some patients with damage to the medial
prefrontal cortex, the anterior cingulate cortex, and the basal
forebrain became confused about what was real life and what was dreaming
(waking dreams occurred).
Studies using fMRI show that the sensory occipital lobe (BA 18) and
posterior thalamus, especially the lateral geniculate nuclei, are
activated in REM sleep, weaker activations of the posterior cingulate,
putamen and midbrain were also found (Wehrle *et al.* 2005, Loveblad *et
al.* 1999). These findings are consistent with activation of the
ponto-geniculo-occipital system (PGO) during REM.
So dreams may be more like primary activations of sensory cortex than
imagining or recall. This suggests that dreams have a thalamic origin or
are managed via connections from the cortex through the thalamus to the
visual cortex.
Hallucinations seem to differ from dreams. In Charles Bonnett Syndrome
patients can have clear hallucinations. These, like imaginations, seem
to involve areas of the visual cortex that deal with processed data, for
instance hallucinations of faces activate the \"face area\" rather than
visual cortical area V1 (Ffytche *et al.* 1998).
### Suppression of data acquisition during saccades - perception as a patchwork
If you look at yourself in the mirror you will not see your eyes moving
even though they will be darting all over the view of your face. Even
when you deliberately look from place to place your eyes will appear
steady. The natural darting of the eyes from place to place as you view
a scene is known as \"saccadic\" movement of the eyes. The suppression
of the visual image during the motion of the eyes is known as \"saccadic
suppression\" or \"saccadic masking\". The suppression of the
acquisition of image data extends to suppression of awareness of flashes
of light during saccades, this effect is known as \"flash suppression\",
however, flash suppression seems to apply only to rather dull flashes
(Volkman (1962). The suppression during saccades is probably due to
suppression of the magnocellular pathway (the motion sensitive pathway)
in the lateral geniculate nucleus (Burr *et al.* (1996).
The most intriguing feature of this suppression of data acquisition
during saccades is that each snapshot that is obtained between saccades
can only contain a relatively small amount of information. This is
because the fovea, which is the most sensitive area of the eye, is tiny
(about 1mm diameter) and only receives input from a few degrees of the
visual field. As a result what we consider to be a uniform scene in our
minds is actually a patchwork of intersaccade snapshots.
Another aspect of saccades is that the timing of events is referred back
to the beginning of the saccade. This effect is known as \"saccadic
chronostasis\". For example, if an object changes colour during a
saccade the observer feels as if the colour change occurred at the
beginning of the saccade, so extending the amount of time that the
object possesses the changed colour. This effect can extend apparent
durations by up to 500 ms and is consistent with the idea that the
visual system models events prior to perception (see Yarrow *et al.*
2006).
Burr D, Morrone M, Ross J. (1996) Selective suppression of the
magnocellular visual pathway during saccades\]\'\', Behavioral Brain
Research 80 1-8 (1996)
<http://www.pisavisionlab.org/downloads/BBRReview96.pdf>
Volkman, F. (1962). Vision during voluntary saccadic eye movements. J.
Opt Soc. Am. 52:571-578. 1962.
Yarrow, K, Whiteley, L, Rothwell, J.C & Haggard,P. (2006) Spatial
consequences of bridging the saccadic gap. Vision Res. 2006 February;
46(4): 545--555.
<http://www.hexicon.co.uk/Kielan/papers/Moving_chrono.pdf>
## Blindsight
Blindsight studies illuminate the relationship between the cerebral
cortex and our experience. When the visual cortex is removed subjects
become almost totally blind. If the visual cortex on one side is removed
subjects become relatively blind in the contra-lateral hemifield. One of
the most revealing studies of blindsight is Marcel\'s 1998 paper: \"
Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of visual consciousness or
visual function?\".
It is useful when considering blindsight to contemplate for a while the
appearance of the world with both eyes closed and then with one eye
closed. When both eyes are closed our experience is of a darkish space
radiating out from our heads, with one eye closed we tend to ignore the
darkish areas that cannot be seen even though they are still present.
Marcel notes that patients who have a right blind field still have an
underlying visual field on the right side and that this can even contain
conscious visual experience. This sounds a bit like the darkish space
that we all experience if deprived of visual input on one side. As
Marcel says: \"A question that naturally arises is whether the loss is a
\'total\' loss of visual consciousness in the blind field. It is often
assumed to be so, especially by those who discuss blindsight without
carefully reading the literature or working with the subjects. One can
immediately respond negatively to the question..\"
The consciousness of the completion of Kanizsa figures in blindsight
patients is particularly indicative of the preservation of the field
even though the content was largely missing. A Kanizsa figure is shown
below:
![](Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg "Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg")
If we put Marcel\'s observations together with cortical anatomy and
function it seems that the space of our experience is located outside of
the cerebral cortex. The cortex generates much of visual and other
content but it does not generate the space.
## The Role of the Thalamus
The thalamus is connected to the entire bottom layer of the cerebral
cortex. It is the nexus of the various cortical processors as well as a
recipient of independent input from most of the rest of the brain.
![](Constudbrain.png "Constudbrain.png")
The thalamus is subdivided into numerous small and medium sized nuclei
that between them receive inputs from every process in the nervous
system (the white fibres in the illustration above largely penetrate the
thalamus). The thalamic nuclei are interconnected which means that any
of them could, potentially host activity from anywhere in the body or
brain. Although the founders of neurology such as Hughlings Jackson and
Penfield & Jasper located conscious experience in the diencephalon,
including the thalamus, this is no longer the conventional wisdom. The
small size of the thalamic nuclei means that they cannot support the
processes that are assumed to compose access consciousness, however,
even some of the smallest thalamic nuclei host millions of synapses so
size would not be an obstacle if the thalamus contains the substrate of
phenomenal consciousness. Indeed, the diencephalon and the thalamus in
particular can be shown to be excellent candidates for a possible
location of phenomenal experience.
![](constudintralam.jpg "constudintralam.jpg")
`<font size=1>`{=html} The Intralaminar Nuclei of the thalamus. The
white space above and to the left of RN is the third ventricle.
MD=mediodorsal nucleus. CM=Centromedian nucleus, RN=red nucleus (not
part of thalamus) The black areas are stained white fibres. Picture
from: <http://www.neurophys.wisc.edu/> University of Wisconsin and
Michigan State Comparative Mammalian Brain Collections. Preparation of
image has been funded by the National Science Foundation, as well as by
the National Institutes of Health. May only be used with these
acknowledgements.`</font>`{=html}
If the thalamus contains a location for conscious experience then
lesions should abolish this experience. Unlike the cerebral hemispheres,
lesions of the thalamus do indeed seem to abolish consciousness. The
area that is most sensitive to lesions contains the Intralaminar Nuclei,
especially the Parafascicular and Centromedian Nuclei. If these are
damaged bilaterally patients suffer death, coma, akinetic mutism,
hypersomnia, dementia and other equally serious impairments of
consciousness that depend upon the size and placement of the lesions
(Bogen 1995, Schiff & Plum 1999). In cases of fatal familial insomnia,
in which patients exhibit many of these symptoms, there is marked neuron
loss in the Intralaminar Nuclei (Budka 1998).
The effect of interrupting the blood supply to the medial thalamus
depends upon the severity of the damage. There is frequently initial
coma. The recovery after coma is often incomplete, Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) described bilateral paramedian thalamic infarcts as normally
being \"followed by persisting dementia with severe mnemic disturbance,
global aspontaneity and apathy.\" The symptoms of bilateral damage to
the ILN can be so severe that it is possible that, even after recovery
from coma, some patients may cease to be conscious and are being
coordinated by automatic cortical processes.
Bjornstad *et al.* (2003) and Woernera *et al.* (2005) both reported
that the initial coma after bilateral paramedian infarct was accompanied
by a similar pattern of EEG activity to stage 2 sleep. Woernera *et al.*
(2005) also discovered that painful stimuli gave rise to a range of EEG
activity, transiently breaking the stage 2 sleep pattern but without
recovery of consciousness. Unfortunately even in those patients who
recover consciousness Kumral *et al.* (2001) report that \"Cognitive
functions in patients with bilateral paramedian infarction did not
change significantly during the follow-up, in contrast to those with
infarcts in varied arterial territories\" although Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) did report a single patient who made a total recovery.
Laureys *et al.* (2002) investigated recovery from \'persistent
vegetative state\' (wakefulness without awareness). They found that
overall cortical metabolism remained almost constant during recovery but
that the metabolism in the prefrontal and association cortices became
correlated with thalamic ILN and precuneus activity. Again confirming
that thalamo-cortico-thalamic activity is required for consciousness and
that cortical activity by itself is not conscious. Yamamoto *et al.*
(2005) investigated persistent vegetative state and found that deep
brain stimulation (25Hz) of the centromedian-parafascicular complex (19
cases) or mesencephalic reticular formation (2 cases) resulted in 8 of
the patients emerging from persistent vegetative state. It is
interesting that zolpidem, a GABA agonist, has recently been found to
reverse PVS in some patients (Claus & Nel 2006). The effect is rapid and
might be used to demonstrate the correlations that occur on recovery
from PVS.
As Bogen(1995) demonstrates, the ILN receive inputs, either directly or
indirectly, from every part of the CNS but what do they do?
Interest in the thalamus has recently been revived by the theories of
Newman & Baars (1993), Baars, Newman, & Taylor1998) and Crick & Koch
(1990). In Baars, Newman and Taylors\' (1998) theory it is suggested
that \"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not
the detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\".
They also propose that the \"nucleus reticularis thalami\" (Thalamic
Reticular Nucleus, TRN), which is a thin sheet of neurons that covers
the thalamus, is involved in a selective attention system. This concept
is reinforced by the way that point stimulation of the TRN causes focal
activity in the overlying cortex (MacDonald *et al.* 1998) and the way
the TRN is organised topographically (i.e.: has activity that is like an
electrical image of receptor fields).
The thalamus is ideally placed for integrating brain activity, if tiny
parts of the thalamus are removed consciousness is abolished and the
thalamus is involved in attention and the global integration of cortical
activity. Any impartial judge might pronounce that the site of conscious
experience has been found, possibly in the ILN of the thalamus, but no
one can say how it works.
## General Anaesthesia and the Thalamus
General anaesthesia should result in a profound depression of activity
in the ILN if these are indeed the sites of the conscious state. White &
Alkire (2003) administered halothane or isoflurane to volunteers and
used positron emission tomography (PET) to monitor brain activity. They
found severe depression of activity in the thalamus. The depression
appeared to be higher in the non-specific nuclei than in the relay
nuclei of the thalamus. In other words the anaesthesia is neither
turning off the cortex nor turning off the input to the cortex but it is
turning off an important part of the thalamus. Fiset *et al.* (1999)
have also demonstrated a similar pattern of medial thalamic inactivity
and cortical activity in propofol anaesthesia. Suppression of cortical
activity is not the cause of unconsciousness; for instance, the
anaesthetic agent chloralose leads to increased neural activity in the
cortex relative to conscious patients (Cariani 2000).
## The function of consciousness
When we walk our conscious experience does not contain data about the
control of the spinal, cerebellar and vestibular reflexes that keep us
on an even keel. When we reach out for a cup our conscious experience
only contains data related to the need for the cup, not data about the
elaborate control system that enables the action. When we talk the words
just come into mind, we do not painstakingly control the syntax and
vocal chords. When our attention shifts the conscious experience
containing the shift happens after the attention has shifted. This
passive nature of experience recurs throughout the neuroscience of
consciousness from the \"readiness potential\" to the \"auditory
continuity illusion\". So what does conscious observation do? The
medical evidence of the lack of consciousness in some forms of delirium,
mutism, PVS etc. suggest that the role of conscious observation is to
stabilise the brain so that it acts as a coordinated whole. Conscious
observation is an orderly arrangement of events, a stable groundform
that reflects the environment and composes the stage for action. It
could be speculated that if quantum events were prominent in brain
function then such a groundform would be essential but even a classical
brain might require a stabilising form that could be continuously
compared with the world beyond the body.
A stable form of neural information that contains bound data from the
senses and internal neural processes is likely to have a role in the
functioning of the organism. There is now an *integration consensus*
that proposes that phenomenal states somehow integrate neural activities
and information-processing that would otherwise be independent (see
review in Baars, 2002).
However, it has remained unspecified which kinds of information are
integrated in a conscious manner and which kinds can be integrated
without consciousness. Obviously not all kinds of information are
capable of being disseminated consciously (e.g., neural activity related
to vegetative functions, reflexes, unconscious motor programs, low-level
perceptual analyses, etc.) and many kinds can be disseminated and
combined with other kinds without consciousness, as in intersensory
interactions such as the ventriloquism effect.
Morsella (2005) proposed a *Supramodular Interaction Theory* (SIT) that
contrasts the task demands of consciously penetrable processes (e.g.:
those that can be part of conscious experience such as pain, conflicting
urges, and the delay of gratification) and consciously impenetrable
processes (e.g.: intersensory conflicts, peristalsis, and the pupillary
reflex). With this contrastive approach, SIT builds upon the integration
consensus by specifying which kinds of interaction require conscious
processing and which kinds do not (e.g., some intersensory processes).
SIT proposes that conscious processes are required to integrate
high-level systems in the brain that are vying for (specifically)
skeletomotor control, as described by the principle of *parallel
responses into skeletal muscle* (PRISM). Accordingly, regarding
processes such as digestion and excretion, one is conscious of only
those phases of the processes that require coordination with
skeletomotor plans (e.g., chewing or micturating) and none of those that
do not (e.g., peristalsis). From this standpoint, consciousness
functions above the level of the traditional module to "cross-talk"
among high-level, specialized and often multi-modal, systems.
**References**
Baars, B. J. (2002). The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent
evidence. *Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6,* 47 -- 52.
Morsella, E. (2005). The function of phenomenal states: Supramodular
interaction theory. *Psychological Review, 112,* 1000 - 1021.
More\... Click here for Rivalries and synchronisation, bibliography
and references
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 1#Perception, Imagination, Memory and Dreams
## The cortex and consciousness
The cerebral cortex consists of a set of specialised areas that process
different aspects of sensation and motor control. There are about ten
times as many nerve fibres going from the cortex to the thalamus as
there are from the thalamus to the cortex (Destexhe 2000).
![](constudconn.gif "constudconn.gif")
Histologically the cerebral cortex is a layer of greyish neurons
overlying a huge mass of white nerve fibres, the cerebral medulla. The
cortex consists of six main layers. The upper layers receive input from
the relays in the thalamus such as the lateral geniculate, from the
thalamus in general and from other areas of cortex plus a few
specialised inputs from other locations. The lower layers give rise to
output fibres that largely connect with the thalamus and other areas of
cortex although particular specialised processors in the cortex may also
have direct connections elsewhere such as to motor nuclei.
![](Constudcortex2.png "Constudcortex2.png")
The cerebral cortex has many functions and is divided up into numerous
separate processors. The most important function of the cortex from the
point of view of consciousness studies is that it creates models. As was
seen in Part I, philosophers debate whether these models are actually
experienced consciously but in the neurophysiological literature it is
normally assumed that we do experience models and rehearsals such as
inner speech and imaginings. There is considerable evidence that the
parts of the brain that deal with imagining (modelling) things are also
the parts that deal with perception (i.e.: modelling the world). The
overlap between imagination and normal perception is not complete
because, as Tong(2003), in a review of visual consciousness, put it:
\"Internally generated experiences share some, but not all, of the
phenomenal properties of actual perception\". There is also considerable
overlap between the areas used for imaginary speech (thought) and actual
speech, areas dealing with the control of sensation and of the tongue
etc. being used in actual speech but not in imagined speech (Fu *et al.*
2002). Kreiman *et al.* (2000) investigated the activity of single
neurons in humans and also found that the brain activity evoked by
visual imagination overlapped that which occurs upon direct stimulation
by the same image.
Our conscious experience consists of the output of the cortical
modelling and perceptual processes. The cerebral cortex itself appears
to be non-conscious. The evidence for the non-conscious nature of the
cerebral cortex consists of lesion studies in which large amounts of
cortex can be removed without removing consciousness and physiological
studies in which it is demonstrated that the cerebral cortex can be
active without conscious experience.
Lesion studies have shown that up to 60% of the cerebral cortex can be
removed without abolishing consciousness (Austin and Grant 1958). An
entire hemisphere can be removed or much of the front or back of the
cerebral cortex can be cut off yet consciousness persists.
Fiset *et al.* (1999) and Cariani (2000) have shown that cortical
activity can be normal or even elevated during the unconscious state of
general anaesthesia. Alkire *et al.* (1996) also showed that cortical
activity related to word recognition occurred during general
anaesthesia.
Libet *et al.* (1967) found that there could be cerebral cortical
activity in response to weak stimulation of the skin without any
conscious awareness of the stimulus. This work provides a
neurophysiological basis for subliminal (non-conscious) perception and
also shows that large areas of the cerebral cortex can be active without
conscious experience. The insensitivity of experience to cortical
activity has been further confirmed by Libet *et al.* (1979). They
electrically stimulated the cerebral cortex of conscious patients and
discovered that the stimulus must be continued for about 0.5 seconds for
subjects to report a conscious experience of the stimulation. Libet\'s
findings have been analysed at length but there still appears to be a
0.25 to 0.5 secs delay (Klein 2002).
It has been demonstrated that cerebral cortical activity is not
synonymous with conscious experience but why should there be a delay of
up to 0.5 seconds or so between cortical stimulation and a conscious
percept? What is the cortex doing in the 0.5 seconds between the start
of stimulation and the report of awareness of the stimulation? It is
probably synchronising its various processors and creating a waking
dream, a structured set of events that accounts for the activity. The
synchronisation of cerebral cortical processes will be discussed later,
but what evidence is there for the cerebral cortex constructing a waking
dream, or model, to describe the world?
The \'Attentional Blink\' (Raymond *et al.* 1992) is consistent with the
concept of the cerebral cortex being a device that creates models. In
the \'Attentional Blink\' the identification of an object impairs the
identification of a second object that is presented within 0.5 seconds
of the first. Raymond *et al.* used a stream of letters (11 letters per
second) and the identification of a first letter impaired the
identification of a subsequent \'probe\' letter in the stream. If the
probe letter followed the first letter within about 180 msecs it could
easily be identified, suggesting that chunks of about 180 msecs of data
stream are modelled together. Christmann & Leuthold (2004) have
theorised that the \'Attentional Blink\' involves perceptual and central
components of visual processing. This is supported by the fMRI studies
of Marois *et al.* (2004) who presented subjects with faces mounted on
scenes of places. The scenes of places often went undetected by subjects
but they activated regions of the medial temporal cortex involved in
high-level scene representations, the parahippocampal place area (PPA).
When the scenes of places were detected by the subjects there was
activity in the frontal cortex and the PPA activity was increased. These
experiments are consistent with the idea of a cerebral cortex that is a
multiprocessor system that creates consistent models of the environment.
Bregman\'s (1990) auditory continuity illusion is another example of how
sensory events are modelled. If a pure tone is followed by broadband
noise and the noise followed by the same pure tone it seems as if the
tone occurs throughout the period of noise. If the noise is not followed
by the pure tone there is no sound of the tone during the period of
noise. This effect is similar to the results found by Libet because a
delay of several hundred milliseconds between sensory stimulation and
conscious experience is needed to account for the apparent rewriting of
history after the second tone appears.
Dennett and Kinsbourne (1992) argued strongly against modelling as the
source of conscious experience. They discussed two illusions, the
\"cutaneous rabbit illusion\", in which the subject is tapped
successively in such a way that some illusory taps appear and the \"phi
illusion\" in which successively illuminated lights appear as a motion
of the light. Dennett and Kinsbourne declared that there should be no
cerebral cortical filling in of the gaps in the these illusions. Both
these illusions have now been investigated. Blankenburg *et al.* (2006)
found that cerebral cortical activity occurred at the locations expected
for the missing taps in the \"cutaneous rabbit\" illusion and Larsen *et
al.* (2006) found that the areas of cerebral cortex that would be
stimulated by a moving light were active during the \"phi illusion\".
## The delay before consciousness of \"voluntary\" actions
The 0.5 second delay required for the cortex to model an event has
implications for the role of conscious experience in the control of our
lives. If experience is about 0.5 seconds behind the true present
instant then how can we be said to control anything? The brain must be
acting automatically whilst performing most tasks. The 0.5 second delay
also seems to contradict our everyday experience. We certainly feel like
we are aware of things in less than 0.5 seconds, for example, the direct
stimulation of sense organs seems to be experienced much more rapidly
than the delayed experience of cortical stimulation. In fact subjects
report that they are conscious of stimuli, such as being touched or
seeing flashing lights, within 0.1 to 0.2 seconds of the event. So how
can subjects report events within 0.2 seconds even though it seems to
take 0.5 seconds for the cortex to generate activity that can be
experienced? The simplest explanation is that the reaction occurs
automatically within 0.2 seconds and then the conscious experience of
this reaction occurs 0.3 seconds later. This gives a total 0.5 seconds
delay before conscious experience whilst allowing fast reactions.
Libet *et al.* extended their experiments by stimulating a \"relay
nucleus\" in the thalamus that intercepts signals from the senses before
they reach the somatosensory cortex. It was found that when this nucleus
was stimulated for 0.5 seconds the subjects reported that the stimulus
occurred 0.2 seconds after it had begun. When the nucleus was stimulated
for less than 0.5 seconds the subjects did not report any sensation.
This supports the concept of a 0.5 second delay whilst the cortex puts a
stimulus in context before it is experienced.
These experiments show that our experience is an output of cortical
processing rather than the processing itself. If our conscious
experience is non-cortical then this raises the possibility that the
non-conscious cerebral cortex can perform actions without conscious
control. Of course, the cortex does this all the time when we are
indulging in skilled or routine behaviour. The ability of the
non-conscious cortex is quite remarkable; for instance car drivers
sometimes discover that they have driven for several miles without
conscious experience of driving, even at the level of having no
recollection of the route.
!Typical recording of the readiness
potential.{width="150"}Although
it might be accepted that much of our everyday behaviour is automatic is
there any behaviour that is definitely initiated by conscious
experience? This is probably a pointless question because consciousness
is about observation, not action; however, despite this there have been
several experiments that have attempted to determine the relationship
between consciousness and action.
In 1964 Kornhuber and Deecke performed a series of experiments that
measured the electrical activity from the scalp (EEG) during voluntary
actions. They averaged many EEG\'s from subjects who were about to move
a finger and discovered that there is an increase in scalp potential
before the movement takes place. The increase in potential can start as
long as 2 seconds or so before the movement and is known as the
\"readiness potential\" (Bereitschaftspotential). The readiness
potential is strange because it seems to contradict our conscious
experience; we do not decide to move a hand and then wait 2 seconds
before the hand moves. It seems that the non-conscious brain may be
taking things into its own hands.
Libet *et al.* (1983) extended the readiness potential experiments by
asking subjects to observe a Wundt clock whilst flexing a finger. The
Wundt clock had a spot of light that moved around a circle every 2.56
seconds and allowed the subjects to obtain timings that were related to
their mental experiences. When the subjects flexed a finger it was found
that the readiness potential occurred about 0.5 seconds before the
finger moved and the subjects reported they were going to move the
finger about 0.2 seconds before the movement. This suggested that a
subject\'s cerebral cortex was preparing for the movement about 0.3
seconds before the subject was conscious of this. Libet\'s experiments
have been reproduced elsewhere (see Keller & Heckhausen 1990). (It is
important to note that the subjects in Libet\'s experiment were asked to
wait until they felt the urge to move the finger.) These results are
consistent with the idea of the cortex as a modelling system that
constructs a consistent model of events to pass on to whatever mediates
conscious experience.
More recently fMRI and direct electrode recording have borne out the
readiness potential experiments. Soon *et al.* (2008) allowed subjects
to decide to press either a left or right button. They used fMRI to show
that there was spatially organised activity in the polar frontal cortex
and parietal cortex (from precuneus into posterior cingulate cortex)
that predicted the conscious left/right decision and preceded it by
about **seven seconds**. Rektor *et al.* (2001) used direct electrode
recordings to show a 2 second latency. Haggard & Eimer (1999) and also
Trevena and Miller (2002, 2009) have identified a \"Lateralized
Readiness Potential\" that is correlated with the movement of a
particular hand (left or right) in their EEG experiments and Trevena and
Miller claim that this potential always follows the making of a
conscious decision and precedes the actions being studied. However, Soon
*et al.* (2008) showed that fMRI can predict which button will be used
well before any conscious decision is reported. (See Haggard (2008) for
a review of conscious volition).
## Perception, Imagination, Memory and Dreams
### More about Models
Our dreams are clearly models that form a \'dreamworld\' but the idea
that perception might be like a dream that is updated by sensation is
not so obvious. Experience seems to be an active model of the world
(virtual reality) based on sense data rather than a simple mapping of
retinal and other sensory data. This is demonstrated by visual illusions
such as the Ames Room, Spoke Illusion and Muller Lyer illusions shown
below:
![](Constudame.png "Constudame.png")
Notice how the circle is distorted without any distortion in the
\'spokes\', it is as if the circle has been treated as a separate object
by the processes in the brain that rearranged it. In all of these
illusions the brain has rearranged large areas of the visual field and
has managed the input as a collection of \'objects\' that are
manipulated separately. Even movement seems to occur in some figures
showing that the brain models the position of things:
![](Constudcafe.png "Constudcafe.png")
The creation of a model is also demonstrated by the illusion of movement
experienced when we watch the cinema or television. This is due to the
cortical modelling that is known as \'short-range apparent motion\'
rather than flicker fusion or persistence of vision. It is intriguing
that, although it has been known for decades that the joining together
of static images in our minds is due to modelling activity in the brain
the myth that it is due to persistence of vision or flicker fusion is
universal. As Anderson and Anderson (1993) noted:
`Indeed, in the past decade, psychoanalytic-Marxist film scholars `\
`have retained the model implied by persistence of vision: theirs `\
`is a passive viewer, a spectator who is "positioned," unwittingly `\
`"sutured" into the text, and victimized by excess ideology.`
Our experience of the cinema is like a dream updated by sensation rather
than sensation updated by interpretation. In fact the most compelling
evidence for the modelling power of the brain is the existence of
dreams; our dreams are often models of worlds that do not exist and
involve little or no sensory input yet can involve effects as powerful
as any television drama.
Short range apparent motion occurs when the interval between
presentations of an object is brief (c. 50-100 msecs). Motion modelling
in response to longer intervals is known as long range apparent motion.
There is evidence that the modelling in short range apparent motion is
enhanced if the moving patterns are similar to moving human forms (such
as patterns of dots outlining a person)(Thornton *et al.* 1998). The
accuracy of predicting movement can actually improve if the interval
between presentations is increased when human forms are used.
Motion modelling can also be seen in visual illusions such as the
*Waterfall Illusion* (motion aftereffect). The waterfall illusion is
commonly seen after viewing a sequence of scrolling credits on the
television; when the credits stop rolling it appears as if they briefly
move in the opposite direction. Tootel *et al.* (1995) have used fMRI to
show that this is correlated with activity in the motion modelling area
of visual cortex (area MT/V5). The waterfall illusion is also associated
with an intriguing aftereffect known as **storage of the motion
aftereffect**. Normal motion aftereffects last for up to about ten
seconds after the stimulus, however, if the subjects close their eyes
for the normal duration of the aftereffect then reopen them they see the
illusion for almost the normal duration. Culham *et al.* (1999) used
fMRI to show that activity in area MT/V5 was low during the period when
the eyes were closed then increased dramatically when the eyes were
opened. This is strongly suggestive of a modelling mechanism outside
MT/V5 that has adapted to motion and then models stationary data with
movement in the wrong direction.
Visual area MT/V5 is also involved in the separation of moving visual
scenes into *sprites* or objects that move together as a whole within a
scene (Muckli *et al.* 2002).
The way that mental models may be the basis of ordinary reasoning was
outlined by Johnson-Laird (1980), based on earlier work by Kenneth
Craik.
Studies of \'change blindness\' and \'inattentional blindness\', where
subjects fail to spot outrageous changes in their environment, also
demonstrate that we experience a model and suggest that the brain must
analyse an object to incorporate it fully into the model (See for
instance Rensink (2000), Simons & Rensink (2005)).
### Brain areas used in perception overlap those used in imagination and recall
Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI) has shown that similar
areas of brain are used during perception involving the senses as during
imagination (Tong 2003, Kosslyn and Thompson 2003). The substrate of the
mental images that occur in both modes of brain activity has not yet
been found. This overlap of the brain areas used in perception with
those used in imagination, memory and recall has been demonstrated in a
wide range of experiments.
Ganis *et al.* (2004) used fairly complex perceptual and imagination
tasks that activated large areas of the brain, they found an overlap
between the brain areas activated during perception and imagery. The
principle areas that were different in the two tasks were found in the
primary sensory areas of the visual cortex. Other areas in the visual
cortex and activity in the rest of the brain showed a remarkable degree
of overlap. The authors suggested that the differences in the activity
of primary visual cortex may have been due to differences between the
perceptual and imaginary stimuli such as speed of onset etc. The
hippocampus was not activated.
It is intriguing that, contrary to object imagery, spatial imagery such
as predicting when a cross on a screen would fall on an imaginary letter
actually seems to inhibit activity in sensory visual cortex (Aleman *et
al.*). Both fMRI and blocking with transcranial magnetic stimulation
(TMS) showed that the posterior parietal cortex was involved in the
spatial imagery.
Imagery involving places and faces activates the place and face areas
that are activated during perception (Ishai *et al.* 2000).
The recall and recognition of things also seems to involve very similar
brain areas to those used during perception. Wheeler and Buckner (2003)
showed that areas involved in perception were also involved in the
recall of the perceptual stimuli.
Recall causes activation of areas used in perception but also seems to
use areas that may be particularly related to the process of recall
iself, such as the left parietal cortex (Konishi *et al.* 2000)
(Brodmann\'s area 40/39). Frontal and parietal regions are involved in
the recognition of whether stimuli have been experienced before.
Image generation during sleep seems to differ from that during
imagination and recall. In particular it seems to involve a few well
defined areas of cortex and considerable activation of the posterior
thalamus.
Sleep studies have shown that people dream throughout sleep. However,
dreams are more frequent during the REM (rapid eye movement) periods of
sleep than the NREM (non-REM) periods. Dreams are reported after 70-95%
of awakenings in REM sleep and 5-10% of awakenings in NREM sleep. REM
dreams are more visual than NREM dreams which are more \'thoughtlike\'
(Solms 2000). Thoughtlike events (mentation) are reported after 43% of
awakenings from NREM sleep.
Solms (1997) found that patients who had lesions in the
parietal-temporo-occipital junction reported a cessation of visual
images in dreams. Solms also found that patients with lesions in the
white matter inferior to the frontal horns of the lateral ventricles, in
the ventromesial quadrant of the frontal lobes, also reported loss of
dreaming. Loss of dreaming is also reported by leucotomised patients
with frontal ventromesial damage. Damasio *et al.* (1985) and Solms
(1997) also reported that some patients with damage to the medial
prefrontal cortex, the anterior cingulate cortex, and the basal
forebrain became confused about what was real life and what was dreaming
(waking dreams occurred).
Studies using fMRI show that the sensory occipital lobe (BA 18) and
posterior thalamus, especially the lateral geniculate nuclei, are
activated in REM sleep, weaker activations of the posterior cingulate,
putamen and midbrain were also found (Wehrle *et al.* 2005, Loveblad *et
al.* 1999). These findings are consistent with activation of the
ponto-geniculo-occipital system (PGO) during REM.
So dreams may be more like primary activations of sensory cortex than
imagining or recall. This suggests that dreams have a thalamic origin or
are managed via connections from the cortex through the thalamus to the
visual cortex.
Hallucinations seem to differ from dreams. In Charles Bonnett Syndrome
patients can have clear hallucinations. These, like imaginations, seem
to involve areas of the visual cortex that deal with processed data, for
instance hallucinations of faces activate the \"face area\" rather than
visual cortical area V1 (Ffytche *et al.* 1998).
### Suppression of data acquisition during saccades - perception as a patchwork
If you look at yourself in the mirror you will not see your eyes moving
even though they will be darting all over the view of your face. Even
when you deliberately look from place to place your eyes will appear
steady. The natural darting of the eyes from place to place as you view
a scene is known as \"saccadic\" movement of the eyes. The suppression
of the visual image during the motion of the eyes is known as \"saccadic
suppression\" or \"saccadic masking\". The suppression of the
acquisition of image data extends to suppression of awareness of flashes
of light during saccades, this effect is known as \"flash suppression\",
however, flash suppression seems to apply only to rather dull flashes
(Volkman (1962). The suppression during saccades is probably due to
suppression of the magnocellular pathway (the motion sensitive pathway)
in the lateral geniculate nucleus (Burr *et al.* (1996).
The most intriguing feature of this suppression of data acquisition
during saccades is that each snapshot that is obtained between saccades
can only contain a relatively small amount of information. This is
because the fovea, which is the most sensitive area of the eye, is tiny
(about 1mm diameter) and only receives input from a few degrees of the
visual field. As a result what we consider to be a uniform scene in our
minds is actually a patchwork of intersaccade snapshots.
Another aspect of saccades is that the timing of events is referred back
to the beginning of the saccade. This effect is known as \"saccadic
chronostasis\". For example, if an object changes colour during a
saccade the observer feels as if the colour change occurred at the
beginning of the saccade, so extending the amount of time that the
object possesses the changed colour. This effect can extend apparent
durations by up to 500 ms and is consistent with the idea that the
visual system models events prior to perception (see Yarrow *et al.*
2006).
Burr D, Morrone M, Ross J. (1996) Selective suppression of the
magnocellular visual pathway during saccades\]\'\', Behavioral Brain
Research 80 1-8 (1996)
<http://www.pisavisionlab.org/downloads/BBRReview96.pdf>
Volkman, F. (1962). Vision during voluntary saccadic eye movements. J.
Opt Soc. Am. 52:571-578. 1962.
Yarrow, K, Whiteley, L, Rothwell, J.C & Haggard,P. (2006) Spatial
consequences of bridging the saccadic gap. Vision Res. 2006 February;
46(4): 545--555.
<http://www.hexicon.co.uk/Kielan/papers/Moving_chrono.pdf>
## Blindsight
Blindsight studies illuminate the relationship between the cerebral
cortex and our experience. When the visual cortex is removed subjects
become almost totally blind. If the visual cortex on one side is removed
subjects become relatively blind in the contra-lateral hemifield. One of
the most revealing studies of blindsight is Marcel\'s 1998 paper: \"
Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of visual consciousness or
visual function?\".
It is useful when considering blindsight to contemplate for a while the
appearance of the world with both eyes closed and then with one eye
closed. When both eyes are closed our experience is of a darkish space
radiating out from our heads, with one eye closed we tend to ignore the
darkish areas that cannot be seen even though they are still present.
Marcel notes that patients who have a right blind field still have an
underlying visual field on the right side and that this can even contain
conscious visual experience. This sounds a bit like the darkish space
that we all experience if deprived of visual input on one side. As
Marcel says: \"A question that naturally arises is whether the loss is a
\'total\' loss of visual consciousness in the blind field. It is often
assumed to be so, especially by those who discuss blindsight without
carefully reading the literature or working with the subjects. One can
immediately respond negatively to the question..\"
The consciousness of the completion of Kanizsa figures in blindsight
patients is particularly indicative of the preservation of the field
even though the content was largely missing. A Kanizsa figure is shown
below:
![](Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg "Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg")
If we put Marcel\'s observations together with cortical anatomy and
function it seems that the space of our experience is located outside of
the cerebral cortex. The cortex generates much of visual and other
content but it does not generate the space.
## The Role of the Thalamus
The thalamus is connected to the entire bottom layer of the cerebral
cortex. It is the nexus of the various cortical processors as well as a
recipient of independent input from most of the rest of the brain.
![](Constudbrain.png "Constudbrain.png")
The thalamus is subdivided into numerous small and medium sized nuclei
that between them receive inputs from every process in the nervous
system (the white fibres in the illustration above largely penetrate the
thalamus). The thalamic nuclei are interconnected which means that any
of them could, potentially host activity from anywhere in the body or
brain. Although the founders of neurology such as Hughlings Jackson and
Penfield & Jasper located conscious experience in the diencephalon,
including the thalamus, this is no longer the conventional wisdom. The
small size of the thalamic nuclei means that they cannot support the
processes that are assumed to compose access consciousness, however,
even some of the smallest thalamic nuclei host millions of synapses so
size would not be an obstacle if the thalamus contains the substrate of
phenomenal consciousness. Indeed, the diencephalon and the thalamus in
particular can be shown to be excellent candidates for a possible
location of phenomenal experience.
![](constudintralam.jpg "constudintralam.jpg")
`<font size=1>`{=html} The Intralaminar Nuclei of the thalamus. The
white space above and to the left of RN is the third ventricle.
MD=mediodorsal nucleus. CM=Centromedian nucleus, RN=red nucleus (not
part of thalamus) The black areas are stained white fibres. Picture
from: <http://www.neurophys.wisc.edu/> University of Wisconsin and
Michigan State Comparative Mammalian Brain Collections. Preparation of
image has been funded by the National Science Foundation, as well as by
the National Institutes of Health. May only be used with these
acknowledgements.`</font>`{=html}
If the thalamus contains a location for conscious experience then
lesions should abolish this experience. Unlike the cerebral hemispheres,
lesions of the thalamus do indeed seem to abolish consciousness. The
area that is most sensitive to lesions contains the Intralaminar Nuclei,
especially the Parafascicular and Centromedian Nuclei. If these are
damaged bilaterally patients suffer death, coma, akinetic mutism,
hypersomnia, dementia and other equally serious impairments of
consciousness that depend upon the size and placement of the lesions
(Bogen 1995, Schiff & Plum 1999). In cases of fatal familial insomnia,
in which patients exhibit many of these symptoms, there is marked neuron
loss in the Intralaminar Nuclei (Budka 1998).
The effect of interrupting the blood supply to the medial thalamus
depends upon the severity of the damage. There is frequently initial
coma. The recovery after coma is often incomplete, Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) described bilateral paramedian thalamic infarcts as normally
being \"followed by persisting dementia with severe mnemic disturbance,
global aspontaneity and apathy.\" The symptoms of bilateral damage to
the ILN can be so severe that it is possible that, even after recovery
from coma, some patients may cease to be conscious and are being
coordinated by automatic cortical processes.
Bjornstad *et al.* (2003) and Woernera *et al.* (2005) both reported
that the initial coma after bilateral paramedian infarct was accompanied
by a similar pattern of EEG activity to stage 2 sleep. Woernera *et al.*
(2005) also discovered that painful stimuli gave rise to a range of EEG
activity, transiently breaking the stage 2 sleep pattern but without
recovery of consciousness. Unfortunately even in those patients who
recover consciousness Kumral *et al.* (2001) report that \"Cognitive
functions in patients with bilateral paramedian infarction did not
change significantly during the follow-up, in contrast to those with
infarcts in varied arterial territories\" although Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) did report a single patient who made a total recovery.
Laureys *et al.* (2002) investigated recovery from \'persistent
vegetative state\' (wakefulness without awareness). They found that
overall cortical metabolism remained almost constant during recovery but
that the metabolism in the prefrontal and association cortices became
correlated with thalamic ILN and precuneus activity. Again confirming
that thalamo-cortico-thalamic activity is required for consciousness and
that cortical activity by itself is not conscious. Yamamoto *et al.*
(2005) investigated persistent vegetative state and found that deep
brain stimulation (25Hz) of the centromedian-parafascicular complex (19
cases) or mesencephalic reticular formation (2 cases) resulted in 8 of
the patients emerging from persistent vegetative state. It is
interesting that zolpidem, a GABA agonist, has recently been found to
reverse PVS in some patients (Claus & Nel 2006). The effect is rapid and
might be used to demonstrate the correlations that occur on recovery
from PVS.
As Bogen(1995) demonstrates, the ILN receive inputs, either directly or
indirectly, from every part of the CNS but what do they do?
Interest in the thalamus has recently been revived by the theories of
Newman & Baars (1993), Baars, Newman, & Taylor1998) and Crick & Koch
(1990). In Baars, Newman and Taylors\' (1998) theory it is suggested
that \"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not
the detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\".
They also propose that the \"nucleus reticularis thalami\" (Thalamic
Reticular Nucleus, TRN), which is a thin sheet of neurons that covers
the thalamus, is involved in a selective attention system. This concept
is reinforced by the way that point stimulation of the TRN causes focal
activity in the overlying cortex (MacDonald *et al.* 1998) and the way
the TRN is organised topographically (i.e.: has activity that is like an
electrical image of receptor fields).
The thalamus is ideally placed for integrating brain activity, if tiny
parts of the thalamus are removed consciousness is abolished and the
thalamus is involved in attention and the global integration of cortical
activity. Any impartial judge might pronounce that the site of conscious
experience has been found, possibly in the ILN of the thalamus, but no
one can say how it works.
## General Anaesthesia and the Thalamus
General anaesthesia should result in a profound depression of activity
in the ILN if these are indeed the sites of the conscious state. White &
Alkire (2003) administered halothane or isoflurane to volunteers and
used positron emission tomography (PET) to monitor brain activity. They
found severe depression of activity in the thalamus. The depression
appeared to be higher in the non-specific nuclei than in the relay
nuclei of the thalamus. In other words the anaesthesia is neither
turning off the cortex nor turning off the input to the cortex but it is
turning off an important part of the thalamus. Fiset *et al.* (1999)
have also demonstrated a similar pattern of medial thalamic inactivity
and cortical activity in propofol anaesthesia. Suppression of cortical
activity is not the cause of unconsciousness; for instance, the
anaesthetic agent chloralose leads to increased neural activity in the
cortex relative to conscious patients (Cariani 2000).
## The function of consciousness
When we walk our conscious experience does not contain data about the
control of the spinal, cerebellar and vestibular reflexes that keep us
on an even keel. When we reach out for a cup our conscious experience
only contains data related to the need for the cup, not data about the
elaborate control system that enables the action. When we talk the words
just come into mind, we do not painstakingly control the syntax and
vocal chords. When our attention shifts the conscious experience
containing the shift happens after the attention has shifted. This
passive nature of experience recurs throughout the neuroscience of
consciousness from the \"readiness potential\" to the \"auditory
continuity illusion\". So what does conscious observation do? The
medical evidence of the lack of consciousness in some forms of delirium,
mutism, PVS etc. suggest that the role of conscious observation is to
stabilise the brain so that it acts as a coordinated whole. Conscious
observation is an orderly arrangement of events, a stable groundform
that reflects the environment and composes the stage for action. It
could be speculated that if quantum events were prominent in brain
function then such a groundform would be essential but even a classical
brain might require a stabilising form that could be continuously
compared with the world beyond the body.
A stable form of neural information that contains bound data from the
senses and internal neural processes is likely to have a role in the
functioning of the organism. There is now an *integration consensus*
that proposes that phenomenal states somehow integrate neural activities
and information-processing that would otherwise be independent (see
review in Baars, 2002).
However, it has remained unspecified which kinds of information are
integrated in a conscious manner and which kinds can be integrated
without consciousness. Obviously not all kinds of information are
capable of being disseminated consciously (e.g., neural activity related
to vegetative functions, reflexes, unconscious motor programs, low-level
perceptual analyses, etc.) and many kinds can be disseminated and
combined with other kinds without consciousness, as in intersensory
interactions such as the ventriloquism effect.
Morsella (2005) proposed a *Supramodular Interaction Theory* (SIT) that
contrasts the task demands of consciously penetrable processes (e.g.:
those that can be part of conscious experience such as pain, conflicting
urges, and the delay of gratification) and consciously impenetrable
processes (e.g.: intersensory conflicts, peristalsis, and the pupillary
reflex). With this contrastive approach, SIT builds upon the integration
consensus by specifying which kinds of interaction require conscious
processing and which kinds do not (e.g., some intersensory processes).
SIT proposes that conscious processes are required to integrate
high-level systems in the brain that are vying for (specifically)
skeletomotor control, as described by the principle of *parallel
responses into skeletal muscle* (PRISM). Accordingly, regarding
processes such as digestion and excretion, one is conscious of only
those phases of the processes that require coordination with
skeletomotor plans (e.g., chewing or micturating) and none of those that
do not (e.g., peristalsis). From this standpoint, consciousness
functions above the level of the traditional module to "cross-talk"
among high-level, specialized and often multi-modal, systems.
**References**
Baars, B. J. (2002). The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent
evidence. *Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6,* 47 -- 52.
Morsella, E. (2005). The function of phenomenal states: Supramodular
interaction theory. *Psychological Review, 112,* 1000 - 1021.
More\... Click here for Rivalries and synchronisation, bibliography
and references
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 1#More about Models
## The cortex and consciousness
The cerebral cortex consists of a set of specialised areas that process
different aspects of sensation and motor control. There are about ten
times as many nerve fibres going from the cortex to the thalamus as
there are from the thalamus to the cortex (Destexhe 2000).
![](constudconn.gif "constudconn.gif")
Histologically the cerebral cortex is a layer of greyish neurons
overlying a huge mass of white nerve fibres, the cerebral medulla. The
cortex consists of six main layers. The upper layers receive input from
the relays in the thalamus such as the lateral geniculate, from the
thalamus in general and from other areas of cortex plus a few
specialised inputs from other locations. The lower layers give rise to
output fibres that largely connect with the thalamus and other areas of
cortex although particular specialised processors in the cortex may also
have direct connections elsewhere such as to motor nuclei.
![](Constudcortex2.png "Constudcortex2.png")
The cerebral cortex has many functions and is divided up into numerous
separate processors. The most important function of the cortex from the
point of view of consciousness studies is that it creates models. As was
seen in Part I, philosophers debate whether these models are actually
experienced consciously but in the neurophysiological literature it is
normally assumed that we do experience models and rehearsals such as
inner speech and imaginings. There is considerable evidence that the
parts of the brain that deal with imagining (modelling) things are also
the parts that deal with perception (i.e.: modelling the world). The
overlap between imagination and normal perception is not complete
because, as Tong(2003), in a review of visual consciousness, put it:
\"Internally generated experiences share some, but not all, of the
phenomenal properties of actual perception\". There is also considerable
overlap between the areas used for imaginary speech (thought) and actual
speech, areas dealing with the control of sensation and of the tongue
etc. being used in actual speech but not in imagined speech (Fu *et al.*
2002). Kreiman *et al.* (2000) investigated the activity of single
neurons in humans and also found that the brain activity evoked by
visual imagination overlapped that which occurs upon direct stimulation
by the same image.
Our conscious experience consists of the output of the cortical
modelling and perceptual processes. The cerebral cortex itself appears
to be non-conscious. The evidence for the non-conscious nature of the
cerebral cortex consists of lesion studies in which large amounts of
cortex can be removed without removing consciousness and physiological
studies in which it is demonstrated that the cerebral cortex can be
active without conscious experience.
Lesion studies have shown that up to 60% of the cerebral cortex can be
removed without abolishing consciousness (Austin and Grant 1958). An
entire hemisphere can be removed or much of the front or back of the
cerebral cortex can be cut off yet consciousness persists.
Fiset *et al.* (1999) and Cariani (2000) have shown that cortical
activity can be normal or even elevated during the unconscious state of
general anaesthesia. Alkire *et al.* (1996) also showed that cortical
activity related to word recognition occurred during general
anaesthesia.
Libet *et al.* (1967) found that there could be cerebral cortical
activity in response to weak stimulation of the skin without any
conscious awareness of the stimulus. This work provides a
neurophysiological basis for subliminal (non-conscious) perception and
also shows that large areas of the cerebral cortex can be active without
conscious experience. The insensitivity of experience to cortical
activity has been further confirmed by Libet *et al.* (1979). They
electrically stimulated the cerebral cortex of conscious patients and
discovered that the stimulus must be continued for about 0.5 seconds for
subjects to report a conscious experience of the stimulation. Libet\'s
findings have been analysed at length but there still appears to be a
0.25 to 0.5 secs delay (Klein 2002).
It has been demonstrated that cerebral cortical activity is not
synonymous with conscious experience but why should there be a delay of
up to 0.5 seconds or so between cortical stimulation and a conscious
percept? What is the cortex doing in the 0.5 seconds between the start
of stimulation and the report of awareness of the stimulation? It is
probably synchronising its various processors and creating a waking
dream, a structured set of events that accounts for the activity. The
synchronisation of cerebral cortical processes will be discussed later,
but what evidence is there for the cerebral cortex constructing a waking
dream, or model, to describe the world?
The \'Attentional Blink\' (Raymond *et al.* 1992) is consistent with the
concept of the cerebral cortex being a device that creates models. In
the \'Attentional Blink\' the identification of an object impairs the
identification of a second object that is presented within 0.5 seconds
of the first. Raymond *et al.* used a stream of letters (11 letters per
second) and the identification of a first letter impaired the
identification of a subsequent \'probe\' letter in the stream. If the
probe letter followed the first letter within about 180 msecs it could
easily be identified, suggesting that chunks of about 180 msecs of data
stream are modelled together. Christmann & Leuthold (2004) have
theorised that the \'Attentional Blink\' involves perceptual and central
components of visual processing. This is supported by the fMRI studies
of Marois *et al.* (2004) who presented subjects with faces mounted on
scenes of places. The scenes of places often went undetected by subjects
but they activated regions of the medial temporal cortex involved in
high-level scene representations, the parahippocampal place area (PPA).
When the scenes of places were detected by the subjects there was
activity in the frontal cortex and the PPA activity was increased. These
experiments are consistent with the idea of a cerebral cortex that is a
multiprocessor system that creates consistent models of the environment.
Bregman\'s (1990) auditory continuity illusion is another example of how
sensory events are modelled. If a pure tone is followed by broadband
noise and the noise followed by the same pure tone it seems as if the
tone occurs throughout the period of noise. If the noise is not followed
by the pure tone there is no sound of the tone during the period of
noise. This effect is similar to the results found by Libet because a
delay of several hundred milliseconds between sensory stimulation and
conscious experience is needed to account for the apparent rewriting of
history after the second tone appears.
Dennett and Kinsbourne (1992) argued strongly against modelling as the
source of conscious experience. They discussed two illusions, the
\"cutaneous rabbit illusion\", in which the subject is tapped
successively in such a way that some illusory taps appear and the \"phi
illusion\" in which successively illuminated lights appear as a motion
of the light. Dennett and Kinsbourne declared that there should be no
cerebral cortical filling in of the gaps in the these illusions. Both
these illusions have now been investigated. Blankenburg *et al.* (2006)
found that cerebral cortical activity occurred at the locations expected
for the missing taps in the \"cutaneous rabbit\" illusion and Larsen *et
al.* (2006) found that the areas of cerebral cortex that would be
stimulated by a moving light were active during the \"phi illusion\".
## The delay before consciousness of \"voluntary\" actions
The 0.5 second delay required for the cortex to model an event has
implications for the role of conscious experience in the control of our
lives. If experience is about 0.5 seconds behind the true present
instant then how can we be said to control anything? The brain must be
acting automatically whilst performing most tasks. The 0.5 second delay
also seems to contradict our everyday experience. We certainly feel like
we are aware of things in less than 0.5 seconds, for example, the direct
stimulation of sense organs seems to be experienced much more rapidly
than the delayed experience of cortical stimulation. In fact subjects
report that they are conscious of stimuli, such as being touched or
seeing flashing lights, within 0.1 to 0.2 seconds of the event. So how
can subjects report events within 0.2 seconds even though it seems to
take 0.5 seconds for the cortex to generate activity that can be
experienced? The simplest explanation is that the reaction occurs
automatically within 0.2 seconds and then the conscious experience of
this reaction occurs 0.3 seconds later. This gives a total 0.5 seconds
delay before conscious experience whilst allowing fast reactions.
Libet *et al.* extended their experiments by stimulating a \"relay
nucleus\" in the thalamus that intercepts signals from the senses before
they reach the somatosensory cortex. It was found that when this nucleus
was stimulated for 0.5 seconds the subjects reported that the stimulus
occurred 0.2 seconds after it had begun. When the nucleus was stimulated
for less than 0.5 seconds the subjects did not report any sensation.
This supports the concept of a 0.5 second delay whilst the cortex puts a
stimulus in context before it is experienced.
These experiments show that our experience is an output of cortical
processing rather than the processing itself. If our conscious
experience is non-cortical then this raises the possibility that the
non-conscious cerebral cortex can perform actions without conscious
control. Of course, the cortex does this all the time when we are
indulging in skilled or routine behaviour. The ability of the
non-conscious cortex is quite remarkable; for instance car drivers
sometimes discover that they have driven for several miles without
conscious experience of driving, even at the level of having no
recollection of the route.
!Typical recording of the readiness
potential.{width="150"}Although
it might be accepted that much of our everyday behaviour is automatic is
there any behaviour that is definitely initiated by conscious
experience? This is probably a pointless question because consciousness
is about observation, not action; however, despite this there have been
several experiments that have attempted to determine the relationship
between consciousness and action.
In 1964 Kornhuber and Deecke performed a series of experiments that
measured the electrical activity from the scalp (EEG) during voluntary
actions. They averaged many EEG\'s from subjects who were about to move
a finger and discovered that there is an increase in scalp potential
before the movement takes place. The increase in potential can start as
long as 2 seconds or so before the movement and is known as the
\"readiness potential\" (Bereitschaftspotential). The readiness
potential is strange because it seems to contradict our conscious
experience; we do not decide to move a hand and then wait 2 seconds
before the hand moves. It seems that the non-conscious brain may be
taking things into its own hands.
Libet *et al.* (1983) extended the readiness potential experiments by
asking subjects to observe a Wundt clock whilst flexing a finger. The
Wundt clock had a spot of light that moved around a circle every 2.56
seconds and allowed the subjects to obtain timings that were related to
their mental experiences. When the subjects flexed a finger it was found
that the readiness potential occurred about 0.5 seconds before the
finger moved and the subjects reported they were going to move the
finger about 0.2 seconds before the movement. This suggested that a
subject\'s cerebral cortex was preparing for the movement about 0.3
seconds before the subject was conscious of this. Libet\'s experiments
have been reproduced elsewhere (see Keller & Heckhausen 1990). (It is
important to note that the subjects in Libet\'s experiment were asked to
wait until they felt the urge to move the finger.) These results are
consistent with the idea of the cortex as a modelling system that
constructs a consistent model of events to pass on to whatever mediates
conscious experience.
More recently fMRI and direct electrode recording have borne out the
readiness potential experiments. Soon *et al.* (2008) allowed subjects
to decide to press either a left or right button. They used fMRI to show
that there was spatially organised activity in the polar frontal cortex
and parietal cortex (from precuneus into posterior cingulate cortex)
that predicted the conscious left/right decision and preceded it by
about **seven seconds**. Rektor *et al.* (2001) used direct electrode
recordings to show a 2 second latency. Haggard & Eimer (1999) and also
Trevena and Miller (2002, 2009) have identified a \"Lateralized
Readiness Potential\" that is correlated with the movement of a
particular hand (left or right) in their EEG experiments and Trevena and
Miller claim that this potential always follows the making of a
conscious decision and precedes the actions being studied. However, Soon
*et al.* (2008) showed that fMRI can predict which button will be used
well before any conscious decision is reported. (See Haggard (2008) for
a review of conscious volition).
## Perception, Imagination, Memory and Dreams
### More about Models
Our dreams are clearly models that form a \'dreamworld\' but the idea
that perception might be like a dream that is updated by sensation is
not so obvious. Experience seems to be an active model of the world
(virtual reality) based on sense data rather than a simple mapping of
retinal and other sensory data. This is demonstrated by visual illusions
such as the Ames Room, Spoke Illusion and Muller Lyer illusions shown
below:
![](Constudame.png "Constudame.png")
Notice how the circle is distorted without any distortion in the
\'spokes\', it is as if the circle has been treated as a separate object
by the processes in the brain that rearranged it. In all of these
illusions the brain has rearranged large areas of the visual field and
has managed the input as a collection of \'objects\' that are
manipulated separately. Even movement seems to occur in some figures
showing that the brain models the position of things:
![](Constudcafe.png "Constudcafe.png")
The creation of a model is also demonstrated by the illusion of movement
experienced when we watch the cinema or television. This is due to the
cortical modelling that is known as \'short-range apparent motion\'
rather than flicker fusion or persistence of vision. It is intriguing
that, although it has been known for decades that the joining together
of static images in our minds is due to modelling activity in the brain
the myth that it is due to persistence of vision or flicker fusion is
universal. As Anderson and Anderson (1993) noted:
`Indeed, in the past decade, psychoanalytic-Marxist film scholars `\
`have retained the model implied by persistence of vision: theirs `\
`is a passive viewer, a spectator who is "positioned," unwittingly `\
`"sutured" into the text, and victimized by excess ideology.`
Our experience of the cinema is like a dream updated by sensation rather
than sensation updated by interpretation. In fact the most compelling
evidence for the modelling power of the brain is the existence of
dreams; our dreams are often models of worlds that do not exist and
involve little or no sensory input yet can involve effects as powerful
as any television drama.
Short range apparent motion occurs when the interval between
presentations of an object is brief (c. 50-100 msecs). Motion modelling
in response to longer intervals is known as long range apparent motion.
There is evidence that the modelling in short range apparent motion is
enhanced if the moving patterns are similar to moving human forms (such
as patterns of dots outlining a person)(Thornton *et al.* 1998). The
accuracy of predicting movement can actually improve if the interval
between presentations is increased when human forms are used.
Motion modelling can also be seen in visual illusions such as the
*Waterfall Illusion* (motion aftereffect). The waterfall illusion is
commonly seen after viewing a sequence of scrolling credits on the
television; when the credits stop rolling it appears as if they briefly
move in the opposite direction. Tootel *et al.* (1995) have used fMRI to
show that this is correlated with activity in the motion modelling area
of visual cortex (area MT/V5). The waterfall illusion is also associated
with an intriguing aftereffect known as **storage of the motion
aftereffect**. Normal motion aftereffects last for up to about ten
seconds after the stimulus, however, if the subjects close their eyes
for the normal duration of the aftereffect then reopen them they see the
illusion for almost the normal duration. Culham *et al.* (1999) used
fMRI to show that activity in area MT/V5 was low during the period when
the eyes were closed then increased dramatically when the eyes were
opened. This is strongly suggestive of a modelling mechanism outside
MT/V5 that has adapted to motion and then models stationary data with
movement in the wrong direction.
Visual area MT/V5 is also involved in the separation of moving visual
scenes into *sprites* or objects that move together as a whole within a
scene (Muckli *et al.* 2002).
The way that mental models may be the basis of ordinary reasoning was
outlined by Johnson-Laird (1980), based on earlier work by Kenneth
Craik.
Studies of \'change blindness\' and \'inattentional blindness\', where
subjects fail to spot outrageous changes in their environment, also
demonstrate that we experience a model and suggest that the brain must
analyse an object to incorporate it fully into the model (See for
instance Rensink (2000), Simons & Rensink (2005)).
### Brain areas used in perception overlap those used in imagination and recall
Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI) has shown that similar
areas of brain are used during perception involving the senses as during
imagination (Tong 2003, Kosslyn and Thompson 2003). The substrate of the
mental images that occur in both modes of brain activity has not yet
been found. This overlap of the brain areas used in perception with
those used in imagination, memory and recall has been demonstrated in a
wide range of experiments.
Ganis *et al.* (2004) used fairly complex perceptual and imagination
tasks that activated large areas of the brain, they found an overlap
between the brain areas activated during perception and imagery. The
principle areas that were different in the two tasks were found in the
primary sensory areas of the visual cortex. Other areas in the visual
cortex and activity in the rest of the brain showed a remarkable degree
of overlap. The authors suggested that the differences in the activity
of primary visual cortex may have been due to differences between the
perceptual and imaginary stimuli such as speed of onset etc. The
hippocampus was not activated.
It is intriguing that, contrary to object imagery, spatial imagery such
as predicting when a cross on a screen would fall on an imaginary letter
actually seems to inhibit activity in sensory visual cortex (Aleman *et
al.*). Both fMRI and blocking with transcranial magnetic stimulation
(TMS) showed that the posterior parietal cortex was involved in the
spatial imagery.
Imagery involving places and faces activates the place and face areas
that are activated during perception (Ishai *et al.* 2000).
The recall and recognition of things also seems to involve very similar
brain areas to those used during perception. Wheeler and Buckner (2003)
showed that areas involved in perception were also involved in the
recall of the perceptual stimuli.
Recall causes activation of areas used in perception but also seems to
use areas that may be particularly related to the process of recall
iself, such as the left parietal cortex (Konishi *et al.* 2000)
(Brodmann\'s area 40/39). Frontal and parietal regions are involved in
the recognition of whether stimuli have been experienced before.
Image generation during sleep seems to differ from that during
imagination and recall. In particular it seems to involve a few well
defined areas of cortex and considerable activation of the posterior
thalamus.
Sleep studies have shown that people dream throughout sleep. However,
dreams are more frequent during the REM (rapid eye movement) periods of
sleep than the NREM (non-REM) periods. Dreams are reported after 70-95%
of awakenings in REM sleep and 5-10% of awakenings in NREM sleep. REM
dreams are more visual than NREM dreams which are more \'thoughtlike\'
(Solms 2000). Thoughtlike events (mentation) are reported after 43% of
awakenings from NREM sleep.
Solms (1997) found that patients who had lesions in the
parietal-temporo-occipital junction reported a cessation of visual
images in dreams. Solms also found that patients with lesions in the
white matter inferior to the frontal horns of the lateral ventricles, in
the ventromesial quadrant of the frontal lobes, also reported loss of
dreaming. Loss of dreaming is also reported by leucotomised patients
with frontal ventromesial damage. Damasio *et al.* (1985) and Solms
(1997) also reported that some patients with damage to the medial
prefrontal cortex, the anterior cingulate cortex, and the basal
forebrain became confused about what was real life and what was dreaming
(waking dreams occurred).
Studies using fMRI show that the sensory occipital lobe (BA 18) and
posterior thalamus, especially the lateral geniculate nuclei, are
activated in REM sleep, weaker activations of the posterior cingulate,
putamen and midbrain were also found (Wehrle *et al.* 2005, Loveblad *et
al.* 1999). These findings are consistent with activation of the
ponto-geniculo-occipital system (PGO) during REM.
So dreams may be more like primary activations of sensory cortex than
imagining or recall. This suggests that dreams have a thalamic origin or
are managed via connections from the cortex through the thalamus to the
visual cortex.
Hallucinations seem to differ from dreams. In Charles Bonnett Syndrome
patients can have clear hallucinations. These, like imaginations, seem
to involve areas of the visual cortex that deal with processed data, for
instance hallucinations of faces activate the \"face area\" rather than
visual cortical area V1 (Ffytche *et al.* 1998).
### Suppression of data acquisition during saccades - perception as a patchwork
If you look at yourself in the mirror you will not see your eyes moving
even though they will be darting all over the view of your face. Even
when you deliberately look from place to place your eyes will appear
steady. The natural darting of the eyes from place to place as you view
a scene is known as \"saccadic\" movement of the eyes. The suppression
of the visual image during the motion of the eyes is known as \"saccadic
suppression\" or \"saccadic masking\". The suppression of the
acquisition of image data extends to suppression of awareness of flashes
of light during saccades, this effect is known as \"flash suppression\",
however, flash suppression seems to apply only to rather dull flashes
(Volkman (1962). The suppression during saccades is probably due to
suppression of the magnocellular pathway (the motion sensitive pathway)
in the lateral geniculate nucleus (Burr *et al.* (1996).
The most intriguing feature of this suppression of data acquisition
during saccades is that each snapshot that is obtained between saccades
can only contain a relatively small amount of information. This is
because the fovea, which is the most sensitive area of the eye, is tiny
(about 1mm diameter) and only receives input from a few degrees of the
visual field. As a result what we consider to be a uniform scene in our
minds is actually a patchwork of intersaccade snapshots.
Another aspect of saccades is that the timing of events is referred back
to the beginning of the saccade. This effect is known as \"saccadic
chronostasis\". For example, if an object changes colour during a
saccade the observer feels as if the colour change occurred at the
beginning of the saccade, so extending the amount of time that the
object possesses the changed colour. This effect can extend apparent
durations by up to 500 ms and is consistent with the idea that the
visual system models events prior to perception (see Yarrow *et al.*
2006).
Burr D, Morrone M, Ross J. (1996) Selective suppression of the
magnocellular visual pathway during saccades\]\'\', Behavioral Brain
Research 80 1-8 (1996)
<http://www.pisavisionlab.org/downloads/BBRReview96.pdf>
Volkman, F. (1962). Vision during voluntary saccadic eye movements. J.
Opt Soc. Am. 52:571-578. 1962.
Yarrow, K, Whiteley, L, Rothwell, J.C & Haggard,P. (2006) Spatial
consequences of bridging the saccadic gap. Vision Res. 2006 February;
46(4): 545--555.
<http://www.hexicon.co.uk/Kielan/papers/Moving_chrono.pdf>
## Blindsight
Blindsight studies illuminate the relationship between the cerebral
cortex and our experience. When the visual cortex is removed subjects
become almost totally blind. If the visual cortex on one side is removed
subjects become relatively blind in the contra-lateral hemifield. One of
the most revealing studies of blindsight is Marcel\'s 1998 paper: \"
Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of visual consciousness or
visual function?\".
It is useful when considering blindsight to contemplate for a while the
appearance of the world with both eyes closed and then with one eye
closed. When both eyes are closed our experience is of a darkish space
radiating out from our heads, with one eye closed we tend to ignore the
darkish areas that cannot be seen even though they are still present.
Marcel notes that patients who have a right blind field still have an
underlying visual field on the right side and that this can even contain
conscious visual experience. This sounds a bit like the darkish space
that we all experience if deprived of visual input on one side. As
Marcel says: \"A question that naturally arises is whether the loss is a
\'total\' loss of visual consciousness in the blind field. It is often
assumed to be so, especially by those who discuss blindsight without
carefully reading the literature or working with the subjects. One can
immediately respond negatively to the question..\"
The consciousness of the completion of Kanizsa figures in blindsight
patients is particularly indicative of the preservation of the field
even though the content was largely missing. A Kanizsa figure is shown
below:
![](Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg "Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg")
If we put Marcel\'s observations together with cortical anatomy and
function it seems that the space of our experience is located outside of
the cerebral cortex. The cortex generates much of visual and other
content but it does not generate the space.
## The Role of the Thalamus
The thalamus is connected to the entire bottom layer of the cerebral
cortex. It is the nexus of the various cortical processors as well as a
recipient of independent input from most of the rest of the brain.
![](Constudbrain.png "Constudbrain.png")
The thalamus is subdivided into numerous small and medium sized nuclei
that between them receive inputs from every process in the nervous
system (the white fibres in the illustration above largely penetrate the
thalamus). The thalamic nuclei are interconnected which means that any
of them could, potentially host activity from anywhere in the body or
brain. Although the founders of neurology such as Hughlings Jackson and
Penfield & Jasper located conscious experience in the diencephalon,
including the thalamus, this is no longer the conventional wisdom. The
small size of the thalamic nuclei means that they cannot support the
processes that are assumed to compose access consciousness, however,
even some of the smallest thalamic nuclei host millions of synapses so
size would not be an obstacle if the thalamus contains the substrate of
phenomenal consciousness. Indeed, the diencephalon and the thalamus in
particular can be shown to be excellent candidates for a possible
location of phenomenal experience.
![](constudintralam.jpg "constudintralam.jpg")
`<font size=1>`{=html} The Intralaminar Nuclei of the thalamus. The
white space above and to the left of RN is the third ventricle.
MD=mediodorsal nucleus. CM=Centromedian nucleus, RN=red nucleus (not
part of thalamus) The black areas are stained white fibres. Picture
from: <http://www.neurophys.wisc.edu/> University of Wisconsin and
Michigan State Comparative Mammalian Brain Collections. Preparation of
image has been funded by the National Science Foundation, as well as by
the National Institutes of Health. May only be used with these
acknowledgements.`</font>`{=html}
If the thalamus contains a location for conscious experience then
lesions should abolish this experience. Unlike the cerebral hemispheres,
lesions of the thalamus do indeed seem to abolish consciousness. The
area that is most sensitive to lesions contains the Intralaminar Nuclei,
especially the Parafascicular and Centromedian Nuclei. If these are
damaged bilaterally patients suffer death, coma, akinetic mutism,
hypersomnia, dementia and other equally serious impairments of
consciousness that depend upon the size and placement of the lesions
(Bogen 1995, Schiff & Plum 1999). In cases of fatal familial insomnia,
in which patients exhibit many of these symptoms, there is marked neuron
loss in the Intralaminar Nuclei (Budka 1998).
The effect of interrupting the blood supply to the medial thalamus
depends upon the severity of the damage. There is frequently initial
coma. The recovery after coma is often incomplete, Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) described bilateral paramedian thalamic infarcts as normally
being \"followed by persisting dementia with severe mnemic disturbance,
global aspontaneity and apathy.\" The symptoms of bilateral damage to
the ILN can be so severe that it is possible that, even after recovery
from coma, some patients may cease to be conscious and are being
coordinated by automatic cortical processes.
Bjornstad *et al.* (2003) and Woernera *et al.* (2005) both reported
that the initial coma after bilateral paramedian infarct was accompanied
by a similar pattern of EEG activity to stage 2 sleep. Woernera *et al.*
(2005) also discovered that painful stimuli gave rise to a range of EEG
activity, transiently breaking the stage 2 sleep pattern but without
recovery of consciousness. Unfortunately even in those patients who
recover consciousness Kumral *et al.* (2001) report that \"Cognitive
functions in patients with bilateral paramedian infarction did not
change significantly during the follow-up, in contrast to those with
infarcts in varied arterial territories\" although Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) did report a single patient who made a total recovery.
Laureys *et al.* (2002) investigated recovery from \'persistent
vegetative state\' (wakefulness without awareness). They found that
overall cortical metabolism remained almost constant during recovery but
that the metabolism in the prefrontal and association cortices became
correlated with thalamic ILN and precuneus activity. Again confirming
that thalamo-cortico-thalamic activity is required for consciousness and
that cortical activity by itself is not conscious. Yamamoto *et al.*
(2005) investigated persistent vegetative state and found that deep
brain stimulation (25Hz) of the centromedian-parafascicular complex (19
cases) or mesencephalic reticular formation (2 cases) resulted in 8 of
the patients emerging from persistent vegetative state. It is
interesting that zolpidem, a GABA agonist, has recently been found to
reverse PVS in some patients (Claus & Nel 2006). The effect is rapid and
might be used to demonstrate the correlations that occur on recovery
from PVS.
As Bogen(1995) demonstrates, the ILN receive inputs, either directly or
indirectly, from every part of the CNS but what do they do?
Interest in the thalamus has recently been revived by the theories of
Newman & Baars (1993), Baars, Newman, & Taylor1998) and Crick & Koch
(1990). In Baars, Newman and Taylors\' (1998) theory it is suggested
that \"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not
the detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\".
They also propose that the \"nucleus reticularis thalami\" (Thalamic
Reticular Nucleus, TRN), which is a thin sheet of neurons that covers
the thalamus, is involved in a selective attention system. This concept
is reinforced by the way that point stimulation of the TRN causes focal
activity in the overlying cortex (MacDonald *et al.* 1998) and the way
the TRN is organised topographically (i.e.: has activity that is like an
electrical image of receptor fields).
The thalamus is ideally placed for integrating brain activity, if tiny
parts of the thalamus are removed consciousness is abolished and the
thalamus is involved in attention and the global integration of cortical
activity. Any impartial judge might pronounce that the site of conscious
experience has been found, possibly in the ILN of the thalamus, but no
one can say how it works.
## General Anaesthesia and the Thalamus
General anaesthesia should result in a profound depression of activity
in the ILN if these are indeed the sites of the conscious state. White &
Alkire (2003) administered halothane or isoflurane to volunteers and
used positron emission tomography (PET) to monitor brain activity. They
found severe depression of activity in the thalamus. The depression
appeared to be higher in the non-specific nuclei than in the relay
nuclei of the thalamus. In other words the anaesthesia is neither
turning off the cortex nor turning off the input to the cortex but it is
turning off an important part of the thalamus. Fiset *et al.* (1999)
have also demonstrated a similar pattern of medial thalamic inactivity
and cortical activity in propofol anaesthesia. Suppression of cortical
activity is not the cause of unconsciousness; for instance, the
anaesthetic agent chloralose leads to increased neural activity in the
cortex relative to conscious patients (Cariani 2000).
## The function of consciousness
When we walk our conscious experience does not contain data about the
control of the spinal, cerebellar and vestibular reflexes that keep us
on an even keel. When we reach out for a cup our conscious experience
only contains data related to the need for the cup, not data about the
elaborate control system that enables the action. When we talk the words
just come into mind, we do not painstakingly control the syntax and
vocal chords. When our attention shifts the conscious experience
containing the shift happens after the attention has shifted. This
passive nature of experience recurs throughout the neuroscience of
consciousness from the \"readiness potential\" to the \"auditory
continuity illusion\". So what does conscious observation do? The
medical evidence of the lack of consciousness in some forms of delirium,
mutism, PVS etc. suggest that the role of conscious observation is to
stabilise the brain so that it acts as a coordinated whole. Conscious
observation is an orderly arrangement of events, a stable groundform
that reflects the environment and composes the stage for action. It
could be speculated that if quantum events were prominent in brain
function then such a groundform would be essential but even a classical
brain might require a stabilising form that could be continuously
compared with the world beyond the body.
A stable form of neural information that contains bound data from the
senses and internal neural processes is likely to have a role in the
functioning of the organism. There is now an *integration consensus*
that proposes that phenomenal states somehow integrate neural activities
and information-processing that would otherwise be independent (see
review in Baars, 2002).
However, it has remained unspecified which kinds of information are
integrated in a conscious manner and which kinds can be integrated
without consciousness. Obviously not all kinds of information are
capable of being disseminated consciously (e.g., neural activity related
to vegetative functions, reflexes, unconscious motor programs, low-level
perceptual analyses, etc.) and many kinds can be disseminated and
combined with other kinds without consciousness, as in intersensory
interactions such as the ventriloquism effect.
Morsella (2005) proposed a *Supramodular Interaction Theory* (SIT) that
contrasts the task demands of consciously penetrable processes (e.g.:
those that can be part of conscious experience such as pain, conflicting
urges, and the delay of gratification) and consciously impenetrable
processes (e.g.: intersensory conflicts, peristalsis, and the pupillary
reflex). With this contrastive approach, SIT builds upon the integration
consensus by specifying which kinds of interaction require conscious
processing and which kinds do not (e.g., some intersensory processes).
SIT proposes that conscious processes are required to integrate
high-level systems in the brain that are vying for (specifically)
skeletomotor control, as described by the principle of *parallel
responses into skeletal muscle* (PRISM). Accordingly, regarding
processes such as digestion and excretion, one is conscious of only
those phases of the processes that require coordination with
skeletomotor plans (e.g., chewing or micturating) and none of those that
do not (e.g., peristalsis). From this standpoint, consciousness
functions above the level of the traditional module to "cross-talk"
among high-level, specialized and often multi-modal, systems.
**References**
Baars, B. J. (2002). The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent
evidence. *Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6,* 47 -- 52.
Morsella, E. (2005). The function of phenomenal states: Supramodular
interaction theory. *Psychological Review, 112,* 1000 - 1021.
More\... Click here for Rivalries and synchronisation, bibliography
and references
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 1#Blindsight
## The cortex and consciousness
The cerebral cortex consists of a set of specialised areas that process
different aspects of sensation and motor control. There are about ten
times as many nerve fibres going from the cortex to the thalamus as
there are from the thalamus to the cortex (Destexhe 2000).
![](constudconn.gif "constudconn.gif")
Histologically the cerebral cortex is a layer of greyish neurons
overlying a huge mass of white nerve fibres, the cerebral medulla. The
cortex consists of six main layers. The upper layers receive input from
the relays in the thalamus such as the lateral geniculate, from the
thalamus in general and from other areas of cortex plus a few
specialised inputs from other locations. The lower layers give rise to
output fibres that largely connect with the thalamus and other areas of
cortex although particular specialised processors in the cortex may also
have direct connections elsewhere such as to motor nuclei.
![](Constudcortex2.png "Constudcortex2.png")
The cerebral cortex has many functions and is divided up into numerous
separate processors. The most important function of the cortex from the
point of view of consciousness studies is that it creates models. As was
seen in Part I, philosophers debate whether these models are actually
experienced consciously but in the neurophysiological literature it is
normally assumed that we do experience models and rehearsals such as
inner speech and imaginings. There is considerable evidence that the
parts of the brain that deal with imagining (modelling) things are also
the parts that deal with perception (i.e.: modelling the world). The
overlap between imagination and normal perception is not complete
because, as Tong(2003), in a review of visual consciousness, put it:
\"Internally generated experiences share some, but not all, of the
phenomenal properties of actual perception\". There is also considerable
overlap between the areas used for imaginary speech (thought) and actual
speech, areas dealing with the control of sensation and of the tongue
etc. being used in actual speech but not in imagined speech (Fu *et al.*
2002). Kreiman *et al.* (2000) investigated the activity of single
neurons in humans and also found that the brain activity evoked by
visual imagination overlapped that which occurs upon direct stimulation
by the same image.
Our conscious experience consists of the output of the cortical
modelling and perceptual processes. The cerebral cortex itself appears
to be non-conscious. The evidence for the non-conscious nature of the
cerebral cortex consists of lesion studies in which large amounts of
cortex can be removed without removing consciousness and physiological
studies in which it is demonstrated that the cerebral cortex can be
active without conscious experience.
Lesion studies have shown that up to 60% of the cerebral cortex can be
removed without abolishing consciousness (Austin and Grant 1958). An
entire hemisphere can be removed or much of the front or back of the
cerebral cortex can be cut off yet consciousness persists.
Fiset *et al.* (1999) and Cariani (2000) have shown that cortical
activity can be normal or even elevated during the unconscious state of
general anaesthesia. Alkire *et al.* (1996) also showed that cortical
activity related to word recognition occurred during general
anaesthesia.
Libet *et al.* (1967) found that there could be cerebral cortical
activity in response to weak stimulation of the skin without any
conscious awareness of the stimulus. This work provides a
neurophysiological basis for subliminal (non-conscious) perception and
also shows that large areas of the cerebral cortex can be active without
conscious experience. The insensitivity of experience to cortical
activity has been further confirmed by Libet *et al.* (1979). They
electrically stimulated the cerebral cortex of conscious patients and
discovered that the stimulus must be continued for about 0.5 seconds for
subjects to report a conscious experience of the stimulation. Libet\'s
findings have been analysed at length but there still appears to be a
0.25 to 0.5 secs delay (Klein 2002).
It has been demonstrated that cerebral cortical activity is not
synonymous with conscious experience but why should there be a delay of
up to 0.5 seconds or so between cortical stimulation and a conscious
percept? What is the cortex doing in the 0.5 seconds between the start
of stimulation and the report of awareness of the stimulation? It is
probably synchronising its various processors and creating a waking
dream, a structured set of events that accounts for the activity. The
synchronisation of cerebral cortical processes will be discussed later,
but what evidence is there for the cerebral cortex constructing a waking
dream, or model, to describe the world?
The \'Attentional Blink\' (Raymond *et al.* 1992) is consistent with the
concept of the cerebral cortex being a device that creates models. In
the \'Attentional Blink\' the identification of an object impairs the
identification of a second object that is presented within 0.5 seconds
of the first. Raymond *et al.* used a stream of letters (11 letters per
second) and the identification of a first letter impaired the
identification of a subsequent \'probe\' letter in the stream. If the
probe letter followed the first letter within about 180 msecs it could
easily be identified, suggesting that chunks of about 180 msecs of data
stream are modelled together. Christmann & Leuthold (2004) have
theorised that the \'Attentional Blink\' involves perceptual and central
components of visual processing. This is supported by the fMRI studies
of Marois *et al.* (2004) who presented subjects with faces mounted on
scenes of places. The scenes of places often went undetected by subjects
but they activated regions of the medial temporal cortex involved in
high-level scene representations, the parahippocampal place area (PPA).
When the scenes of places were detected by the subjects there was
activity in the frontal cortex and the PPA activity was increased. These
experiments are consistent with the idea of a cerebral cortex that is a
multiprocessor system that creates consistent models of the environment.
Bregman\'s (1990) auditory continuity illusion is another example of how
sensory events are modelled. If a pure tone is followed by broadband
noise and the noise followed by the same pure tone it seems as if the
tone occurs throughout the period of noise. If the noise is not followed
by the pure tone there is no sound of the tone during the period of
noise. This effect is similar to the results found by Libet because a
delay of several hundred milliseconds between sensory stimulation and
conscious experience is needed to account for the apparent rewriting of
history after the second tone appears.
Dennett and Kinsbourne (1992) argued strongly against modelling as the
source of conscious experience. They discussed two illusions, the
\"cutaneous rabbit illusion\", in which the subject is tapped
successively in such a way that some illusory taps appear and the \"phi
illusion\" in which successively illuminated lights appear as a motion
of the light. Dennett and Kinsbourne declared that there should be no
cerebral cortical filling in of the gaps in the these illusions. Both
these illusions have now been investigated. Blankenburg *et al.* (2006)
found that cerebral cortical activity occurred at the locations expected
for the missing taps in the \"cutaneous rabbit\" illusion and Larsen *et
al.* (2006) found that the areas of cerebral cortex that would be
stimulated by a moving light were active during the \"phi illusion\".
## The delay before consciousness of \"voluntary\" actions
The 0.5 second delay required for the cortex to model an event has
implications for the role of conscious experience in the control of our
lives. If experience is about 0.5 seconds behind the true present
instant then how can we be said to control anything? The brain must be
acting automatically whilst performing most tasks. The 0.5 second delay
also seems to contradict our everyday experience. We certainly feel like
we are aware of things in less than 0.5 seconds, for example, the direct
stimulation of sense organs seems to be experienced much more rapidly
than the delayed experience of cortical stimulation. In fact subjects
report that they are conscious of stimuli, such as being touched or
seeing flashing lights, within 0.1 to 0.2 seconds of the event. So how
can subjects report events within 0.2 seconds even though it seems to
take 0.5 seconds for the cortex to generate activity that can be
experienced? The simplest explanation is that the reaction occurs
automatically within 0.2 seconds and then the conscious experience of
this reaction occurs 0.3 seconds later. This gives a total 0.5 seconds
delay before conscious experience whilst allowing fast reactions.
Libet *et al.* extended their experiments by stimulating a \"relay
nucleus\" in the thalamus that intercepts signals from the senses before
they reach the somatosensory cortex. It was found that when this nucleus
was stimulated for 0.5 seconds the subjects reported that the stimulus
occurred 0.2 seconds after it had begun. When the nucleus was stimulated
for less than 0.5 seconds the subjects did not report any sensation.
This supports the concept of a 0.5 second delay whilst the cortex puts a
stimulus in context before it is experienced.
These experiments show that our experience is an output of cortical
processing rather than the processing itself. If our conscious
experience is non-cortical then this raises the possibility that the
non-conscious cerebral cortex can perform actions without conscious
control. Of course, the cortex does this all the time when we are
indulging in skilled or routine behaviour. The ability of the
non-conscious cortex is quite remarkable; for instance car drivers
sometimes discover that they have driven for several miles without
conscious experience of driving, even at the level of having no
recollection of the route.
!Typical recording of the readiness
potential.{width="150"}Although
it might be accepted that much of our everyday behaviour is automatic is
there any behaviour that is definitely initiated by conscious
experience? This is probably a pointless question because consciousness
is about observation, not action; however, despite this there have been
several experiments that have attempted to determine the relationship
between consciousness and action.
In 1964 Kornhuber and Deecke performed a series of experiments that
measured the electrical activity from the scalp (EEG) during voluntary
actions. They averaged many EEG\'s from subjects who were about to move
a finger and discovered that there is an increase in scalp potential
before the movement takes place. The increase in potential can start as
long as 2 seconds or so before the movement and is known as the
\"readiness potential\" (Bereitschaftspotential). The readiness
potential is strange because it seems to contradict our conscious
experience; we do not decide to move a hand and then wait 2 seconds
before the hand moves. It seems that the non-conscious brain may be
taking things into its own hands.
Libet *et al.* (1983) extended the readiness potential experiments by
asking subjects to observe a Wundt clock whilst flexing a finger. The
Wundt clock had a spot of light that moved around a circle every 2.56
seconds and allowed the subjects to obtain timings that were related to
their mental experiences. When the subjects flexed a finger it was found
that the readiness potential occurred about 0.5 seconds before the
finger moved and the subjects reported they were going to move the
finger about 0.2 seconds before the movement. This suggested that a
subject\'s cerebral cortex was preparing for the movement about 0.3
seconds before the subject was conscious of this. Libet\'s experiments
have been reproduced elsewhere (see Keller & Heckhausen 1990). (It is
important to note that the subjects in Libet\'s experiment were asked to
wait until they felt the urge to move the finger.) These results are
consistent with the idea of the cortex as a modelling system that
constructs a consistent model of events to pass on to whatever mediates
conscious experience.
More recently fMRI and direct electrode recording have borne out the
readiness potential experiments. Soon *et al.* (2008) allowed subjects
to decide to press either a left or right button. They used fMRI to show
that there was spatially organised activity in the polar frontal cortex
and parietal cortex (from precuneus into posterior cingulate cortex)
that predicted the conscious left/right decision and preceded it by
about **seven seconds**. Rektor *et al.* (2001) used direct electrode
recordings to show a 2 second latency. Haggard & Eimer (1999) and also
Trevena and Miller (2002, 2009) have identified a \"Lateralized
Readiness Potential\" that is correlated with the movement of a
particular hand (left or right) in their EEG experiments and Trevena and
Miller claim that this potential always follows the making of a
conscious decision and precedes the actions being studied. However, Soon
*et al.* (2008) showed that fMRI can predict which button will be used
well before any conscious decision is reported. (See Haggard (2008) for
a review of conscious volition).
## Perception, Imagination, Memory and Dreams
### More about Models
Our dreams are clearly models that form a \'dreamworld\' but the idea
that perception might be like a dream that is updated by sensation is
not so obvious. Experience seems to be an active model of the world
(virtual reality) based on sense data rather than a simple mapping of
retinal and other sensory data. This is demonstrated by visual illusions
such as the Ames Room, Spoke Illusion and Muller Lyer illusions shown
below:
![](Constudame.png "Constudame.png")
Notice how the circle is distorted without any distortion in the
\'spokes\', it is as if the circle has been treated as a separate object
by the processes in the brain that rearranged it. In all of these
illusions the brain has rearranged large areas of the visual field and
has managed the input as a collection of \'objects\' that are
manipulated separately. Even movement seems to occur in some figures
showing that the brain models the position of things:
![](Constudcafe.png "Constudcafe.png")
The creation of a model is also demonstrated by the illusion of movement
experienced when we watch the cinema or television. This is due to the
cortical modelling that is known as \'short-range apparent motion\'
rather than flicker fusion or persistence of vision. It is intriguing
that, although it has been known for decades that the joining together
of static images in our minds is due to modelling activity in the brain
the myth that it is due to persistence of vision or flicker fusion is
universal. As Anderson and Anderson (1993) noted:
`Indeed, in the past decade, psychoanalytic-Marxist film scholars `\
`have retained the model implied by persistence of vision: theirs `\
`is a passive viewer, a spectator who is "positioned," unwittingly `\
`"sutured" into the text, and victimized by excess ideology.`
Our experience of the cinema is like a dream updated by sensation rather
than sensation updated by interpretation. In fact the most compelling
evidence for the modelling power of the brain is the existence of
dreams; our dreams are often models of worlds that do not exist and
involve little or no sensory input yet can involve effects as powerful
as any television drama.
Short range apparent motion occurs when the interval between
presentations of an object is brief (c. 50-100 msecs). Motion modelling
in response to longer intervals is known as long range apparent motion.
There is evidence that the modelling in short range apparent motion is
enhanced if the moving patterns are similar to moving human forms (such
as patterns of dots outlining a person)(Thornton *et al.* 1998). The
accuracy of predicting movement can actually improve if the interval
between presentations is increased when human forms are used.
Motion modelling can also be seen in visual illusions such as the
*Waterfall Illusion* (motion aftereffect). The waterfall illusion is
commonly seen after viewing a sequence of scrolling credits on the
television; when the credits stop rolling it appears as if they briefly
move in the opposite direction. Tootel *et al.* (1995) have used fMRI to
show that this is correlated with activity in the motion modelling area
of visual cortex (area MT/V5). The waterfall illusion is also associated
with an intriguing aftereffect known as **storage of the motion
aftereffect**. Normal motion aftereffects last for up to about ten
seconds after the stimulus, however, if the subjects close their eyes
for the normal duration of the aftereffect then reopen them they see the
illusion for almost the normal duration. Culham *et al.* (1999) used
fMRI to show that activity in area MT/V5 was low during the period when
the eyes were closed then increased dramatically when the eyes were
opened. This is strongly suggestive of a modelling mechanism outside
MT/V5 that has adapted to motion and then models stationary data with
movement in the wrong direction.
Visual area MT/V5 is also involved in the separation of moving visual
scenes into *sprites* or objects that move together as a whole within a
scene (Muckli *et al.* 2002).
The way that mental models may be the basis of ordinary reasoning was
outlined by Johnson-Laird (1980), based on earlier work by Kenneth
Craik.
Studies of \'change blindness\' and \'inattentional blindness\', where
subjects fail to spot outrageous changes in their environment, also
demonstrate that we experience a model and suggest that the brain must
analyse an object to incorporate it fully into the model (See for
instance Rensink (2000), Simons & Rensink (2005)).
### Brain areas used in perception overlap those used in imagination and recall
Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI) has shown that similar
areas of brain are used during perception involving the senses as during
imagination (Tong 2003, Kosslyn and Thompson 2003). The substrate of the
mental images that occur in both modes of brain activity has not yet
been found. This overlap of the brain areas used in perception with
those used in imagination, memory and recall has been demonstrated in a
wide range of experiments.
Ganis *et al.* (2004) used fairly complex perceptual and imagination
tasks that activated large areas of the brain, they found an overlap
between the brain areas activated during perception and imagery. The
principle areas that were different in the two tasks were found in the
primary sensory areas of the visual cortex. Other areas in the visual
cortex and activity in the rest of the brain showed a remarkable degree
of overlap. The authors suggested that the differences in the activity
of primary visual cortex may have been due to differences between the
perceptual and imaginary stimuli such as speed of onset etc. The
hippocampus was not activated.
It is intriguing that, contrary to object imagery, spatial imagery such
as predicting when a cross on a screen would fall on an imaginary letter
actually seems to inhibit activity in sensory visual cortex (Aleman *et
al.*). Both fMRI and blocking with transcranial magnetic stimulation
(TMS) showed that the posterior parietal cortex was involved in the
spatial imagery.
Imagery involving places and faces activates the place and face areas
that are activated during perception (Ishai *et al.* 2000).
The recall and recognition of things also seems to involve very similar
brain areas to those used during perception. Wheeler and Buckner (2003)
showed that areas involved in perception were also involved in the
recall of the perceptual stimuli.
Recall causes activation of areas used in perception but also seems to
use areas that may be particularly related to the process of recall
iself, such as the left parietal cortex (Konishi *et al.* 2000)
(Brodmann\'s area 40/39). Frontal and parietal regions are involved in
the recognition of whether stimuli have been experienced before.
Image generation during sleep seems to differ from that during
imagination and recall. In particular it seems to involve a few well
defined areas of cortex and considerable activation of the posterior
thalamus.
Sleep studies have shown that people dream throughout sleep. However,
dreams are more frequent during the REM (rapid eye movement) periods of
sleep than the NREM (non-REM) periods. Dreams are reported after 70-95%
of awakenings in REM sleep and 5-10% of awakenings in NREM sleep. REM
dreams are more visual than NREM dreams which are more \'thoughtlike\'
(Solms 2000). Thoughtlike events (mentation) are reported after 43% of
awakenings from NREM sleep.
Solms (1997) found that patients who had lesions in the
parietal-temporo-occipital junction reported a cessation of visual
images in dreams. Solms also found that patients with lesions in the
white matter inferior to the frontal horns of the lateral ventricles, in
the ventromesial quadrant of the frontal lobes, also reported loss of
dreaming. Loss of dreaming is also reported by leucotomised patients
with frontal ventromesial damage. Damasio *et al.* (1985) and Solms
(1997) also reported that some patients with damage to the medial
prefrontal cortex, the anterior cingulate cortex, and the basal
forebrain became confused about what was real life and what was dreaming
(waking dreams occurred).
Studies using fMRI show that the sensory occipital lobe (BA 18) and
posterior thalamus, especially the lateral geniculate nuclei, are
activated in REM sleep, weaker activations of the posterior cingulate,
putamen and midbrain were also found (Wehrle *et al.* 2005, Loveblad *et
al.* 1999). These findings are consistent with activation of the
ponto-geniculo-occipital system (PGO) during REM.
So dreams may be more like primary activations of sensory cortex than
imagining or recall. This suggests that dreams have a thalamic origin or
are managed via connections from the cortex through the thalamus to the
visual cortex.
Hallucinations seem to differ from dreams. In Charles Bonnett Syndrome
patients can have clear hallucinations. These, like imaginations, seem
to involve areas of the visual cortex that deal with processed data, for
instance hallucinations of faces activate the \"face area\" rather than
visual cortical area V1 (Ffytche *et al.* 1998).
### Suppression of data acquisition during saccades - perception as a patchwork
If you look at yourself in the mirror you will not see your eyes moving
even though they will be darting all over the view of your face. Even
when you deliberately look from place to place your eyes will appear
steady. The natural darting of the eyes from place to place as you view
a scene is known as \"saccadic\" movement of the eyes. The suppression
of the visual image during the motion of the eyes is known as \"saccadic
suppression\" or \"saccadic masking\". The suppression of the
acquisition of image data extends to suppression of awareness of flashes
of light during saccades, this effect is known as \"flash suppression\",
however, flash suppression seems to apply only to rather dull flashes
(Volkman (1962). The suppression during saccades is probably due to
suppression of the magnocellular pathway (the motion sensitive pathway)
in the lateral geniculate nucleus (Burr *et al.* (1996).
The most intriguing feature of this suppression of data acquisition
during saccades is that each snapshot that is obtained between saccades
can only contain a relatively small amount of information. This is
because the fovea, which is the most sensitive area of the eye, is tiny
(about 1mm diameter) and only receives input from a few degrees of the
visual field. As a result what we consider to be a uniform scene in our
minds is actually a patchwork of intersaccade snapshots.
Another aspect of saccades is that the timing of events is referred back
to the beginning of the saccade. This effect is known as \"saccadic
chronostasis\". For example, if an object changes colour during a
saccade the observer feels as if the colour change occurred at the
beginning of the saccade, so extending the amount of time that the
object possesses the changed colour. This effect can extend apparent
durations by up to 500 ms and is consistent with the idea that the
visual system models events prior to perception (see Yarrow *et al.*
2006).
Burr D, Morrone M, Ross J. (1996) Selective suppression of the
magnocellular visual pathway during saccades\]\'\', Behavioral Brain
Research 80 1-8 (1996)
<http://www.pisavisionlab.org/downloads/BBRReview96.pdf>
Volkman, F. (1962). Vision during voluntary saccadic eye movements. J.
Opt Soc. Am. 52:571-578. 1962.
Yarrow, K, Whiteley, L, Rothwell, J.C & Haggard,P. (2006) Spatial
consequences of bridging the saccadic gap. Vision Res. 2006 February;
46(4): 545--555.
<http://www.hexicon.co.uk/Kielan/papers/Moving_chrono.pdf>
## Blindsight
Blindsight studies illuminate the relationship between the cerebral
cortex and our experience. When the visual cortex is removed subjects
become almost totally blind. If the visual cortex on one side is removed
subjects become relatively blind in the contra-lateral hemifield. One of
the most revealing studies of blindsight is Marcel\'s 1998 paper: \"
Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of visual consciousness or
visual function?\".
It is useful when considering blindsight to contemplate for a while the
appearance of the world with both eyes closed and then with one eye
closed. When both eyes are closed our experience is of a darkish space
radiating out from our heads, with one eye closed we tend to ignore the
darkish areas that cannot be seen even though they are still present.
Marcel notes that patients who have a right blind field still have an
underlying visual field on the right side and that this can even contain
conscious visual experience. This sounds a bit like the darkish space
that we all experience if deprived of visual input on one side. As
Marcel says: \"A question that naturally arises is whether the loss is a
\'total\' loss of visual consciousness in the blind field. It is often
assumed to be so, especially by those who discuss blindsight without
carefully reading the literature or working with the subjects. One can
immediately respond negatively to the question..\"
The consciousness of the completion of Kanizsa figures in blindsight
patients is particularly indicative of the preservation of the field
even though the content was largely missing. A Kanizsa figure is shown
below:
![](Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg "Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg")
If we put Marcel\'s observations together with cortical anatomy and
function it seems that the space of our experience is located outside of
the cerebral cortex. The cortex generates much of visual and other
content but it does not generate the space.
## The Role of the Thalamus
The thalamus is connected to the entire bottom layer of the cerebral
cortex. It is the nexus of the various cortical processors as well as a
recipient of independent input from most of the rest of the brain.
![](Constudbrain.png "Constudbrain.png")
The thalamus is subdivided into numerous small and medium sized nuclei
that between them receive inputs from every process in the nervous
system (the white fibres in the illustration above largely penetrate the
thalamus). The thalamic nuclei are interconnected which means that any
of them could, potentially host activity from anywhere in the body or
brain. Although the founders of neurology such as Hughlings Jackson and
Penfield & Jasper located conscious experience in the diencephalon,
including the thalamus, this is no longer the conventional wisdom. The
small size of the thalamic nuclei means that they cannot support the
processes that are assumed to compose access consciousness, however,
even some of the smallest thalamic nuclei host millions of synapses so
size would not be an obstacle if the thalamus contains the substrate of
phenomenal consciousness. Indeed, the diencephalon and the thalamus in
particular can be shown to be excellent candidates for a possible
location of phenomenal experience.
![](constudintralam.jpg "constudintralam.jpg")
`<font size=1>`{=html} The Intralaminar Nuclei of the thalamus. The
white space above and to the left of RN is the third ventricle.
MD=mediodorsal nucleus. CM=Centromedian nucleus, RN=red nucleus (not
part of thalamus) The black areas are stained white fibres. Picture
from: <http://www.neurophys.wisc.edu/> University of Wisconsin and
Michigan State Comparative Mammalian Brain Collections. Preparation of
image has been funded by the National Science Foundation, as well as by
the National Institutes of Health. May only be used with these
acknowledgements.`</font>`{=html}
If the thalamus contains a location for conscious experience then
lesions should abolish this experience. Unlike the cerebral hemispheres,
lesions of the thalamus do indeed seem to abolish consciousness. The
area that is most sensitive to lesions contains the Intralaminar Nuclei,
especially the Parafascicular and Centromedian Nuclei. If these are
damaged bilaterally patients suffer death, coma, akinetic mutism,
hypersomnia, dementia and other equally serious impairments of
consciousness that depend upon the size and placement of the lesions
(Bogen 1995, Schiff & Plum 1999). In cases of fatal familial insomnia,
in which patients exhibit many of these symptoms, there is marked neuron
loss in the Intralaminar Nuclei (Budka 1998).
The effect of interrupting the blood supply to the medial thalamus
depends upon the severity of the damage. There is frequently initial
coma. The recovery after coma is often incomplete, Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) described bilateral paramedian thalamic infarcts as normally
being \"followed by persisting dementia with severe mnemic disturbance,
global aspontaneity and apathy.\" The symptoms of bilateral damage to
the ILN can be so severe that it is possible that, even after recovery
from coma, some patients may cease to be conscious and are being
coordinated by automatic cortical processes.
Bjornstad *et al.* (2003) and Woernera *et al.* (2005) both reported
that the initial coma after bilateral paramedian infarct was accompanied
by a similar pattern of EEG activity to stage 2 sleep. Woernera *et al.*
(2005) also discovered that painful stimuli gave rise to a range of EEG
activity, transiently breaking the stage 2 sleep pattern but without
recovery of consciousness. Unfortunately even in those patients who
recover consciousness Kumral *et al.* (2001) report that \"Cognitive
functions in patients with bilateral paramedian infarction did not
change significantly during the follow-up, in contrast to those with
infarcts in varied arterial territories\" although Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) did report a single patient who made a total recovery.
Laureys *et al.* (2002) investigated recovery from \'persistent
vegetative state\' (wakefulness without awareness). They found that
overall cortical metabolism remained almost constant during recovery but
that the metabolism in the prefrontal and association cortices became
correlated with thalamic ILN and precuneus activity. Again confirming
that thalamo-cortico-thalamic activity is required for consciousness and
that cortical activity by itself is not conscious. Yamamoto *et al.*
(2005) investigated persistent vegetative state and found that deep
brain stimulation (25Hz) of the centromedian-parafascicular complex (19
cases) or mesencephalic reticular formation (2 cases) resulted in 8 of
the patients emerging from persistent vegetative state. It is
interesting that zolpidem, a GABA agonist, has recently been found to
reverse PVS in some patients (Claus & Nel 2006). The effect is rapid and
might be used to demonstrate the correlations that occur on recovery
from PVS.
As Bogen(1995) demonstrates, the ILN receive inputs, either directly or
indirectly, from every part of the CNS but what do they do?
Interest in the thalamus has recently been revived by the theories of
Newman & Baars (1993), Baars, Newman, & Taylor1998) and Crick & Koch
(1990). In Baars, Newman and Taylors\' (1998) theory it is suggested
that \"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not
the detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\".
They also propose that the \"nucleus reticularis thalami\" (Thalamic
Reticular Nucleus, TRN), which is a thin sheet of neurons that covers
the thalamus, is involved in a selective attention system. This concept
is reinforced by the way that point stimulation of the TRN causes focal
activity in the overlying cortex (MacDonald *et al.* 1998) and the way
the TRN is organised topographically (i.e.: has activity that is like an
electrical image of receptor fields).
The thalamus is ideally placed for integrating brain activity, if tiny
parts of the thalamus are removed consciousness is abolished and the
thalamus is involved in attention and the global integration of cortical
activity. Any impartial judge might pronounce that the site of conscious
experience has been found, possibly in the ILN of the thalamus, but no
one can say how it works.
## General Anaesthesia and the Thalamus
General anaesthesia should result in a profound depression of activity
in the ILN if these are indeed the sites of the conscious state. White &
Alkire (2003) administered halothane or isoflurane to volunteers and
used positron emission tomography (PET) to monitor brain activity. They
found severe depression of activity in the thalamus. The depression
appeared to be higher in the non-specific nuclei than in the relay
nuclei of the thalamus. In other words the anaesthesia is neither
turning off the cortex nor turning off the input to the cortex but it is
turning off an important part of the thalamus. Fiset *et al.* (1999)
have also demonstrated a similar pattern of medial thalamic inactivity
and cortical activity in propofol anaesthesia. Suppression of cortical
activity is not the cause of unconsciousness; for instance, the
anaesthetic agent chloralose leads to increased neural activity in the
cortex relative to conscious patients (Cariani 2000).
## The function of consciousness
When we walk our conscious experience does not contain data about the
control of the spinal, cerebellar and vestibular reflexes that keep us
on an even keel. When we reach out for a cup our conscious experience
only contains data related to the need for the cup, not data about the
elaborate control system that enables the action. When we talk the words
just come into mind, we do not painstakingly control the syntax and
vocal chords. When our attention shifts the conscious experience
containing the shift happens after the attention has shifted. This
passive nature of experience recurs throughout the neuroscience of
consciousness from the \"readiness potential\" to the \"auditory
continuity illusion\". So what does conscious observation do? The
medical evidence of the lack of consciousness in some forms of delirium,
mutism, PVS etc. suggest that the role of conscious observation is to
stabilise the brain so that it acts as a coordinated whole. Conscious
observation is an orderly arrangement of events, a stable groundform
that reflects the environment and composes the stage for action. It
could be speculated that if quantum events were prominent in brain
function then such a groundform would be essential but even a classical
brain might require a stabilising form that could be continuously
compared with the world beyond the body.
A stable form of neural information that contains bound data from the
senses and internal neural processes is likely to have a role in the
functioning of the organism. There is now an *integration consensus*
that proposes that phenomenal states somehow integrate neural activities
and information-processing that would otherwise be independent (see
review in Baars, 2002).
However, it has remained unspecified which kinds of information are
integrated in a conscious manner and which kinds can be integrated
without consciousness. Obviously not all kinds of information are
capable of being disseminated consciously (e.g., neural activity related
to vegetative functions, reflexes, unconscious motor programs, low-level
perceptual analyses, etc.) and many kinds can be disseminated and
combined with other kinds without consciousness, as in intersensory
interactions such as the ventriloquism effect.
Morsella (2005) proposed a *Supramodular Interaction Theory* (SIT) that
contrasts the task demands of consciously penetrable processes (e.g.:
those that can be part of conscious experience such as pain, conflicting
urges, and the delay of gratification) and consciously impenetrable
processes (e.g.: intersensory conflicts, peristalsis, and the pupillary
reflex). With this contrastive approach, SIT builds upon the integration
consensus by specifying which kinds of interaction require conscious
processing and which kinds do not (e.g., some intersensory processes).
SIT proposes that conscious processes are required to integrate
high-level systems in the brain that are vying for (specifically)
skeletomotor control, as described by the principle of *parallel
responses into skeletal muscle* (PRISM). Accordingly, regarding
processes such as digestion and excretion, one is conscious of only
those phases of the processes that require coordination with
skeletomotor plans (e.g., chewing or micturating) and none of those that
do not (e.g., peristalsis). From this standpoint, consciousness
functions above the level of the traditional module to "cross-talk"
among high-level, specialized and often multi-modal, systems.
**References**
Baars, B. J. (2002). The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent
evidence. *Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6,* 47 -- 52.
Morsella, E. (2005). The function of phenomenal states: Supramodular
interaction theory. *Psychological Review, 112,* 1000 - 1021.
More\... Click here for Rivalries and synchronisation, bibliography
and references
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 1#The Role of the Thalamus
## The cortex and consciousness
The cerebral cortex consists of a set of specialised areas that process
different aspects of sensation and motor control. There are about ten
times as many nerve fibres going from the cortex to the thalamus as
there are from the thalamus to the cortex (Destexhe 2000).
![](constudconn.gif "constudconn.gif")
Histologically the cerebral cortex is a layer of greyish neurons
overlying a huge mass of white nerve fibres, the cerebral medulla. The
cortex consists of six main layers. The upper layers receive input from
the relays in the thalamus such as the lateral geniculate, from the
thalamus in general and from other areas of cortex plus a few
specialised inputs from other locations. The lower layers give rise to
output fibres that largely connect with the thalamus and other areas of
cortex although particular specialised processors in the cortex may also
have direct connections elsewhere such as to motor nuclei.
![](Constudcortex2.png "Constudcortex2.png")
The cerebral cortex has many functions and is divided up into numerous
separate processors. The most important function of the cortex from the
point of view of consciousness studies is that it creates models. As was
seen in Part I, philosophers debate whether these models are actually
experienced consciously but in the neurophysiological literature it is
normally assumed that we do experience models and rehearsals such as
inner speech and imaginings. There is considerable evidence that the
parts of the brain that deal with imagining (modelling) things are also
the parts that deal with perception (i.e.: modelling the world). The
overlap between imagination and normal perception is not complete
because, as Tong(2003), in a review of visual consciousness, put it:
\"Internally generated experiences share some, but not all, of the
phenomenal properties of actual perception\". There is also considerable
overlap between the areas used for imaginary speech (thought) and actual
speech, areas dealing with the control of sensation and of the tongue
etc. being used in actual speech but not in imagined speech (Fu *et al.*
2002). Kreiman *et al.* (2000) investigated the activity of single
neurons in humans and also found that the brain activity evoked by
visual imagination overlapped that which occurs upon direct stimulation
by the same image.
Our conscious experience consists of the output of the cortical
modelling and perceptual processes. The cerebral cortex itself appears
to be non-conscious. The evidence for the non-conscious nature of the
cerebral cortex consists of lesion studies in which large amounts of
cortex can be removed without removing consciousness and physiological
studies in which it is demonstrated that the cerebral cortex can be
active without conscious experience.
Lesion studies have shown that up to 60% of the cerebral cortex can be
removed without abolishing consciousness (Austin and Grant 1958). An
entire hemisphere can be removed or much of the front or back of the
cerebral cortex can be cut off yet consciousness persists.
Fiset *et al.* (1999) and Cariani (2000) have shown that cortical
activity can be normal or even elevated during the unconscious state of
general anaesthesia. Alkire *et al.* (1996) also showed that cortical
activity related to word recognition occurred during general
anaesthesia.
Libet *et al.* (1967) found that there could be cerebral cortical
activity in response to weak stimulation of the skin without any
conscious awareness of the stimulus. This work provides a
neurophysiological basis for subliminal (non-conscious) perception and
also shows that large areas of the cerebral cortex can be active without
conscious experience. The insensitivity of experience to cortical
activity has been further confirmed by Libet *et al.* (1979). They
electrically stimulated the cerebral cortex of conscious patients and
discovered that the stimulus must be continued for about 0.5 seconds for
subjects to report a conscious experience of the stimulation. Libet\'s
findings have been analysed at length but there still appears to be a
0.25 to 0.5 secs delay (Klein 2002).
It has been demonstrated that cerebral cortical activity is not
synonymous with conscious experience but why should there be a delay of
up to 0.5 seconds or so between cortical stimulation and a conscious
percept? What is the cortex doing in the 0.5 seconds between the start
of stimulation and the report of awareness of the stimulation? It is
probably synchronising its various processors and creating a waking
dream, a structured set of events that accounts for the activity. The
synchronisation of cerebral cortical processes will be discussed later,
but what evidence is there for the cerebral cortex constructing a waking
dream, or model, to describe the world?
The \'Attentional Blink\' (Raymond *et al.* 1992) is consistent with the
concept of the cerebral cortex being a device that creates models. In
the \'Attentional Blink\' the identification of an object impairs the
identification of a second object that is presented within 0.5 seconds
of the first. Raymond *et al.* used a stream of letters (11 letters per
second) and the identification of a first letter impaired the
identification of a subsequent \'probe\' letter in the stream. If the
probe letter followed the first letter within about 180 msecs it could
easily be identified, suggesting that chunks of about 180 msecs of data
stream are modelled together. Christmann & Leuthold (2004) have
theorised that the \'Attentional Blink\' involves perceptual and central
components of visual processing. This is supported by the fMRI studies
of Marois *et al.* (2004) who presented subjects with faces mounted on
scenes of places. The scenes of places often went undetected by subjects
but they activated regions of the medial temporal cortex involved in
high-level scene representations, the parahippocampal place area (PPA).
When the scenes of places were detected by the subjects there was
activity in the frontal cortex and the PPA activity was increased. These
experiments are consistent with the idea of a cerebral cortex that is a
multiprocessor system that creates consistent models of the environment.
Bregman\'s (1990) auditory continuity illusion is another example of how
sensory events are modelled. If a pure tone is followed by broadband
noise and the noise followed by the same pure tone it seems as if the
tone occurs throughout the period of noise. If the noise is not followed
by the pure tone there is no sound of the tone during the period of
noise. This effect is similar to the results found by Libet because a
delay of several hundred milliseconds between sensory stimulation and
conscious experience is needed to account for the apparent rewriting of
history after the second tone appears.
Dennett and Kinsbourne (1992) argued strongly against modelling as the
source of conscious experience. They discussed two illusions, the
\"cutaneous rabbit illusion\", in which the subject is tapped
successively in such a way that some illusory taps appear and the \"phi
illusion\" in which successively illuminated lights appear as a motion
of the light. Dennett and Kinsbourne declared that there should be no
cerebral cortical filling in of the gaps in the these illusions. Both
these illusions have now been investigated. Blankenburg *et al.* (2006)
found that cerebral cortical activity occurred at the locations expected
for the missing taps in the \"cutaneous rabbit\" illusion and Larsen *et
al.* (2006) found that the areas of cerebral cortex that would be
stimulated by a moving light were active during the \"phi illusion\".
## The delay before consciousness of \"voluntary\" actions
The 0.5 second delay required for the cortex to model an event has
implications for the role of conscious experience in the control of our
lives. If experience is about 0.5 seconds behind the true present
instant then how can we be said to control anything? The brain must be
acting automatically whilst performing most tasks. The 0.5 second delay
also seems to contradict our everyday experience. We certainly feel like
we are aware of things in less than 0.5 seconds, for example, the direct
stimulation of sense organs seems to be experienced much more rapidly
than the delayed experience of cortical stimulation. In fact subjects
report that they are conscious of stimuli, such as being touched or
seeing flashing lights, within 0.1 to 0.2 seconds of the event. So how
can subjects report events within 0.2 seconds even though it seems to
take 0.5 seconds for the cortex to generate activity that can be
experienced? The simplest explanation is that the reaction occurs
automatically within 0.2 seconds and then the conscious experience of
this reaction occurs 0.3 seconds later. This gives a total 0.5 seconds
delay before conscious experience whilst allowing fast reactions.
Libet *et al.* extended their experiments by stimulating a \"relay
nucleus\" in the thalamus that intercepts signals from the senses before
they reach the somatosensory cortex. It was found that when this nucleus
was stimulated for 0.5 seconds the subjects reported that the stimulus
occurred 0.2 seconds after it had begun. When the nucleus was stimulated
for less than 0.5 seconds the subjects did not report any sensation.
This supports the concept of a 0.5 second delay whilst the cortex puts a
stimulus in context before it is experienced.
These experiments show that our experience is an output of cortical
processing rather than the processing itself. If our conscious
experience is non-cortical then this raises the possibility that the
non-conscious cerebral cortex can perform actions without conscious
control. Of course, the cortex does this all the time when we are
indulging in skilled or routine behaviour. The ability of the
non-conscious cortex is quite remarkable; for instance car drivers
sometimes discover that they have driven for several miles without
conscious experience of driving, even at the level of having no
recollection of the route.
!Typical recording of the readiness
potential.{width="150"}Although
it might be accepted that much of our everyday behaviour is automatic is
there any behaviour that is definitely initiated by conscious
experience? This is probably a pointless question because consciousness
is about observation, not action; however, despite this there have been
several experiments that have attempted to determine the relationship
between consciousness and action.
In 1964 Kornhuber and Deecke performed a series of experiments that
measured the electrical activity from the scalp (EEG) during voluntary
actions. They averaged many EEG\'s from subjects who were about to move
a finger and discovered that there is an increase in scalp potential
before the movement takes place. The increase in potential can start as
long as 2 seconds or so before the movement and is known as the
\"readiness potential\" (Bereitschaftspotential). The readiness
potential is strange because it seems to contradict our conscious
experience; we do not decide to move a hand and then wait 2 seconds
before the hand moves. It seems that the non-conscious brain may be
taking things into its own hands.
Libet *et al.* (1983) extended the readiness potential experiments by
asking subjects to observe a Wundt clock whilst flexing a finger. The
Wundt clock had a spot of light that moved around a circle every 2.56
seconds and allowed the subjects to obtain timings that were related to
their mental experiences. When the subjects flexed a finger it was found
that the readiness potential occurred about 0.5 seconds before the
finger moved and the subjects reported they were going to move the
finger about 0.2 seconds before the movement. This suggested that a
subject\'s cerebral cortex was preparing for the movement about 0.3
seconds before the subject was conscious of this. Libet\'s experiments
have been reproduced elsewhere (see Keller & Heckhausen 1990). (It is
important to note that the subjects in Libet\'s experiment were asked to
wait until they felt the urge to move the finger.) These results are
consistent with the idea of the cortex as a modelling system that
constructs a consistent model of events to pass on to whatever mediates
conscious experience.
More recently fMRI and direct electrode recording have borne out the
readiness potential experiments. Soon *et al.* (2008) allowed subjects
to decide to press either a left or right button. They used fMRI to show
that there was spatially organised activity in the polar frontal cortex
and parietal cortex (from precuneus into posterior cingulate cortex)
that predicted the conscious left/right decision and preceded it by
about **seven seconds**. Rektor *et al.* (2001) used direct electrode
recordings to show a 2 second latency. Haggard & Eimer (1999) and also
Trevena and Miller (2002, 2009) have identified a \"Lateralized
Readiness Potential\" that is correlated with the movement of a
particular hand (left or right) in their EEG experiments and Trevena and
Miller claim that this potential always follows the making of a
conscious decision and precedes the actions being studied. However, Soon
*et al.* (2008) showed that fMRI can predict which button will be used
well before any conscious decision is reported. (See Haggard (2008) for
a review of conscious volition).
## Perception, Imagination, Memory and Dreams
### More about Models
Our dreams are clearly models that form a \'dreamworld\' but the idea
that perception might be like a dream that is updated by sensation is
not so obvious. Experience seems to be an active model of the world
(virtual reality) based on sense data rather than a simple mapping of
retinal and other sensory data. This is demonstrated by visual illusions
such as the Ames Room, Spoke Illusion and Muller Lyer illusions shown
below:
![](Constudame.png "Constudame.png")
Notice how the circle is distorted without any distortion in the
\'spokes\', it is as if the circle has been treated as a separate object
by the processes in the brain that rearranged it. In all of these
illusions the brain has rearranged large areas of the visual field and
has managed the input as a collection of \'objects\' that are
manipulated separately. Even movement seems to occur in some figures
showing that the brain models the position of things:
![](Constudcafe.png "Constudcafe.png")
The creation of a model is also demonstrated by the illusion of movement
experienced when we watch the cinema or television. This is due to the
cortical modelling that is known as \'short-range apparent motion\'
rather than flicker fusion or persistence of vision. It is intriguing
that, although it has been known for decades that the joining together
of static images in our minds is due to modelling activity in the brain
the myth that it is due to persistence of vision or flicker fusion is
universal. As Anderson and Anderson (1993) noted:
`Indeed, in the past decade, psychoanalytic-Marxist film scholars `\
`have retained the model implied by persistence of vision: theirs `\
`is a passive viewer, a spectator who is "positioned," unwittingly `\
`"sutured" into the text, and victimized by excess ideology.`
Our experience of the cinema is like a dream updated by sensation rather
than sensation updated by interpretation. In fact the most compelling
evidence for the modelling power of the brain is the existence of
dreams; our dreams are often models of worlds that do not exist and
involve little or no sensory input yet can involve effects as powerful
as any television drama.
Short range apparent motion occurs when the interval between
presentations of an object is brief (c. 50-100 msecs). Motion modelling
in response to longer intervals is known as long range apparent motion.
There is evidence that the modelling in short range apparent motion is
enhanced if the moving patterns are similar to moving human forms (such
as patterns of dots outlining a person)(Thornton *et al.* 1998). The
accuracy of predicting movement can actually improve if the interval
between presentations is increased when human forms are used.
Motion modelling can also be seen in visual illusions such as the
*Waterfall Illusion* (motion aftereffect). The waterfall illusion is
commonly seen after viewing a sequence of scrolling credits on the
television; when the credits stop rolling it appears as if they briefly
move in the opposite direction. Tootel *et al.* (1995) have used fMRI to
show that this is correlated with activity in the motion modelling area
of visual cortex (area MT/V5). The waterfall illusion is also associated
with an intriguing aftereffect known as **storage of the motion
aftereffect**. Normal motion aftereffects last for up to about ten
seconds after the stimulus, however, if the subjects close their eyes
for the normal duration of the aftereffect then reopen them they see the
illusion for almost the normal duration. Culham *et al.* (1999) used
fMRI to show that activity in area MT/V5 was low during the period when
the eyes were closed then increased dramatically when the eyes were
opened. This is strongly suggestive of a modelling mechanism outside
MT/V5 that has adapted to motion and then models stationary data with
movement in the wrong direction.
Visual area MT/V5 is also involved in the separation of moving visual
scenes into *sprites* or objects that move together as a whole within a
scene (Muckli *et al.* 2002).
The way that mental models may be the basis of ordinary reasoning was
outlined by Johnson-Laird (1980), based on earlier work by Kenneth
Craik.
Studies of \'change blindness\' and \'inattentional blindness\', where
subjects fail to spot outrageous changes in their environment, also
demonstrate that we experience a model and suggest that the brain must
analyse an object to incorporate it fully into the model (See for
instance Rensink (2000), Simons & Rensink (2005)).
### Brain areas used in perception overlap those used in imagination and recall
Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI) has shown that similar
areas of brain are used during perception involving the senses as during
imagination (Tong 2003, Kosslyn and Thompson 2003). The substrate of the
mental images that occur in both modes of brain activity has not yet
been found. This overlap of the brain areas used in perception with
those used in imagination, memory and recall has been demonstrated in a
wide range of experiments.
Ganis *et al.* (2004) used fairly complex perceptual and imagination
tasks that activated large areas of the brain, they found an overlap
between the brain areas activated during perception and imagery. The
principle areas that were different in the two tasks were found in the
primary sensory areas of the visual cortex. Other areas in the visual
cortex and activity in the rest of the brain showed a remarkable degree
of overlap. The authors suggested that the differences in the activity
of primary visual cortex may have been due to differences between the
perceptual and imaginary stimuli such as speed of onset etc. The
hippocampus was not activated.
It is intriguing that, contrary to object imagery, spatial imagery such
as predicting when a cross on a screen would fall on an imaginary letter
actually seems to inhibit activity in sensory visual cortex (Aleman *et
al.*). Both fMRI and blocking with transcranial magnetic stimulation
(TMS) showed that the posterior parietal cortex was involved in the
spatial imagery.
Imagery involving places and faces activates the place and face areas
that are activated during perception (Ishai *et al.* 2000).
The recall and recognition of things also seems to involve very similar
brain areas to those used during perception. Wheeler and Buckner (2003)
showed that areas involved in perception were also involved in the
recall of the perceptual stimuli.
Recall causes activation of areas used in perception but also seems to
use areas that may be particularly related to the process of recall
iself, such as the left parietal cortex (Konishi *et al.* 2000)
(Brodmann\'s area 40/39). Frontal and parietal regions are involved in
the recognition of whether stimuli have been experienced before.
Image generation during sleep seems to differ from that during
imagination and recall. In particular it seems to involve a few well
defined areas of cortex and considerable activation of the posterior
thalamus.
Sleep studies have shown that people dream throughout sleep. However,
dreams are more frequent during the REM (rapid eye movement) periods of
sleep than the NREM (non-REM) periods. Dreams are reported after 70-95%
of awakenings in REM sleep and 5-10% of awakenings in NREM sleep. REM
dreams are more visual than NREM dreams which are more \'thoughtlike\'
(Solms 2000). Thoughtlike events (mentation) are reported after 43% of
awakenings from NREM sleep.
Solms (1997) found that patients who had lesions in the
parietal-temporo-occipital junction reported a cessation of visual
images in dreams. Solms also found that patients with lesions in the
white matter inferior to the frontal horns of the lateral ventricles, in
the ventromesial quadrant of the frontal lobes, also reported loss of
dreaming. Loss of dreaming is also reported by leucotomised patients
with frontal ventromesial damage. Damasio *et al.* (1985) and Solms
(1997) also reported that some patients with damage to the medial
prefrontal cortex, the anterior cingulate cortex, and the basal
forebrain became confused about what was real life and what was dreaming
(waking dreams occurred).
Studies using fMRI show that the sensory occipital lobe (BA 18) and
posterior thalamus, especially the lateral geniculate nuclei, are
activated in REM sleep, weaker activations of the posterior cingulate,
putamen and midbrain were also found (Wehrle *et al.* 2005, Loveblad *et
al.* 1999). These findings are consistent with activation of the
ponto-geniculo-occipital system (PGO) during REM.
So dreams may be more like primary activations of sensory cortex than
imagining or recall. This suggests that dreams have a thalamic origin or
are managed via connections from the cortex through the thalamus to the
visual cortex.
Hallucinations seem to differ from dreams. In Charles Bonnett Syndrome
patients can have clear hallucinations. These, like imaginations, seem
to involve areas of the visual cortex that deal with processed data, for
instance hallucinations of faces activate the \"face area\" rather than
visual cortical area V1 (Ffytche *et al.* 1998).
### Suppression of data acquisition during saccades - perception as a patchwork
If you look at yourself in the mirror you will not see your eyes moving
even though they will be darting all over the view of your face. Even
when you deliberately look from place to place your eyes will appear
steady. The natural darting of the eyes from place to place as you view
a scene is known as \"saccadic\" movement of the eyes. The suppression
of the visual image during the motion of the eyes is known as \"saccadic
suppression\" or \"saccadic masking\". The suppression of the
acquisition of image data extends to suppression of awareness of flashes
of light during saccades, this effect is known as \"flash suppression\",
however, flash suppression seems to apply only to rather dull flashes
(Volkman (1962). The suppression during saccades is probably due to
suppression of the magnocellular pathway (the motion sensitive pathway)
in the lateral geniculate nucleus (Burr *et al.* (1996).
The most intriguing feature of this suppression of data acquisition
during saccades is that each snapshot that is obtained between saccades
can only contain a relatively small amount of information. This is
because the fovea, which is the most sensitive area of the eye, is tiny
(about 1mm diameter) and only receives input from a few degrees of the
visual field. As a result what we consider to be a uniform scene in our
minds is actually a patchwork of intersaccade snapshots.
Another aspect of saccades is that the timing of events is referred back
to the beginning of the saccade. This effect is known as \"saccadic
chronostasis\". For example, if an object changes colour during a
saccade the observer feels as if the colour change occurred at the
beginning of the saccade, so extending the amount of time that the
object possesses the changed colour. This effect can extend apparent
durations by up to 500 ms and is consistent with the idea that the
visual system models events prior to perception (see Yarrow *et al.*
2006).
Burr D, Morrone M, Ross J. (1996) Selective suppression of the
magnocellular visual pathway during saccades\]\'\', Behavioral Brain
Research 80 1-8 (1996)
<http://www.pisavisionlab.org/downloads/BBRReview96.pdf>
Volkman, F. (1962). Vision during voluntary saccadic eye movements. J.
Opt Soc. Am. 52:571-578. 1962.
Yarrow, K, Whiteley, L, Rothwell, J.C & Haggard,P. (2006) Spatial
consequences of bridging the saccadic gap. Vision Res. 2006 February;
46(4): 545--555.
<http://www.hexicon.co.uk/Kielan/papers/Moving_chrono.pdf>
## Blindsight
Blindsight studies illuminate the relationship between the cerebral
cortex and our experience. When the visual cortex is removed subjects
become almost totally blind. If the visual cortex on one side is removed
subjects become relatively blind in the contra-lateral hemifield. One of
the most revealing studies of blindsight is Marcel\'s 1998 paper: \"
Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of visual consciousness or
visual function?\".
It is useful when considering blindsight to contemplate for a while the
appearance of the world with both eyes closed and then with one eye
closed. When both eyes are closed our experience is of a darkish space
radiating out from our heads, with one eye closed we tend to ignore the
darkish areas that cannot be seen even though they are still present.
Marcel notes that patients who have a right blind field still have an
underlying visual field on the right side and that this can even contain
conscious visual experience. This sounds a bit like the darkish space
that we all experience if deprived of visual input on one side. As
Marcel says: \"A question that naturally arises is whether the loss is a
\'total\' loss of visual consciousness in the blind field. It is often
assumed to be so, especially by those who discuss blindsight without
carefully reading the literature or working with the subjects. One can
immediately respond negatively to the question..\"
The consciousness of the completion of Kanizsa figures in blindsight
patients is particularly indicative of the preservation of the field
even though the content was largely missing. A Kanizsa figure is shown
below:
![](Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg "Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg")
If we put Marcel\'s observations together with cortical anatomy and
function it seems that the space of our experience is located outside of
the cerebral cortex. The cortex generates much of visual and other
content but it does not generate the space.
## The Role of the Thalamus
The thalamus is connected to the entire bottom layer of the cerebral
cortex. It is the nexus of the various cortical processors as well as a
recipient of independent input from most of the rest of the brain.
![](Constudbrain.png "Constudbrain.png")
The thalamus is subdivided into numerous small and medium sized nuclei
that between them receive inputs from every process in the nervous
system (the white fibres in the illustration above largely penetrate the
thalamus). The thalamic nuclei are interconnected which means that any
of them could, potentially host activity from anywhere in the body or
brain. Although the founders of neurology such as Hughlings Jackson and
Penfield & Jasper located conscious experience in the diencephalon,
including the thalamus, this is no longer the conventional wisdom. The
small size of the thalamic nuclei means that they cannot support the
processes that are assumed to compose access consciousness, however,
even some of the smallest thalamic nuclei host millions of synapses so
size would not be an obstacle if the thalamus contains the substrate of
phenomenal consciousness. Indeed, the diencephalon and the thalamus in
particular can be shown to be excellent candidates for a possible
location of phenomenal experience.
![](constudintralam.jpg "constudintralam.jpg")
`<font size=1>`{=html} The Intralaminar Nuclei of the thalamus. The
white space above and to the left of RN is the third ventricle.
MD=mediodorsal nucleus. CM=Centromedian nucleus, RN=red nucleus (not
part of thalamus) The black areas are stained white fibres. Picture
from: <http://www.neurophys.wisc.edu/> University of Wisconsin and
Michigan State Comparative Mammalian Brain Collections. Preparation of
image has been funded by the National Science Foundation, as well as by
the National Institutes of Health. May only be used with these
acknowledgements.`</font>`{=html}
If the thalamus contains a location for conscious experience then
lesions should abolish this experience. Unlike the cerebral hemispheres,
lesions of the thalamus do indeed seem to abolish consciousness. The
area that is most sensitive to lesions contains the Intralaminar Nuclei,
especially the Parafascicular and Centromedian Nuclei. If these are
damaged bilaterally patients suffer death, coma, akinetic mutism,
hypersomnia, dementia and other equally serious impairments of
consciousness that depend upon the size and placement of the lesions
(Bogen 1995, Schiff & Plum 1999). In cases of fatal familial insomnia,
in which patients exhibit many of these symptoms, there is marked neuron
loss in the Intralaminar Nuclei (Budka 1998).
The effect of interrupting the blood supply to the medial thalamus
depends upon the severity of the damage. There is frequently initial
coma. The recovery after coma is often incomplete, Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) described bilateral paramedian thalamic infarcts as normally
being \"followed by persisting dementia with severe mnemic disturbance,
global aspontaneity and apathy.\" The symptoms of bilateral damage to
the ILN can be so severe that it is possible that, even after recovery
from coma, some patients may cease to be conscious and are being
coordinated by automatic cortical processes.
Bjornstad *et al.* (2003) and Woernera *et al.* (2005) both reported
that the initial coma after bilateral paramedian infarct was accompanied
by a similar pattern of EEG activity to stage 2 sleep. Woernera *et al.*
(2005) also discovered that painful stimuli gave rise to a range of EEG
activity, transiently breaking the stage 2 sleep pattern but without
recovery of consciousness. Unfortunately even in those patients who
recover consciousness Kumral *et al.* (2001) report that \"Cognitive
functions in patients with bilateral paramedian infarction did not
change significantly during the follow-up, in contrast to those with
infarcts in varied arterial territories\" although Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) did report a single patient who made a total recovery.
Laureys *et al.* (2002) investigated recovery from \'persistent
vegetative state\' (wakefulness without awareness). They found that
overall cortical metabolism remained almost constant during recovery but
that the metabolism in the prefrontal and association cortices became
correlated with thalamic ILN and precuneus activity. Again confirming
that thalamo-cortico-thalamic activity is required for consciousness and
that cortical activity by itself is not conscious. Yamamoto *et al.*
(2005) investigated persistent vegetative state and found that deep
brain stimulation (25Hz) of the centromedian-parafascicular complex (19
cases) or mesencephalic reticular formation (2 cases) resulted in 8 of
the patients emerging from persistent vegetative state. It is
interesting that zolpidem, a GABA agonist, has recently been found to
reverse PVS in some patients (Claus & Nel 2006). The effect is rapid and
might be used to demonstrate the correlations that occur on recovery
from PVS.
As Bogen(1995) demonstrates, the ILN receive inputs, either directly or
indirectly, from every part of the CNS but what do they do?
Interest in the thalamus has recently been revived by the theories of
Newman & Baars (1993), Baars, Newman, & Taylor1998) and Crick & Koch
(1990). In Baars, Newman and Taylors\' (1998) theory it is suggested
that \"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not
the detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\".
They also propose that the \"nucleus reticularis thalami\" (Thalamic
Reticular Nucleus, TRN), which is a thin sheet of neurons that covers
the thalamus, is involved in a selective attention system. This concept
is reinforced by the way that point stimulation of the TRN causes focal
activity in the overlying cortex (MacDonald *et al.* 1998) and the way
the TRN is organised topographically (i.e.: has activity that is like an
electrical image of receptor fields).
The thalamus is ideally placed for integrating brain activity, if tiny
parts of the thalamus are removed consciousness is abolished and the
thalamus is involved in attention and the global integration of cortical
activity. Any impartial judge might pronounce that the site of conscious
experience has been found, possibly in the ILN of the thalamus, but no
one can say how it works.
## General Anaesthesia and the Thalamus
General anaesthesia should result in a profound depression of activity
in the ILN if these are indeed the sites of the conscious state. White &
Alkire (2003) administered halothane or isoflurane to volunteers and
used positron emission tomography (PET) to monitor brain activity. They
found severe depression of activity in the thalamus. The depression
appeared to be higher in the non-specific nuclei than in the relay
nuclei of the thalamus. In other words the anaesthesia is neither
turning off the cortex nor turning off the input to the cortex but it is
turning off an important part of the thalamus. Fiset *et al.* (1999)
have also demonstrated a similar pattern of medial thalamic inactivity
and cortical activity in propofol anaesthesia. Suppression of cortical
activity is not the cause of unconsciousness; for instance, the
anaesthetic agent chloralose leads to increased neural activity in the
cortex relative to conscious patients (Cariani 2000).
## The function of consciousness
When we walk our conscious experience does not contain data about the
control of the spinal, cerebellar and vestibular reflexes that keep us
on an even keel. When we reach out for a cup our conscious experience
only contains data related to the need for the cup, not data about the
elaborate control system that enables the action. When we talk the words
just come into mind, we do not painstakingly control the syntax and
vocal chords. When our attention shifts the conscious experience
containing the shift happens after the attention has shifted. This
passive nature of experience recurs throughout the neuroscience of
consciousness from the \"readiness potential\" to the \"auditory
continuity illusion\". So what does conscious observation do? The
medical evidence of the lack of consciousness in some forms of delirium,
mutism, PVS etc. suggest that the role of conscious observation is to
stabilise the brain so that it acts as a coordinated whole. Conscious
observation is an orderly arrangement of events, a stable groundform
that reflects the environment and composes the stage for action. It
could be speculated that if quantum events were prominent in brain
function then such a groundform would be essential but even a classical
brain might require a stabilising form that could be continuously
compared with the world beyond the body.
A stable form of neural information that contains bound data from the
senses and internal neural processes is likely to have a role in the
functioning of the organism. There is now an *integration consensus*
that proposes that phenomenal states somehow integrate neural activities
and information-processing that would otherwise be independent (see
review in Baars, 2002).
However, it has remained unspecified which kinds of information are
integrated in a conscious manner and which kinds can be integrated
without consciousness. Obviously not all kinds of information are
capable of being disseminated consciously (e.g., neural activity related
to vegetative functions, reflexes, unconscious motor programs, low-level
perceptual analyses, etc.) and many kinds can be disseminated and
combined with other kinds without consciousness, as in intersensory
interactions such as the ventriloquism effect.
Morsella (2005) proposed a *Supramodular Interaction Theory* (SIT) that
contrasts the task demands of consciously penetrable processes (e.g.:
those that can be part of conscious experience such as pain, conflicting
urges, and the delay of gratification) and consciously impenetrable
processes (e.g.: intersensory conflicts, peristalsis, and the pupillary
reflex). With this contrastive approach, SIT builds upon the integration
consensus by specifying which kinds of interaction require conscious
processing and which kinds do not (e.g., some intersensory processes).
SIT proposes that conscious processes are required to integrate
high-level systems in the brain that are vying for (specifically)
skeletomotor control, as described by the principle of *parallel
responses into skeletal muscle* (PRISM). Accordingly, regarding
processes such as digestion and excretion, one is conscious of only
those phases of the processes that require coordination with
skeletomotor plans (e.g., chewing or micturating) and none of those that
do not (e.g., peristalsis). From this standpoint, consciousness
functions above the level of the traditional module to "cross-talk"
among high-level, specialized and often multi-modal, systems.
**References**
Baars, B. J. (2002). The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent
evidence. *Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6,* 47 -- 52.
Morsella, E. (2005). The function of phenomenal states: Supramodular
interaction theory. *Psychological Review, 112,* 1000 - 1021.
More\... Click here for Rivalries and synchronisation, bibliography
and references
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 1#General Anaesthesia and the Thalamus
## The cortex and consciousness
The cerebral cortex consists of a set of specialised areas that process
different aspects of sensation and motor control. There are about ten
times as many nerve fibres going from the cortex to the thalamus as
there are from the thalamus to the cortex (Destexhe 2000).
![](constudconn.gif "constudconn.gif")
Histologically the cerebral cortex is a layer of greyish neurons
overlying a huge mass of white nerve fibres, the cerebral medulla. The
cortex consists of six main layers. The upper layers receive input from
the relays in the thalamus such as the lateral geniculate, from the
thalamus in general and from other areas of cortex plus a few
specialised inputs from other locations. The lower layers give rise to
output fibres that largely connect with the thalamus and other areas of
cortex although particular specialised processors in the cortex may also
have direct connections elsewhere such as to motor nuclei.
![](Constudcortex2.png "Constudcortex2.png")
The cerebral cortex has many functions and is divided up into numerous
separate processors. The most important function of the cortex from the
point of view of consciousness studies is that it creates models. As was
seen in Part I, philosophers debate whether these models are actually
experienced consciously but in the neurophysiological literature it is
normally assumed that we do experience models and rehearsals such as
inner speech and imaginings. There is considerable evidence that the
parts of the brain that deal with imagining (modelling) things are also
the parts that deal with perception (i.e.: modelling the world). The
overlap between imagination and normal perception is not complete
because, as Tong(2003), in a review of visual consciousness, put it:
\"Internally generated experiences share some, but not all, of the
phenomenal properties of actual perception\". There is also considerable
overlap between the areas used for imaginary speech (thought) and actual
speech, areas dealing with the control of sensation and of the tongue
etc. being used in actual speech but not in imagined speech (Fu *et al.*
2002). Kreiman *et al.* (2000) investigated the activity of single
neurons in humans and also found that the brain activity evoked by
visual imagination overlapped that which occurs upon direct stimulation
by the same image.
Our conscious experience consists of the output of the cortical
modelling and perceptual processes. The cerebral cortex itself appears
to be non-conscious. The evidence for the non-conscious nature of the
cerebral cortex consists of lesion studies in which large amounts of
cortex can be removed without removing consciousness and physiological
studies in which it is demonstrated that the cerebral cortex can be
active without conscious experience.
Lesion studies have shown that up to 60% of the cerebral cortex can be
removed without abolishing consciousness (Austin and Grant 1958). An
entire hemisphere can be removed or much of the front or back of the
cerebral cortex can be cut off yet consciousness persists.
Fiset *et al.* (1999) and Cariani (2000) have shown that cortical
activity can be normal or even elevated during the unconscious state of
general anaesthesia. Alkire *et al.* (1996) also showed that cortical
activity related to word recognition occurred during general
anaesthesia.
Libet *et al.* (1967) found that there could be cerebral cortical
activity in response to weak stimulation of the skin without any
conscious awareness of the stimulus. This work provides a
neurophysiological basis for subliminal (non-conscious) perception and
also shows that large areas of the cerebral cortex can be active without
conscious experience. The insensitivity of experience to cortical
activity has been further confirmed by Libet *et al.* (1979). They
electrically stimulated the cerebral cortex of conscious patients and
discovered that the stimulus must be continued for about 0.5 seconds for
subjects to report a conscious experience of the stimulation. Libet\'s
findings have been analysed at length but there still appears to be a
0.25 to 0.5 secs delay (Klein 2002).
It has been demonstrated that cerebral cortical activity is not
synonymous with conscious experience but why should there be a delay of
up to 0.5 seconds or so between cortical stimulation and a conscious
percept? What is the cortex doing in the 0.5 seconds between the start
of stimulation and the report of awareness of the stimulation? It is
probably synchronising its various processors and creating a waking
dream, a structured set of events that accounts for the activity. The
synchronisation of cerebral cortical processes will be discussed later,
but what evidence is there for the cerebral cortex constructing a waking
dream, or model, to describe the world?
The \'Attentional Blink\' (Raymond *et al.* 1992) is consistent with the
concept of the cerebral cortex being a device that creates models. In
the \'Attentional Blink\' the identification of an object impairs the
identification of a second object that is presented within 0.5 seconds
of the first. Raymond *et al.* used a stream of letters (11 letters per
second) and the identification of a first letter impaired the
identification of a subsequent \'probe\' letter in the stream. If the
probe letter followed the first letter within about 180 msecs it could
easily be identified, suggesting that chunks of about 180 msecs of data
stream are modelled together. Christmann & Leuthold (2004) have
theorised that the \'Attentional Blink\' involves perceptual and central
components of visual processing. This is supported by the fMRI studies
of Marois *et al.* (2004) who presented subjects with faces mounted on
scenes of places. The scenes of places often went undetected by subjects
but they activated regions of the medial temporal cortex involved in
high-level scene representations, the parahippocampal place area (PPA).
When the scenes of places were detected by the subjects there was
activity in the frontal cortex and the PPA activity was increased. These
experiments are consistent with the idea of a cerebral cortex that is a
multiprocessor system that creates consistent models of the environment.
Bregman\'s (1990) auditory continuity illusion is another example of how
sensory events are modelled. If a pure tone is followed by broadband
noise and the noise followed by the same pure tone it seems as if the
tone occurs throughout the period of noise. If the noise is not followed
by the pure tone there is no sound of the tone during the period of
noise. This effect is similar to the results found by Libet because a
delay of several hundred milliseconds between sensory stimulation and
conscious experience is needed to account for the apparent rewriting of
history after the second tone appears.
Dennett and Kinsbourne (1992) argued strongly against modelling as the
source of conscious experience. They discussed two illusions, the
\"cutaneous rabbit illusion\", in which the subject is tapped
successively in such a way that some illusory taps appear and the \"phi
illusion\" in which successively illuminated lights appear as a motion
of the light. Dennett and Kinsbourne declared that there should be no
cerebral cortical filling in of the gaps in the these illusions. Both
these illusions have now been investigated. Blankenburg *et al.* (2006)
found that cerebral cortical activity occurred at the locations expected
for the missing taps in the \"cutaneous rabbit\" illusion and Larsen *et
al.* (2006) found that the areas of cerebral cortex that would be
stimulated by a moving light were active during the \"phi illusion\".
## The delay before consciousness of \"voluntary\" actions
The 0.5 second delay required for the cortex to model an event has
implications for the role of conscious experience in the control of our
lives. If experience is about 0.5 seconds behind the true present
instant then how can we be said to control anything? The brain must be
acting automatically whilst performing most tasks. The 0.5 second delay
also seems to contradict our everyday experience. We certainly feel like
we are aware of things in less than 0.5 seconds, for example, the direct
stimulation of sense organs seems to be experienced much more rapidly
than the delayed experience of cortical stimulation. In fact subjects
report that they are conscious of stimuli, such as being touched or
seeing flashing lights, within 0.1 to 0.2 seconds of the event. So how
can subjects report events within 0.2 seconds even though it seems to
take 0.5 seconds for the cortex to generate activity that can be
experienced? The simplest explanation is that the reaction occurs
automatically within 0.2 seconds and then the conscious experience of
this reaction occurs 0.3 seconds later. This gives a total 0.5 seconds
delay before conscious experience whilst allowing fast reactions.
Libet *et al.* extended their experiments by stimulating a \"relay
nucleus\" in the thalamus that intercepts signals from the senses before
they reach the somatosensory cortex. It was found that when this nucleus
was stimulated for 0.5 seconds the subjects reported that the stimulus
occurred 0.2 seconds after it had begun. When the nucleus was stimulated
for less than 0.5 seconds the subjects did not report any sensation.
This supports the concept of a 0.5 second delay whilst the cortex puts a
stimulus in context before it is experienced.
These experiments show that our experience is an output of cortical
processing rather than the processing itself. If our conscious
experience is non-cortical then this raises the possibility that the
non-conscious cerebral cortex can perform actions without conscious
control. Of course, the cortex does this all the time when we are
indulging in skilled or routine behaviour. The ability of the
non-conscious cortex is quite remarkable; for instance car drivers
sometimes discover that they have driven for several miles without
conscious experience of driving, even at the level of having no
recollection of the route.
!Typical recording of the readiness
potential.{width="150"}Although
it might be accepted that much of our everyday behaviour is automatic is
there any behaviour that is definitely initiated by conscious
experience? This is probably a pointless question because consciousness
is about observation, not action; however, despite this there have been
several experiments that have attempted to determine the relationship
between consciousness and action.
In 1964 Kornhuber and Deecke performed a series of experiments that
measured the electrical activity from the scalp (EEG) during voluntary
actions. They averaged many EEG\'s from subjects who were about to move
a finger and discovered that there is an increase in scalp potential
before the movement takes place. The increase in potential can start as
long as 2 seconds or so before the movement and is known as the
\"readiness potential\" (Bereitschaftspotential). The readiness
potential is strange because it seems to contradict our conscious
experience; we do not decide to move a hand and then wait 2 seconds
before the hand moves. It seems that the non-conscious brain may be
taking things into its own hands.
Libet *et al.* (1983) extended the readiness potential experiments by
asking subjects to observe a Wundt clock whilst flexing a finger. The
Wundt clock had a spot of light that moved around a circle every 2.56
seconds and allowed the subjects to obtain timings that were related to
their mental experiences. When the subjects flexed a finger it was found
that the readiness potential occurred about 0.5 seconds before the
finger moved and the subjects reported they were going to move the
finger about 0.2 seconds before the movement. This suggested that a
subject\'s cerebral cortex was preparing for the movement about 0.3
seconds before the subject was conscious of this. Libet\'s experiments
have been reproduced elsewhere (see Keller & Heckhausen 1990). (It is
important to note that the subjects in Libet\'s experiment were asked to
wait until they felt the urge to move the finger.) These results are
consistent with the idea of the cortex as a modelling system that
constructs a consistent model of events to pass on to whatever mediates
conscious experience.
More recently fMRI and direct electrode recording have borne out the
readiness potential experiments. Soon *et al.* (2008) allowed subjects
to decide to press either a left or right button. They used fMRI to show
that there was spatially organised activity in the polar frontal cortex
and parietal cortex (from precuneus into posterior cingulate cortex)
that predicted the conscious left/right decision and preceded it by
about **seven seconds**. Rektor *et al.* (2001) used direct electrode
recordings to show a 2 second latency. Haggard & Eimer (1999) and also
Trevena and Miller (2002, 2009) have identified a \"Lateralized
Readiness Potential\" that is correlated with the movement of a
particular hand (left or right) in their EEG experiments and Trevena and
Miller claim that this potential always follows the making of a
conscious decision and precedes the actions being studied. However, Soon
*et al.* (2008) showed that fMRI can predict which button will be used
well before any conscious decision is reported. (See Haggard (2008) for
a review of conscious volition).
## Perception, Imagination, Memory and Dreams
### More about Models
Our dreams are clearly models that form a \'dreamworld\' but the idea
that perception might be like a dream that is updated by sensation is
not so obvious. Experience seems to be an active model of the world
(virtual reality) based on sense data rather than a simple mapping of
retinal and other sensory data. This is demonstrated by visual illusions
such as the Ames Room, Spoke Illusion and Muller Lyer illusions shown
below:
![](Constudame.png "Constudame.png")
Notice how the circle is distorted without any distortion in the
\'spokes\', it is as if the circle has been treated as a separate object
by the processes in the brain that rearranged it. In all of these
illusions the brain has rearranged large areas of the visual field and
has managed the input as a collection of \'objects\' that are
manipulated separately. Even movement seems to occur in some figures
showing that the brain models the position of things:
![](Constudcafe.png "Constudcafe.png")
The creation of a model is also demonstrated by the illusion of movement
experienced when we watch the cinema or television. This is due to the
cortical modelling that is known as \'short-range apparent motion\'
rather than flicker fusion or persistence of vision. It is intriguing
that, although it has been known for decades that the joining together
of static images in our minds is due to modelling activity in the brain
the myth that it is due to persistence of vision or flicker fusion is
universal. As Anderson and Anderson (1993) noted:
`Indeed, in the past decade, psychoanalytic-Marxist film scholars `\
`have retained the model implied by persistence of vision: theirs `\
`is a passive viewer, a spectator who is "positioned," unwittingly `\
`"sutured" into the text, and victimized by excess ideology.`
Our experience of the cinema is like a dream updated by sensation rather
than sensation updated by interpretation. In fact the most compelling
evidence for the modelling power of the brain is the existence of
dreams; our dreams are often models of worlds that do not exist and
involve little or no sensory input yet can involve effects as powerful
as any television drama.
Short range apparent motion occurs when the interval between
presentations of an object is brief (c. 50-100 msecs). Motion modelling
in response to longer intervals is known as long range apparent motion.
There is evidence that the modelling in short range apparent motion is
enhanced if the moving patterns are similar to moving human forms (such
as patterns of dots outlining a person)(Thornton *et al.* 1998). The
accuracy of predicting movement can actually improve if the interval
between presentations is increased when human forms are used.
Motion modelling can also be seen in visual illusions such as the
*Waterfall Illusion* (motion aftereffect). The waterfall illusion is
commonly seen after viewing a sequence of scrolling credits on the
television; when the credits stop rolling it appears as if they briefly
move in the opposite direction. Tootel *et al.* (1995) have used fMRI to
show that this is correlated with activity in the motion modelling area
of visual cortex (area MT/V5). The waterfall illusion is also associated
with an intriguing aftereffect known as **storage of the motion
aftereffect**. Normal motion aftereffects last for up to about ten
seconds after the stimulus, however, if the subjects close their eyes
for the normal duration of the aftereffect then reopen them they see the
illusion for almost the normal duration. Culham *et al.* (1999) used
fMRI to show that activity in area MT/V5 was low during the period when
the eyes were closed then increased dramatically when the eyes were
opened. This is strongly suggestive of a modelling mechanism outside
MT/V5 that has adapted to motion and then models stationary data with
movement in the wrong direction.
Visual area MT/V5 is also involved in the separation of moving visual
scenes into *sprites* or objects that move together as a whole within a
scene (Muckli *et al.* 2002).
The way that mental models may be the basis of ordinary reasoning was
outlined by Johnson-Laird (1980), based on earlier work by Kenneth
Craik.
Studies of \'change blindness\' and \'inattentional blindness\', where
subjects fail to spot outrageous changes in their environment, also
demonstrate that we experience a model and suggest that the brain must
analyse an object to incorporate it fully into the model (See for
instance Rensink (2000), Simons & Rensink (2005)).
### Brain areas used in perception overlap those used in imagination and recall
Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI) has shown that similar
areas of brain are used during perception involving the senses as during
imagination (Tong 2003, Kosslyn and Thompson 2003). The substrate of the
mental images that occur in both modes of brain activity has not yet
been found. This overlap of the brain areas used in perception with
those used in imagination, memory and recall has been demonstrated in a
wide range of experiments.
Ganis *et al.* (2004) used fairly complex perceptual and imagination
tasks that activated large areas of the brain, they found an overlap
between the brain areas activated during perception and imagery. The
principle areas that were different in the two tasks were found in the
primary sensory areas of the visual cortex. Other areas in the visual
cortex and activity in the rest of the brain showed a remarkable degree
of overlap. The authors suggested that the differences in the activity
of primary visual cortex may have been due to differences between the
perceptual and imaginary stimuli such as speed of onset etc. The
hippocampus was not activated.
It is intriguing that, contrary to object imagery, spatial imagery such
as predicting when a cross on a screen would fall on an imaginary letter
actually seems to inhibit activity in sensory visual cortex (Aleman *et
al.*). Both fMRI and blocking with transcranial magnetic stimulation
(TMS) showed that the posterior parietal cortex was involved in the
spatial imagery.
Imagery involving places and faces activates the place and face areas
that are activated during perception (Ishai *et al.* 2000).
The recall and recognition of things also seems to involve very similar
brain areas to those used during perception. Wheeler and Buckner (2003)
showed that areas involved in perception were also involved in the
recall of the perceptual stimuli.
Recall causes activation of areas used in perception but also seems to
use areas that may be particularly related to the process of recall
iself, such as the left parietal cortex (Konishi *et al.* 2000)
(Brodmann\'s area 40/39). Frontal and parietal regions are involved in
the recognition of whether stimuli have been experienced before.
Image generation during sleep seems to differ from that during
imagination and recall. In particular it seems to involve a few well
defined areas of cortex and considerable activation of the posterior
thalamus.
Sleep studies have shown that people dream throughout sleep. However,
dreams are more frequent during the REM (rapid eye movement) periods of
sleep than the NREM (non-REM) periods. Dreams are reported after 70-95%
of awakenings in REM sleep and 5-10% of awakenings in NREM sleep. REM
dreams are more visual than NREM dreams which are more \'thoughtlike\'
(Solms 2000). Thoughtlike events (mentation) are reported after 43% of
awakenings from NREM sleep.
Solms (1997) found that patients who had lesions in the
parietal-temporo-occipital junction reported a cessation of visual
images in dreams. Solms also found that patients with lesions in the
white matter inferior to the frontal horns of the lateral ventricles, in
the ventromesial quadrant of the frontal lobes, also reported loss of
dreaming. Loss of dreaming is also reported by leucotomised patients
with frontal ventromesial damage. Damasio *et al.* (1985) and Solms
(1997) also reported that some patients with damage to the medial
prefrontal cortex, the anterior cingulate cortex, and the basal
forebrain became confused about what was real life and what was dreaming
(waking dreams occurred).
Studies using fMRI show that the sensory occipital lobe (BA 18) and
posterior thalamus, especially the lateral geniculate nuclei, are
activated in REM sleep, weaker activations of the posterior cingulate,
putamen and midbrain were also found (Wehrle *et al.* 2005, Loveblad *et
al.* 1999). These findings are consistent with activation of the
ponto-geniculo-occipital system (PGO) during REM.
So dreams may be more like primary activations of sensory cortex than
imagining or recall. This suggests that dreams have a thalamic origin or
are managed via connections from the cortex through the thalamus to the
visual cortex.
Hallucinations seem to differ from dreams. In Charles Bonnett Syndrome
patients can have clear hallucinations. These, like imaginations, seem
to involve areas of the visual cortex that deal with processed data, for
instance hallucinations of faces activate the \"face area\" rather than
visual cortical area V1 (Ffytche *et al.* 1998).
### Suppression of data acquisition during saccades - perception as a patchwork
If you look at yourself in the mirror you will not see your eyes moving
even though they will be darting all over the view of your face. Even
when you deliberately look from place to place your eyes will appear
steady. The natural darting of the eyes from place to place as you view
a scene is known as \"saccadic\" movement of the eyes. The suppression
of the visual image during the motion of the eyes is known as \"saccadic
suppression\" or \"saccadic masking\". The suppression of the
acquisition of image data extends to suppression of awareness of flashes
of light during saccades, this effect is known as \"flash suppression\",
however, flash suppression seems to apply only to rather dull flashes
(Volkman (1962). The suppression during saccades is probably due to
suppression of the magnocellular pathway (the motion sensitive pathway)
in the lateral geniculate nucleus (Burr *et al.* (1996).
The most intriguing feature of this suppression of data acquisition
during saccades is that each snapshot that is obtained between saccades
can only contain a relatively small amount of information. This is
because the fovea, which is the most sensitive area of the eye, is tiny
(about 1mm diameter) and only receives input from a few degrees of the
visual field. As a result what we consider to be a uniform scene in our
minds is actually a patchwork of intersaccade snapshots.
Another aspect of saccades is that the timing of events is referred back
to the beginning of the saccade. This effect is known as \"saccadic
chronostasis\". For example, if an object changes colour during a
saccade the observer feels as if the colour change occurred at the
beginning of the saccade, so extending the amount of time that the
object possesses the changed colour. This effect can extend apparent
durations by up to 500 ms and is consistent with the idea that the
visual system models events prior to perception (see Yarrow *et al.*
2006).
Burr D, Morrone M, Ross J. (1996) Selective suppression of the
magnocellular visual pathway during saccades\]\'\', Behavioral Brain
Research 80 1-8 (1996)
<http://www.pisavisionlab.org/downloads/BBRReview96.pdf>
Volkman, F. (1962). Vision during voluntary saccadic eye movements. J.
Opt Soc. Am. 52:571-578. 1962.
Yarrow, K, Whiteley, L, Rothwell, J.C & Haggard,P. (2006) Spatial
consequences of bridging the saccadic gap. Vision Res. 2006 February;
46(4): 545--555.
<http://www.hexicon.co.uk/Kielan/papers/Moving_chrono.pdf>
## Blindsight
Blindsight studies illuminate the relationship between the cerebral
cortex and our experience. When the visual cortex is removed subjects
become almost totally blind. If the visual cortex on one side is removed
subjects become relatively blind in the contra-lateral hemifield. One of
the most revealing studies of blindsight is Marcel\'s 1998 paper: \"
Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of visual consciousness or
visual function?\".
It is useful when considering blindsight to contemplate for a while the
appearance of the world with both eyes closed and then with one eye
closed. When both eyes are closed our experience is of a darkish space
radiating out from our heads, with one eye closed we tend to ignore the
darkish areas that cannot be seen even though they are still present.
Marcel notes that patients who have a right blind field still have an
underlying visual field on the right side and that this can even contain
conscious visual experience. This sounds a bit like the darkish space
that we all experience if deprived of visual input on one side. As
Marcel says: \"A question that naturally arises is whether the loss is a
\'total\' loss of visual consciousness in the blind field. It is often
assumed to be so, especially by those who discuss blindsight without
carefully reading the literature or working with the subjects. One can
immediately respond negatively to the question..\"
The consciousness of the completion of Kanizsa figures in blindsight
patients is particularly indicative of the preservation of the field
even though the content was largely missing. A Kanizsa figure is shown
below:
![](Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg "Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg")
If we put Marcel\'s observations together with cortical anatomy and
function it seems that the space of our experience is located outside of
the cerebral cortex. The cortex generates much of visual and other
content but it does not generate the space.
## The Role of the Thalamus
The thalamus is connected to the entire bottom layer of the cerebral
cortex. It is the nexus of the various cortical processors as well as a
recipient of independent input from most of the rest of the brain.
![](Constudbrain.png "Constudbrain.png")
The thalamus is subdivided into numerous small and medium sized nuclei
that between them receive inputs from every process in the nervous
system (the white fibres in the illustration above largely penetrate the
thalamus). The thalamic nuclei are interconnected which means that any
of them could, potentially host activity from anywhere in the body or
brain. Although the founders of neurology such as Hughlings Jackson and
Penfield & Jasper located conscious experience in the diencephalon,
including the thalamus, this is no longer the conventional wisdom. The
small size of the thalamic nuclei means that they cannot support the
processes that are assumed to compose access consciousness, however,
even some of the smallest thalamic nuclei host millions of synapses so
size would not be an obstacle if the thalamus contains the substrate of
phenomenal consciousness. Indeed, the diencephalon and the thalamus in
particular can be shown to be excellent candidates for a possible
location of phenomenal experience.
![](constudintralam.jpg "constudintralam.jpg")
`<font size=1>`{=html} The Intralaminar Nuclei of the thalamus. The
white space above and to the left of RN is the third ventricle.
MD=mediodorsal nucleus. CM=Centromedian nucleus, RN=red nucleus (not
part of thalamus) The black areas are stained white fibres. Picture
from: <http://www.neurophys.wisc.edu/> University of Wisconsin and
Michigan State Comparative Mammalian Brain Collections. Preparation of
image has been funded by the National Science Foundation, as well as by
the National Institutes of Health. May only be used with these
acknowledgements.`</font>`{=html}
If the thalamus contains a location for conscious experience then
lesions should abolish this experience. Unlike the cerebral hemispheres,
lesions of the thalamus do indeed seem to abolish consciousness. The
area that is most sensitive to lesions contains the Intralaminar Nuclei,
especially the Parafascicular and Centromedian Nuclei. If these are
damaged bilaterally patients suffer death, coma, akinetic mutism,
hypersomnia, dementia and other equally serious impairments of
consciousness that depend upon the size and placement of the lesions
(Bogen 1995, Schiff & Plum 1999). In cases of fatal familial insomnia,
in which patients exhibit many of these symptoms, there is marked neuron
loss in the Intralaminar Nuclei (Budka 1998).
The effect of interrupting the blood supply to the medial thalamus
depends upon the severity of the damage. There is frequently initial
coma. The recovery after coma is often incomplete, Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) described bilateral paramedian thalamic infarcts as normally
being \"followed by persisting dementia with severe mnemic disturbance,
global aspontaneity and apathy.\" The symptoms of bilateral damage to
the ILN can be so severe that it is possible that, even after recovery
from coma, some patients may cease to be conscious and are being
coordinated by automatic cortical processes.
Bjornstad *et al.* (2003) and Woernera *et al.* (2005) both reported
that the initial coma after bilateral paramedian infarct was accompanied
by a similar pattern of EEG activity to stage 2 sleep. Woernera *et al.*
(2005) also discovered that painful stimuli gave rise to a range of EEG
activity, transiently breaking the stage 2 sleep pattern but without
recovery of consciousness. Unfortunately even in those patients who
recover consciousness Kumral *et al.* (2001) report that \"Cognitive
functions in patients with bilateral paramedian infarction did not
change significantly during the follow-up, in contrast to those with
infarcts in varied arterial territories\" although Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) did report a single patient who made a total recovery.
Laureys *et al.* (2002) investigated recovery from \'persistent
vegetative state\' (wakefulness without awareness). They found that
overall cortical metabolism remained almost constant during recovery but
that the metabolism in the prefrontal and association cortices became
correlated with thalamic ILN and precuneus activity. Again confirming
that thalamo-cortico-thalamic activity is required for consciousness and
that cortical activity by itself is not conscious. Yamamoto *et al.*
(2005) investigated persistent vegetative state and found that deep
brain stimulation (25Hz) of the centromedian-parafascicular complex (19
cases) or mesencephalic reticular formation (2 cases) resulted in 8 of
the patients emerging from persistent vegetative state. It is
interesting that zolpidem, a GABA agonist, has recently been found to
reverse PVS in some patients (Claus & Nel 2006). The effect is rapid and
might be used to demonstrate the correlations that occur on recovery
from PVS.
As Bogen(1995) demonstrates, the ILN receive inputs, either directly or
indirectly, from every part of the CNS but what do they do?
Interest in the thalamus has recently been revived by the theories of
Newman & Baars (1993), Baars, Newman, & Taylor1998) and Crick & Koch
(1990). In Baars, Newman and Taylors\' (1998) theory it is suggested
that \"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not
the detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\".
They also propose that the \"nucleus reticularis thalami\" (Thalamic
Reticular Nucleus, TRN), which is a thin sheet of neurons that covers
the thalamus, is involved in a selective attention system. This concept
is reinforced by the way that point stimulation of the TRN causes focal
activity in the overlying cortex (MacDonald *et al.* 1998) and the way
the TRN is organised topographically (i.e.: has activity that is like an
electrical image of receptor fields).
The thalamus is ideally placed for integrating brain activity, if tiny
parts of the thalamus are removed consciousness is abolished and the
thalamus is involved in attention and the global integration of cortical
activity. Any impartial judge might pronounce that the site of conscious
experience has been found, possibly in the ILN of the thalamus, but no
one can say how it works.
## General Anaesthesia and the Thalamus
General anaesthesia should result in a profound depression of activity
in the ILN if these are indeed the sites of the conscious state. White &
Alkire (2003) administered halothane or isoflurane to volunteers and
used positron emission tomography (PET) to monitor brain activity. They
found severe depression of activity in the thalamus. The depression
appeared to be higher in the non-specific nuclei than in the relay
nuclei of the thalamus. In other words the anaesthesia is neither
turning off the cortex nor turning off the input to the cortex but it is
turning off an important part of the thalamus. Fiset *et al.* (1999)
have also demonstrated a similar pattern of medial thalamic inactivity
and cortical activity in propofol anaesthesia. Suppression of cortical
activity is not the cause of unconsciousness; for instance, the
anaesthetic agent chloralose leads to increased neural activity in the
cortex relative to conscious patients (Cariani 2000).
## The function of consciousness
When we walk our conscious experience does not contain data about the
control of the spinal, cerebellar and vestibular reflexes that keep us
on an even keel. When we reach out for a cup our conscious experience
only contains data related to the need for the cup, not data about the
elaborate control system that enables the action. When we talk the words
just come into mind, we do not painstakingly control the syntax and
vocal chords. When our attention shifts the conscious experience
containing the shift happens after the attention has shifted. This
passive nature of experience recurs throughout the neuroscience of
consciousness from the \"readiness potential\" to the \"auditory
continuity illusion\". So what does conscious observation do? The
medical evidence of the lack of consciousness in some forms of delirium,
mutism, PVS etc. suggest that the role of conscious observation is to
stabilise the brain so that it acts as a coordinated whole. Conscious
observation is an orderly arrangement of events, a stable groundform
that reflects the environment and composes the stage for action. It
could be speculated that if quantum events were prominent in brain
function then such a groundform would be essential but even a classical
brain might require a stabilising form that could be continuously
compared with the world beyond the body.
A stable form of neural information that contains bound data from the
senses and internal neural processes is likely to have a role in the
functioning of the organism. There is now an *integration consensus*
that proposes that phenomenal states somehow integrate neural activities
and information-processing that would otherwise be independent (see
review in Baars, 2002).
However, it has remained unspecified which kinds of information are
integrated in a conscious manner and which kinds can be integrated
without consciousness. Obviously not all kinds of information are
capable of being disseminated consciously (e.g., neural activity related
to vegetative functions, reflexes, unconscious motor programs, low-level
perceptual analyses, etc.) and many kinds can be disseminated and
combined with other kinds without consciousness, as in intersensory
interactions such as the ventriloquism effect.
Morsella (2005) proposed a *Supramodular Interaction Theory* (SIT) that
contrasts the task demands of consciously penetrable processes (e.g.:
those that can be part of conscious experience such as pain, conflicting
urges, and the delay of gratification) and consciously impenetrable
processes (e.g.: intersensory conflicts, peristalsis, and the pupillary
reflex). With this contrastive approach, SIT builds upon the integration
consensus by specifying which kinds of interaction require conscious
processing and which kinds do not (e.g., some intersensory processes).
SIT proposes that conscious processes are required to integrate
high-level systems in the brain that are vying for (specifically)
skeletomotor control, as described by the principle of *parallel
responses into skeletal muscle* (PRISM). Accordingly, regarding
processes such as digestion and excretion, one is conscious of only
those phases of the processes that require coordination with
skeletomotor plans (e.g., chewing or micturating) and none of those that
do not (e.g., peristalsis). From this standpoint, consciousness
functions above the level of the traditional module to "cross-talk"
among high-level, specialized and often multi-modal, systems.
**References**
Baars, B. J. (2002). The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent
evidence. *Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6,* 47 -- 52.
Morsella, E. (2005). The function of phenomenal states: Supramodular
interaction theory. *Psychological Review, 112,* 1000 - 1021.
More\... Click here for Rivalries and synchronisation, bibliography
and references
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 1#The function of consciousness
## The cortex and consciousness
The cerebral cortex consists of a set of specialised areas that process
different aspects of sensation and motor control. There are about ten
times as many nerve fibres going from the cortex to the thalamus as
there are from the thalamus to the cortex (Destexhe 2000).
![](constudconn.gif "constudconn.gif")
Histologically the cerebral cortex is a layer of greyish neurons
overlying a huge mass of white nerve fibres, the cerebral medulla. The
cortex consists of six main layers. The upper layers receive input from
the relays in the thalamus such as the lateral geniculate, from the
thalamus in general and from other areas of cortex plus a few
specialised inputs from other locations. The lower layers give rise to
output fibres that largely connect with the thalamus and other areas of
cortex although particular specialised processors in the cortex may also
have direct connections elsewhere such as to motor nuclei.
![](Constudcortex2.png "Constudcortex2.png")
The cerebral cortex has many functions and is divided up into numerous
separate processors. The most important function of the cortex from the
point of view of consciousness studies is that it creates models. As was
seen in Part I, philosophers debate whether these models are actually
experienced consciously but in the neurophysiological literature it is
normally assumed that we do experience models and rehearsals such as
inner speech and imaginings. There is considerable evidence that the
parts of the brain that deal with imagining (modelling) things are also
the parts that deal with perception (i.e.: modelling the world). The
overlap between imagination and normal perception is not complete
because, as Tong(2003), in a review of visual consciousness, put it:
\"Internally generated experiences share some, but not all, of the
phenomenal properties of actual perception\". There is also considerable
overlap between the areas used for imaginary speech (thought) and actual
speech, areas dealing with the control of sensation and of the tongue
etc. being used in actual speech but not in imagined speech (Fu *et al.*
2002). Kreiman *et al.* (2000) investigated the activity of single
neurons in humans and also found that the brain activity evoked by
visual imagination overlapped that which occurs upon direct stimulation
by the same image.
Our conscious experience consists of the output of the cortical
modelling and perceptual processes. The cerebral cortex itself appears
to be non-conscious. The evidence for the non-conscious nature of the
cerebral cortex consists of lesion studies in which large amounts of
cortex can be removed without removing consciousness and physiological
studies in which it is demonstrated that the cerebral cortex can be
active without conscious experience.
Lesion studies have shown that up to 60% of the cerebral cortex can be
removed without abolishing consciousness (Austin and Grant 1958). An
entire hemisphere can be removed or much of the front or back of the
cerebral cortex can be cut off yet consciousness persists.
Fiset *et al.* (1999) and Cariani (2000) have shown that cortical
activity can be normal or even elevated during the unconscious state of
general anaesthesia. Alkire *et al.* (1996) also showed that cortical
activity related to word recognition occurred during general
anaesthesia.
Libet *et al.* (1967) found that there could be cerebral cortical
activity in response to weak stimulation of the skin without any
conscious awareness of the stimulus. This work provides a
neurophysiological basis for subliminal (non-conscious) perception and
also shows that large areas of the cerebral cortex can be active without
conscious experience. The insensitivity of experience to cortical
activity has been further confirmed by Libet *et al.* (1979). They
electrically stimulated the cerebral cortex of conscious patients and
discovered that the stimulus must be continued for about 0.5 seconds for
subjects to report a conscious experience of the stimulation. Libet\'s
findings have been analysed at length but there still appears to be a
0.25 to 0.5 secs delay (Klein 2002).
It has been demonstrated that cerebral cortical activity is not
synonymous with conscious experience but why should there be a delay of
up to 0.5 seconds or so between cortical stimulation and a conscious
percept? What is the cortex doing in the 0.5 seconds between the start
of stimulation and the report of awareness of the stimulation? It is
probably synchronising its various processors and creating a waking
dream, a structured set of events that accounts for the activity. The
synchronisation of cerebral cortical processes will be discussed later,
but what evidence is there for the cerebral cortex constructing a waking
dream, or model, to describe the world?
The \'Attentional Blink\' (Raymond *et al.* 1992) is consistent with the
concept of the cerebral cortex being a device that creates models. In
the \'Attentional Blink\' the identification of an object impairs the
identification of a second object that is presented within 0.5 seconds
of the first. Raymond *et al.* used a stream of letters (11 letters per
second) and the identification of a first letter impaired the
identification of a subsequent \'probe\' letter in the stream. If the
probe letter followed the first letter within about 180 msecs it could
easily be identified, suggesting that chunks of about 180 msecs of data
stream are modelled together. Christmann & Leuthold (2004) have
theorised that the \'Attentional Blink\' involves perceptual and central
components of visual processing. This is supported by the fMRI studies
of Marois *et al.* (2004) who presented subjects with faces mounted on
scenes of places. The scenes of places often went undetected by subjects
but they activated regions of the medial temporal cortex involved in
high-level scene representations, the parahippocampal place area (PPA).
When the scenes of places were detected by the subjects there was
activity in the frontal cortex and the PPA activity was increased. These
experiments are consistent with the idea of a cerebral cortex that is a
multiprocessor system that creates consistent models of the environment.
Bregman\'s (1990) auditory continuity illusion is another example of how
sensory events are modelled. If a pure tone is followed by broadband
noise and the noise followed by the same pure tone it seems as if the
tone occurs throughout the period of noise. If the noise is not followed
by the pure tone there is no sound of the tone during the period of
noise. This effect is similar to the results found by Libet because a
delay of several hundred milliseconds between sensory stimulation and
conscious experience is needed to account for the apparent rewriting of
history after the second tone appears.
Dennett and Kinsbourne (1992) argued strongly against modelling as the
source of conscious experience. They discussed two illusions, the
\"cutaneous rabbit illusion\", in which the subject is tapped
successively in such a way that some illusory taps appear and the \"phi
illusion\" in which successively illuminated lights appear as a motion
of the light. Dennett and Kinsbourne declared that there should be no
cerebral cortical filling in of the gaps in the these illusions. Both
these illusions have now been investigated. Blankenburg *et al.* (2006)
found that cerebral cortical activity occurred at the locations expected
for the missing taps in the \"cutaneous rabbit\" illusion and Larsen *et
al.* (2006) found that the areas of cerebral cortex that would be
stimulated by a moving light were active during the \"phi illusion\".
## The delay before consciousness of \"voluntary\" actions
The 0.5 second delay required for the cortex to model an event has
implications for the role of conscious experience in the control of our
lives. If experience is about 0.5 seconds behind the true present
instant then how can we be said to control anything? The brain must be
acting automatically whilst performing most tasks. The 0.5 second delay
also seems to contradict our everyday experience. We certainly feel like
we are aware of things in less than 0.5 seconds, for example, the direct
stimulation of sense organs seems to be experienced much more rapidly
than the delayed experience of cortical stimulation. In fact subjects
report that they are conscious of stimuli, such as being touched or
seeing flashing lights, within 0.1 to 0.2 seconds of the event. So how
can subjects report events within 0.2 seconds even though it seems to
take 0.5 seconds for the cortex to generate activity that can be
experienced? The simplest explanation is that the reaction occurs
automatically within 0.2 seconds and then the conscious experience of
this reaction occurs 0.3 seconds later. This gives a total 0.5 seconds
delay before conscious experience whilst allowing fast reactions.
Libet *et al.* extended their experiments by stimulating a \"relay
nucleus\" in the thalamus that intercepts signals from the senses before
they reach the somatosensory cortex. It was found that when this nucleus
was stimulated for 0.5 seconds the subjects reported that the stimulus
occurred 0.2 seconds after it had begun. When the nucleus was stimulated
for less than 0.5 seconds the subjects did not report any sensation.
This supports the concept of a 0.5 second delay whilst the cortex puts a
stimulus in context before it is experienced.
These experiments show that our experience is an output of cortical
processing rather than the processing itself. If our conscious
experience is non-cortical then this raises the possibility that the
non-conscious cerebral cortex can perform actions without conscious
control. Of course, the cortex does this all the time when we are
indulging in skilled or routine behaviour. The ability of the
non-conscious cortex is quite remarkable; for instance car drivers
sometimes discover that they have driven for several miles without
conscious experience of driving, even at the level of having no
recollection of the route.
!Typical recording of the readiness
potential.{width="150"}Although
it might be accepted that much of our everyday behaviour is automatic is
there any behaviour that is definitely initiated by conscious
experience? This is probably a pointless question because consciousness
is about observation, not action; however, despite this there have been
several experiments that have attempted to determine the relationship
between consciousness and action.
In 1964 Kornhuber and Deecke performed a series of experiments that
measured the electrical activity from the scalp (EEG) during voluntary
actions. They averaged many EEG\'s from subjects who were about to move
a finger and discovered that there is an increase in scalp potential
before the movement takes place. The increase in potential can start as
long as 2 seconds or so before the movement and is known as the
\"readiness potential\" (Bereitschaftspotential). The readiness
potential is strange because it seems to contradict our conscious
experience; we do not decide to move a hand and then wait 2 seconds
before the hand moves. It seems that the non-conscious brain may be
taking things into its own hands.
Libet *et al.* (1983) extended the readiness potential experiments by
asking subjects to observe a Wundt clock whilst flexing a finger. The
Wundt clock had a spot of light that moved around a circle every 2.56
seconds and allowed the subjects to obtain timings that were related to
their mental experiences. When the subjects flexed a finger it was found
that the readiness potential occurred about 0.5 seconds before the
finger moved and the subjects reported they were going to move the
finger about 0.2 seconds before the movement. This suggested that a
subject\'s cerebral cortex was preparing for the movement about 0.3
seconds before the subject was conscious of this. Libet\'s experiments
have been reproduced elsewhere (see Keller & Heckhausen 1990). (It is
important to note that the subjects in Libet\'s experiment were asked to
wait until they felt the urge to move the finger.) These results are
consistent with the idea of the cortex as a modelling system that
constructs a consistent model of events to pass on to whatever mediates
conscious experience.
More recently fMRI and direct electrode recording have borne out the
readiness potential experiments. Soon *et al.* (2008) allowed subjects
to decide to press either a left or right button. They used fMRI to show
that there was spatially organised activity in the polar frontal cortex
and parietal cortex (from precuneus into posterior cingulate cortex)
that predicted the conscious left/right decision and preceded it by
about **seven seconds**. Rektor *et al.* (2001) used direct electrode
recordings to show a 2 second latency. Haggard & Eimer (1999) and also
Trevena and Miller (2002, 2009) have identified a \"Lateralized
Readiness Potential\" that is correlated with the movement of a
particular hand (left or right) in their EEG experiments and Trevena and
Miller claim that this potential always follows the making of a
conscious decision and precedes the actions being studied. However, Soon
*et al.* (2008) showed that fMRI can predict which button will be used
well before any conscious decision is reported. (See Haggard (2008) for
a review of conscious volition).
## Perception, Imagination, Memory and Dreams
### More about Models
Our dreams are clearly models that form a \'dreamworld\' but the idea
that perception might be like a dream that is updated by sensation is
not so obvious. Experience seems to be an active model of the world
(virtual reality) based on sense data rather than a simple mapping of
retinal and other sensory data. This is demonstrated by visual illusions
such as the Ames Room, Spoke Illusion and Muller Lyer illusions shown
below:
![](Constudame.png "Constudame.png")
Notice how the circle is distorted without any distortion in the
\'spokes\', it is as if the circle has been treated as a separate object
by the processes in the brain that rearranged it. In all of these
illusions the brain has rearranged large areas of the visual field and
has managed the input as a collection of \'objects\' that are
manipulated separately. Even movement seems to occur in some figures
showing that the brain models the position of things:
![](Constudcafe.png "Constudcafe.png")
The creation of a model is also demonstrated by the illusion of movement
experienced when we watch the cinema or television. This is due to the
cortical modelling that is known as \'short-range apparent motion\'
rather than flicker fusion or persistence of vision. It is intriguing
that, although it has been known for decades that the joining together
of static images in our minds is due to modelling activity in the brain
the myth that it is due to persistence of vision or flicker fusion is
universal. As Anderson and Anderson (1993) noted:
`Indeed, in the past decade, psychoanalytic-Marxist film scholars `\
`have retained the model implied by persistence of vision: theirs `\
`is a passive viewer, a spectator who is "positioned," unwittingly `\
`"sutured" into the text, and victimized by excess ideology.`
Our experience of the cinema is like a dream updated by sensation rather
than sensation updated by interpretation. In fact the most compelling
evidence for the modelling power of the brain is the existence of
dreams; our dreams are often models of worlds that do not exist and
involve little or no sensory input yet can involve effects as powerful
as any television drama.
Short range apparent motion occurs when the interval between
presentations of an object is brief (c. 50-100 msecs). Motion modelling
in response to longer intervals is known as long range apparent motion.
There is evidence that the modelling in short range apparent motion is
enhanced if the moving patterns are similar to moving human forms (such
as patterns of dots outlining a person)(Thornton *et al.* 1998). The
accuracy of predicting movement can actually improve if the interval
between presentations is increased when human forms are used.
Motion modelling can also be seen in visual illusions such as the
*Waterfall Illusion* (motion aftereffect). The waterfall illusion is
commonly seen after viewing a sequence of scrolling credits on the
television; when the credits stop rolling it appears as if they briefly
move in the opposite direction. Tootel *et al.* (1995) have used fMRI to
show that this is correlated with activity in the motion modelling area
of visual cortex (area MT/V5). The waterfall illusion is also associated
with an intriguing aftereffect known as **storage of the motion
aftereffect**. Normal motion aftereffects last for up to about ten
seconds after the stimulus, however, if the subjects close their eyes
for the normal duration of the aftereffect then reopen them they see the
illusion for almost the normal duration. Culham *et al.* (1999) used
fMRI to show that activity in area MT/V5 was low during the period when
the eyes were closed then increased dramatically when the eyes were
opened. This is strongly suggestive of a modelling mechanism outside
MT/V5 that has adapted to motion and then models stationary data with
movement in the wrong direction.
Visual area MT/V5 is also involved in the separation of moving visual
scenes into *sprites* or objects that move together as a whole within a
scene (Muckli *et al.* 2002).
The way that mental models may be the basis of ordinary reasoning was
outlined by Johnson-Laird (1980), based on earlier work by Kenneth
Craik.
Studies of \'change blindness\' and \'inattentional blindness\', where
subjects fail to spot outrageous changes in their environment, also
demonstrate that we experience a model and suggest that the brain must
analyse an object to incorporate it fully into the model (See for
instance Rensink (2000), Simons & Rensink (2005)).
### Brain areas used in perception overlap those used in imagination and recall
Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI) has shown that similar
areas of brain are used during perception involving the senses as during
imagination (Tong 2003, Kosslyn and Thompson 2003). The substrate of the
mental images that occur in both modes of brain activity has not yet
been found. This overlap of the brain areas used in perception with
those used in imagination, memory and recall has been demonstrated in a
wide range of experiments.
Ganis *et al.* (2004) used fairly complex perceptual and imagination
tasks that activated large areas of the brain, they found an overlap
between the brain areas activated during perception and imagery. The
principle areas that were different in the two tasks were found in the
primary sensory areas of the visual cortex. Other areas in the visual
cortex and activity in the rest of the brain showed a remarkable degree
of overlap. The authors suggested that the differences in the activity
of primary visual cortex may have been due to differences between the
perceptual and imaginary stimuli such as speed of onset etc. The
hippocampus was not activated.
It is intriguing that, contrary to object imagery, spatial imagery such
as predicting when a cross on a screen would fall on an imaginary letter
actually seems to inhibit activity in sensory visual cortex (Aleman *et
al.*). Both fMRI and blocking with transcranial magnetic stimulation
(TMS) showed that the posterior parietal cortex was involved in the
spatial imagery.
Imagery involving places and faces activates the place and face areas
that are activated during perception (Ishai *et al.* 2000).
The recall and recognition of things also seems to involve very similar
brain areas to those used during perception. Wheeler and Buckner (2003)
showed that areas involved in perception were also involved in the
recall of the perceptual stimuli.
Recall causes activation of areas used in perception but also seems to
use areas that may be particularly related to the process of recall
iself, such as the left parietal cortex (Konishi *et al.* 2000)
(Brodmann\'s area 40/39). Frontal and parietal regions are involved in
the recognition of whether stimuli have been experienced before.
Image generation during sleep seems to differ from that during
imagination and recall. In particular it seems to involve a few well
defined areas of cortex and considerable activation of the posterior
thalamus.
Sleep studies have shown that people dream throughout sleep. However,
dreams are more frequent during the REM (rapid eye movement) periods of
sleep than the NREM (non-REM) periods. Dreams are reported after 70-95%
of awakenings in REM sleep and 5-10% of awakenings in NREM sleep. REM
dreams are more visual than NREM dreams which are more \'thoughtlike\'
(Solms 2000). Thoughtlike events (mentation) are reported after 43% of
awakenings from NREM sleep.
Solms (1997) found that patients who had lesions in the
parietal-temporo-occipital junction reported a cessation of visual
images in dreams. Solms also found that patients with lesions in the
white matter inferior to the frontal horns of the lateral ventricles, in
the ventromesial quadrant of the frontal lobes, also reported loss of
dreaming. Loss of dreaming is also reported by leucotomised patients
with frontal ventromesial damage. Damasio *et al.* (1985) and Solms
(1997) also reported that some patients with damage to the medial
prefrontal cortex, the anterior cingulate cortex, and the basal
forebrain became confused about what was real life and what was dreaming
(waking dreams occurred).
Studies using fMRI show that the sensory occipital lobe (BA 18) and
posterior thalamus, especially the lateral geniculate nuclei, are
activated in REM sleep, weaker activations of the posterior cingulate,
putamen and midbrain were also found (Wehrle *et al.* 2005, Loveblad *et
al.* 1999). These findings are consistent with activation of the
ponto-geniculo-occipital system (PGO) during REM.
So dreams may be more like primary activations of sensory cortex than
imagining or recall. This suggests that dreams have a thalamic origin or
are managed via connections from the cortex through the thalamus to the
visual cortex.
Hallucinations seem to differ from dreams. In Charles Bonnett Syndrome
patients can have clear hallucinations. These, like imaginations, seem
to involve areas of the visual cortex that deal with processed data, for
instance hallucinations of faces activate the \"face area\" rather than
visual cortical area V1 (Ffytche *et al.* 1998).
### Suppression of data acquisition during saccades - perception as a patchwork
If you look at yourself in the mirror you will not see your eyes moving
even though they will be darting all over the view of your face. Even
when you deliberately look from place to place your eyes will appear
steady. The natural darting of the eyes from place to place as you view
a scene is known as \"saccadic\" movement of the eyes. The suppression
of the visual image during the motion of the eyes is known as \"saccadic
suppression\" or \"saccadic masking\". The suppression of the
acquisition of image data extends to suppression of awareness of flashes
of light during saccades, this effect is known as \"flash suppression\",
however, flash suppression seems to apply only to rather dull flashes
(Volkman (1962). The suppression during saccades is probably due to
suppression of the magnocellular pathway (the motion sensitive pathway)
in the lateral geniculate nucleus (Burr *et al.* (1996).
The most intriguing feature of this suppression of data acquisition
during saccades is that each snapshot that is obtained between saccades
can only contain a relatively small amount of information. This is
because the fovea, which is the most sensitive area of the eye, is tiny
(about 1mm diameter) and only receives input from a few degrees of the
visual field. As a result what we consider to be a uniform scene in our
minds is actually a patchwork of intersaccade snapshots.
Another aspect of saccades is that the timing of events is referred back
to the beginning of the saccade. This effect is known as \"saccadic
chronostasis\". For example, if an object changes colour during a
saccade the observer feels as if the colour change occurred at the
beginning of the saccade, so extending the amount of time that the
object possesses the changed colour. This effect can extend apparent
durations by up to 500 ms and is consistent with the idea that the
visual system models events prior to perception (see Yarrow *et al.*
2006).
Burr D, Morrone M, Ross J. (1996) Selective suppression of the
magnocellular visual pathway during saccades\]\'\', Behavioral Brain
Research 80 1-8 (1996)
<http://www.pisavisionlab.org/downloads/BBRReview96.pdf>
Volkman, F. (1962). Vision during voluntary saccadic eye movements. J.
Opt Soc. Am. 52:571-578. 1962.
Yarrow, K, Whiteley, L, Rothwell, J.C & Haggard,P. (2006) Spatial
consequences of bridging the saccadic gap. Vision Res. 2006 February;
46(4): 545--555.
<http://www.hexicon.co.uk/Kielan/papers/Moving_chrono.pdf>
## Blindsight
Blindsight studies illuminate the relationship between the cerebral
cortex and our experience. When the visual cortex is removed subjects
become almost totally blind. If the visual cortex on one side is removed
subjects become relatively blind in the contra-lateral hemifield. One of
the most revealing studies of blindsight is Marcel\'s 1998 paper: \"
Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of visual consciousness or
visual function?\".
It is useful when considering blindsight to contemplate for a while the
appearance of the world with both eyes closed and then with one eye
closed. When both eyes are closed our experience is of a darkish space
radiating out from our heads, with one eye closed we tend to ignore the
darkish areas that cannot be seen even though they are still present.
Marcel notes that patients who have a right blind field still have an
underlying visual field on the right side and that this can even contain
conscious visual experience. This sounds a bit like the darkish space
that we all experience if deprived of visual input on one side. As
Marcel says: \"A question that naturally arises is whether the loss is a
\'total\' loss of visual consciousness in the blind field. It is often
assumed to be so, especially by those who discuss blindsight without
carefully reading the literature or working with the subjects. One can
immediately respond negatively to the question..\"
The consciousness of the completion of Kanizsa figures in blindsight
patients is particularly indicative of the preservation of the field
even though the content was largely missing. A Kanizsa figure is shown
below:
![](Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg "Whiter_than_white_illusion.jpg")
If we put Marcel\'s observations together with cortical anatomy and
function it seems that the space of our experience is located outside of
the cerebral cortex. The cortex generates much of visual and other
content but it does not generate the space.
## The Role of the Thalamus
The thalamus is connected to the entire bottom layer of the cerebral
cortex. It is the nexus of the various cortical processors as well as a
recipient of independent input from most of the rest of the brain.
![](Constudbrain.png "Constudbrain.png")
The thalamus is subdivided into numerous small and medium sized nuclei
that between them receive inputs from every process in the nervous
system (the white fibres in the illustration above largely penetrate the
thalamus). The thalamic nuclei are interconnected which means that any
of them could, potentially host activity from anywhere in the body or
brain. Although the founders of neurology such as Hughlings Jackson and
Penfield & Jasper located conscious experience in the diencephalon,
including the thalamus, this is no longer the conventional wisdom. The
small size of the thalamic nuclei means that they cannot support the
processes that are assumed to compose access consciousness, however,
even some of the smallest thalamic nuclei host millions of synapses so
size would not be an obstacle if the thalamus contains the substrate of
phenomenal consciousness. Indeed, the diencephalon and the thalamus in
particular can be shown to be excellent candidates for a possible
location of phenomenal experience.
![](constudintralam.jpg "constudintralam.jpg")
`<font size=1>`{=html} The Intralaminar Nuclei of the thalamus. The
white space above and to the left of RN is the third ventricle.
MD=mediodorsal nucleus. CM=Centromedian nucleus, RN=red nucleus (not
part of thalamus) The black areas are stained white fibres. Picture
from: <http://www.neurophys.wisc.edu/> University of Wisconsin and
Michigan State Comparative Mammalian Brain Collections. Preparation of
image has been funded by the National Science Foundation, as well as by
the National Institutes of Health. May only be used with these
acknowledgements.`</font>`{=html}
If the thalamus contains a location for conscious experience then
lesions should abolish this experience. Unlike the cerebral hemispheres,
lesions of the thalamus do indeed seem to abolish consciousness. The
area that is most sensitive to lesions contains the Intralaminar Nuclei,
especially the Parafascicular and Centromedian Nuclei. If these are
damaged bilaterally patients suffer death, coma, akinetic mutism,
hypersomnia, dementia and other equally serious impairments of
consciousness that depend upon the size and placement of the lesions
(Bogen 1995, Schiff & Plum 1999). In cases of fatal familial insomnia,
in which patients exhibit many of these symptoms, there is marked neuron
loss in the Intralaminar Nuclei (Budka 1998).
The effect of interrupting the blood supply to the medial thalamus
depends upon the severity of the damage. There is frequently initial
coma. The recovery after coma is often incomplete, Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) described bilateral paramedian thalamic infarcts as normally
being \"followed by persisting dementia with severe mnemic disturbance,
global aspontaneity and apathy.\" The symptoms of bilateral damage to
the ILN can be so severe that it is possible that, even after recovery
from coma, some patients may cease to be conscious and are being
coordinated by automatic cortical processes.
Bjornstad *et al.* (2003) and Woernera *et al.* (2005) both reported
that the initial coma after bilateral paramedian infarct was accompanied
by a similar pattern of EEG activity to stage 2 sleep. Woernera *et al.*
(2005) also discovered that painful stimuli gave rise to a range of EEG
activity, transiently breaking the stage 2 sleep pattern but without
recovery of consciousness. Unfortunately even in those patients who
recover consciousness Kumral *et al.* (2001) report that \"Cognitive
functions in patients with bilateral paramedian infarction did not
change significantly during the follow-up, in contrast to those with
infarcts in varied arterial territories\" although Krolak-Salmon *et
al.* (2000) did report a single patient who made a total recovery.
Laureys *et al.* (2002) investigated recovery from \'persistent
vegetative state\' (wakefulness without awareness). They found that
overall cortical metabolism remained almost constant during recovery but
that the metabolism in the prefrontal and association cortices became
correlated with thalamic ILN and precuneus activity. Again confirming
that thalamo-cortico-thalamic activity is required for consciousness and
that cortical activity by itself is not conscious. Yamamoto *et al.*
(2005) investigated persistent vegetative state and found that deep
brain stimulation (25Hz) of the centromedian-parafascicular complex (19
cases) or mesencephalic reticular formation (2 cases) resulted in 8 of
the patients emerging from persistent vegetative state. It is
interesting that zolpidem, a GABA agonist, has recently been found to
reverse PVS in some patients (Claus & Nel 2006). The effect is rapid and
might be used to demonstrate the correlations that occur on recovery
from PVS.
As Bogen(1995) demonstrates, the ILN receive inputs, either directly or
indirectly, from every part of the CNS but what do they do?
Interest in the thalamus has recently been revived by the theories of
Newman & Baars (1993), Baars, Newman, & Taylor1998) and Crick & Koch
(1990). In Baars, Newman and Taylors\' (1998) theory it is suggested
that \"The brain stem-thalamocortical axis supports the state, but not
the detailed contents of consciousness, which are produced by cortex\".
They also propose that the \"nucleus reticularis thalami\" (Thalamic
Reticular Nucleus, TRN), which is a thin sheet of neurons that covers
the thalamus, is involved in a selective attention system. This concept
is reinforced by the way that point stimulation of the TRN causes focal
activity in the overlying cortex (MacDonald *et al.* 1998) and the way
the TRN is organised topographically (i.e.: has activity that is like an
electrical image of receptor fields).
The thalamus is ideally placed for integrating brain activity, if tiny
parts of the thalamus are removed consciousness is abolished and the
thalamus is involved in attention and the global integration of cortical
activity. Any impartial judge might pronounce that the site of conscious
experience has been found, possibly in the ILN of the thalamus, but no
one can say how it works.
## General Anaesthesia and the Thalamus
General anaesthesia should result in a profound depression of activity
in the ILN if these are indeed the sites of the conscious state. White &
Alkire (2003) administered halothane or isoflurane to volunteers and
used positron emission tomography (PET) to monitor brain activity. They
found severe depression of activity in the thalamus. The depression
appeared to be higher in the non-specific nuclei than in the relay
nuclei of the thalamus. In other words the anaesthesia is neither
turning off the cortex nor turning off the input to the cortex but it is
turning off an important part of the thalamus. Fiset *et al.* (1999)
have also demonstrated a similar pattern of medial thalamic inactivity
and cortical activity in propofol anaesthesia. Suppression of cortical
activity is not the cause of unconsciousness; for instance, the
anaesthetic agent chloralose leads to increased neural activity in the
cortex relative to conscious patients (Cariani 2000).
## The function of consciousness
When we walk our conscious experience does not contain data about the
control of the spinal, cerebellar and vestibular reflexes that keep us
on an even keel. When we reach out for a cup our conscious experience
only contains data related to the need for the cup, not data about the
elaborate control system that enables the action. When we talk the words
just come into mind, we do not painstakingly control the syntax and
vocal chords. When our attention shifts the conscious experience
containing the shift happens after the attention has shifted. This
passive nature of experience recurs throughout the neuroscience of
consciousness from the \"readiness potential\" to the \"auditory
continuity illusion\". So what does conscious observation do? The
medical evidence of the lack of consciousness in some forms of delirium,
mutism, PVS etc. suggest that the role of conscious observation is to
stabilise the brain so that it acts as a coordinated whole. Conscious
observation is an orderly arrangement of events, a stable groundform
that reflects the environment and composes the stage for action. It
could be speculated that if quantum events were prominent in brain
function then such a groundform would be essential but even a classical
brain might require a stabilising form that could be continuously
compared with the world beyond the body.
A stable form of neural information that contains bound data from the
senses and internal neural processes is likely to have a role in the
functioning of the organism. There is now an *integration consensus*
that proposes that phenomenal states somehow integrate neural activities
and information-processing that would otherwise be independent (see
review in Baars, 2002).
However, it has remained unspecified which kinds of information are
integrated in a conscious manner and which kinds can be integrated
without consciousness. Obviously not all kinds of information are
capable of being disseminated consciously (e.g., neural activity related
to vegetative functions, reflexes, unconscious motor programs, low-level
perceptual analyses, etc.) and many kinds can be disseminated and
combined with other kinds without consciousness, as in intersensory
interactions such as the ventriloquism effect.
Morsella (2005) proposed a *Supramodular Interaction Theory* (SIT) that
contrasts the task demands of consciously penetrable processes (e.g.:
those that can be part of conscious experience such as pain, conflicting
urges, and the delay of gratification) and consciously impenetrable
processes (e.g.: intersensory conflicts, peristalsis, and the pupillary
reflex). With this contrastive approach, SIT builds upon the integration
consensus by specifying which kinds of interaction require conscious
processing and which kinds do not (e.g., some intersensory processes).
SIT proposes that conscious processes are required to integrate
high-level systems in the brain that are vying for (specifically)
skeletomotor control, as described by the principle of *parallel
responses into skeletal muscle* (PRISM). Accordingly, regarding
processes such as digestion and excretion, one is conscious of only
those phases of the processes that require coordination with
skeletomotor plans (e.g., chewing or micturating) and none of those that
do not (e.g., peristalsis). From this standpoint, consciousness
functions above the level of the traditional module to "cross-talk"
among high-level, specialized and often multi-modal, systems.
**References**
Baars, B. J. (2002). The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent
evidence. *Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6,* 47 -- 52.
Morsella, E. (2005). The function of phenomenal states: Supramodular
interaction theory. *Psychological Review, 112,* 1000 - 1021.
More\... Click here for Rivalries and synchronisation, bibliography
and references
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 2
*Contributors: please include full data in the references section for
all references in the text.*
```{=html}
<div class="noprint">
```
Home
```{=html}
</div>
```
## Perceptual \"filling in\"
Perceptual \"filling in\" occurs when visual properties such as
textures, colours, brightness or motion are extended in the visual field
to areas where they do not have corresponding events in the world.
The filling in of the blind spot by the properties of the field in the
contralateral eye has already been discussed. The part of the visual
field represented by the blind spot is also \"filled in\" in the case of
monocular vision.
![](Constudblindill.png "Constudblindill.png")
Shut the right eye and focus on the pink cross with the left eye, if the
head is moved towards the pink cross there is a point at which the
yellow disk disappears but the white lines are still present. In this
\"filling in\" the visual field does not appear to be distorted.
Fiorani *et al.* (1992) developed a technique for probing the cortical
blind spot using vertical and horizontal bar stimuli. Matsumoto &
komatsu (2005) used this technique on macaque monkeys. In the monocular
case they found that as a bar was moved across the visual field so that
it crossed the blind spot there was a sudden change in neural activity
in the deep layers of the neurons in the blind spot area of V1. When the
bar was moved across the same part of the visual field of the
contralateral eye the neural activity in the blind spot area increased
steadily as the bar was moved. The authors found that there were neurons
in the deep layers of blind spot cortex that had elongated receptive
fields that could respond to stimuli outside the blind spot and transfer
this activation into the blind spot cortex.
Filling in of a slightly different type occurs in \"scotoma\". In
scotoma an area of the retina is damaged and unresonsive to visual
stimuli, immediately after the damage patients report an area of visual
field that is unresponsive to stimuli. After several months patients
report that the area of field represented by the scotoma contains visual
properties related to the physical world surrounding the area that would
have formed an image on the scotoma. This results in a distortion of the
visual field. (see for instance Gilbert(1993)). Direct measurements of
activity in cortical area V1 show that the neurons that represented the
area of the scotoma become sensitive to activity in the surrounding
visual field. At the cortical level the scotoma is literally \"filled
in\".
There are many stimuli that cause \"filling in\". These stimuli are
known as \"illusions\" because they produce phenomenal experience that
has no correlate in the world outside the body. In the \"neon colour
spreading illusion\" a lightly coloured circle appears where there
should be a white background. Sasaki and Watanabe (2004) used fMRI to
show that the part of the topographic map in cortical area V1
corresponding to the light coloured circle was activated.
![](Constudneon.jpg "Constudneon.jpg")
Fiorani, M., Rosa, M.G.P., Gattas, R. & Rocha-Miranda, C.E. (1992).
Dynamic surrounds of receptive fields in primate striate cortex: a
physiological basis for perceptual completion? Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
89, 8547-8551. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/abstract/89/18/8547>
Gilbert, C.D. (1993). Circuitry, architecture and functional dynamics of
visual cortex.
Matsumoto, M & Komatsu, H. (2005). Neural responses in the macaque V1 to
bar stimuli with various lengths presented on the blind spot. J
neurophysiol. 93. 2374-2387.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/abstract/93/5/2374>
Sasaki, Y & Watanabe, T. The primary visual cortex fills in colour.
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 101, 18251-18256. (2004).
## Binocular Rivalry, Pattern Rivalry and Binocular Fusion
Sir Charles Wheatstone (1838) was the first scientist to systematically
investigate binocular rivalry. Binocular rivalry occurs when different
images are presented to the left and right eyes. The subject sees
successively one image, a combined image and then the other image. The
swapping of images can take a second or more. Binocular rivalry is of
interest in consciousness research because the parts of the brain that
contain the dominant image should also be those parts that are
contributing to conscious experience. Binocular rivalry involves at
least two components; the first switches from one image to a merged
image and then to the other image and the second permits the view to be
part of conscious experience.
![](Constudrival.png "Constudrival.png")
The switching of one image for another may involve selecting one of the
images as the percept or selecting one of the eyes. Blake *et al.*
(1979) performed an experiment in which subjects could change the image
at a given eye by pressing a button. When a particular image became
dominant they pressed a button to change the image at the eye receiving
the dominant image for the non-dominant image. They found that the
subjects immediately experienced the second image as the dominant image.
This suggests that binocular rivalry is selecting between eyes rather
than images. Lehky in 1988 proposed that the switching may be occurring
as a result of feedback between visual cortical area V1 and the Lateral
Geniculate Nucleus (a thalamic relay - see Carandini *et al.* 2002) and
Blake in 1989 also proposed that the switching occurred at the level of
area V1. (Visual cortical area V1 receives visual input direct from the
LGN.)
Tong (2001) has argued that, in humans, the switching of images in
binocular rivalry may occur at the earliest levels in the visual cortex.
In particular, Tong and Engel (2001) used an elegant technique measuring
the activity in the visual cortex that represents the blind spot of the
eye to show that almost complete switching to the dominant image occurs
at the level of visual cortical area V1. In support of this idea of
switching at the level of V1 or even before the cortex, Kreimann *et
al.* (2001, 2002) used direct electrode recordings in human cortex and
found that the activity of most neurons changed with the percept. Other
experiments have not shown a single locus in the brain where the
suppressed sensory information gets switched out (Blake & Logothetis
2002, Leopold & Logothetis 1996, Gail et al., 2004).
Functional MRI has also shown cortical activity outside of sensory
visual cortex related to both images in binocular rivalry. Lumer *et
al.* (1998) found that only the fronto-parietal areas of cortex switched
with the percept, Fang & He (2005) found that activity relating to both
suppressed and unsuppressed images were present in the dorsal stream of
the visual system. Wunderlich *et al.* (2005) and Haynes *et al.* (2005)
have both found suppression at the level of the lateral geniculate
nucleus using fMRI in humans.
Pasley *et al.* (2004) have shown that, even during suppression, fearful
faces can produce activity in the amygdala (see Pessoa (2005) for a
review).
Rivalry alternations seem to be the result of widespread activity
changes that cover large parts of the brain, including but not
necessarily originating at the earliest sensory stages of visual
processing. Most investigators have found that, once switching has
occurred, there are areas of the brain that contain activity that is
solely related to the percept but this varies from most of the cortex to
largely more frontal regions depending upon the study. The most likely
explanation for binocular rivalry is that the switching occurs at the
level of the LGN as a result of feedback from the cortex.
Pattern Rivalry is also of interest in consciousness research for the
same reasons as binocular rivalry. In pattern rivalry a figure may have
two or more forms that replace each other. Typical examples of such
figures are the Necker cube and Rubin\'s face-vase. The similarity of
the time course of the switching between percepts in binocular rivalry
and pattern rivalry has led many authors to suggest that these involve
the same mechanism. Logothetis *et al.* (1996) used novel dichoptic
stimuli (different images to each eyes) to produce a form of rivalry
that seems to involve switching at levels in the cerebral cortex that
are more distal to the sensory stimulus than V1. Leopold and Logothetis
(1999), on the basis of their work with monkeys, state that \"..many
neurons throughout the visual system, both monocular and binocular,
continue to respond to a stimulus even when it is perceptually
suppressed.\". Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998) investigated pattern rivalry
with MRI and found activity in higher order visual areas during change
of dominant pattern. Pettigrew (2001) also describes effects on rivalry
due to thought and mood that may require involvement of large areas of
cortex in the switching operation and stresses the way that V1
represents different visual fields in different hemispheres of the brain
so that inter-hemispheric switching must also be considered.
It seems likely that the change of dominant pattern or percept is
associated with higher level cortical activity but once the dominant
percept is established many of the visually responsive neurons in the
cortex are switched over to the new percept. This might account for the
similarities in timing of binocular and pattern rivalry and the
disparate results found by the various groups of authors. In the words
of Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998):
\"The transient activity fluctuations we found suggest that perceptual
metastability elicited by ambiguous stimuli is associated with rapid
redistributions of neural activity between separate specialized cortical
and subcortical structures.\"
Which permits both the idea of selecting particular eyes or percepts,
perhaps by feedback that switches a thalamic relay on the basis of
cortical processing of patterns. Once the cortex has switched the
thalamic relay most of the neurons in V1 would become exposed to the
dominant percept but there would still be a few neurons in the cortical
visual system receiving data from the non dominant image.
The investigations of binocular and pattern rivalry provide evidence
that conscious visual experience is probably distal to V1 (i.e.: cortex
or thalamus).
Perceptual rivalry may be part of complex decision making rather than
being simply a switch to blank out unwelcome input. It is clear from the
Rubin face-vase that pattern rivalry is linked to recognition and would
involve a complex delineation of forms within cortical processing. This
would suggest that many areas of cortex should be involved before a
particular percept is made dominant. Pettigrew (2001) argues that
rivalry is the result of a complex phenomenon rather than being simply a
switching event. Pettigrew\'s discovery that laughter abolishes rivalry
also points to a complex cortical system for switching percepts.
Pettigrew proposes that complex cortical processes control rivalry and
that the actual switching of percepts is performed sub-cortically in the
Ventral Tegmental Area. He concludes his review of the problem by noting
that \"Rivalry may thus reflect fundamental aspects of perceptual
decision making..\" Pettigrew (2001).
Another effect, known as \"binocular fusion\", provides further
compelling evidence for the non-conscious nature of the cerebral cortex.
In binocular fusion images from both eyes are fused together to create a
single image in experience. Moutoussis and Zeki (2002) used a form of
binocular fusion in which images of faces were flashed at 100ms
intervals to both eyes simultaneously. When both eyes received images of
the same colour the subject could see the faces but when one eye
received a green image on a red background and the other a red image on
a green background the subjects reported seeing a uniform yellow field
that contained no faces.
fMRI scans of the subject\'s brains showed that when both eyes were
exposed to images of the same colour the part of the brain that deals
with faces was active and when each eye received images of different
colours the same areas of brain showed activity. In other words the
cortex contained strong activity related to faces whether or not faces
were experienced. Moutoussis and Zeki found a similar effect when they
used images of houses instead of images of faces. The authors concluded
that: \"The present study further suggests that there are no separate
processing and perceptual areas but rather that the same cortical
regions are involved in both the processing and, when certain levels of
activation are reached and probably in combination with the activation
of other areas as well, the generation of a conscious visual percept\".
This conclusion does not seem to be supported by the data. There is no
evidence that any area of cortex contains the percept itself. The
experiment shows that the cortex contains data relating to both red and
green faces which suggests that the cortex is not the site of the
conscious percept. The percept is most likely distal to the cortex
perhaps in the thalamus or some other area that receives cortical
sensory output.
It is interesting that Fries *et al.* (1997) found that neurons that
were activated by the dominant image in binocular rivalry fired
synchronously whereas those that were activated by the non-dominant
image did not. Thalamocorticothalamic oscillations are the most likely
source for synchronising neurons over whole areas of cortex, suggesting
that the conscious percept is located in the thalamus rather than the
cortex.
## Synchronisation of Neural Processes
Our experience seems to contain entities with their attributes attached
to them at the correct places in space and time. When a dog barks we see
its jaws open at the same time as the bark and both jaws and bark are at
the same location. We take this for granted but the brain must be
engaging in some complex processing to achieve this synchronised and
appropriately positioned set of objects and events. The illustration
below shows the two basic processes that might be used to synchronise
events between the different specialised processors in the cerebral
cortex and brain in general.
![](Constudsynch.gif "Constudsynch.gif")
In the first option a complete model of sensation, dream etc. may be
created and then allowed to become part of conscious experience. In the
second model events are released into experience as fast as possible but
are synchronous when recalled, having been synchronised in a storage
buffer. There is a third option in which there is no synchronisation of
events so that the output from different processors would occur at
different times.
The \'experience buffer\' would be a volume of brain in which a
succession of events could be recorded. The buffer might either be
updated in steps, the previous content being discarded, or continuously
updated with the oldest content being lost continuously.
In the first option events from different processes would always appear
to be simultaneous unless the experience buffer were updated as a series
of steps in which case any changes at around the moment of updating
might appear in successive buffers. For instance, if change of position
were processed before change in colour a circle on a screen that changed
from green to red at the start of a motion might seem to be briefly
green during the motion and then turn red.
In the second model events from different processors might appear
asynchronous at the moment of experience but synchronous when recalled.
Colour vision and motion vision are processed in different parts of the
visual cortex and in distinct parts of visual cortical areas V1 and V2.
They are different processes and hence ideal for studying the
synchronisation of cortical activity. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997)
presented subjects with moving coloured squares on a computer screen
that changed from red to green or vice versa as they changed direction
of movement. It was found that subjects seemed to perceive changes in
colour some 70-80 msecs before they perceived a change in the direction
of motion of the squares. Further work by Arnold *et al.* (2001) and
Arnold and Clifford (2001) have confirmed that colour changes seem to be
perceived before motion. Arnold and Clifford (2001) also found a
quantitative relationship between the colour/motion asynchrony and the
direction of change of motion, complete reversals of direction giving
rise to the greatest asynchrony between the detection of colour and
motion changes.
Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) conclude by stating that the asynchrony of
neural processes shows that \"..the perception of each attribute is
solely the result of the activity in the specialised system involved in
its processing..\". It seems more likely that the experiments simply
show that slow neural processes are not synchronised before they become
percepts (the third option above). The experiments are excellent
evidence for the concept of the cortex as a set of specialised
processors that deliver their output asynchronously to some other place
where the output becomes a percept.
These experiments on colour and motion suggest that there is no
synchronisation between the processes that deal with these two aspects
of vision. Another set of experiments by Clifford *et al.* (2003)
supports this idea of processing being asynchronous. They asked subjects
to perform a variety of judgements of when visual events occurred and
found that the degree of synchrony of one visual event with another
depends on the type of judgement. Different judgements probably use
processors in different areas of cortex and the output from these
arrives asynchronously at the part of the brain that supports the
percept.
When the percept is formed there must be feedback to the cortical
processes that create its content. Otherwise it would not be possible to
report about the percept and the cortex would be unable to direct
processing to the percept in preference to other, non-conscious cortical
data.
Although slow processes (20 milliseconds to 1 second) do not seem to be
synchronised there is some evidence for very rapid synchronisation.
Andrews *et al.* (1996) revisited a problem raised by the famous
physiologist Charles Sherrington. Sherrington considered the phenomenon
of \'flicker fusion\' in which a flickering light appears to be a
continuous steady light if it flashes on and off at frequencies of about
45 Hz or higher. He reasoned that if the images from both eyes are
brought together to form a single image then the frequency at which a
flickering light appears to be steady should depend on whether one or
two eyes are used. Flicker fusion should occur if each eye receives
alternate flashes at only half the normal flicker fusion frequency. The
flicker should disappear if the left eye receives flashes at 23 pulses
per second and the right eye receives alternate flashes at 23 pulses per
second. When Sherrington performed the experiment he found that this was
not the case, using approximate figures, each eye required 46 pulses per
second for fusion to occur. Sherrington proposed that the flicker fusion
in alternate binocular presentation was occurring \"psychically\",
outside of normal physiological processes.
Andrews *et al.* duplicated Sherrington\'s result but investigated it
further. They found that when lights were flashed in each eye
alternately at low frequences (2 Hz) the experience was the same as a
light being flashed in both eyes at this rate. At frequencies of four Hz
and higher the subjects began to report that the lights being flashed
alternately in both eyes seemed to flicker at the same rate as lights
being flashed in both eyes at half the frequency. It seemed as if a
flash in one eye followed by a flash in the other eye was being
perceived as a single flash or \"conflated\" as the authors put it. The
authors explained this effect by suggesting that the brain activity
corresponding to the flashes was sampled for a short period and any
number of flashes occurring during this period became perceived as a
single flash. The maximum rate of sampling would be about 45 Hz. This
idea is similar to option (1) above, where the buffer is filled and
emptied 40 - 50 times a second.
An experience buffer that is refreshed at 40-50 times a second might
also explain the results obtained with colour and motion asynchrony
because synchronisation between processes may well happen too quickly to
affect processes that occur at very slow rates. Singer and Gray (1995),
Singer (2001) have proposed that synchronisation between neurones at
about 45 Hz is the discriminator between those neurones with activity
that contributes to conscious experience and activity in other neurones.
A rapid refresh rate in a synchronising buffer agrees with the results
found by Fries *et al.* (1997) in which visual cortical neurones that
represent a percept underwent synchronous oscillations in the gamma
frequency range (39--63 Hz). Tononi *et al.* (1998) have also found
synchronisation of neural activity in neurones that represent the
percept.
The gamma frequency oscillations are intrinsic to the cortex but are
triggered by the thalamus and are part of the \'arousal system\'.
Readers should be wary of the term \'arousal system\' because it evokes
the idea of something waking up a conscious cortex. The cortex can be
fully active during sleep and even during pathological unconsciousness
such as persistent vegetative state so it is possible that the arousal
centres themselves or nearby structures actually host phenomenal
consciousness.
## EEG and synchronisation
If electrodes are placed on the scalp varying electrical potentials of a
few tens of microvolts can be recorded between the electrodes.
Recordings of potentials from electrodes on the scalp are known as
electroencephalograms (EEGs).
The potentials recorded in the EEG are due to postsynaptic potentials in
nerve cells. The EEG is insensitive to the activity of single cells and
occurs as a result of relatively slow, **synchronised**, changes in
large areas of cells. The differences in potential between two scalp
electrodes are largely due to depolarisation and hyperpolarisation of
the dendritic trees of cortical pyramidal cells. The folding of the
cortex (gyri) is problematical for recording and interpreting EEGs
because opposing layers of cortex can cancel any net potentials.
The EEG shows rhythmic activity. This is conventionally divided into the
following frequency bands:
Delta waves 0--4 Hz
Theta waves 4--8 Hz
Alpha waves 8--12 Hz
Beta waves \>10 Hz
Gamma waves (also called fast beta) 25--100 Hz
EEGs also contain short bursts of activity called spindles and very fast
oscillations (VFOs). Spindles last for 1--2 seconds and contain rhythmic
activity at 7--14 Hz. They are associated with the onset of sleep. The
VFOs consist of short bursts at frequencies of over 80 Hz.
When the eyes are closed the amplitude of activity from most pairs of
electrodes is increased compared with when the eyes are open. When
subjects are awake the EEG consists mainly of alpha and beta activity
with considerable low amplitude gamma when the eyes are open. In stage 1
sleep the EEG consists of theta waves, in stage 2 sleep of varied
activity and spindles, in stage 4 sleep of delta and during REM sleep of
beta and theta activity. In epileptic seizures there tends to be high
amplitude activity with pronounced synchronisation between many pairs of
electrodes.
The rhythmic electrical activity is due to cortical feedback loops,
cortico-cortical synchronisation, thalamic pacemakers and
thalamo-cortical synchronisation. VFOs have been attributed to the
activity of electrical connections between cells (dendro-dendritic gap
junctions) (Traub (2003)).
The gamma activity, centred on a frequency of 40 Hz appears to be
related to activity in cortical interneurons that form electrical
connections between their dendrites (Tamas *et al.* 2000). These
oscillations can be triggered by high frequency stimulation of the
posterior intralaminar nuclei of the thalamus (Barth and MacDonald 1996,
Sukov and Barth 2001) and as a result of activation of the reticular
system (Munk *et al.* 1996). This suggests that stimulation of cortex by
thalamic sensory relays triggers gamma band activity in the cortex. A
shift from gamma to beta waves can occur in human event related
potentials after about 0.2 secs (Pantev 1995, Traub *et al.* 1999).
The alpha activity is related to thalamic pacemakers, perhaps as a
result of intrinsic oscillatory activity in thalamic sensory relays (see
Roy & Prichep 2005 for a brief review). Theta activity, which occurs
during some cognitive tasks and mental arithmetic involves a loop from
the cortex to the non-specific thalamic nuclei. Delta activity seems to
be endogenous to cortex when input is suppressed during sleep. Beta
activity is due to cortico-cortical interactions, often after a brief
period of gamma activation. It should be noted that gamma and beta
activity can be expressed as impulses in cortico-thalamic pathways and
that when cortical and thalamic activity is correlated there is a
conscious state. In other words gamma or beta waves in the cortex are
not correlates of consciousness on their own - see for instance Laureys
*et al.* (2002).
## Event related potentials
After a sudden event there are a characteristic set of changes in EEG
activity known as **event related potentials** or ERPs. The time course
of the ERP is shown in the diagram below.
![](Constudevent.png "Constudevent.png")
ERPs occur in response to novel stimuli and are also produced by brief
transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS)(Iramina *et al.* 2002). The slow
component is known as the P3 or P300 phase of the ERP. It is due to
activation of areas of the brain that are relatively remote from the
primary sensory areas of brain.
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) have reviewed the origin of the P300 ERP:
\"To summarize, convergent evidence suggests that P3-like activity can
be recorded in several, widely separated brain areas. These include some
medial temporal and subcortical structures (e.g., the hippocampal
formation, amygdala, and thalamus), but these structures are unlikely to
contribute directly to the scalp-recorded P3.\". According to
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) the recorded P300 may be due to
temporo-parietal and prefrontal cortical activity. Linden (2005) has
also concluded that widespread, but specific, cortical activation is
correlated with the recorded P300 ERP.
The generator of the P300 is still obscure. Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005)
consider that the Locus coeruleus, a nucleus in the pons that regulates
task related attention and part of the sleep-wake cycle, may be
responsible. In line with this, Mashour *et al.* (2005) have discovered
that TMS induced P300 activity is reduced in unconscious states.
Whether the P300 is related to Libet\'s 0.5 second delay is still
obscure but the discovery that the P300 occurs in association with
subliminal stimuli (stimuli that do not enter awareness)(Bernat *et al.*
2001) suggests that it is associated with non-conscious cortical
processing. Williams *et al.* (2004), in an investigation of subliminal
and supraliminal fear perception, found that \"conscious fear perception
was distinguished by a more prominent N4, peaking around 400 msec\"; the
N4 component follows the P300 component in the succession of phases of
the ERP. Williams *et al.* considered that the earlier phases in the ERP
are probably related to non-conscious processing. In contrast Vogel *et
al.* (1998) found that suppression of the P300 was associated with
suppression of awareness.
## The integration delay
Psychological experiments often involve binary decisions where subjects
give one of two outputs in response to stimuli. It is found that if the
stimuli are made increasingly noisy or complex the response time tends
to increase. Psychophyicists have developed various mathematical models
to explain the increased response times due to noise such as the
Integrator and Accumulator models (cf: Luce(1986)). These models have
been fairly successful when explaining experiments such as judging the
net direction of movement of sets of dots on a screen when the dots are
given semi-random paths and different brightness etc. In these
circumstances it can take up to 2 seconds for an accurate decision.
There are many tasks however where the accuracy of decision making does
not improve after about 300 milliseconds. The accuracy of the
performance of rats when choosing between two alternatives when reacting
to odours peaks at about 300 ms (Uchida and Mainen(2003), Abraham *et
al.* (2004)). The accuracy of humans when performing vernier acuity
tasks, line detection, contrast sensitivity, motion velocity
discrimination and stereoscopic depth discrimination seems to peak at
300ms (Uchida *et al.* 2006).
Uchida, Kepecs and Mainen (2006) suggest that \"rapid and short
integration time is a sensible strategy for rapid processing of
low-level sensory information in order to form more complex sensory
images, both in vision and olfaction.\" Whether these authors regard
these derived sensory images as the content of consciousness is not
mentioned. The authors propose that the 300ms optimal integration time
may be partly due to the mechanics of sniffing (a sniff takes about
125-200ms) and the nature of optical fixation (inter-saccade intervals
are typically 200-400 ms ). The authors note that the animal or human
could, in principle, choose to integrate over longer intervals but if it
is moving this may not lead to information that is current for changed
circumstances.
An optimal processing time of about 300 ms would be consistent with the
delays observed before conscious awareness occurs in response to a
stimulus - an interval required to form \"more complex sensory images\".
## Global Workspace Theory
Global Workspace Theory is the idea that somewhere in the brain there is
a facility that integrates the processes that occur in the various
separate areas of the brain. The theory was first proposed by Descartes
as the *sensus communis*, the common sense, but the modern form of the
theory dispenses with the idea of a point soul looking at the brain. In
modern Global Workspace theory it is proposed that an area of brain
receives input from most of the cerebral cortex and broadcasts its
outputs to all of the unconscious modular information processors in the
brain.
Modern Global Workspace Theory has been championed by Baars (1983,
1988).
There is increasing evidence for a Global Workspace or Global Workspaces
in the brain. Much of this evidence comes from fMRI, single unit and
magnetoencephalography studies in which it is shown that non-conscious
or subliminal processing mainly occupies primary, sensory cortex whereas
conscious processing occupies large areas of cerebral cortex.
In binocular rivalry the stimulus that is consciously perceived is
responsible for relatively intense activation of large areas of brain
whereas the non-conscious stimulus is often suppressed (see above and
Sheinberg & Logothetis (1997), Tononi *et al.* (1998)). The suppression
is likely to occur in the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei which suggests a
role for the Thalamic Reticular Nuclei, which modulate LGN activity, in
the control of the percept.
### Masking and visual awareness
Word masking has also been used to investigate the idea of a Global
Workspace. When a word is presented on its own for a few tens of
milliseconds it remains readable but if it is immediately succeeded by,
or accompanied by, another word it becomes indistinct or invisible. This
effect is known as \"word masking\". Vogel *et al.* (1998) have
investigated a version of word masking known as the \"attentional
blink\". They found that when stimuli became invisible the P3 component
of the Event Related Potential, which peaks at around 300-500 millisecs
after a stimulus, was completely suppressed. The P3 component of the ERP
has been related to the lodging of data in working memory and also to
gamma band activity in the EEG. This strongly suggests the involvement
of a cortico-thalamic loop in the \"attentional blink\". The delay of
0.3 to 0.5 secs is typical of the time required for conscious awareness
(see above).
Word masking in conjunction with fMRI and Event Related Potential (ERP)
recordings has been used by Dehaene *et al.* (2001) to expose control by
a central mechanism. It was found that masked words activate mainly the
visual cortex and ventral stream (inferior temporal lobe) whereas
visible words also activated distant parietal, prefrontal and cingulate
sites.
Dehaene *et al.* (2003) and found that the dynamics of the loss of
visibility of words in an attentional blink experiment could be modelled
by a simulated cortico-thalamic loop. In their simulation a distributed
cortical process determined which events would receive attention and the
system used the thalamic gating systems to exclude those that did not
receive attention.
Tse *et al.* (2005) have used purely visual stimuli in masking
experiments and concluded that, in the case of purely visual stimuli,
the neural correlates of awareness were limited to the occipital cortex:
\"We suggest that there are both lower and upper bounds within the
visual hierarchy for the processing of visual masking and the
maintenance of visual awareness of simple unattended targets; the lower
bound is at least as high as the border between V2 and V3, and the upper
bound is within the occipital lobe, possibly somewhere downstream of
V4.\"
This discovery would mean that activation of large areas of cortex are
unnecessary for awareness.
Melloni *et al.* (2007) compared compared the electrophysiological
responses related to the processing of visible and invisible words in a
delayed matching to sample task. Both perceived and nonperceived words
caused a similar increase of local (gamma) oscillations in the EEG, but
only perceived words induced a transient long-distance synchronization
of gamma oscillations across widely separated regions of the brain.
After this transient period of temporal coordination, the electrographic
signatures of conscious and unconscious processes continue to diverge.
Only words reported as perceivedinduced (1) enhanced theta oscillations
over frontal regions during the maintenance interval, (2) an increase of
the P300 component of the event-related potential, and (3) an increase
in power and phase synchrony of gamma oscillationsbefore the anticipated
presentation of the test word. We propose that the critical process
mediating the access to conscious perception is the earlytransient
global increase of phase synchrony of oscillatory activity in the
gammafrequency.
Melloni L, Molina C, Pena M, Torres D, Singer W, Rodriguez E. (2007).
Synchronization of neural activity across cortical areas correlates
withconscious perception.J Neurosci. 2007 Mar 14;27(11):2858-65.
### Attention and the global workspace
Baars (2002) in his review of evidence for the Global Workspace Theory
quotes many other experiments that show activation of larger areas of
cortex in response to conscious stimuli compared with unconscious or
subliminal stimuli.The effect is also seen in change blindness, learning
and attention. Newman and Baars (1993) consider that the \"workspace\"
is fairly global in the brain:
\"This Neural Global Workspace (NGW) model views conscious processes in
terms of a globally integrative brain system. The neural circuitry
contributing to this system is not only widely distributed across the
neocortex, but includes key corticothalamic and midbrain circuits as
well. These cortico-subcortical circuits are hypothesized to be critical
to understanding the mechanisms of attentional control that provide an
essential basis for the conscious processing of information\".
However they focus particularly on the role of the thalamic Reticular
Nucleus and cortico-thalamic connectivity in the control of attention.
Other ideas for the location of the Global Workspace are the idea of
Singer et al. that gamma synchrony controls access to the content of
consciousness and Llinas et al. (1998) that the thalamus is the hub
through which communication occurs between areas of cortex.
One of the problems with Global Workspace theory is that it suggests
that attention, working memory, cognitive control and consciousness may
all be in the same area of the brain. It is likely that the mechanisms
of attention, working memory, and cognitive control may involve several,
interlinked systems perhaps co-opting the basal ganglia in the process.
In view of this Maia and Cleeremans (2005) propose that \".. attention,
working memory, cognitive control and consciousness are not distinct
functions implemented by separate brain systems. Attempting to find
separate neural correlates for each may therefore be the wrong approach.
Instead, we suggest that they should be understood in terms of the
dynamics of global competition, with biasing from PFC (prefrontal
cortex).\". The inclusion by Maia and Cleeremans of consciousness with
distributed attention, working memory and cognitive control is
reminiscent of Zeki & Bartel\'s idea of microconsciousness.
It should be noted that, in common with Libet\'s data, the percept seems
to be available to phenomenal consciousness some 0.3 to 0.5 secs after a
stimulus; this suggests that whatever determines the content of
phenomenal consciousness operates before events become part of
phenomenal consciousness. This relegates phenomenal consciousness from
being a controller of attention to being the recipient of content that
is the subject of attention. This finding is consistent with the
philosophical problem of the **apparently** epiphenomenal nature of
phenomenal consciousness.
Given the data on the timing of conscious awareness it seems that there
may be two \"workspaces\", an active workspace that models the world,
discarding and suppressing data during rivalry, and a passive workspace
that receives the final, edited product. The active workspace would
correlate with the cortical systems stressed by Dehaene *et al.* and
Maia and Cleermans although, given the results of Tse et al., the
workspace would be limited to small zones of cortex. The loading of the
passive workspace with the output of the active workspace would
correlate with thalamo-cortical activity during component P3 of the ERP
in which data is transferred from the cortex to the thalamus. This
workspace might constitute the source for reports of the content of
phenomenal consciousness.
Llinas *et al.* (1998) have proposed two parallel cortico-thalamic
attentional systems, one of which is related to the thalamic specific
nuclei and the other to the thalamic non-specific nuclei, especially the
ILN. The non-specific system would be related to consciousness itself.
## The \"cognitive map\" and the neural basis of perceptual space
Our bodies appear to be mobile within a constant space. We walk around a
room; the room does not rotate around us. The constancy of the location
of things gives us the feeling that we are directly viewing a constant
world. But how does the brain provide a constant world rather than a
world that rotates with the movement of the sense organs? Why is our
view of the world when we move our eyes so different from the disturbing
flow of images that occur when a video camera is waved around? Do our
brains contain a constant \"cognitive map\" (O\'Keefe and Nadel 1978) of
our surroundings?
Mittelstaedt & Mittelstaedt (1980, 1982) discovered that female gerbils
were able to recover their pups in darkened surroundings by searching in
a semi random fashion on the outbound journey and then proceeding
directly back to the nest on the inbound journey. The direct journey
back to the nest seemed to be due to an integration of the various
directions taken on the outward journey (**path integration**). If the
equipment being explored by the mother gerbil was rotated very slowly
the mother would make an error equivalent to the amount of rotation.
More rapid rotations that activated the vestibular system of the rat
(acceleration measurement) did not cause errors in navigation. This
demonstration that rodents could navigate accurately on the basis of
**idiothetic** cues (cues that are due to internal senses) led to
research on the neural basis of the navigation.
As early as 1971 O\'Keefe and Dostrovsky had discovered that there are
particular cells in the hippocampus that fire according to the position
of an animal in the environment. This has been complimented by research
that showed that changes in visual cues within the environment caused
changes in the firing rate of place cells in hippocampal area CA3 (.
![](Gray717.png "Gray717.png")
![](HippocampalRegions.jpg "HippocampalRegions.jpg")
!Entorhinal cortex approximately maps to areas 28 and
34{width="500"}
F. P. Battaglia and A. Treves. 1998 Attractor neural networks storing
multiple space representations: A model for hippocampal place fields.
PHYSICAL REVIEW E DECEMBER 1998 VOLUME 58, NUMBER 6
<http://www.sissa.it/~ale/Bat+98b.pdf>
Leutgeb, S., Leutgeb, J.K., Moser, M-B, and Moser, E.I. 2005. Place
cells, spatial maps and the population code for memory. Current Opinion
in Neurobiology 2005, 15:738--746.
<http://instruct1.cit.cornell.edu/courses/bionb720nejc/reprints/LeutgebEtAl2005.pdf>
Mittelstaedt, H. & Mittelstaedt, M-L. 1982. Avian Navigation. (ed. Papi,
F. & Wallraff, H.) 290-297. Springer, Berlin.
Mittelstaedt, M-L & Glasauer, S. 1991. Idiothetic Navigation in Gerbils
and Humans. Zool. Jb. Physiol. 95 (1991), 427-435
<http://web.archive.org/web/20110125132449/http://www.nefo.med.uni-muenchen.de/~sglasauer/MittelstaedtGlasauer1991.pdf>
O\'Keefe, J. & Dostrovsky, J. (1971). The hippocampus as a spatial map:
preliminary evidence from unit activity in the freely moving rat. Brain
Res. 34, 171-175.
O\'Keefe, J. & Nadel, L. (1978). The Hippocampus as a cognitive map.
(Oxford)
## Bibliography
Defining the States of Consciousness. Tassi, P., Muzet, A. (2001)
Neuroscience and Behavioural Reviews 25(2001) 175-191.
Neuroanatomy: \"Digital Slice of Life\" by Stensaas and Millhouse
<http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/subj2.html>
See also: <http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/index.html>
EEG\'s: Coles, M.G.H., Rugg, M.D. Event Related Brain Potentials: An
Introduction.
<http://whalen.psych.udel.edu/667/1.What_is_ERP/ColesRugg1995chpt1.pdf>
Visual System: Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual
Awareness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
Professor Bogen\'s Consciousness Page
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/toccons.htm>
Demonstrations of Auditory Illusions and Tricks. Yoshitaka Nakajima
<http://www.kyushu-id.ac.jp/~ynhome/ENG/Demo/illusions2nd.html>
## References
- Abraham, N.M. (2004) Maintaining accuracy at the expense of speed:
stimulus similarity defines odor discrimination time in mice. Neuron
44, 865-876.
- Aleman, A., Ramsey, N., Van Honk, J.E., Kessels, R.P.C., Hoogduin,
J., Schutter, D.L.G., Postma, A., Kahn, R.S., De Haan, E.H.F.
(submitted). Parietal cortex mediates visuospatial imagery: evidence
from fMRI and rTMS.
<http://igitur-archive.library.uu.nl/dissertations/1954455/c10.pdf>
- Alkire, M.T., Haier, R.J., Fallon, J.H., and Barker, S.J.(1996). PET
imaging of conscious and unconscious verbal memory. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, 3 ( 5-6) 1996 , pp. 448--462
<http://www.imprint.co.uk/jcs_3_5-6.html>
- Anderson, J. & Anderson, B. (1993). \"The Myth of Persistence of
Vision Revisited,\" Journal of Film and Video, Vol. 45, No. 1
(Spring 1993): 3-12.
<http://www.uca.edu/org/ccsmi/ccsmi/classicwork/Myth%20Revisited.htm>
- Andrews, T.J., White, L.E., Binder, D. & Purves, D. (1996). Temporal
events in cyclopean vision. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 93,
pp. 3689--3692, April 1996. Neurobiology.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030510095149/http://www.dur.ac.uk/tim.andrews/PNAS_93_3689.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G. (2001) Determinants of asynchronous
processing in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London,
Series B: Biological Sciences, 269, 579 - 583.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031205165920/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/AC02.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G, Wenderoth, P. (2001). Asynchronous
processing in vision: Color leads motion. Current Biology, 11,
596 - 600.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030617120017/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/ACW01.pdf>
- Austin, G.M. & Grant, F.C. (1958). Physiologic observations
following total hemispherectomy in man. Surgery 38, 239-258.
- Baars, B.J. (1983) Conscious contents provide the nervous system
with coherent, global information. In Consciousness and
Self-Regulation (Vol 3). Davidson, R.J. et al., editors. Plenum
Press.
- Baars, B.J. (1988) A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness, Cambridge
University Press.
- Baars, B., Newman, J., & Taylor, J. (1998) Neuronal mechanisms of
consciousness: A Relational Global Workspace framework., in
Hameroff, Stuart and Kaszniak, Al and Laukes, James, Eds. Toward a
Science of Consciousness II: The second Tucson discussions and
debates., chapter 24, pages 269-278. MIT Press.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000946/>
- Baars, B.J. (2002) The conscious access hypothesis: origins and
recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. Vol 6, No 1,
47-52. 2002. <http://www.cs.memphis.edu/~wrcm/BaarsTICS2002.pdf>
- Barth, D. S. and MacDonald, K. D. (1996) Thalamic modulation of
high-frequency oscillating potentials in auditory cortex. Nature.
383, 78-81.
- Bernat E, Shevrin H, Snodgrass M. (2001). Subliminal visual oddball
stimuli evoke a P300 component. Clin Neurophysiol. 2001
Jan;112(1):159-71.
- Blake, R., Westendorf, D. and Overton, R. (1979) What is suppressed
during binocular rivalry? Perception 9: 223-231.
- Blake, R. and Lee, S.-H. (1999). Rival ideas about binocular
rivalry. Vision Research. 39: 1447-1454
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/faculty/blake/PDFs/Lee_Blake_99VR.pdf>
- Blankenburg, F., Ruff, C.C., Deichmann, R., Rees, G. and
Driver, J. (2006) The cutaneous rabbit illusion affects human
primary sensory cortex somatotopically, PLoS Biol 2006;4(3):e69.
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness: I. An
overview. Consciousness and Cognition, 4, 52-62.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/bogen-95.pdf>
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness:
Part II. Constraining the semantic problem. Consciousness and
Cognition, 4, 137-158.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/concog95.htm>
- Bregman, A.S. (1990). Auditory scene analysis: The perceptual
organization of sound. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Budka, H. (1998). Fatal Familial Insomnia Around the World. Brain
Pathology, 8: 553-570.
<http://brainpath.medsch.ucla.edu/pdfs/0803pdf/budka.pdf>
- Carandini M, Heeger DJ, & Senn W, (2002). A synaptic explanation of
suppression in visual cortex, Journal of Neuroscience,
22:10053-10065, 2002.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031031214953/http://www.cns.nyu.edu/~david/ftp/reprints/Carandini-JNeurosci2002.pdf>
- Cariani, P. (2000). Anesthesia, Neural Information Processing, And
Conscious Awareness. Consciousness And Cognition Vol. 9, No. 3,
September 2000 p. 387-395
- Castro-Alamancos, M.A., Connors, B.W. (1997). Thalamo-cortical
synapses. Progress in Neurobiology, Vol.51, pp. 581 to 606, 1997
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051025163047/http://neurobio.drexel.edu/castroweb/progneurobio1.pdf>
- Christmann, C. & Leuthold, H. (2004). The Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Section A. Volume 57, Number 2 /
February 2004. 357-381.
- Claus, R. & Nel, W. (2006). Drug induced arousal from the permanent
vegetative state. NeuroRehabilitation. 2006;21(1):23-8.
- Clifford, C.W.G., Arnold, D.H., Pearson, J. (2003). A paradox of
temporal perception revealed by a stimulus oscillating in colour and
orientation. Vision Research 43 (2003) 2245-2253.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031102125210/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/CAP03.pdf>
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of
consciousness Seminars in the Neurosciences (1990) 2, 263-275
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1998). Consciousness and Neuroscience.
Cerebral Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
- Culham, J.C., Dukelow, S.P., Vilis, T., Hassard, F.A., Gati, J.S.,
Menon, R.S. and Goodale, M.A. (1999). Recovery of fMRI Activation in
Motion Area MT Following Storage of the Motion Aftereffect. The
Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 81 No. 1 January 1999, pp. 388--393.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/81/1/388>
- Deecke, L. (1996) Planning, preparation, execution, and imagery of
volitional action, (Introduction / Editorial) in: L. Deecke W.
Lang, A. Berthoz (Eds) Mental Representations of Motor Acts.
Cognitive Brain Res 3 / Special Issue (2) 59-64.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000015/00/COGBRAIN.html>
- Dehaene, S., Sergent, C., and Changeux, J. (2003) A neuronal network
model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data
during conscious perception. PNAS July 8, 2003 vol. 100 no. 14
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/DehaeneSergentChangeux_BlinkModel_PNAS2003.pdf>
- Dehaene, S. et al. (2001) Cerebral mechanisms of word masking and
unconscious repetition priming. Nat. Neurosci, 4, 752-758.
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/Dehaene_MaskedWords_NatureNeuroscience2001.pdf>
- Dennett, D. and Kinsbourne, M. (1992) Time and the Observer: the
Where and When of Consciousness in the Brain. (1992) Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 15, 183-247, 1992. Reprinted in The Philosopher\'s
Annual, Grim, Mar and Williams, eds., vol. XV-1992, 1994,
pp. 23--68; Noel Sheehy and Tony Chapman, eds., Cognitive Science,
Vol. I, Elgar, 1995,
pp. 210--274.http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/time&obs.htm
- Destexhe, A. (2000). Modelling corticothalamic feedback and the
gating of the thalamus by the cerebral cortex. J. Physiol (Paris),
94 (2000) 391-410. <http://cns.iaf.cnrs-gif.fr/files/Brem2000.pdf>
- Fang, F. & He, S. (2005).Cortical responses to invisible objects in
the human dorsal and ventral pathways. Nat Neurosci. 2005
Oct;8(10):1380-5. Epub 2005 Sep 4.
- Ffytche, D. H., Howard, R. J., Brammer, M. J., David, A., Woodruff,
P., & Williams, S. (1998). The anatomy of conscious vision: an fMRI
study of visual hallucinations. Nature Neuroscience, 1, 738--742.
- Fiset, P., Paus, T., Daloze, T., Plourde, G., Meuret, P., Bonhomme,
V., Hajj-Ali, N., Backman, S.B., and Evans, A.C. (1999). Brain
Mechanisms of Propofol-Induced Loss of Consciousness in Humans: a
Positron Emission Tomographic Study. The Journal of Neuroscience,
July 1, 1999, 19(13):5506-5513.
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/13/5506>
- Fu, C.H.Y., Morgan, K., Suckling, J., Williams, S.C.R., Andrew, C.,
Vythelingum, G.N., McGuire, P.K. (2002). A Functional Magnetic
Resonance Imaging Study of Overt Letter Verbal Fluency Using a
Clustered Acquisition Sequence: Greater Anterior Cingulate
Activation with Increased Task Demand. NeuroImage 17, 871-
879 (2002)
<http://www-bmu.psychiatry.cam.ac.uk/PUBLICATION_STORE/fu02fun.pdf>
- Ganis, G., Thomson, W.L. and Kosslyn, S.M. (2004). Brain areas
underlying visual mental imagery and visual perception: an fMRI
study. Cognitive Brain Research 20 (2004) 226--241
<http://www.wjh.harvard.edu/~kwn/Kosslyn_pdfs/2004Ganis_CogBrainRes20_BrainAreas.pdf>
- Hultin, L. (1997). On Neuromagnetic Assessment of the Contingent
Negative Variation.
<http://www2.lib.chalmers.se/cth/diss/doc/9697/HultinLeif.html>
- Fries, P.. Roelfsema, P.R., Engel, A.K., König, P. and Singer, W.
(1997). Synchronization of oscillatory responses in visual cortex
correlates with perception in interocular rivalry. Proc. Natl. Acad.
Sci. USA, Vol. 94, pp. 12699--12704, November 1997.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/23/12699>
- Fuentealba, P., Crochet, S., Timofeev, I., Bazhenov, M., Sejnowski,
T.J. and Steriade, M. (2004). European Journal of Neuroscience
20(1):111-119. <http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2004/22126/ch03.html>
- Goaillard, J. & Vincent, P. (2002). Serotonin suppresses the slow
afterhyperpolarization in rat intralaminar and midline thalamic
neurones by activating 5-HT7 receptors. Journal of Physiology
(2002), 541.2, pp. 453--465
<http://jp.physoc.org/cgi/content/full/541/2/453>
- Haggard, P. & Eimer, M. (1999) On the relation between brain
potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Exp. Brain Res.
126, 128--133 (1999).
- Haggard, P. (2008) Human volition:towards a neuroscience of will.
Nature Rev Neurosci 9, 934-946
- Haynes, J., Deichmann, R. and Rees, G. (2005). Eye-specific effects
of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate nucleus. Nature
438, 496-499 (24 November 2005)
- Hughes S.W., Blethyn K.L. , Cope D.W. , & Crunelli V. (2003).
Properties and origin of spikelets in thalamocortical neurones in
vitro. Neuroscience. 2002;110(3):395-401
- Iramina, K., Maeno, T., Kowatari, Y. and Ueno, S.. (2002). Effects
of Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation on EEG Activity .IEEE
TRANSACTIONS ON MAGNETICS, VOL. 38, NO. 5, SEPTEMBER 2002
- Ishai, A., Ungerleider, L.G., Haxby, J.V.. (2000) Distributed neural
systems for the generation of visual images. Neuron 28, 979-990.
- Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1980). Mental models in cognitive science.
Cognitive Science, 4, 71-115.
<http://cognitrn.psych.indiana.edu/rgoldsto/cogsci/classics.html>
- Keller, J. & Heckhausen, H. (1990). Readiness potentials preceding
spontaneous motor acts: voluntary vs. involuntary control.
Electroencephalography and Clinical Neuropsychology, 76, 351-361.
- King, C.C. (1991). Fractal and Chaotic Dynamics in Nervous Systems.
Progress in Neurobiology, 36, pp. 279--308, 1991.
<http://citeseer.nj.nec.com/king91fractal.html>
- Klein, S.A (2002). Libet's Temporal Anomalies: A Reassessment of the
Data.
Consciousness and Cognition 11, 198--214 (2002)
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/160.pdf>
- Klein, S. (2002). Libet\'s Timing of Mental Events: Commentary on
the Commentaries. Consciousness and Cognition. 11, 326-333.
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/ccog_2002_0580-Klein-Commentary_on_the_commentaries.pdf>
- Kleinschmidt, A., Bichel, C. Zeki, S. and Frackowiak, R.S.J. (1998).
Human brain activity during spontaneously reversing perception of
ambiguous figures. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 1998 Dec
22;265(1413):2427-33
- Konishi, S., Wheeler, M.E., Donaldson, D.I., Buckner, R.L.. (2000)
Neural correlates of episodic retrieval success. NeuroImage: 12:
276-286.
- Kornhuber HH, Deecke L: Hirnpotentialänderungen beim Menschen vor
und nach Willkürbewegungen, dargestellt mit Magnetbandspeicherung
und Rückwärtsanalyse. Pflügers Arch. ges. Physiol. 281 (1964) 52.
- Kosslyn, S.M., Thompson, W.L. (2003). When is early visual cortex
activated during visual mental imagery? Psychol. Bull. 129
(2003)723-746.
- Kreiman, G., Koch, C. and Fried, I. (2000). Imagery neurons in the
human brain. Nature (2000) 408: 357-361
<http://www.cns.caltech.edu/~gabriel/publications/imagination1.html>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I., & Koch, C. (2001). Single neuron responses
in humans during binocular rivalry and flash suppression. Journal of
Vision, 1(3), 131a, <http://journalofvision.org/1/3/131>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I. And Koch, C. (2002) Single Neuron responses
in the human brain during flash suppression. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Science USA, 99:8378-8383
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031015091920/http://www.ai.mit.edu/projects/cbcl/publications/ps/kreimanetal_flash-suppression.pdf>
- Larsen, A., Madsen, K.H., Lund, T.E., and Bundesen, C. (2006).
Images of Illusory Motion in Primary Visual Cortex. Journal of
Cognitive Neuroscience. 2006;18:1174-1180.
- Laureys, S. et al. (2002). Brain function in the vegetative state.
Acta neurol. belg., 2002, 102, 177-185
<http://www.jsmf.org/meetings/2003/nov/LaureysANB2002.pdf>
- Lee. S, and Blake, R. (2002). V1 activity is reduced during
binocular rivalry. Journal of Vision (2002) 2, 618-626
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030722173225/http://journalofvision.org/2/9/4/article.pdf>
- Leopold, D.A. and Logothetis, N.K. (1999). Multistable phenomena:
changing views in perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 3:
254-264.
<http://www.kyb.tuebingen.mpg.de/publications/pdfs/pdf201.pdf>
- Libet, B., Alberts, E.W., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B.(1967).
Responses of Human Somatosensory Cortex to Stimuli Below Threshold
for Conscious Sensation. Science 158, 1597-1600.
- Libet, B., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B., and Pearl, D.(1979).
Subjective referral of the timing for a conscious sensory
experience. Brain, 102, pp. 192--224.
<http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/entrez/query.fcgi?holding=npg&cmd=Retrieve&db=PubMed&list_uids=427530&dopt=Abstract>
- Linden, D.E.J. (2005) The P300: Where in the Brain Is It Produced
and What Does It Tell Us? The Neuroscientist, Vol. 11, No. 6,
563-576 (2005) <http://nro.sagepub.com/cgi/reprint/11/6/563.pdf>
- Llinas, R., Ribary, U., Contreras, D. & Pedroarena, C. (1998). The
neuronal basis for consciousness. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London Ser.
B.353, 1841-1849
<http://big.cs.uiuc.edu/anncbt-papers/fall05/Llinas.the-neuronal-basis-of-consciousness.pdf>
- Logothetis, N.K., Leopold, D.A. and Sheinberg, D.L. (1996). What is
Rivalling During Binocular Rivalry. Nature, 380:621-624.
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nature/journal/v380/n6575/abs/380621a0.html>
- Loveblad, KO. et al. (1999). Silent functional magnetic resonance
imaging demonstrates focal activation in rapid eye movement sleep.
Neurology 1999;53:2193Z
- Luce, R.D. (1986). Response times: their role in inferring
elementary mental organization. Oxford University Press, New York.
- Lumer, E.D., Friston, K.J. & Rees, G. (1998) Neural correlates of
perceptual rivalry in the human brain. Science. 280(5371):1930-4.
- Macdonald, K.D., Fifkova, E., Jones, M.S. and Barth, D.S. (1998)
Focal Stimulation of the Thalamic Reticular Nucleus Induces Focal
Gamma Waves in Cortex. The Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 79 No. 1
January 1998, pp. 474--477
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/79/1/474>
- Maia, T.V. & Cleeremans, A. (2005). Consciousness: converging
insights from connectionist modeling and neuroscience. TRENDS in
Cognitive Sciences Vol.9 No.8 August 2005
<http://srsc.ulb.ac.be/axcWWW/papers/pdf/05-TICS.pdf>
- Marcel AJ. (1998). Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of
visual consciousness or visual function? Brain 1998, 121, 1565-1588.
<http://brain.oupjournals.org/cgi/reprint/121/8/1565.pdf>
- Marois, R., Yi, D-J., & Chun, M.M. (2004). The Neural Fate of
Consciously Perceived and Missed Events in the Attentional Blink.
Neuron, 41, 3: 465-472.
- Mashour, G.A., Tononi, G. and Massimini, M. (2005). Cognitive
Unbinding in Sleep and Anesthesia. Science 16 December 2005:
1768-1769.
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
<http://juno.ingentaselect.com/vl=6492085/cl=26/nw=1/rpsv/cgi-bin/cgi?body=linker&ini=nlm&reqidx=issn=0962-8452vl=264is=1380yr=1997mn=Marpg=393>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). Responses of Spectrally
Selective Cells in Macaque Area V2 to Wavelengths and Colors. J
Neurophysiol 87: 2104-2112, 2002.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/87/4/2104>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). The relationship between
cortical activation and perception investigated with invisible
stimuli. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA, 99(14):9527-9532.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/99/14/9527>
- Muckli, L., Singer, W., Zanella, F.E. and Goebel, R. (2002)
Integration of multiple motion vectors over space: an fMRI study of
transparent motion perception. Neuroimage. 2002 Aug;16(4):843-56.
- Munhall, K.G. (2001). Functional Imaging During Speech Production.
Acta Psychologica 107 (2001) 95-117.
<http://pavlov.psyc.queensu.ca/~munhallk/07_acta_version.pdf>
- Munk MHJ, Roelfsema PR, König P, Engel AK, and Singer W. (1996).
Role of reticular activation in the modulation of intracortical
synchronization Science. 272, 271-274.
- Newman, J. & Baars, B.J. (1993) A neural attentional model for
access to consciousness: A Global Workspace perspective. Concepts in
Neuroscience, 4:2, 255-290
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000073/>
- Nieuwenhuis S, Aston-Jones G & Cohen JD (2005). Decision making, the
P3, and the locus coeruleus-norepinephrine system. Psychological
Bulletin, 131(4), 510-532.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051117045339/http://www.csbmb.princeton.edu/conte/pdfs/project5/Proj5Pub06.pdf>
- Nørretranders, T. (1991) Consciousness: The User Illusion
(translated from Danish), Penguin Books,
; 1999 revision:
<http://www.worldcat.org/title/user-illusion-cutting-consciousness-down-to-size/oclc/41311618>.
- Pantev C (1995) Evoked and induced gamma-band activity of the human
cortex. Brain Topogr 7:321-330
- Pasley BN, Mayes LC, Schultz RT (2004) Subcortical discrimination of
unperceived objects during binocular rivalry. Neuron 2004,
42:163-172.
- Pessoa, L. (2005) To what extent are emotional visual stimuli
processed without attention and awareness? Current Opinion in
Neurobiology 2005, 15:188-196
<http://web.archive.org/web/20060623004726/http://www.brown.edu/Research/LCE/publications_files/Pessoa_CONB_2005.pdf>
- Pettigrew, J.D. (2001) Searching for the Switch: Neural Bases for
Perceptual Rivalry Alternations. Brain and Mind 2: 85-118, 2001.
<http://www.uq.edu.au/nuq/jack/searchswitch.pdf>
- Raymond, J. E, Shapiro, K. L., & Arnell, K. M. (1992). Temporary
suppression of visual processing in an RSVP task: An attentional
blink? Journal of Experimental Psychology. Human Perception and
Performance, 18 (3), 849-60.
- Rektor, I., Bares, M., Kanovsky, P. and Kukleta, M. (2001)
Intracerebral recording of readiness potential induced by a complex
motor task. Movement Disorders, Volume 16, Issue 4, Pages 698-704
- Rees, G., Kreiman, G., & Koch, C. (2002) Neural Correlates of
Consciousness in Humans. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3, 261
-270 (2002)
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nrn/journal/v3/n4/abs/nrn783_fs.html&dynoptions=doi1069842948>
- Rensink, RA. (2000). When Good Observers Go Bad: Change Blindness,
Inattentional Blindness, and Visual Experience. PSYCHE, 6(09),
August 2000.
<http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v6/psyche-6-09-rensink.html>
- Roy, J.E. & Prichep, L.S. (2005) The Anesthetic Cascade: A Theory of
How Anesthesia Suppresses Consciousness Anesthesiology: Volume
102(2) February 2005 pp 447--471
<http://www.anesthesiology.org/pt/re/anes/fulltext.00000542-200502000-00030.htm>
- Schiff, N.D., & Plum F. 1999. The Neurology of Impaired
Consciousness: Global Disorders and Implied Models. \[Target
article\]. Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness.
<http://www.phil.vt.edu/assc/niko.html>
- Schiff ND, Plum F. (2000) The Role of Arousal and \"Gating\" Systems
in the Neurology of Impaired Consciousness. Journal of
Neurophysiology. 17(5):438-452. (
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030924010953/http://www.uni-tuebingen.de/cog/lehre/ss2003/seminar_bewusstsein/epapers/SchiffPlum00.pdf>
- Sheinberg, D.L. and Logothetis, N.K. (1997). The role of temporal
cortical areas in perceptual organization. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA 94, 3408-3413. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/7/3408>
- Simons, D.J. & Rensink, RA. (2005). Change blindness: Past, present,
and future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol.9, pp16--20, No.1
January 2005.
<http://www.psych.ubc.ca/~rensink/publications/download/S&R-TICS-05a.pdf>
- Singer, W. & Gray, C.W. (1995). Visual feature integration and the
temporal correlation hypothesis. Annu. Rev. Neurosci., 18,
pp. 555--86, 1995.
- Singer, W. (2001). Consciousness and the Binding Problem. Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences 929:123-146 (2001)
- Solms, Mark (2000) DREAMING AND REM SLEEP ARE CONTROLLED BY
DIFFERENT BRAIN MECHANISMS, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23
(6): 793.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/Preprints/OldArchive/bbs.solms.html>
- Soon, C.S., Brass, M., Heinze, H-J. and Haynes, J-D. (2008).
Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain.
Nature Neuroscience 11, 543 - 545 (2008)
- Sukov, W. & Barth, D.S. (2001). Cellular Mechanisms of Thalamically
Evoked Gamma Oscillations in Auditory Cortex. J Neurophysiol 85:
1235-1245, 2001;
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/85/3/1235>
- Takeuchi, T., Miyasita, A., Inugami, M. & Yamamoto, Y. (2001).
Intrinsic dreams are not produced without REM sleep mechanisms:
evidence through elicitation of sleep onset REM periods. Journal of
Sleep Research Volume 10 Issue 1 Page 43 - March 2001
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tamás, G., Buh, E.H., Lörincz, A., and Somogyi, P. (2000).
Proximally targeted GABAergic synapses and gap junctions synchronize
cortical interneurons. Nature Neuroscience volume 3 no 4 April 2000.
<http://mrcanu.pharm.ox.ac.uk/pdfs/TamasNatureNeurosci2000.pdf>
- Tanaka, Y. & Sagi, D. (1998). A perceptual memory for low contrast
visual signals. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol 95:12729-12733.
<http://www.weizmann.ac.il/~masagi/TS98b.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2001). Competing Theories of Binocular Rivalry: A Possible
Resolution. Brain and Mind 2: 55-83, 2001
<http://web.archive.org/web/20041212094810/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_Brain&Mind2001.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual Awareness. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030723135239/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
- Tootell, R.B., Reppas, J.B., Dale, A.M., Look, R.B., Sereno, M.I.,
Malach, R., Brady, T.J. and Rosen, B.R. (1995) Visual motion
aftereffect in human cortical area MT revealed by functional
magnetic resonance imaging. Nature. 1995 May 11;375(6527):139-41.
- Tononi, G., Srinivasan, R., Russell, P.D. & Edelman, G.M. (1998).
Investigating neural correlates of conscious perception by
frequency-tagged neuromagnetic responses . Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA. Vol. 95, Issue 6, 3198-3203, March 17, 1998
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/95/6/3198>
- Thornton, I.M., Pinto, J. and Shiffrar, M. (1998).
THE VISUAL PERCEPTION OF HUMAN LOCOMOTION. COGNITIVE NEUROPSYCHOLOGY,
1998, 15 (6/7/8 ), 535-552.
<http://psychology.rutgers.edu/~mag/TPS98.pdf>
- Traub, D.R., Whittington, M.A., Buhl, E.H., Jefferys, J.G.R., &
Faulkner, H.J. (1999). On the Mechanism of the Frequency Shift in
Neuronal Oscillations Induced in Rat Hippocampal Slices by Tetanic
Stimulation. The Journal of Neuroscience, February 1, 1999,
19(3):1088-1105
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/3/1088>
- Traub, R.D. (2003). Fast Oscillations and Epilepsy. Epilepsy Curr.
2003 May; 3(3): 77-79.
<http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/articlerender.fcgi?artid=321178>
- Trevena J & Miller, J (2002) Cortical Movement Preparation before
and after a Conscious Decision to Move. Consciousness and Cognition,
Volume 11, Issue 2, June 2002, Pages 162-190
- Trevena, J & Miller, J (2009) Brain preparation before a voluntary
action: Evidence against unconscious movement initiation. Conscious
Cogn. 2009 Sep 5. \[Epub ahead of print\]
- Tse, P.U., Susana Martinez-Conde, S., Schlegel, A.A. and Macknik,
S.L. (2005). Visibility, visual awareness, and visual masking of
simple unattended targets are confined to areas in the occipital
cortex beyond human V1/V2. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA November 22,
2005 vol. 102 no. 47. 17178-17183.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/102/47/17178>
- Uchida, N., Kepecs, A. and Mainen, Z.F. (2006) Seeing at a glance,
smelling in a whiff: rapid forms of perceptual decision making.
Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 7. 485-491.
- Uchida, N & Mainen, Z.F. (2003) Speed and accuracy of olfacory
discrimination in the rat. Nature Neurosci. 6, 1224-1229.
- Vogel, E.K., Luck, S.J. & Shapiro, K.L. (1998) Electrophysiological
Evidence for a Postperceptual Locus of Suppression During the
Attentional Blink. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
Perception and Performance 1998, Vol. 24. No. 6,1656-1674
<http://web.archive.org/web/20050304211722/http://www.psychology.uiowa.edu/faculty/Luck/lucklab/pdfs/Vogel_1998_JEPHPP.pdf>
- Wehrle, R., Czisch, M., Kaufmann, C., Wetter, T.C., Holsboer, F.,
Auer, D.P., and Pollmacher, T. (2005). Rapid eye movement-related
brain activation in human sleep: a functional magnetic resonance
imaging study. NeuroReport 16:853-857
<http://www.univie.ac.at/mcogneu/lit/wehrle.pdf>
- White, NS., Alkire, MT. (2003). Impaired thalamocortical
connectivity in humans during
general-anesthetic-induced unconsciousness. NeuroImage. Volume 19, Issue
2 , June 2003, Pages 402-411. <http://smallurl.com?i=2597>
(http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/B6WNP-48GP5CG-5/1/cedb33dc0bec4301d1960c7c27cea70f)
- Wheeler, M.E., Buckner, R.L.. (2003) Functional dissociation among
components
of remembering: control, perceived oldness, and content. J. Neurosci.
23, 3869-3880.
- Williams LM, Liddell BJ, Rathjen J, Brown KJ, Shevrin H, Gray JA,
Phillips M, Young A & Gordon E (2004). Mapping the time course of
nonconscious and conscious perception of fear: An integration of
central and peripheral measures. Human Brain Mapping,21, 64 - 74
<http://psychmed.iop.kcl.ac.uk/neuroscience-and-emotion/downloads/46.pdf>
- Wunderlich, K. Schneider, K.A., & Kastner, S. (2005).Neural
correlates of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate
nucleus. Nature Neuroscience 8, 1595 - 1602 (2005)
- Yamamoto, T. & Katayama, Y. (2005). Deep brain stimulation therapy
for the vegetative state. in Neuropsychol Rehabil. 2005 Jul-Sep ;
15(3-4): 406-13
- Zeki, S., & Bartel, A. (1999). Toward a Theory of Visual
Consciousness. Consciousness & Cognition, 8, 225-259.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 2#Binocular Rivalry, Pattern Rivalry and Binocular Fusion
*Contributors: please include full data in the references section for
all references in the text.*
```{=html}
<div class="noprint">
```
Home
```{=html}
</div>
```
## Perceptual \"filling in\"
Perceptual \"filling in\" occurs when visual properties such as
textures, colours, brightness or motion are extended in the visual field
to areas where they do not have corresponding events in the world.
The filling in of the blind spot by the properties of the field in the
contralateral eye has already been discussed. The part of the visual
field represented by the blind spot is also \"filled in\" in the case of
monocular vision.
![](Constudblindill.png "Constudblindill.png")
Shut the right eye and focus on the pink cross with the left eye, if the
head is moved towards the pink cross there is a point at which the
yellow disk disappears but the white lines are still present. In this
\"filling in\" the visual field does not appear to be distorted.
Fiorani *et al.* (1992) developed a technique for probing the cortical
blind spot using vertical and horizontal bar stimuli. Matsumoto &
komatsu (2005) used this technique on macaque monkeys. In the monocular
case they found that as a bar was moved across the visual field so that
it crossed the blind spot there was a sudden change in neural activity
in the deep layers of the neurons in the blind spot area of V1. When the
bar was moved across the same part of the visual field of the
contralateral eye the neural activity in the blind spot area increased
steadily as the bar was moved. The authors found that there were neurons
in the deep layers of blind spot cortex that had elongated receptive
fields that could respond to stimuli outside the blind spot and transfer
this activation into the blind spot cortex.
Filling in of a slightly different type occurs in \"scotoma\". In
scotoma an area of the retina is damaged and unresonsive to visual
stimuli, immediately after the damage patients report an area of visual
field that is unresponsive to stimuli. After several months patients
report that the area of field represented by the scotoma contains visual
properties related to the physical world surrounding the area that would
have formed an image on the scotoma. This results in a distortion of the
visual field. (see for instance Gilbert(1993)). Direct measurements of
activity in cortical area V1 show that the neurons that represented the
area of the scotoma become sensitive to activity in the surrounding
visual field. At the cortical level the scotoma is literally \"filled
in\".
There are many stimuli that cause \"filling in\". These stimuli are
known as \"illusions\" because they produce phenomenal experience that
has no correlate in the world outside the body. In the \"neon colour
spreading illusion\" a lightly coloured circle appears where there
should be a white background. Sasaki and Watanabe (2004) used fMRI to
show that the part of the topographic map in cortical area V1
corresponding to the light coloured circle was activated.
![](Constudneon.jpg "Constudneon.jpg")
Fiorani, M., Rosa, M.G.P., Gattas, R. & Rocha-Miranda, C.E. (1992).
Dynamic surrounds of receptive fields in primate striate cortex: a
physiological basis for perceptual completion? Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
89, 8547-8551. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/abstract/89/18/8547>
Gilbert, C.D. (1993). Circuitry, architecture and functional dynamics of
visual cortex.
Matsumoto, M & Komatsu, H. (2005). Neural responses in the macaque V1 to
bar stimuli with various lengths presented on the blind spot. J
neurophysiol. 93. 2374-2387.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/abstract/93/5/2374>
Sasaki, Y & Watanabe, T. The primary visual cortex fills in colour.
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 101, 18251-18256. (2004).
## Binocular Rivalry, Pattern Rivalry and Binocular Fusion
Sir Charles Wheatstone (1838) was the first scientist to systematically
investigate binocular rivalry. Binocular rivalry occurs when different
images are presented to the left and right eyes. The subject sees
successively one image, a combined image and then the other image. The
swapping of images can take a second or more. Binocular rivalry is of
interest in consciousness research because the parts of the brain that
contain the dominant image should also be those parts that are
contributing to conscious experience. Binocular rivalry involves at
least two components; the first switches from one image to a merged
image and then to the other image and the second permits the view to be
part of conscious experience.
![](Constudrival.png "Constudrival.png")
The switching of one image for another may involve selecting one of the
images as the percept or selecting one of the eyes. Blake *et al.*
(1979) performed an experiment in which subjects could change the image
at a given eye by pressing a button. When a particular image became
dominant they pressed a button to change the image at the eye receiving
the dominant image for the non-dominant image. They found that the
subjects immediately experienced the second image as the dominant image.
This suggests that binocular rivalry is selecting between eyes rather
than images. Lehky in 1988 proposed that the switching may be occurring
as a result of feedback between visual cortical area V1 and the Lateral
Geniculate Nucleus (a thalamic relay - see Carandini *et al.* 2002) and
Blake in 1989 also proposed that the switching occurred at the level of
area V1. (Visual cortical area V1 receives visual input direct from the
LGN.)
Tong (2001) has argued that, in humans, the switching of images in
binocular rivalry may occur at the earliest levels in the visual cortex.
In particular, Tong and Engel (2001) used an elegant technique measuring
the activity in the visual cortex that represents the blind spot of the
eye to show that almost complete switching to the dominant image occurs
at the level of visual cortical area V1. In support of this idea of
switching at the level of V1 or even before the cortex, Kreimann *et
al.* (2001, 2002) used direct electrode recordings in human cortex and
found that the activity of most neurons changed with the percept. Other
experiments have not shown a single locus in the brain where the
suppressed sensory information gets switched out (Blake & Logothetis
2002, Leopold & Logothetis 1996, Gail et al., 2004).
Functional MRI has also shown cortical activity outside of sensory
visual cortex related to both images in binocular rivalry. Lumer *et
al.* (1998) found that only the fronto-parietal areas of cortex switched
with the percept, Fang & He (2005) found that activity relating to both
suppressed and unsuppressed images were present in the dorsal stream of
the visual system. Wunderlich *et al.* (2005) and Haynes *et al.* (2005)
have both found suppression at the level of the lateral geniculate
nucleus using fMRI in humans.
Pasley *et al.* (2004) have shown that, even during suppression, fearful
faces can produce activity in the amygdala (see Pessoa (2005) for a
review).
Rivalry alternations seem to be the result of widespread activity
changes that cover large parts of the brain, including but not
necessarily originating at the earliest sensory stages of visual
processing. Most investigators have found that, once switching has
occurred, there are areas of the brain that contain activity that is
solely related to the percept but this varies from most of the cortex to
largely more frontal regions depending upon the study. The most likely
explanation for binocular rivalry is that the switching occurs at the
level of the LGN as a result of feedback from the cortex.
Pattern Rivalry is also of interest in consciousness research for the
same reasons as binocular rivalry. In pattern rivalry a figure may have
two or more forms that replace each other. Typical examples of such
figures are the Necker cube and Rubin\'s face-vase. The similarity of
the time course of the switching between percepts in binocular rivalry
and pattern rivalry has led many authors to suggest that these involve
the same mechanism. Logothetis *et al.* (1996) used novel dichoptic
stimuli (different images to each eyes) to produce a form of rivalry
that seems to involve switching at levels in the cerebral cortex that
are more distal to the sensory stimulus than V1. Leopold and Logothetis
(1999), on the basis of their work with monkeys, state that \"..many
neurons throughout the visual system, both monocular and binocular,
continue to respond to a stimulus even when it is perceptually
suppressed.\". Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998) investigated pattern rivalry
with MRI and found activity in higher order visual areas during change
of dominant pattern. Pettigrew (2001) also describes effects on rivalry
due to thought and mood that may require involvement of large areas of
cortex in the switching operation and stresses the way that V1
represents different visual fields in different hemispheres of the brain
so that inter-hemispheric switching must also be considered.
It seems likely that the change of dominant pattern or percept is
associated with higher level cortical activity but once the dominant
percept is established many of the visually responsive neurons in the
cortex are switched over to the new percept. This might account for the
similarities in timing of binocular and pattern rivalry and the
disparate results found by the various groups of authors. In the words
of Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998):
\"The transient activity fluctuations we found suggest that perceptual
metastability elicited by ambiguous stimuli is associated with rapid
redistributions of neural activity between separate specialized cortical
and subcortical structures.\"
Which permits both the idea of selecting particular eyes or percepts,
perhaps by feedback that switches a thalamic relay on the basis of
cortical processing of patterns. Once the cortex has switched the
thalamic relay most of the neurons in V1 would become exposed to the
dominant percept but there would still be a few neurons in the cortical
visual system receiving data from the non dominant image.
The investigations of binocular and pattern rivalry provide evidence
that conscious visual experience is probably distal to V1 (i.e.: cortex
or thalamus).
Perceptual rivalry may be part of complex decision making rather than
being simply a switch to blank out unwelcome input. It is clear from the
Rubin face-vase that pattern rivalry is linked to recognition and would
involve a complex delineation of forms within cortical processing. This
would suggest that many areas of cortex should be involved before a
particular percept is made dominant. Pettigrew (2001) argues that
rivalry is the result of a complex phenomenon rather than being simply a
switching event. Pettigrew\'s discovery that laughter abolishes rivalry
also points to a complex cortical system for switching percepts.
Pettigrew proposes that complex cortical processes control rivalry and
that the actual switching of percepts is performed sub-cortically in the
Ventral Tegmental Area. He concludes his review of the problem by noting
that \"Rivalry may thus reflect fundamental aspects of perceptual
decision making..\" Pettigrew (2001).
Another effect, known as \"binocular fusion\", provides further
compelling evidence for the non-conscious nature of the cerebral cortex.
In binocular fusion images from both eyes are fused together to create a
single image in experience. Moutoussis and Zeki (2002) used a form of
binocular fusion in which images of faces were flashed at 100ms
intervals to both eyes simultaneously. When both eyes received images of
the same colour the subject could see the faces but when one eye
received a green image on a red background and the other a red image on
a green background the subjects reported seeing a uniform yellow field
that contained no faces.
fMRI scans of the subject\'s brains showed that when both eyes were
exposed to images of the same colour the part of the brain that deals
with faces was active and when each eye received images of different
colours the same areas of brain showed activity. In other words the
cortex contained strong activity related to faces whether or not faces
were experienced. Moutoussis and Zeki found a similar effect when they
used images of houses instead of images of faces. The authors concluded
that: \"The present study further suggests that there are no separate
processing and perceptual areas but rather that the same cortical
regions are involved in both the processing and, when certain levels of
activation are reached and probably in combination with the activation
of other areas as well, the generation of a conscious visual percept\".
This conclusion does not seem to be supported by the data. There is no
evidence that any area of cortex contains the percept itself. The
experiment shows that the cortex contains data relating to both red and
green faces which suggests that the cortex is not the site of the
conscious percept. The percept is most likely distal to the cortex
perhaps in the thalamus or some other area that receives cortical
sensory output.
It is interesting that Fries *et al.* (1997) found that neurons that
were activated by the dominant image in binocular rivalry fired
synchronously whereas those that were activated by the non-dominant
image did not. Thalamocorticothalamic oscillations are the most likely
source for synchronising neurons over whole areas of cortex, suggesting
that the conscious percept is located in the thalamus rather than the
cortex.
## Synchronisation of Neural Processes
Our experience seems to contain entities with their attributes attached
to them at the correct places in space and time. When a dog barks we see
its jaws open at the same time as the bark and both jaws and bark are at
the same location. We take this for granted but the brain must be
engaging in some complex processing to achieve this synchronised and
appropriately positioned set of objects and events. The illustration
below shows the two basic processes that might be used to synchronise
events between the different specialised processors in the cerebral
cortex and brain in general.
![](Constudsynch.gif "Constudsynch.gif")
In the first option a complete model of sensation, dream etc. may be
created and then allowed to become part of conscious experience. In the
second model events are released into experience as fast as possible but
are synchronous when recalled, having been synchronised in a storage
buffer. There is a third option in which there is no synchronisation of
events so that the output from different processors would occur at
different times.
The \'experience buffer\' would be a volume of brain in which a
succession of events could be recorded. The buffer might either be
updated in steps, the previous content being discarded, or continuously
updated with the oldest content being lost continuously.
In the first option events from different processes would always appear
to be simultaneous unless the experience buffer were updated as a series
of steps in which case any changes at around the moment of updating
might appear in successive buffers. For instance, if change of position
were processed before change in colour a circle on a screen that changed
from green to red at the start of a motion might seem to be briefly
green during the motion and then turn red.
In the second model events from different processors might appear
asynchronous at the moment of experience but synchronous when recalled.
Colour vision and motion vision are processed in different parts of the
visual cortex and in distinct parts of visual cortical areas V1 and V2.
They are different processes and hence ideal for studying the
synchronisation of cortical activity. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997)
presented subjects with moving coloured squares on a computer screen
that changed from red to green or vice versa as they changed direction
of movement. It was found that subjects seemed to perceive changes in
colour some 70-80 msecs before they perceived a change in the direction
of motion of the squares. Further work by Arnold *et al.* (2001) and
Arnold and Clifford (2001) have confirmed that colour changes seem to be
perceived before motion. Arnold and Clifford (2001) also found a
quantitative relationship between the colour/motion asynchrony and the
direction of change of motion, complete reversals of direction giving
rise to the greatest asynchrony between the detection of colour and
motion changes.
Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) conclude by stating that the asynchrony of
neural processes shows that \"..the perception of each attribute is
solely the result of the activity in the specialised system involved in
its processing..\". It seems more likely that the experiments simply
show that slow neural processes are not synchronised before they become
percepts (the third option above). The experiments are excellent
evidence for the concept of the cortex as a set of specialised
processors that deliver their output asynchronously to some other place
where the output becomes a percept.
These experiments on colour and motion suggest that there is no
synchronisation between the processes that deal with these two aspects
of vision. Another set of experiments by Clifford *et al.* (2003)
supports this idea of processing being asynchronous. They asked subjects
to perform a variety of judgements of when visual events occurred and
found that the degree of synchrony of one visual event with another
depends on the type of judgement. Different judgements probably use
processors in different areas of cortex and the output from these
arrives asynchronously at the part of the brain that supports the
percept.
When the percept is formed there must be feedback to the cortical
processes that create its content. Otherwise it would not be possible to
report about the percept and the cortex would be unable to direct
processing to the percept in preference to other, non-conscious cortical
data.
Although slow processes (20 milliseconds to 1 second) do not seem to be
synchronised there is some evidence for very rapid synchronisation.
Andrews *et al.* (1996) revisited a problem raised by the famous
physiologist Charles Sherrington. Sherrington considered the phenomenon
of \'flicker fusion\' in which a flickering light appears to be a
continuous steady light if it flashes on and off at frequencies of about
45 Hz or higher. He reasoned that if the images from both eyes are
brought together to form a single image then the frequency at which a
flickering light appears to be steady should depend on whether one or
two eyes are used. Flicker fusion should occur if each eye receives
alternate flashes at only half the normal flicker fusion frequency. The
flicker should disappear if the left eye receives flashes at 23 pulses
per second and the right eye receives alternate flashes at 23 pulses per
second. When Sherrington performed the experiment he found that this was
not the case, using approximate figures, each eye required 46 pulses per
second for fusion to occur. Sherrington proposed that the flicker fusion
in alternate binocular presentation was occurring \"psychically\",
outside of normal physiological processes.
Andrews *et al.* duplicated Sherrington\'s result but investigated it
further. They found that when lights were flashed in each eye
alternately at low frequences (2 Hz) the experience was the same as a
light being flashed in both eyes at this rate. At frequencies of four Hz
and higher the subjects began to report that the lights being flashed
alternately in both eyes seemed to flicker at the same rate as lights
being flashed in both eyes at half the frequency. It seemed as if a
flash in one eye followed by a flash in the other eye was being
perceived as a single flash or \"conflated\" as the authors put it. The
authors explained this effect by suggesting that the brain activity
corresponding to the flashes was sampled for a short period and any
number of flashes occurring during this period became perceived as a
single flash. The maximum rate of sampling would be about 45 Hz. This
idea is similar to option (1) above, where the buffer is filled and
emptied 40 - 50 times a second.
An experience buffer that is refreshed at 40-50 times a second might
also explain the results obtained with colour and motion asynchrony
because synchronisation between processes may well happen too quickly to
affect processes that occur at very slow rates. Singer and Gray (1995),
Singer (2001) have proposed that synchronisation between neurones at
about 45 Hz is the discriminator between those neurones with activity
that contributes to conscious experience and activity in other neurones.
A rapid refresh rate in a synchronising buffer agrees with the results
found by Fries *et al.* (1997) in which visual cortical neurones that
represent a percept underwent synchronous oscillations in the gamma
frequency range (39--63 Hz). Tononi *et al.* (1998) have also found
synchronisation of neural activity in neurones that represent the
percept.
The gamma frequency oscillations are intrinsic to the cortex but are
triggered by the thalamus and are part of the \'arousal system\'.
Readers should be wary of the term \'arousal system\' because it evokes
the idea of something waking up a conscious cortex. The cortex can be
fully active during sleep and even during pathological unconsciousness
such as persistent vegetative state so it is possible that the arousal
centres themselves or nearby structures actually host phenomenal
consciousness.
## EEG and synchronisation
If electrodes are placed on the scalp varying electrical potentials of a
few tens of microvolts can be recorded between the electrodes.
Recordings of potentials from electrodes on the scalp are known as
electroencephalograms (EEGs).
The potentials recorded in the EEG are due to postsynaptic potentials in
nerve cells. The EEG is insensitive to the activity of single cells and
occurs as a result of relatively slow, **synchronised**, changes in
large areas of cells. The differences in potential between two scalp
electrodes are largely due to depolarisation and hyperpolarisation of
the dendritic trees of cortical pyramidal cells. The folding of the
cortex (gyri) is problematical for recording and interpreting EEGs
because opposing layers of cortex can cancel any net potentials.
The EEG shows rhythmic activity. This is conventionally divided into the
following frequency bands:
Delta waves 0--4 Hz
Theta waves 4--8 Hz
Alpha waves 8--12 Hz
Beta waves \>10 Hz
Gamma waves (also called fast beta) 25--100 Hz
EEGs also contain short bursts of activity called spindles and very fast
oscillations (VFOs). Spindles last for 1--2 seconds and contain rhythmic
activity at 7--14 Hz. They are associated with the onset of sleep. The
VFOs consist of short bursts at frequencies of over 80 Hz.
When the eyes are closed the amplitude of activity from most pairs of
electrodes is increased compared with when the eyes are open. When
subjects are awake the EEG consists mainly of alpha and beta activity
with considerable low amplitude gamma when the eyes are open. In stage 1
sleep the EEG consists of theta waves, in stage 2 sleep of varied
activity and spindles, in stage 4 sleep of delta and during REM sleep of
beta and theta activity. In epileptic seizures there tends to be high
amplitude activity with pronounced synchronisation between many pairs of
electrodes.
The rhythmic electrical activity is due to cortical feedback loops,
cortico-cortical synchronisation, thalamic pacemakers and
thalamo-cortical synchronisation. VFOs have been attributed to the
activity of electrical connections between cells (dendro-dendritic gap
junctions) (Traub (2003)).
The gamma activity, centred on a frequency of 40 Hz appears to be
related to activity in cortical interneurons that form electrical
connections between their dendrites (Tamas *et al.* 2000). These
oscillations can be triggered by high frequency stimulation of the
posterior intralaminar nuclei of the thalamus (Barth and MacDonald 1996,
Sukov and Barth 2001) and as a result of activation of the reticular
system (Munk *et al.* 1996). This suggests that stimulation of cortex by
thalamic sensory relays triggers gamma band activity in the cortex. A
shift from gamma to beta waves can occur in human event related
potentials after about 0.2 secs (Pantev 1995, Traub *et al.* 1999).
The alpha activity is related to thalamic pacemakers, perhaps as a
result of intrinsic oscillatory activity in thalamic sensory relays (see
Roy & Prichep 2005 for a brief review). Theta activity, which occurs
during some cognitive tasks and mental arithmetic involves a loop from
the cortex to the non-specific thalamic nuclei. Delta activity seems to
be endogenous to cortex when input is suppressed during sleep. Beta
activity is due to cortico-cortical interactions, often after a brief
period of gamma activation. It should be noted that gamma and beta
activity can be expressed as impulses in cortico-thalamic pathways and
that when cortical and thalamic activity is correlated there is a
conscious state. In other words gamma or beta waves in the cortex are
not correlates of consciousness on their own - see for instance Laureys
*et al.* (2002).
## Event related potentials
After a sudden event there are a characteristic set of changes in EEG
activity known as **event related potentials** or ERPs. The time course
of the ERP is shown in the diagram below.
![](Constudevent.png "Constudevent.png")
ERPs occur in response to novel stimuli and are also produced by brief
transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS)(Iramina *et al.* 2002). The slow
component is known as the P3 or P300 phase of the ERP. It is due to
activation of areas of the brain that are relatively remote from the
primary sensory areas of brain.
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) have reviewed the origin of the P300 ERP:
\"To summarize, convergent evidence suggests that P3-like activity can
be recorded in several, widely separated brain areas. These include some
medial temporal and subcortical structures (e.g., the hippocampal
formation, amygdala, and thalamus), but these structures are unlikely to
contribute directly to the scalp-recorded P3.\". According to
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) the recorded P300 may be due to
temporo-parietal and prefrontal cortical activity. Linden (2005) has
also concluded that widespread, but specific, cortical activation is
correlated with the recorded P300 ERP.
The generator of the P300 is still obscure. Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005)
consider that the Locus coeruleus, a nucleus in the pons that regulates
task related attention and part of the sleep-wake cycle, may be
responsible. In line with this, Mashour *et al.* (2005) have discovered
that TMS induced P300 activity is reduced in unconscious states.
Whether the P300 is related to Libet\'s 0.5 second delay is still
obscure but the discovery that the P300 occurs in association with
subliminal stimuli (stimuli that do not enter awareness)(Bernat *et al.*
2001) suggests that it is associated with non-conscious cortical
processing. Williams *et al.* (2004), in an investigation of subliminal
and supraliminal fear perception, found that \"conscious fear perception
was distinguished by a more prominent N4, peaking around 400 msec\"; the
N4 component follows the P300 component in the succession of phases of
the ERP. Williams *et al.* considered that the earlier phases in the ERP
are probably related to non-conscious processing. In contrast Vogel *et
al.* (1998) found that suppression of the P300 was associated with
suppression of awareness.
## The integration delay
Psychological experiments often involve binary decisions where subjects
give one of two outputs in response to stimuli. It is found that if the
stimuli are made increasingly noisy or complex the response time tends
to increase. Psychophyicists have developed various mathematical models
to explain the increased response times due to noise such as the
Integrator and Accumulator models (cf: Luce(1986)). These models have
been fairly successful when explaining experiments such as judging the
net direction of movement of sets of dots on a screen when the dots are
given semi-random paths and different brightness etc. In these
circumstances it can take up to 2 seconds for an accurate decision.
There are many tasks however where the accuracy of decision making does
not improve after about 300 milliseconds. The accuracy of the
performance of rats when choosing between two alternatives when reacting
to odours peaks at about 300 ms (Uchida and Mainen(2003), Abraham *et
al.* (2004)). The accuracy of humans when performing vernier acuity
tasks, line detection, contrast sensitivity, motion velocity
discrimination and stereoscopic depth discrimination seems to peak at
300ms (Uchida *et al.* 2006).
Uchida, Kepecs and Mainen (2006) suggest that \"rapid and short
integration time is a sensible strategy for rapid processing of
low-level sensory information in order to form more complex sensory
images, both in vision and olfaction.\" Whether these authors regard
these derived sensory images as the content of consciousness is not
mentioned. The authors propose that the 300ms optimal integration time
may be partly due to the mechanics of sniffing (a sniff takes about
125-200ms) and the nature of optical fixation (inter-saccade intervals
are typically 200-400 ms ). The authors note that the animal or human
could, in principle, choose to integrate over longer intervals but if it
is moving this may not lead to information that is current for changed
circumstances.
An optimal processing time of about 300 ms would be consistent with the
delays observed before conscious awareness occurs in response to a
stimulus - an interval required to form \"more complex sensory images\".
## Global Workspace Theory
Global Workspace Theory is the idea that somewhere in the brain there is
a facility that integrates the processes that occur in the various
separate areas of the brain. The theory was first proposed by Descartes
as the *sensus communis*, the common sense, but the modern form of the
theory dispenses with the idea of a point soul looking at the brain. In
modern Global Workspace theory it is proposed that an area of brain
receives input from most of the cerebral cortex and broadcasts its
outputs to all of the unconscious modular information processors in the
brain.
Modern Global Workspace Theory has been championed by Baars (1983,
1988).
There is increasing evidence for a Global Workspace or Global Workspaces
in the brain. Much of this evidence comes from fMRI, single unit and
magnetoencephalography studies in which it is shown that non-conscious
or subliminal processing mainly occupies primary, sensory cortex whereas
conscious processing occupies large areas of cerebral cortex.
In binocular rivalry the stimulus that is consciously perceived is
responsible for relatively intense activation of large areas of brain
whereas the non-conscious stimulus is often suppressed (see above and
Sheinberg & Logothetis (1997), Tononi *et al.* (1998)). The suppression
is likely to occur in the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei which suggests a
role for the Thalamic Reticular Nuclei, which modulate LGN activity, in
the control of the percept.
### Masking and visual awareness
Word masking has also been used to investigate the idea of a Global
Workspace. When a word is presented on its own for a few tens of
milliseconds it remains readable but if it is immediately succeeded by,
or accompanied by, another word it becomes indistinct or invisible. This
effect is known as \"word masking\". Vogel *et al.* (1998) have
investigated a version of word masking known as the \"attentional
blink\". They found that when stimuli became invisible the P3 component
of the Event Related Potential, which peaks at around 300-500 millisecs
after a stimulus, was completely suppressed. The P3 component of the ERP
has been related to the lodging of data in working memory and also to
gamma band activity in the EEG. This strongly suggests the involvement
of a cortico-thalamic loop in the \"attentional blink\". The delay of
0.3 to 0.5 secs is typical of the time required for conscious awareness
(see above).
Word masking in conjunction with fMRI and Event Related Potential (ERP)
recordings has been used by Dehaene *et al.* (2001) to expose control by
a central mechanism. It was found that masked words activate mainly the
visual cortex and ventral stream (inferior temporal lobe) whereas
visible words also activated distant parietal, prefrontal and cingulate
sites.
Dehaene *et al.* (2003) and found that the dynamics of the loss of
visibility of words in an attentional blink experiment could be modelled
by a simulated cortico-thalamic loop. In their simulation a distributed
cortical process determined which events would receive attention and the
system used the thalamic gating systems to exclude those that did not
receive attention.
Tse *et al.* (2005) have used purely visual stimuli in masking
experiments and concluded that, in the case of purely visual stimuli,
the neural correlates of awareness were limited to the occipital cortex:
\"We suggest that there are both lower and upper bounds within the
visual hierarchy for the processing of visual masking and the
maintenance of visual awareness of simple unattended targets; the lower
bound is at least as high as the border between V2 and V3, and the upper
bound is within the occipital lobe, possibly somewhere downstream of
V4.\"
This discovery would mean that activation of large areas of cortex are
unnecessary for awareness.
Melloni *et al.* (2007) compared compared the electrophysiological
responses related to the processing of visible and invisible words in a
delayed matching to sample task. Both perceived and nonperceived words
caused a similar increase of local (gamma) oscillations in the EEG, but
only perceived words induced a transient long-distance synchronization
of gamma oscillations across widely separated regions of the brain.
After this transient period of temporal coordination, the electrographic
signatures of conscious and unconscious processes continue to diverge.
Only words reported as perceivedinduced (1) enhanced theta oscillations
over frontal regions during the maintenance interval, (2) an increase of
the P300 component of the event-related potential, and (3) an increase
in power and phase synchrony of gamma oscillationsbefore the anticipated
presentation of the test word. We propose that the critical process
mediating the access to conscious perception is the earlytransient
global increase of phase synchrony of oscillatory activity in the
gammafrequency.
Melloni L, Molina C, Pena M, Torres D, Singer W, Rodriguez E. (2007).
Synchronization of neural activity across cortical areas correlates
withconscious perception.J Neurosci. 2007 Mar 14;27(11):2858-65.
### Attention and the global workspace
Baars (2002) in his review of evidence for the Global Workspace Theory
quotes many other experiments that show activation of larger areas of
cortex in response to conscious stimuli compared with unconscious or
subliminal stimuli.The effect is also seen in change blindness, learning
and attention. Newman and Baars (1993) consider that the \"workspace\"
is fairly global in the brain:
\"This Neural Global Workspace (NGW) model views conscious processes in
terms of a globally integrative brain system. The neural circuitry
contributing to this system is not only widely distributed across the
neocortex, but includes key corticothalamic and midbrain circuits as
well. These cortico-subcortical circuits are hypothesized to be critical
to understanding the mechanisms of attentional control that provide an
essential basis for the conscious processing of information\".
However they focus particularly on the role of the thalamic Reticular
Nucleus and cortico-thalamic connectivity in the control of attention.
Other ideas for the location of the Global Workspace are the idea of
Singer et al. that gamma synchrony controls access to the content of
consciousness and Llinas et al. (1998) that the thalamus is the hub
through which communication occurs between areas of cortex.
One of the problems with Global Workspace theory is that it suggests
that attention, working memory, cognitive control and consciousness may
all be in the same area of the brain. It is likely that the mechanisms
of attention, working memory, and cognitive control may involve several,
interlinked systems perhaps co-opting the basal ganglia in the process.
In view of this Maia and Cleeremans (2005) propose that \".. attention,
working memory, cognitive control and consciousness are not distinct
functions implemented by separate brain systems. Attempting to find
separate neural correlates for each may therefore be the wrong approach.
Instead, we suggest that they should be understood in terms of the
dynamics of global competition, with biasing from PFC (prefrontal
cortex).\". The inclusion by Maia and Cleeremans of consciousness with
distributed attention, working memory and cognitive control is
reminiscent of Zeki & Bartel\'s idea of microconsciousness.
It should be noted that, in common with Libet\'s data, the percept seems
to be available to phenomenal consciousness some 0.3 to 0.5 secs after a
stimulus; this suggests that whatever determines the content of
phenomenal consciousness operates before events become part of
phenomenal consciousness. This relegates phenomenal consciousness from
being a controller of attention to being the recipient of content that
is the subject of attention. This finding is consistent with the
philosophical problem of the **apparently** epiphenomenal nature of
phenomenal consciousness.
Given the data on the timing of conscious awareness it seems that there
may be two \"workspaces\", an active workspace that models the world,
discarding and suppressing data during rivalry, and a passive workspace
that receives the final, edited product. The active workspace would
correlate with the cortical systems stressed by Dehaene *et al.* and
Maia and Cleermans although, given the results of Tse et al., the
workspace would be limited to small zones of cortex. The loading of the
passive workspace with the output of the active workspace would
correlate with thalamo-cortical activity during component P3 of the ERP
in which data is transferred from the cortex to the thalamus. This
workspace might constitute the source for reports of the content of
phenomenal consciousness.
Llinas *et al.* (1998) have proposed two parallel cortico-thalamic
attentional systems, one of which is related to the thalamic specific
nuclei and the other to the thalamic non-specific nuclei, especially the
ILN. The non-specific system would be related to consciousness itself.
## The \"cognitive map\" and the neural basis of perceptual space
Our bodies appear to be mobile within a constant space. We walk around a
room; the room does not rotate around us. The constancy of the location
of things gives us the feeling that we are directly viewing a constant
world. But how does the brain provide a constant world rather than a
world that rotates with the movement of the sense organs? Why is our
view of the world when we move our eyes so different from the disturbing
flow of images that occur when a video camera is waved around? Do our
brains contain a constant \"cognitive map\" (O\'Keefe and Nadel 1978) of
our surroundings?
Mittelstaedt & Mittelstaedt (1980, 1982) discovered that female gerbils
were able to recover their pups in darkened surroundings by searching in
a semi random fashion on the outbound journey and then proceeding
directly back to the nest on the inbound journey. The direct journey
back to the nest seemed to be due to an integration of the various
directions taken on the outward journey (**path integration**). If the
equipment being explored by the mother gerbil was rotated very slowly
the mother would make an error equivalent to the amount of rotation.
More rapid rotations that activated the vestibular system of the rat
(acceleration measurement) did not cause errors in navigation. This
demonstration that rodents could navigate accurately on the basis of
**idiothetic** cues (cues that are due to internal senses) led to
research on the neural basis of the navigation.
As early as 1971 O\'Keefe and Dostrovsky had discovered that there are
particular cells in the hippocampus that fire according to the position
of an animal in the environment. This has been complimented by research
that showed that changes in visual cues within the environment caused
changes in the firing rate of place cells in hippocampal area CA3 (.
![](Gray717.png "Gray717.png")
![](HippocampalRegions.jpg "HippocampalRegions.jpg")
!Entorhinal cortex approximately maps to areas 28 and
34{width="500"}
F. P. Battaglia and A. Treves. 1998 Attractor neural networks storing
multiple space representations: A model for hippocampal place fields.
PHYSICAL REVIEW E DECEMBER 1998 VOLUME 58, NUMBER 6
<http://www.sissa.it/~ale/Bat+98b.pdf>
Leutgeb, S., Leutgeb, J.K., Moser, M-B, and Moser, E.I. 2005. Place
cells, spatial maps and the population code for memory. Current Opinion
in Neurobiology 2005, 15:738--746.
<http://instruct1.cit.cornell.edu/courses/bionb720nejc/reprints/LeutgebEtAl2005.pdf>
Mittelstaedt, H. & Mittelstaedt, M-L. 1982. Avian Navigation. (ed. Papi,
F. & Wallraff, H.) 290-297. Springer, Berlin.
Mittelstaedt, M-L & Glasauer, S. 1991. Idiothetic Navigation in Gerbils
and Humans. Zool. Jb. Physiol. 95 (1991), 427-435
<http://web.archive.org/web/20110125132449/http://www.nefo.med.uni-muenchen.de/~sglasauer/MittelstaedtGlasauer1991.pdf>
O\'Keefe, J. & Dostrovsky, J. (1971). The hippocampus as a spatial map:
preliminary evidence from unit activity in the freely moving rat. Brain
Res. 34, 171-175.
O\'Keefe, J. & Nadel, L. (1978). The Hippocampus as a cognitive map.
(Oxford)
## Bibliography
Defining the States of Consciousness. Tassi, P., Muzet, A. (2001)
Neuroscience and Behavioural Reviews 25(2001) 175-191.
Neuroanatomy: \"Digital Slice of Life\" by Stensaas and Millhouse
<http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/subj2.html>
See also: <http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/index.html>
EEG\'s: Coles, M.G.H., Rugg, M.D. Event Related Brain Potentials: An
Introduction.
<http://whalen.psych.udel.edu/667/1.What_is_ERP/ColesRugg1995chpt1.pdf>
Visual System: Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual
Awareness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
Professor Bogen\'s Consciousness Page
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/toccons.htm>
Demonstrations of Auditory Illusions and Tricks. Yoshitaka Nakajima
<http://www.kyushu-id.ac.jp/~ynhome/ENG/Demo/illusions2nd.html>
## References
- Abraham, N.M. (2004) Maintaining accuracy at the expense of speed:
stimulus similarity defines odor discrimination time in mice. Neuron
44, 865-876.
- Aleman, A., Ramsey, N., Van Honk, J.E., Kessels, R.P.C., Hoogduin,
J., Schutter, D.L.G., Postma, A., Kahn, R.S., De Haan, E.H.F.
(submitted). Parietal cortex mediates visuospatial imagery: evidence
from fMRI and rTMS.
<http://igitur-archive.library.uu.nl/dissertations/1954455/c10.pdf>
- Alkire, M.T., Haier, R.J., Fallon, J.H., and Barker, S.J.(1996). PET
imaging of conscious and unconscious verbal memory. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, 3 ( 5-6) 1996 , pp. 448--462
<http://www.imprint.co.uk/jcs_3_5-6.html>
- Anderson, J. & Anderson, B. (1993). \"The Myth of Persistence of
Vision Revisited,\" Journal of Film and Video, Vol. 45, No. 1
(Spring 1993): 3-12.
<http://www.uca.edu/org/ccsmi/ccsmi/classicwork/Myth%20Revisited.htm>
- Andrews, T.J., White, L.E., Binder, D. & Purves, D. (1996). Temporal
events in cyclopean vision. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 93,
pp. 3689--3692, April 1996. Neurobiology.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030510095149/http://www.dur.ac.uk/tim.andrews/PNAS_93_3689.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G. (2001) Determinants of asynchronous
processing in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London,
Series B: Biological Sciences, 269, 579 - 583.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031205165920/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/AC02.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G, Wenderoth, P. (2001). Asynchronous
processing in vision: Color leads motion. Current Biology, 11,
596 - 600.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030617120017/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/ACW01.pdf>
- Austin, G.M. & Grant, F.C. (1958). Physiologic observations
following total hemispherectomy in man. Surgery 38, 239-258.
- Baars, B.J. (1983) Conscious contents provide the nervous system
with coherent, global information. In Consciousness and
Self-Regulation (Vol 3). Davidson, R.J. et al., editors. Plenum
Press.
- Baars, B.J. (1988) A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness, Cambridge
University Press.
- Baars, B., Newman, J., & Taylor, J. (1998) Neuronal mechanisms of
consciousness: A Relational Global Workspace framework., in
Hameroff, Stuart and Kaszniak, Al and Laukes, James, Eds. Toward a
Science of Consciousness II: The second Tucson discussions and
debates., chapter 24, pages 269-278. MIT Press.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000946/>
- Baars, B.J. (2002) The conscious access hypothesis: origins and
recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. Vol 6, No 1,
47-52. 2002. <http://www.cs.memphis.edu/~wrcm/BaarsTICS2002.pdf>
- Barth, D. S. and MacDonald, K. D. (1996) Thalamic modulation of
high-frequency oscillating potentials in auditory cortex. Nature.
383, 78-81.
- Bernat E, Shevrin H, Snodgrass M. (2001). Subliminal visual oddball
stimuli evoke a P300 component. Clin Neurophysiol. 2001
Jan;112(1):159-71.
- Blake, R., Westendorf, D. and Overton, R. (1979) What is suppressed
during binocular rivalry? Perception 9: 223-231.
- Blake, R. and Lee, S.-H. (1999). Rival ideas about binocular
rivalry. Vision Research. 39: 1447-1454
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/faculty/blake/PDFs/Lee_Blake_99VR.pdf>
- Blankenburg, F., Ruff, C.C., Deichmann, R., Rees, G. and
Driver, J. (2006) The cutaneous rabbit illusion affects human
primary sensory cortex somatotopically, PLoS Biol 2006;4(3):e69.
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness: I. An
overview. Consciousness and Cognition, 4, 52-62.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/bogen-95.pdf>
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness:
Part II. Constraining the semantic problem. Consciousness and
Cognition, 4, 137-158.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/concog95.htm>
- Bregman, A.S. (1990). Auditory scene analysis: The perceptual
organization of sound. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Budka, H. (1998). Fatal Familial Insomnia Around the World. Brain
Pathology, 8: 553-570.
<http://brainpath.medsch.ucla.edu/pdfs/0803pdf/budka.pdf>
- Carandini M, Heeger DJ, & Senn W, (2002). A synaptic explanation of
suppression in visual cortex, Journal of Neuroscience,
22:10053-10065, 2002.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031031214953/http://www.cns.nyu.edu/~david/ftp/reprints/Carandini-JNeurosci2002.pdf>
- Cariani, P. (2000). Anesthesia, Neural Information Processing, And
Conscious Awareness. Consciousness And Cognition Vol. 9, No. 3,
September 2000 p. 387-395
- Castro-Alamancos, M.A., Connors, B.W. (1997). Thalamo-cortical
synapses. Progress in Neurobiology, Vol.51, pp. 581 to 606, 1997
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051025163047/http://neurobio.drexel.edu/castroweb/progneurobio1.pdf>
- Christmann, C. & Leuthold, H. (2004). The Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Section A. Volume 57, Number 2 /
February 2004. 357-381.
- Claus, R. & Nel, W. (2006). Drug induced arousal from the permanent
vegetative state. NeuroRehabilitation. 2006;21(1):23-8.
- Clifford, C.W.G., Arnold, D.H., Pearson, J. (2003). A paradox of
temporal perception revealed by a stimulus oscillating in colour and
orientation. Vision Research 43 (2003) 2245-2253.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031102125210/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/CAP03.pdf>
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of
consciousness Seminars in the Neurosciences (1990) 2, 263-275
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1998). Consciousness and Neuroscience.
Cerebral Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
- Culham, J.C., Dukelow, S.P., Vilis, T., Hassard, F.A., Gati, J.S.,
Menon, R.S. and Goodale, M.A. (1999). Recovery of fMRI Activation in
Motion Area MT Following Storage of the Motion Aftereffect. The
Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 81 No. 1 January 1999, pp. 388--393.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/81/1/388>
- Deecke, L. (1996) Planning, preparation, execution, and imagery of
volitional action, (Introduction / Editorial) in: L. Deecke W.
Lang, A. Berthoz (Eds) Mental Representations of Motor Acts.
Cognitive Brain Res 3 / Special Issue (2) 59-64.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000015/00/COGBRAIN.html>
- Dehaene, S., Sergent, C., and Changeux, J. (2003) A neuronal network
model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data
during conscious perception. PNAS July 8, 2003 vol. 100 no. 14
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/DehaeneSergentChangeux_BlinkModel_PNAS2003.pdf>
- Dehaene, S. et al. (2001) Cerebral mechanisms of word masking and
unconscious repetition priming. Nat. Neurosci, 4, 752-758.
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/Dehaene_MaskedWords_NatureNeuroscience2001.pdf>
- Dennett, D. and Kinsbourne, M. (1992) Time and the Observer: the
Where and When of Consciousness in the Brain. (1992) Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 15, 183-247, 1992. Reprinted in The Philosopher\'s
Annual, Grim, Mar and Williams, eds., vol. XV-1992, 1994,
pp. 23--68; Noel Sheehy and Tony Chapman, eds., Cognitive Science,
Vol. I, Elgar, 1995,
pp. 210--274.http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/time&obs.htm
- Destexhe, A. (2000). Modelling corticothalamic feedback and the
gating of the thalamus by the cerebral cortex. J. Physiol (Paris),
94 (2000) 391-410. <http://cns.iaf.cnrs-gif.fr/files/Brem2000.pdf>
- Fang, F. & He, S. (2005).Cortical responses to invisible objects in
the human dorsal and ventral pathways. Nat Neurosci. 2005
Oct;8(10):1380-5. Epub 2005 Sep 4.
- Ffytche, D. H., Howard, R. J., Brammer, M. J., David, A., Woodruff,
P., & Williams, S. (1998). The anatomy of conscious vision: an fMRI
study of visual hallucinations. Nature Neuroscience, 1, 738--742.
- Fiset, P., Paus, T., Daloze, T., Plourde, G., Meuret, P., Bonhomme,
V., Hajj-Ali, N., Backman, S.B., and Evans, A.C. (1999). Brain
Mechanisms of Propofol-Induced Loss of Consciousness in Humans: a
Positron Emission Tomographic Study. The Journal of Neuroscience,
July 1, 1999, 19(13):5506-5513.
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/13/5506>
- Fu, C.H.Y., Morgan, K., Suckling, J., Williams, S.C.R., Andrew, C.,
Vythelingum, G.N., McGuire, P.K. (2002). A Functional Magnetic
Resonance Imaging Study of Overt Letter Verbal Fluency Using a
Clustered Acquisition Sequence: Greater Anterior Cingulate
Activation with Increased Task Demand. NeuroImage 17, 871-
879 (2002)
<http://www-bmu.psychiatry.cam.ac.uk/PUBLICATION_STORE/fu02fun.pdf>
- Ganis, G., Thomson, W.L. and Kosslyn, S.M. (2004). Brain areas
underlying visual mental imagery and visual perception: an fMRI
study. Cognitive Brain Research 20 (2004) 226--241
<http://www.wjh.harvard.edu/~kwn/Kosslyn_pdfs/2004Ganis_CogBrainRes20_BrainAreas.pdf>
- Hultin, L. (1997). On Neuromagnetic Assessment of the Contingent
Negative Variation.
<http://www2.lib.chalmers.se/cth/diss/doc/9697/HultinLeif.html>
- Fries, P.. Roelfsema, P.R., Engel, A.K., König, P. and Singer, W.
(1997). Synchronization of oscillatory responses in visual cortex
correlates with perception in interocular rivalry. Proc. Natl. Acad.
Sci. USA, Vol. 94, pp. 12699--12704, November 1997.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/23/12699>
- Fuentealba, P., Crochet, S., Timofeev, I., Bazhenov, M., Sejnowski,
T.J. and Steriade, M. (2004). European Journal of Neuroscience
20(1):111-119. <http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2004/22126/ch03.html>
- Goaillard, J. & Vincent, P. (2002). Serotonin suppresses the slow
afterhyperpolarization in rat intralaminar and midline thalamic
neurones by activating 5-HT7 receptors. Journal of Physiology
(2002), 541.2, pp. 453--465
<http://jp.physoc.org/cgi/content/full/541/2/453>
- Haggard, P. & Eimer, M. (1999) On the relation between brain
potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Exp. Brain Res.
126, 128--133 (1999).
- Haggard, P. (2008) Human volition:towards a neuroscience of will.
Nature Rev Neurosci 9, 934-946
- Haynes, J., Deichmann, R. and Rees, G. (2005). Eye-specific effects
of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate nucleus. Nature
438, 496-499 (24 November 2005)
- Hughes S.W., Blethyn K.L. , Cope D.W. , & Crunelli V. (2003).
Properties and origin of spikelets in thalamocortical neurones in
vitro. Neuroscience. 2002;110(3):395-401
- Iramina, K., Maeno, T., Kowatari, Y. and Ueno, S.. (2002). Effects
of Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation on EEG Activity .IEEE
TRANSACTIONS ON MAGNETICS, VOL. 38, NO. 5, SEPTEMBER 2002
- Ishai, A., Ungerleider, L.G., Haxby, J.V.. (2000) Distributed neural
systems for the generation of visual images. Neuron 28, 979-990.
- Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1980). Mental models in cognitive science.
Cognitive Science, 4, 71-115.
<http://cognitrn.psych.indiana.edu/rgoldsto/cogsci/classics.html>
- Keller, J. & Heckhausen, H. (1990). Readiness potentials preceding
spontaneous motor acts: voluntary vs. involuntary control.
Electroencephalography and Clinical Neuropsychology, 76, 351-361.
- King, C.C. (1991). Fractal and Chaotic Dynamics in Nervous Systems.
Progress in Neurobiology, 36, pp. 279--308, 1991.
<http://citeseer.nj.nec.com/king91fractal.html>
- Klein, S.A (2002). Libet's Temporal Anomalies: A Reassessment of the
Data.
Consciousness and Cognition 11, 198--214 (2002)
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/160.pdf>
- Klein, S. (2002). Libet\'s Timing of Mental Events: Commentary on
the Commentaries. Consciousness and Cognition. 11, 326-333.
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/ccog_2002_0580-Klein-Commentary_on_the_commentaries.pdf>
- Kleinschmidt, A., Bichel, C. Zeki, S. and Frackowiak, R.S.J. (1998).
Human brain activity during spontaneously reversing perception of
ambiguous figures. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 1998 Dec
22;265(1413):2427-33
- Konishi, S., Wheeler, M.E., Donaldson, D.I., Buckner, R.L.. (2000)
Neural correlates of episodic retrieval success. NeuroImage: 12:
276-286.
- Kornhuber HH, Deecke L: Hirnpotentialänderungen beim Menschen vor
und nach Willkürbewegungen, dargestellt mit Magnetbandspeicherung
und Rückwärtsanalyse. Pflügers Arch. ges. Physiol. 281 (1964) 52.
- Kosslyn, S.M., Thompson, W.L. (2003). When is early visual cortex
activated during visual mental imagery? Psychol. Bull. 129
(2003)723-746.
- Kreiman, G., Koch, C. and Fried, I. (2000). Imagery neurons in the
human brain. Nature (2000) 408: 357-361
<http://www.cns.caltech.edu/~gabriel/publications/imagination1.html>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I., & Koch, C. (2001). Single neuron responses
in humans during binocular rivalry and flash suppression. Journal of
Vision, 1(3), 131a, <http://journalofvision.org/1/3/131>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I. And Koch, C. (2002) Single Neuron responses
in the human brain during flash suppression. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Science USA, 99:8378-8383
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031015091920/http://www.ai.mit.edu/projects/cbcl/publications/ps/kreimanetal_flash-suppression.pdf>
- Larsen, A., Madsen, K.H., Lund, T.E., and Bundesen, C. (2006).
Images of Illusory Motion in Primary Visual Cortex. Journal of
Cognitive Neuroscience. 2006;18:1174-1180.
- Laureys, S. et al. (2002). Brain function in the vegetative state.
Acta neurol. belg., 2002, 102, 177-185
<http://www.jsmf.org/meetings/2003/nov/LaureysANB2002.pdf>
- Lee. S, and Blake, R. (2002). V1 activity is reduced during
binocular rivalry. Journal of Vision (2002) 2, 618-626
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030722173225/http://journalofvision.org/2/9/4/article.pdf>
- Leopold, D.A. and Logothetis, N.K. (1999). Multistable phenomena:
changing views in perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 3:
254-264.
<http://www.kyb.tuebingen.mpg.de/publications/pdfs/pdf201.pdf>
- Libet, B., Alberts, E.W., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B.(1967).
Responses of Human Somatosensory Cortex to Stimuli Below Threshold
for Conscious Sensation. Science 158, 1597-1600.
- Libet, B., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B., and Pearl, D.(1979).
Subjective referral of the timing for a conscious sensory
experience. Brain, 102, pp. 192--224.
<http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/entrez/query.fcgi?holding=npg&cmd=Retrieve&db=PubMed&list_uids=427530&dopt=Abstract>
- Linden, D.E.J. (2005) The P300: Where in the Brain Is It Produced
and What Does It Tell Us? The Neuroscientist, Vol. 11, No. 6,
563-576 (2005) <http://nro.sagepub.com/cgi/reprint/11/6/563.pdf>
- Llinas, R., Ribary, U., Contreras, D. & Pedroarena, C. (1998). The
neuronal basis for consciousness. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London Ser.
B.353, 1841-1849
<http://big.cs.uiuc.edu/anncbt-papers/fall05/Llinas.the-neuronal-basis-of-consciousness.pdf>
- Logothetis, N.K., Leopold, D.A. and Sheinberg, D.L. (1996). What is
Rivalling During Binocular Rivalry. Nature, 380:621-624.
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nature/journal/v380/n6575/abs/380621a0.html>
- Loveblad, KO. et al. (1999). Silent functional magnetic resonance
imaging demonstrates focal activation in rapid eye movement sleep.
Neurology 1999;53:2193Z
- Luce, R.D. (1986). Response times: their role in inferring
elementary mental organization. Oxford University Press, New York.
- Lumer, E.D., Friston, K.J. & Rees, G. (1998) Neural correlates of
perceptual rivalry in the human brain. Science. 280(5371):1930-4.
- Macdonald, K.D., Fifkova, E., Jones, M.S. and Barth, D.S. (1998)
Focal Stimulation of the Thalamic Reticular Nucleus Induces Focal
Gamma Waves in Cortex. The Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 79 No. 1
January 1998, pp. 474--477
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/79/1/474>
- Maia, T.V. & Cleeremans, A. (2005). Consciousness: converging
insights from connectionist modeling and neuroscience. TRENDS in
Cognitive Sciences Vol.9 No.8 August 2005
<http://srsc.ulb.ac.be/axcWWW/papers/pdf/05-TICS.pdf>
- Marcel AJ. (1998). Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of
visual consciousness or visual function? Brain 1998, 121, 1565-1588.
<http://brain.oupjournals.org/cgi/reprint/121/8/1565.pdf>
- Marois, R., Yi, D-J., & Chun, M.M. (2004). The Neural Fate of
Consciously Perceived and Missed Events in the Attentional Blink.
Neuron, 41, 3: 465-472.
- Mashour, G.A., Tononi, G. and Massimini, M. (2005). Cognitive
Unbinding in Sleep and Anesthesia. Science 16 December 2005:
1768-1769.
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
<http://juno.ingentaselect.com/vl=6492085/cl=26/nw=1/rpsv/cgi-bin/cgi?body=linker&ini=nlm&reqidx=issn=0962-8452vl=264is=1380yr=1997mn=Marpg=393>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). Responses of Spectrally
Selective Cells in Macaque Area V2 to Wavelengths and Colors. J
Neurophysiol 87: 2104-2112, 2002.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/87/4/2104>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). The relationship between
cortical activation and perception investigated with invisible
stimuli. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA, 99(14):9527-9532.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/99/14/9527>
- Muckli, L., Singer, W., Zanella, F.E. and Goebel, R. (2002)
Integration of multiple motion vectors over space: an fMRI study of
transparent motion perception. Neuroimage. 2002 Aug;16(4):843-56.
- Munhall, K.G. (2001). Functional Imaging During Speech Production.
Acta Psychologica 107 (2001) 95-117.
<http://pavlov.psyc.queensu.ca/~munhallk/07_acta_version.pdf>
- Munk MHJ, Roelfsema PR, König P, Engel AK, and Singer W. (1996).
Role of reticular activation in the modulation of intracortical
synchronization Science. 272, 271-274.
- Newman, J. & Baars, B.J. (1993) A neural attentional model for
access to consciousness: A Global Workspace perspective. Concepts in
Neuroscience, 4:2, 255-290
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000073/>
- Nieuwenhuis S, Aston-Jones G & Cohen JD (2005). Decision making, the
P3, and the locus coeruleus-norepinephrine system. Psychological
Bulletin, 131(4), 510-532.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051117045339/http://www.csbmb.princeton.edu/conte/pdfs/project5/Proj5Pub06.pdf>
- Nørretranders, T. (1991) Consciousness: The User Illusion
(translated from Danish), Penguin Books,
; 1999 revision:
<http://www.worldcat.org/title/user-illusion-cutting-consciousness-down-to-size/oclc/41311618>.
- Pantev C (1995) Evoked and induced gamma-band activity of the human
cortex. Brain Topogr 7:321-330
- Pasley BN, Mayes LC, Schultz RT (2004) Subcortical discrimination of
unperceived objects during binocular rivalry. Neuron 2004,
42:163-172.
- Pessoa, L. (2005) To what extent are emotional visual stimuli
processed without attention and awareness? Current Opinion in
Neurobiology 2005, 15:188-196
<http://web.archive.org/web/20060623004726/http://www.brown.edu/Research/LCE/publications_files/Pessoa_CONB_2005.pdf>
- Pettigrew, J.D. (2001) Searching for the Switch: Neural Bases for
Perceptual Rivalry Alternations. Brain and Mind 2: 85-118, 2001.
<http://www.uq.edu.au/nuq/jack/searchswitch.pdf>
- Raymond, J. E, Shapiro, K. L., & Arnell, K. M. (1992). Temporary
suppression of visual processing in an RSVP task: An attentional
blink? Journal of Experimental Psychology. Human Perception and
Performance, 18 (3), 849-60.
- Rektor, I., Bares, M., Kanovsky, P. and Kukleta, M. (2001)
Intracerebral recording of readiness potential induced by a complex
motor task. Movement Disorders, Volume 16, Issue 4, Pages 698-704
- Rees, G., Kreiman, G., & Koch, C. (2002) Neural Correlates of
Consciousness in Humans. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3, 261
-270 (2002)
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nrn/journal/v3/n4/abs/nrn783_fs.html&dynoptions=doi1069842948>
- Rensink, RA. (2000). When Good Observers Go Bad: Change Blindness,
Inattentional Blindness, and Visual Experience. PSYCHE, 6(09),
August 2000.
<http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v6/psyche-6-09-rensink.html>
- Roy, J.E. & Prichep, L.S. (2005) The Anesthetic Cascade: A Theory of
How Anesthesia Suppresses Consciousness Anesthesiology: Volume
102(2) February 2005 pp 447--471
<http://www.anesthesiology.org/pt/re/anes/fulltext.00000542-200502000-00030.htm>
- Schiff, N.D., & Plum F. 1999. The Neurology of Impaired
Consciousness: Global Disorders and Implied Models. \[Target
article\]. Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness.
<http://www.phil.vt.edu/assc/niko.html>
- Schiff ND, Plum F. (2000) The Role of Arousal and \"Gating\" Systems
in the Neurology of Impaired Consciousness. Journal of
Neurophysiology. 17(5):438-452. (
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030924010953/http://www.uni-tuebingen.de/cog/lehre/ss2003/seminar_bewusstsein/epapers/SchiffPlum00.pdf>
- Sheinberg, D.L. and Logothetis, N.K. (1997). The role of temporal
cortical areas in perceptual organization. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA 94, 3408-3413. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/7/3408>
- Simons, D.J. & Rensink, RA. (2005). Change blindness: Past, present,
and future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol.9, pp16--20, No.1
January 2005.
<http://www.psych.ubc.ca/~rensink/publications/download/S&R-TICS-05a.pdf>
- Singer, W. & Gray, C.W. (1995). Visual feature integration and the
temporal correlation hypothesis. Annu. Rev. Neurosci., 18,
pp. 555--86, 1995.
- Singer, W. (2001). Consciousness and the Binding Problem. Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences 929:123-146 (2001)
- Solms, Mark (2000) DREAMING AND REM SLEEP ARE CONTROLLED BY
DIFFERENT BRAIN MECHANISMS, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23
(6): 793.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/Preprints/OldArchive/bbs.solms.html>
- Soon, C.S., Brass, M., Heinze, H-J. and Haynes, J-D. (2008).
Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain.
Nature Neuroscience 11, 543 - 545 (2008)
- Sukov, W. & Barth, D.S. (2001). Cellular Mechanisms of Thalamically
Evoked Gamma Oscillations in Auditory Cortex. J Neurophysiol 85:
1235-1245, 2001;
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/85/3/1235>
- Takeuchi, T., Miyasita, A., Inugami, M. & Yamamoto, Y. (2001).
Intrinsic dreams are not produced without REM sleep mechanisms:
evidence through elicitation of sleep onset REM periods. Journal of
Sleep Research Volume 10 Issue 1 Page 43 - March 2001
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tamás, G., Buh, E.H., Lörincz, A., and Somogyi, P. (2000).
Proximally targeted GABAergic synapses and gap junctions synchronize
cortical interneurons. Nature Neuroscience volume 3 no 4 April 2000.
<http://mrcanu.pharm.ox.ac.uk/pdfs/TamasNatureNeurosci2000.pdf>
- Tanaka, Y. & Sagi, D. (1998). A perceptual memory for low contrast
visual signals. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol 95:12729-12733.
<http://www.weizmann.ac.il/~masagi/TS98b.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2001). Competing Theories of Binocular Rivalry: A Possible
Resolution. Brain and Mind 2: 55-83, 2001
<http://web.archive.org/web/20041212094810/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_Brain&Mind2001.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual Awareness. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030723135239/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
- Tootell, R.B., Reppas, J.B., Dale, A.M., Look, R.B., Sereno, M.I.,
Malach, R., Brady, T.J. and Rosen, B.R. (1995) Visual motion
aftereffect in human cortical area MT revealed by functional
magnetic resonance imaging. Nature. 1995 May 11;375(6527):139-41.
- Tononi, G., Srinivasan, R., Russell, P.D. & Edelman, G.M. (1998).
Investigating neural correlates of conscious perception by
frequency-tagged neuromagnetic responses . Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA. Vol. 95, Issue 6, 3198-3203, March 17, 1998
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/95/6/3198>
- Thornton, I.M., Pinto, J. and Shiffrar, M. (1998).
THE VISUAL PERCEPTION OF HUMAN LOCOMOTION. COGNITIVE NEUROPSYCHOLOGY,
1998, 15 (6/7/8 ), 535-552.
<http://psychology.rutgers.edu/~mag/TPS98.pdf>
- Traub, D.R., Whittington, M.A., Buhl, E.H., Jefferys, J.G.R., &
Faulkner, H.J. (1999). On the Mechanism of the Frequency Shift in
Neuronal Oscillations Induced in Rat Hippocampal Slices by Tetanic
Stimulation. The Journal of Neuroscience, February 1, 1999,
19(3):1088-1105
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/3/1088>
- Traub, R.D. (2003). Fast Oscillations and Epilepsy. Epilepsy Curr.
2003 May; 3(3): 77-79.
<http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/articlerender.fcgi?artid=321178>
- Trevena J & Miller, J (2002) Cortical Movement Preparation before
and after a Conscious Decision to Move. Consciousness and Cognition,
Volume 11, Issue 2, June 2002, Pages 162-190
- Trevena, J & Miller, J (2009) Brain preparation before a voluntary
action: Evidence against unconscious movement initiation. Conscious
Cogn. 2009 Sep 5. \[Epub ahead of print\]
- Tse, P.U., Susana Martinez-Conde, S., Schlegel, A.A. and Macknik,
S.L. (2005). Visibility, visual awareness, and visual masking of
simple unattended targets are confined to areas in the occipital
cortex beyond human V1/V2. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA November 22,
2005 vol. 102 no. 47. 17178-17183.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/102/47/17178>
- Uchida, N., Kepecs, A. and Mainen, Z.F. (2006) Seeing at a glance,
smelling in a whiff: rapid forms of perceptual decision making.
Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 7. 485-491.
- Uchida, N & Mainen, Z.F. (2003) Speed and accuracy of olfacory
discrimination in the rat. Nature Neurosci. 6, 1224-1229.
- Vogel, E.K., Luck, S.J. & Shapiro, K.L. (1998) Electrophysiological
Evidence for a Postperceptual Locus of Suppression During the
Attentional Blink. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
Perception and Performance 1998, Vol. 24. No. 6,1656-1674
<http://web.archive.org/web/20050304211722/http://www.psychology.uiowa.edu/faculty/Luck/lucklab/pdfs/Vogel_1998_JEPHPP.pdf>
- Wehrle, R., Czisch, M., Kaufmann, C., Wetter, T.C., Holsboer, F.,
Auer, D.P., and Pollmacher, T. (2005). Rapid eye movement-related
brain activation in human sleep: a functional magnetic resonance
imaging study. NeuroReport 16:853-857
<http://www.univie.ac.at/mcogneu/lit/wehrle.pdf>
- White, NS., Alkire, MT. (2003). Impaired thalamocortical
connectivity in humans during
general-anesthetic-induced unconsciousness. NeuroImage. Volume 19, Issue
2 , June 2003, Pages 402-411. <http://smallurl.com?i=2597>
(http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/B6WNP-48GP5CG-5/1/cedb33dc0bec4301d1960c7c27cea70f)
- Wheeler, M.E., Buckner, R.L.. (2003) Functional dissociation among
components
of remembering: control, perceived oldness, and content. J. Neurosci.
23, 3869-3880.
- Williams LM, Liddell BJ, Rathjen J, Brown KJ, Shevrin H, Gray JA,
Phillips M, Young A & Gordon E (2004). Mapping the time course of
nonconscious and conscious perception of fear: An integration of
central and peripheral measures. Human Brain Mapping,21, 64 - 74
<http://psychmed.iop.kcl.ac.uk/neuroscience-and-emotion/downloads/46.pdf>
- Wunderlich, K. Schneider, K.A., & Kastner, S. (2005).Neural
correlates of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate
nucleus. Nature Neuroscience 8, 1595 - 1602 (2005)
- Yamamoto, T. & Katayama, Y. (2005). Deep brain stimulation therapy
for the vegetative state. in Neuropsychol Rehabil. 2005 Jul-Sep ;
15(3-4): 406-13
- Zeki, S., & Bartel, A. (1999). Toward a Theory of Visual
Consciousness. Consciousness & Cognition, 8, 225-259.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 2#Synchronisation of Neural Processes
*Contributors: please include full data in the references section for
all references in the text.*
```{=html}
<div class="noprint">
```
Home
```{=html}
</div>
```
## Perceptual \"filling in\"
Perceptual \"filling in\" occurs when visual properties such as
textures, colours, brightness or motion are extended in the visual field
to areas where they do not have corresponding events in the world.
The filling in of the blind spot by the properties of the field in the
contralateral eye has already been discussed. The part of the visual
field represented by the blind spot is also \"filled in\" in the case of
monocular vision.
![](Constudblindill.png "Constudblindill.png")
Shut the right eye and focus on the pink cross with the left eye, if the
head is moved towards the pink cross there is a point at which the
yellow disk disappears but the white lines are still present. In this
\"filling in\" the visual field does not appear to be distorted.
Fiorani *et al.* (1992) developed a technique for probing the cortical
blind spot using vertical and horizontal bar stimuli. Matsumoto &
komatsu (2005) used this technique on macaque monkeys. In the monocular
case they found that as a bar was moved across the visual field so that
it crossed the blind spot there was a sudden change in neural activity
in the deep layers of the neurons in the blind spot area of V1. When the
bar was moved across the same part of the visual field of the
contralateral eye the neural activity in the blind spot area increased
steadily as the bar was moved. The authors found that there were neurons
in the deep layers of blind spot cortex that had elongated receptive
fields that could respond to stimuli outside the blind spot and transfer
this activation into the blind spot cortex.
Filling in of a slightly different type occurs in \"scotoma\". In
scotoma an area of the retina is damaged and unresonsive to visual
stimuli, immediately after the damage patients report an area of visual
field that is unresponsive to stimuli. After several months patients
report that the area of field represented by the scotoma contains visual
properties related to the physical world surrounding the area that would
have formed an image on the scotoma. This results in a distortion of the
visual field. (see for instance Gilbert(1993)). Direct measurements of
activity in cortical area V1 show that the neurons that represented the
area of the scotoma become sensitive to activity in the surrounding
visual field. At the cortical level the scotoma is literally \"filled
in\".
There are many stimuli that cause \"filling in\". These stimuli are
known as \"illusions\" because they produce phenomenal experience that
has no correlate in the world outside the body. In the \"neon colour
spreading illusion\" a lightly coloured circle appears where there
should be a white background. Sasaki and Watanabe (2004) used fMRI to
show that the part of the topographic map in cortical area V1
corresponding to the light coloured circle was activated.
![](Constudneon.jpg "Constudneon.jpg")
Fiorani, M., Rosa, M.G.P., Gattas, R. & Rocha-Miranda, C.E. (1992).
Dynamic surrounds of receptive fields in primate striate cortex: a
physiological basis for perceptual completion? Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
89, 8547-8551. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/abstract/89/18/8547>
Gilbert, C.D. (1993). Circuitry, architecture and functional dynamics of
visual cortex.
Matsumoto, M & Komatsu, H. (2005). Neural responses in the macaque V1 to
bar stimuli with various lengths presented on the blind spot. J
neurophysiol. 93. 2374-2387.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/abstract/93/5/2374>
Sasaki, Y & Watanabe, T. The primary visual cortex fills in colour.
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 101, 18251-18256. (2004).
## Binocular Rivalry, Pattern Rivalry and Binocular Fusion
Sir Charles Wheatstone (1838) was the first scientist to systematically
investigate binocular rivalry. Binocular rivalry occurs when different
images are presented to the left and right eyes. The subject sees
successively one image, a combined image and then the other image. The
swapping of images can take a second or more. Binocular rivalry is of
interest in consciousness research because the parts of the brain that
contain the dominant image should also be those parts that are
contributing to conscious experience. Binocular rivalry involves at
least two components; the first switches from one image to a merged
image and then to the other image and the second permits the view to be
part of conscious experience.
![](Constudrival.png "Constudrival.png")
The switching of one image for another may involve selecting one of the
images as the percept or selecting one of the eyes. Blake *et al.*
(1979) performed an experiment in which subjects could change the image
at a given eye by pressing a button. When a particular image became
dominant they pressed a button to change the image at the eye receiving
the dominant image for the non-dominant image. They found that the
subjects immediately experienced the second image as the dominant image.
This suggests that binocular rivalry is selecting between eyes rather
than images. Lehky in 1988 proposed that the switching may be occurring
as a result of feedback between visual cortical area V1 and the Lateral
Geniculate Nucleus (a thalamic relay - see Carandini *et al.* 2002) and
Blake in 1989 also proposed that the switching occurred at the level of
area V1. (Visual cortical area V1 receives visual input direct from the
LGN.)
Tong (2001) has argued that, in humans, the switching of images in
binocular rivalry may occur at the earliest levels in the visual cortex.
In particular, Tong and Engel (2001) used an elegant technique measuring
the activity in the visual cortex that represents the blind spot of the
eye to show that almost complete switching to the dominant image occurs
at the level of visual cortical area V1. In support of this idea of
switching at the level of V1 or even before the cortex, Kreimann *et
al.* (2001, 2002) used direct electrode recordings in human cortex and
found that the activity of most neurons changed with the percept. Other
experiments have not shown a single locus in the brain where the
suppressed sensory information gets switched out (Blake & Logothetis
2002, Leopold & Logothetis 1996, Gail et al., 2004).
Functional MRI has also shown cortical activity outside of sensory
visual cortex related to both images in binocular rivalry. Lumer *et
al.* (1998) found that only the fronto-parietal areas of cortex switched
with the percept, Fang & He (2005) found that activity relating to both
suppressed and unsuppressed images were present in the dorsal stream of
the visual system. Wunderlich *et al.* (2005) and Haynes *et al.* (2005)
have both found suppression at the level of the lateral geniculate
nucleus using fMRI in humans.
Pasley *et al.* (2004) have shown that, even during suppression, fearful
faces can produce activity in the amygdala (see Pessoa (2005) for a
review).
Rivalry alternations seem to be the result of widespread activity
changes that cover large parts of the brain, including but not
necessarily originating at the earliest sensory stages of visual
processing. Most investigators have found that, once switching has
occurred, there are areas of the brain that contain activity that is
solely related to the percept but this varies from most of the cortex to
largely more frontal regions depending upon the study. The most likely
explanation for binocular rivalry is that the switching occurs at the
level of the LGN as a result of feedback from the cortex.
Pattern Rivalry is also of interest in consciousness research for the
same reasons as binocular rivalry. In pattern rivalry a figure may have
two or more forms that replace each other. Typical examples of such
figures are the Necker cube and Rubin\'s face-vase. The similarity of
the time course of the switching between percepts in binocular rivalry
and pattern rivalry has led many authors to suggest that these involve
the same mechanism. Logothetis *et al.* (1996) used novel dichoptic
stimuli (different images to each eyes) to produce a form of rivalry
that seems to involve switching at levels in the cerebral cortex that
are more distal to the sensory stimulus than V1. Leopold and Logothetis
(1999), on the basis of their work with monkeys, state that \"..many
neurons throughout the visual system, both monocular and binocular,
continue to respond to a stimulus even when it is perceptually
suppressed.\". Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998) investigated pattern rivalry
with MRI and found activity in higher order visual areas during change
of dominant pattern. Pettigrew (2001) also describes effects on rivalry
due to thought and mood that may require involvement of large areas of
cortex in the switching operation and stresses the way that V1
represents different visual fields in different hemispheres of the brain
so that inter-hemispheric switching must also be considered.
It seems likely that the change of dominant pattern or percept is
associated with higher level cortical activity but once the dominant
percept is established many of the visually responsive neurons in the
cortex are switched over to the new percept. This might account for the
similarities in timing of binocular and pattern rivalry and the
disparate results found by the various groups of authors. In the words
of Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998):
\"The transient activity fluctuations we found suggest that perceptual
metastability elicited by ambiguous stimuli is associated with rapid
redistributions of neural activity between separate specialized cortical
and subcortical structures.\"
Which permits both the idea of selecting particular eyes or percepts,
perhaps by feedback that switches a thalamic relay on the basis of
cortical processing of patterns. Once the cortex has switched the
thalamic relay most of the neurons in V1 would become exposed to the
dominant percept but there would still be a few neurons in the cortical
visual system receiving data from the non dominant image.
The investigations of binocular and pattern rivalry provide evidence
that conscious visual experience is probably distal to V1 (i.e.: cortex
or thalamus).
Perceptual rivalry may be part of complex decision making rather than
being simply a switch to blank out unwelcome input. It is clear from the
Rubin face-vase that pattern rivalry is linked to recognition and would
involve a complex delineation of forms within cortical processing. This
would suggest that many areas of cortex should be involved before a
particular percept is made dominant. Pettigrew (2001) argues that
rivalry is the result of a complex phenomenon rather than being simply a
switching event. Pettigrew\'s discovery that laughter abolishes rivalry
also points to a complex cortical system for switching percepts.
Pettigrew proposes that complex cortical processes control rivalry and
that the actual switching of percepts is performed sub-cortically in the
Ventral Tegmental Area. He concludes his review of the problem by noting
that \"Rivalry may thus reflect fundamental aspects of perceptual
decision making..\" Pettigrew (2001).
Another effect, known as \"binocular fusion\", provides further
compelling evidence for the non-conscious nature of the cerebral cortex.
In binocular fusion images from both eyes are fused together to create a
single image in experience. Moutoussis and Zeki (2002) used a form of
binocular fusion in which images of faces were flashed at 100ms
intervals to both eyes simultaneously. When both eyes received images of
the same colour the subject could see the faces but when one eye
received a green image on a red background and the other a red image on
a green background the subjects reported seeing a uniform yellow field
that contained no faces.
fMRI scans of the subject\'s brains showed that when both eyes were
exposed to images of the same colour the part of the brain that deals
with faces was active and when each eye received images of different
colours the same areas of brain showed activity. In other words the
cortex contained strong activity related to faces whether or not faces
were experienced. Moutoussis and Zeki found a similar effect when they
used images of houses instead of images of faces. The authors concluded
that: \"The present study further suggests that there are no separate
processing and perceptual areas but rather that the same cortical
regions are involved in both the processing and, when certain levels of
activation are reached and probably in combination with the activation
of other areas as well, the generation of a conscious visual percept\".
This conclusion does not seem to be supported by the data. There is no
evidence that any area of cortex contains the percept itself. The
experiment shows that the cortex contains data relating to both red and
green faces which suggests that the cortex is not the site of the
conscious percept. The percept is most likely distal to the cortex
perhaps in the thalamus or some other area that receives cortical
sensory output.
It is interesting that Fries *et al.* (1997) found that neurons that
were activated by the dominant image in binocular rivalry fired
synchronously whereas those that were activated by the non-dominant
image did not. Thalamocorticothalamic oscillations are the most likely
source for synchronising neurons over whole areas of cortex, suggesting
that the conscious percept is located in the thalamus rather than the
cortex.
## Synchronisation of Neural Processes
Our experience seems to contain entities with their attributes attached
to them at the correct places in space and time. When a dog barks we see
its jaws open at the same time as the bark and both jaws and bark are at
the same location. We take this for granted but the brain must be
engaging in some complex processing to achieve this synchronised and
appropriately positioned set of objects and events. The illustration
below shows the two basic processes that might be used to synchronise
events between the different specialised processors in the cerebral
cortex and brain in general.
![](Constudsynch.gif "Constudsynch.gif")
In the first option a complete model of sensation, dream etc. may be
created and then allowed to become part of conscious experience. In the
second model events are released into experience as fast as possible but
are synchronous when recalled, having been synchronised in a storage
buffer. There is a third option in which there is no synchronisation of
events so that the output from different processors would occur at
different times.
The \'experience buffer\' would be a volume of brain in which a
succession of events could be recorded. The buffer might either be
updated in steps, the previous content being discarded, or continuously
updated with the oldest content being lost continuously.
In the first option events from different processes would always appear
to be simultaneous unless the experience buffer were updated as a series
of steps in which case any changes at around the moment of updating
might appear in successive buffers. For instance, if change of position
were processed before change in colour a circle on a screen that changed
from green to red at the start of a motion might seem to be briefly
green during the motion and then turn red.
In the second model events from different processors might appear
asynchronous at the moment of experience but synchronous when recalled.
Colour vision and motion vision are processed in different parts of the
visual cortex and in distinct parts of visual cortical areas V1 and V2.
They are different processes and hence ideal for studying the
synchronisation of cortical activity. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997)
presented subjects with moving coloured squares on a computer screen
that changed from red to green or vice versa as they changed direction
of movement. It was found that subjects seemed to perceive changes in
colour some 70-80 msecs before they perceived a change in the direction
of motion of the squares. Further work by Arnold *et al.* (2001) and
Arnold and Clifford (2001) have confirmed that colour changes seem to be
perceived before motion. Arnold and Clifford (2001) also found a
quantitative relationship between the colour/motion asynchrony and the
direction of change of motion, complete reversals of direction giving
rise to the greatest asynchrony between the detection of colour and
motion changes.
Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) conclude by stating that the asynchrony of
neural processes shows that \"..the perception of each attribute is
solely the result of the activity in the specialised system involved in
its processing..\". It seems more likely that the experiments simply
show that slow neural processes are not synchronised before they become
percepts (the third option above). The experiments are excellent
evidence for the concept of the cortex as a set of specialised
processors that deliver their output asynchronously to some other place
where the output becomes a percept.
These experiments on colour and motion suggest that there is no
synchronisation between the processes that deal with these two aspects
of vision. Another set of experiments by Clifford *et al.* (2003)
supports this idea of processing being asynchronous. They asked subjects
to perform a variety of judgements of when visual events occurred and
found that the degree of synchrony of one visual event with another
depends on the type of judgement. Different judgements probably use
processors in different areas of cortex and the output from these
arrives asynchronously at the part of the brain that supports the
percept.
When the percept is formed there must be feedback to the cortical
processes that create its content. Otherwise it would not be possible to
report about the percept and the cortex would be unable to direct
processing to the percept in preference to other, non-conscious cortical
data.
Although slow processes (20 milliseconds to 1 second) do not seem to be
synchronised there is some evidence for very rapid synchronisation.
Andrews *et al.* (1996) revisited a problem raised by the famous
physiologist Charles Sherrington. Sherrington considered the phenomenon
of \'flicker fusion\' in which a flickering light appears to be a
continuous steady light if it flashes on and off at frequencies of about
45 Hz or higher. He reasoned that if the images from both eyes are
brought together to form a single image then the frequency at which a
flickering light appears to be steady should depend on whether one or
two eyes are used. Flicker fusion should occur if each eye receives
alternate flashes at only half the normal flicker fusion frequency. The
flicker should disappear if the left eye receives flashes at 23 pulses
per second and the right eye receives alternate flashes at 23 pulses per
second. When Sherrington performed the experiment he found that this was
not the case, using approximate figures, each eye required 46 pulses per
second for fusion to occur. Sherrington proposed that the flicker fusion
in alternate binocular presentation was occurring \"psychically\",
outside of normal physiological processes.
Andrews *et al.* duplicated Sherrington\'s result but investigated it
further. They found that when lights were flashed in each eye
alternately at low frequences (2 Hz) the experience was the same as a
light being flashed in both eyes at this rate. At frequencies of four Hz
and higher the subjects began to report that the lights being flashed
alternately in both eyes seemed to flicker at the same rate as lights
being flashed in both eyes at half the frequency. It seemed as if a
flash in one eye followed by a flash in the other eye was being
perceived as a single flash or \"conflated\" as the authors put it. The
authors explained this effect by suggesting that the brain activity
corresponding to the flashes was sampled for a short period and any
number of flashes occurring during this period became perceived as a
single flash. The maximum rate of sampling would be about 45 Hz. This
idea is similar to option (1) above, where the buffer is filled and
emptied 40 - 50 times a second.
An experience buffer that is refreshed at 40-50 times a second might
also explain the results obtained with colour and motion asynchrony
because synchronisation between processes may well happen too quickly to
affect processes that occur at very slow rates. Singer and Gray (1995),
Singer (2001) have proposed that synchronisation between neurones at
about 45 Hz is the discriminator between those neurones with activity
that contributes to conscious experience and activity in other neurones.
A rapid refresh rate in a synchronising buffer agrees with the results
found by Fries *et al.* (1997) in which visual cortical neurones that
represent a percept underwent synchronous oscillations in the gamma
frequency range (39--63 Hz). Tononi *et al.* (1998) have also found
synchronisation of neural activity in neurones that represent the
percept.
The gamma frequency oscillations are intrinsic to the cortex but are
triggered by the thalamus and are part of the \'arousal system\'.
Readers should be wary of the term \'arousal system\' because it evokes
the idea of something waking up a conscious cortex. The cortex can be
fully active during sleep and even during pathological unconsciousness
such as persistent vegetative state so it is possible that the arousal
centres themselves or nearby structures actually host phenomenal
consciousness.
## EEG and synchronisation
If electrodes are placed on the scalp varying electrical potentials of a
few tens of microvolts can be recorded between the electrodes.
Recordings of potentials from electrodes on the scalp are known as
electroencephalograms (EEGs).
The potentials recorded in the EEG are due to postsynaptic potentials in
nerve cells. The EEG is insensitive to the activity of single cells and
occurs as a result of relatively slow, **synchronised**, changes in
large areas of cells. The differences in potential between two scalp
electrodes are largely due to depolarisation and hyperpolarisation of
the dendritic trees of cortical pyramidal cells. The folding of the
cortex (gyri) is problematical for recording and interpreting EEGs
because opposing layers of cortex can cancel any net potentials.
The EEG shows rhythmic activity. This is conventionally divided into the
following frequency bands:
Delta waves 0--4 Hz
Theta waves 4--8 Hz
Alpha waves 8--12 Hz
Beta waves \>10 Hz
Gamma waves (also called fast beta) 25--100 Hz
EEGs also contain short bursts of activity called spindles and very fast
oscillations (VFOs). Spindles last for 1--2 seconds and contain rhythmic
activity at 7--14 Hz. They are associated with the onset of sleep. The
VFOs consist of short bursts at frequencies of over 80 Hz.
When the eyes are closed the amplitude of activity from most pairs of
electrodes is increased compared with when the eyes are open. When
subjects are awake the EEG consists mainly of alpha and beta activity
with considerable low amplitude gamma when the eyes are open. In stage 1
sleep the EEG consists of theta waves, in stage 2 sleep of varied
activity and spindles, in stage 4 sleep of delta and during REM sleep of
beta and theta activity. In epileptic seizures there tends to be high
amplitude activity with pronounced synchronisation between many pairs of
electrodes.
The rhythmic electrical activity is due to cortical feedback loops,
cortico-cortical synchronisation, thalamic pacemakers and
thalamo-cortical synchronisation. VFOs have been attributed to the
activity of electrical connections between cells (dendro-dendritic gap
junctions) (Traub (2003)).
The gamma activity, centred on a frequency of 40 Hz appears to be
related to activity in cortical interneurons that form electrical
connections between their dendrites (Tamas *et al.* 2000). These
oscillations can be triggered by high frequency stimulation of the
posterior intralaminar nuclei of the thalamus (Barth and MacDonald 1996,
Sukov and Barth 2001) and as a result of activation of the reticular
system (Munk *et al.* 1996). This suggests that stimulation of cortex by
thalamic sensory relays triggers gamma band activity in the cortex. A
shift from gamma to beta waves can occur in human event related
potentials after about 0.2 secs (Pantev 1995, Traub *et al.* 1999).
The alpha activity is related to thalamic pacemakers, perhaps as a
result of intrinsic oscillatory activity in thalamic sensory relays (see
Roy & Prichep 2005 for a brief review). Theta activity, which occurs
during some cognitive tasks and mental arithmetic involves a loop from
the cortex to the non-specific thalamic nuclei. Delta activity seems to
be endogenous to cortex when input is suppressed during sleep. Beta
activity is due to cortico-cortical interactions, often after a brief
period of gamma activation. It should be noted that gamma and beta
activity can be expressed as impulses in cortico-thalamic pathways and
that when cortical and thalamic activity is correlated there is a
conscious state. In other words gamma or beta waves in the cortex are
not correlates of consciousness on their own - see for instance Laureys
*et al.* (2002).
## Event related potentials
After a sudden event there are a characteristic set of changes in EEG
activity known as **event related potentials** or ERPs. The time course
of the ERP is shown in the diagram below.
![](Constudevent.png "Constudevent.png")
ERPs occur in response to novel stimuli and are also produced by brief
transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS)(Iramina *et al.* 2002). The slow
component is known as the P3 or P300 phase of the ERP. It is due to
activation of areas of the brain that are relatively remote from the
primary sensory areas of brain.
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) have reviewed the origin of the P300 ERP:
\"To summarize, convergent evidence suggests that P3-like activity can
be recorded in several, widely separated brain areas. These include some
medial temporal and subcortical structures (e.g., the hippocampal
formation, amygdala, and thalamus), but these structures are unlikely to
contribute directly to the scalp-recorded P3.\". According to
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) the recorded P300 may be due to
temporo-parietal and prefrontal cortical activity. Linden (2005) has
also concluded that widespread, but specific, cortical activation is
correlated with the recorded P300 ERP.
The generator of the P300 is still obscure. Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005)
consider that the Locus coeruleus, a nucleus in the pons that regulates
task related attention and part of the sleep-wake cycle, may be
responsible. In line with this, Mashour *et al.* (2005) have discovered
that TMS induced P300 activity is reduced in unconscious states.
Whether the P300 is related to Libet\'s 0.5 second delay is still
obscure but the discovery that the P300 occurs in association with
subliminal stimuli (stimuli that do not enter awareness)(Bernat *et al.*
2001) suggests that it is associated with non-conscious cortical
processing. Williams *et al.* (2004), in an investigation of subliminal
and supraliminal fear perception, found that \"conscious fear perception
was distinguished by a more prominent N4, peaking around 400 msec\"; the
N4 component follows the P300 component in the succession of phases of
the ERP. Williams *et al.* considered that the earlier phases in the ERP
are probably related to non-conscious processing. In contrast Vogel *et
al.* (1998) found that suppression of the P300 was associated with
suppression of awareness.
## The integration delay
Psychological experiments often involve binary decisions where subjects
give one of two outputs in response to stimuli. It is found that if the
stimuli are made increasingly noisy or complex the response time tends
to increase. Psychophyicists have developed various mathematical models
to explain the increased response times due to noise such as the
Integrator and Accumulator models (cf: Luce(1986)). These models have
been fairly successful when explaining experiments such as judging the
net direction of movement of sets of dots on a screen when the dots are
given semi-random paths and different brightness etc. In these
circumstances it can take up to 2 seconds for an accurate decision.
There are many tasks however where the accuracy of decision making does
not improve after about 300 milliseconds. The accuracy of the
performance of rats when choosing between two alternatives when reacting
to odours peaks at about 300 ms (Uchida and Mainen(2003), Abraham *et
al.* (2004)). The accuracy of humans when performing vernier acuity
tasks, line detection, contrast sensitivity, motion velocity
discrimination and stereoscopic depth discrimination seems to peak at
300ms (Uchida *et al.* 2006).
Uchida, Kepecs and Mainen (2006) suggest that \"rapid and short
integration time is a sensible strategy for rapid processing of
low-level sensory information in order to form more complex sensory
images, both in vision and olfaction.\" Whether these authors regard
these derived sensory images as the content of consciousness is not
mentioned. The authors propose that the 300ms optimal integration time
may be partly due to the mechanics of sniffing (a sniff takes about
125-200ms) and the nature of optical fixation (inter-saccade intervals
are typically 200-400 ms ). The authors note that the animal or human
could, in principle, choose to integrate over longer intervals but if it
is moving this may not lead to information that is current for changed
circumstances.
An optimal processing time of about 300 ms would be consistent with the
delays observed before conscious awareness occurs in response to a
stimulus - an interval required to form \"more complex sensory images\".
## Global Workspace Theory
Global Workspace Theory is the idea that somewhere in the brain there is
a facility that integrates the processes that occur in the various
separate areas of the brain. The theory was first proposed by Descartes
as the *sensus communis*, the common sense, but the modern form of the
theory dispenses with the idea of a point soul looking at the brain. In
modern Global Workspace theory it is proposed that an area of brain
receives input from most of the cerebral cortex and broadcasts its
outputs to all of the unconscious modular information processors in the
brain.
Modern Global Workspace Theory has been championed by Baars (1983,
1988).
There is increasing evidence for a Global Workspace or Global Workspaces
in the brain. Much of this evidence comes from fMRI, single unit and
magnetoencephalography studies in which it is shown that non-conscious
or subliminal processing mainly occupies primary, sensory cortex whereas
conscious processing occupies large areas of cerebral cortex.
In binocular rivalry the stimulus that is consciously perceived is
responsible for relatively intense activation of large areas of brain
whereas the non-conscious stimulus is often suppressed (see above and
Sheinberg & Logothetis (1997), Tononi *et al.* (1998)). The suppression
is likely to occur in the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei which suggests a
role for the Thalamic Reticular Nuclei, which modulate LGN activity, in
the control of the percept.
### Masking and visual awareness
Word masking has also been used to investigate the idea of a Global
Workspace. When a word is presented on its own for a few tens of
milliseconds it remains readable but if it is immediately succeeded by,
or accompanied by, another word it becomes indistinct or invisible. This
effect is known as \"word masking\". Vogel *et al.* (1998) have
investigated a version of word masking known as the \"attentional
blink\". They found that when stimuli became invisible the P3 component
of the Event Related Potential, which peaks at around 300-500 millisecs
after a stimulus, was completely suppressed. The P3 component of the ERP
has been related to the lodging of data in working memory and also to
gamma band activity in the EEG. This strongly suggests the involvement
of a cortico-thalamic loop in the \"attentional blink\". The delay of
0.3 to 0.5 secs is typical of the time required for conscious awareness
(see above).
Word masking in conjunction with fMRI and Event Related Potential (ERP)
recordings has been used by Dehaene *et al.* (2001) to expose control by
a central mechanism. It was found that masked words activate mainly the
visual cortex and ventral stream (inferior temporal lobe) whereas
visible words also activated distant parietal, prefrontal and cingulate
sites.
Dehaene *et al.* (2003) and found that the dynamics of the loss of
visibility of words in an attentional blink experiment could be modelled
by a simulated cortico-thalamic loop. In their simulation a distributed
cortical process determined which events would receive attention and the
system used the thalamic gating systems to exclude those that did not
receive attention.
Tse *et al.* (2005) have used purely visual stimuli in masking
experiments and concluded that, in the case of purely visual stimuli,
the neural correlates of awareness were limited to the occipital cortex:
\"We suggest that there are both lower and upper bounds within the
visual hierarchy for the processing of visual masking and the
maintenance of visual awareness of simple unattended targets; the lower
bound is at least as high as the border between V2 and V3, and the upper
bound is within the occipital lobe, possibly somewhere downstream of
V4.\"
This discovery would mean that activation of large areas of cortex are
unnecessary for awareness.
Melloni *et al.* (2007) compared compared the electrophysiological
responses related to the processing of visible and invisible words in a
delayed matching to sample task. Both perceived and nonperceived words
caused a similar increase of local (gamma) oscillations in the EEG, but
only perceived words induced a transient long-distance synchronization
of gamma oscillations across widely separated regions of the brain.
After this transient period of temporal coordination, the electrographic
signatures of conscious and unconscious processes continue to diverge.
Only words reported as perceivedinduced (1) enhanced theta oscillations
over frontal regions during the maintenance interval, (2) an increase of
the P300 component of the event-related potential, and (3) an increase
in power and phase synchrony of gamma oscillationsbefore the anticipated
presentation of the test word. We propose that the critical process
mediating the access to conscious perception is the earlytransient
global increase of phase synchrony of oscillatory activity in the
gammafrequency.
Melloni L, Molina C, Pena M, Torres D, Singer W, Rodriguez E. (2007).
Synchronization of neural activity across cortical areas correlates
withconscious perception.J Neurosci. 2007 Mar 14;27(11):2858-65.
### Attention and the global workspace
Baars (2002) in his review of evidence for the Global Workspace Theory
quotes many other experiments that show activation of larger areas of
cortex in response to conscious stimuli compared with unconscious or
subliminal stimuli.The effect is also seen in change blindness, learning
and attention. Newman and Baars (1993) consider that the \"workspace\"
is fairly global in the brain:
\"This Neural Global Workspace (NGW) model views conscious processes in
terms of a globally integrative brain system. The neural circuitry
contributing to this system is not only widely distributed across the
neocortex, but includes key corticothalamic and midbrain circuits as
well. These cortico-subcortical circuits are hypothesized to be critical
to understanding the mechanisms of attentional control that provide an
essential basis for the conscious processing of information\".
However they focus particularly on the role of the thalamic Reticular
Nucleus and cortico-thalamic connectivity in the control of attention.
Other ideas for the location of the Global Workspace are the idea of
Singer et al. that gamma synchrony controls access to the content of
consciousness and Llinas et al. (1998) that the thalamus is the hub
through which communication occurs between areas of cortex.
One of the problems with Global Workspace theory is that it suggests
that attention, working memory, cognitive control and consciousness may
all be in the same area of the brain. It is likely that the mechanisms
of attention, working memory, and cognitive control may involve several,
interlinked systems perhaps co-opting the basal ganglia in the process.
In view of this Maia and Cleeremans (2005) propose that \".. attention,
working memory, cognitive control and consciousness are not distinct
functions implemented by separate brain systems. Attempting to find
separate neural correlates for each may therefore be the wrong approach.
Instead, we suggest that they should be understood in terms of the
dynamics of global competition, with biasing from PFC (prefrontal
cortex).\". The inclusion by Maia and Cleeremans of consciousness with
distributed attention, working memory and cognitive control is
reminiscent of Zeki & Bartel\'s idea of microconsciousness.
It should be noted that, in common with Libet\'s data, the percept seems
to be available to phenomenal consciousness some 0.3 to 0.5 secs after a
stimulus; this suggests that whatever determines the content of
phenomenal consciousness operates before events become part of
phenomenal consciousness. This relegates phenomenal consciousness from
being a controller of attention to being the recipient of content that
is the subject of attention. This finding is consistent with the
philosophical problem of the **apparently** epiphenomenal nature of
phenomenal consciousness.
Given the data on the timing of conscious awareness it seems that there
may be two \"workspaces\", an active workspace that models the world,
discarding and suppressing data during rivalry, and a passive workspace
that receives the final, edited product. The active workspace would
correlate with the cortical systems stressed by Dehaene *et al.* and
Maia and Cleermans although, given the results of Tse et al., the
workspace would be limited to small zones of cortex. The loading of the
passive workspace with the output of the active workspace would
correlate with thalamo-cortical activity during component P3 of the ERP
in which data is transferred from the cortex to the thalamus. This
workspace might constitute the source for reports of the content of
phenomenal consciousness.
Llinas *et al.* (1998) have proposed two parallel cortico-thalamic
attentional systems, one of which is related to the thalamic specific
nuclei and the other to the thalamic non-specific nuclei, especially the
ILN. The non-specific system would be related to consciousness itself.
## The \"cognitive map\" and the neural basis of perceptual space
Our bodies appear to be mobile within a constant space. We walk around a
room; the room does not rotate around us. The constancy of the location
of things gives us the feeling that we are directly viewing a constant
world. But how does the brain provide a constant world rather than a
world that rotates with the movement of the sense organs? Why is our
view of the world when we move our eyes so different from the disturbing
flow of images that occur when a video camera is waved around? Do our
brains contain a constant \"cognitive map\" (O\'Keefe and Nadel 1978) of
our surroundings?
Mittelstaedt & Mittelstaedt (1980, 1982) discovered that female gerbils
were able to recover their pups in darkened surroundings by searching in
a semi random fashion on the outbound journey and then proceeding
directly back to the nest on the inbound journey. The direct journey
back to the nest seemed to be due to an integration of the various
directions taken on the outward journey (**path integration**). If the
equipment being explored by the mother gerbil was rotated very slowly
the mother would make an error equivalent to the amount of rotation.
More rapid rotations that activated the vestibular system of the rat
(acceleration measurement) did not cause errors in navigation. This
demonstration that rodents could navigate accurately on the basis of
**idiothetic** cues (cues that are due to internal senses) led to
research on the neural basis of the navigation.
As early as 1971 O\'Keefe and Dostrovsky had discovered that there are
particular cells in the hippocampus that fire according to the position
of an animal in the environment. This has been complimented by research
that showed that changes in visual cues within the environment caused
changes in the firing rate of place cells in hippocampal area CA3 (.
![](Gray717.png "Gray717.png")
![](HippocampalRegions.jpg "HippocampalRegions.jpg")
!Entorhinal cortex approximately maps to areas 28 and
34{width="500"}
F. P. Battaglia and A. Treves. 1998 Attractor neural networks storing
multiple space representations: A model for hippocampal place fields.
PHYSICAL REVIEW E DECEMBER 1998 VOLUME 58, NUMBER 6
<http://www.sissa.it/~ale/Bat+98b.pdf>
Leutgeb, S., Leutgeb, J.K., Moser, M-B, and Moser, E.I. 2005. Place
cells, spatial maps and the population code for memory. Current Opinion
in Neurobiology 2005, 15:738--746.
<http://instruct1.cit.cornell.edu/courses/bionb720nejc/reprints/LeutgebEtAl2005.pdf>
Mittelstaedt, H. & Mittelstaedt, M-L. 1982. Avian Navigation. (ed. Papi,
F. & Wallraff, H.) 290-297. Springer, Berlin.
Mittelstaedt, M-L & Glasauer, S. 1991. Idiothetic Navigation in Gerbils
and Humans. Zool. Jb. Physiol. 95 (1991), 427-435
<http://web.archive.org/web/20110125132449/http://www.nefo.med.uni-muenchen.de/~sglasauer/MittelstaedtGlasauer1991.pdf>
O\'Keefe, J. & Dostrovsky, J. (1971). The hippocampus as a spatial map:
preliminary evidence from unit activity in the freely moving rat. Brain
Res. 34, 171-175.
O\'Keefe, J. & Nadel, L. (1978). The Hippocampus as a cognitive map.
(Oxford)
## Bibliography
Defining the States of Consciousness. Tassi, P., Muzet, A. (2001)
Neuroscience and Behavioural Reviews 25(2001) 175-191.
Neuroanatomy: \"Digital Slice of Life\" by Stensaas and Millhouse
<http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/subj2.html>
See also: <http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/index.html>
EEG\'s: Coles, M.G.H., Rugg, M.D. Event Related Brain Potentials: An
Introduction.
<http://whalen.psych.udel.edu/667/1.What_is_ERP/ColesRugg1995chpt1.pdf>
Visual System: Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual
Awareness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
Professor Bogen\'s Consciousness Page
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/toccons.htm>
Demonstrations of Auditory Illusions and Tricks. Yoshitaka Nakajima
<http://www.kyushu-id.ac.jp/~ynhome/ENG/Demo/illusions2nd.html>
## References
- Abraham, N.M. (2004) Maintaining accuracy at the expense of speed:
stimulus similarity defines odor discrimination time in mice. Neuron
44, 865-876.
- Aleman, A., Ramsey, N., Van Honk, J.E., Kessels, R.P.C., Hoogduin,
J., Schutter, D.L.G., Postma, A., Kahn, R.S., De Haan, E.H.F.
(submitted). Parietal cortex mediates visuospatial imagery: evidence
from fMRI and rTMS.
<http://igitur-archive.library.uu.nl/dissertations/1954455/c10.pdf>
- Alkire, M.T., Haier, R.J., Fallon, J.H., and Barker, S.J.(1996). PET
imaging of conscious and unconscious verbal memory. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, 3 ( 5-6) 1996 , pp. 448--462
<http://www.imprint.co.uk/jcs_3_5-6.html>
- Anderson, J. & Anderson, B. (1993). \"The Myth of Persistence of
Vision Revisited,\" Journal of Film and Video, Vol. 45, No. 1
(Spring 1993): 3-12.
<http://www.uca.edu/org/ccsmi/ccsmi/classicwork/Myth%20Revisited.htm>
- Andrews, T.J., White, L.E., Binder, D. & Purves, D. (1996). Temporal
events in cyclopean vision. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 93,
pp. 3689--3692, April 1996. Neurobiology.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030510095149/http://www.dur.ac.uk/tim.andrews/PNAS_93_3689.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G. (2001) Determinants of asynchronous
processing in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London,
Series B: Biological Sciences, 269, 579 - 583.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031205165920/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/AC02.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G, Wenderoth, P. (2001). Asynchronous
processing in vision: Color leads motion. Current Biology, 11,
596 - 600.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030617120017/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/ACW01.pdf>
- Austin, G.M. & Grant, F.C. (1958). Physiologic observations
following total hemispherectomy in man. Surgery 38, 239-258.
- Baars, B.J. (1983) Conscious contents provide the nervous system
with coherent, global information. In Consciousness and
Self-Regulation (Vol 3). Davidson, R.J. et al., editors. Plenum
Press.
- Baars, B.J. (1988) A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness, Cambridge
University Press.
- Baars, B., Newman, J., & Taylor, J. (1998) Neuronal mechanisms of
consciousness: A Relational Global Workspace framework., in
Hameroff, Stuart and Kaszniak, Al and Laukes, James, Eds. Toward a
Science of Consciousness II: The second Tucson discussions and
debates., chapter 24, pages 269-278. MIT Press.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000946/>
- Baars, B.J. (2002) The conscious access hypothesis: origins and
recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. Vol 6, No 1,
47-52. 2002. <http://www.cs.memphis.edu/~wrcm/BaarsTICS2002.pdf>
- Barth, D. S. and MacDonald, K. D. (1996) Thalamic modulation of
high-frequency oscillating potentials in auditory cortex. Nature.
383, 78-81.
- Bernat E, Shevrin H, Snodgrass M. (2001). Subliminal visual oddball
stimuli evoke a P300 component. Clin Neurophysiol. 2001
Jan;112(1):159-71.
- Blake, R., Westendorf, D. and Overton, R. (1979) What is suppressed
during binocular rivalry? Perception 9: 223-231.
- Blake, R. and Lee, S.-H. (1999). Rival ideas about binocular
rivalry. Vision Research. 39: 1447-1454
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/faculty/blake/PDFs/Lee_Blake_99VR.pdf>
- Blankenburg, F., Ruff, C.C., Deichmann, R., Rees, G. and
Driver, J. (2006) The cutaneous rabbit illusion affects human
primary sensory cortex somatotopically, PLoS Biol 2006;4(3):e69.
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness: I. An
overview. Consciousness and Cognition, 4, 52-62.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/bogen-95.pdf>
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness:
Part II. Constraining the semantic problem. Consciousness and
Cognition, 4, 137-158.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/concog95.htm>
- Bregman, A.S. (1990). Auditory scene analysis: The perceptual
organization of sound. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Budka, H. (1998). Fatal Familial Insomnia Around the World. Brain
Pathology, 8: 553-570.
<http://brainpath.medsch.ucla.edu/pdfs/0803pdf/budka.pdf>
- Carandini M, Heeger DJ, & Senn W, (2002). A synaptic explanation of
suppression in visual cortex, Journal of Neuroscience,
22:10053-10065, 2002.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031031214953/http://www.cns.nyu.edu/~david/ftp/reprints/Carandini-JNeurosci2002.pdf>
- Cariani, P. (2000). Anesthesia, Neural Information Processing, And
Conscious Awareness. Consciousness And Cognition Vol. 9, No. 3,
September 2000 p. 387-395
- Castro-Alamancos, M.A., Connors, B.W. (1997). Thalamo-cortical
synapses. Progress in Neurobiology, Vol.51, pp. 581 to 606, 1997
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051025163047/http://neurobio.drexel.edu/castroweb/progneurobio1.pdf>
- Christmann, C. & Leuthold, H. (2004). The Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Section A. Volume 57, Number 2 /
February 2004. 357-381.
- Claus, R. & Nel, W. (2006). Drug induced arousal from the permanent
vegetative state. NeuroRehabilitation. 2006;21(1):23-8.
- Clifford, C.W.G., Arnold, D.H., Pearson, J. (2003). A paradox of
temporal perception revealed by a stimulus oscillating in colour and
orientation. Vision Research 43 (2003) 2245-2253.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031102125210/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/CAP03.pdf>
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of
consciousness Seminars in the Neurosciences (1990) 2, 263-275
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1998). Consciousness and Neuroscience.
Cerebral Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
- Culham, J.C., Dukelow, S.P., Vilis, T., Hassard, F.A., Gati, J.S.,
Menon, R.S. and Goodale, M.A. (1999). Recovery of fMRI Activation in
Motion Area MT Following Storage of the Motion Aftereffect. The
Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 81 No. 1 January 1999, pp. 388--393.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/81/1/388>
- Deecke, L. (1996) Planning, preparation, execution, and imagery of
volitional action, (Introduction / Editorial) in: L. Deecke W.
Lang, A. Berthoz (Eds) Mental Representations of Motor Acts.
Cognitive Brain Res 3 / Special Issue (2) 59-64.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000015/00/COGBRAIN.html>
- Dehaene, S., Sergent, C., and Changeux, J. (2003) A neuronal network
model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data
during conscious perception. PNAS July 8, 2003 vol. 100 no. 14
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/DehaeneSergentChangeux_BlinkModel_PNAS2003.pdf>
- Dehaene, S. et al. (2001) Cerebral mechanisms of word masking and
unconscious repetition priming. Nat. Neurosci, 4, 752-758.
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/Dehaene_MaskedWords_NatureNeuroscience2001.pdf>
- Dennett, D. and Kinsbourne, M. (1992) Time and the Observer: the
Where and When of Consciousness in the Brain. (1992) Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 15, 183-247, 1992. Reprinted in The Philosopher\'s
Annual, Grim, Mar and Williams, eds., vol. XV-1992, 1994,
pp. 23--68; Noel Sheehy and Tony Chapman, eds., Cognitive Science,
Vol. I, Elgar, 1995,
pp. 210--274.http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/time&obs.htm
- Destexhe, A. (2000). Modelling corticothalamic feedback and the
gating of the thalamus by the cerebral cortex. J. Physiol (Paris),
94 (2000) 391-410. <http://cns.iaf.cnrs-gif.fr/files/Brem2000.pdf>
- Fang, F. & He, S. (2005).Cortical responses to invisible objects in
the human dorsal and ventral pathways. Nat Neurosci. 2005
Oct;8(10):1380-5. Epub 2005 Sep 4.
- Ffytche, D. H., Howard, R. J., Brammer, M. J., David, A., Woodruff,
P., & Williams, S. (1998). The anatomy of conscious vision: an fMRI
study of visual hallucinations. Nature Neuroscience, 1, 738--742.
- Fiset, P., Paus, T., Daloze, T., Plourde, G., Meuret, P., Bonhomme,
V., Hajj-Ali, N., Backman, S.B., and Evans, A.C. (1999). Brain
Mechanisms of Propofol-Induced Loss of Consciousness in Humans: a
Positron Emission Tomographic Study. The Journal of Neuroscience,
July 1, 1999, 19(13):5506-5513.
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/13/5506>
- Fu, C.H.Y., Morgan, K., Suckling, J., Williams, S.C.R., Andrew, C.,
Vythelingum, G.N., McGuire, P.K. (2002). A Functional Magnetic
Resonance Imaging Study of Overt Letter Verbal Fluency Using a
Clustered Acquisition Sequence: Greater Anterior Cingulate
Activation with Increased Task Demand. NeuroImage 17, 871-
879 (2002)
<http://www-bmu.psychiatry.cam.ac.uk/PUBLICATION_STORE/fu02fun.pdf>
- Ganis, G., Thomson, W.L. and Kosslyn, S.M. (2004). Brain areas
underlying visual mental imagery and visual perception: an fMRI
study. Cognitive Brain Research 20 (2004) 226--241
<http://www.wjh.harvard.edu/~kwn/Kosslyn_pdfs/2004Ganis_CogBrainRes20_BrainAreas.pdf>
- Hultin, L. (1997). On Neuromagnetic Assessment of the Contingent
Negative Variation.
<http://www2.lib.chalmers.se/cth/diss/doc/9697/HultinLeif.html>
- Fries, P.. Roelfsema, P.R., Engel, A.K., König, P. and Singer, W.
(1997). Synchronization of oscillatory responses in visual cortex
correlates with perception in interocular rivalry. Proc. Natl. Acad.
Sci. USA, Vol. 94, pp. 12699--12704, November 1997.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/23/12699>
- Fuentealba, P., Crochet, S., Timofeev, I., Bazhenov, M., Sejnowski,
T.J. and Steriade, M. (2004). European Journal of Neuroscience
20(1):111-119. <http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2004/22126/ch03.html>
- Goaillard, J. & Vincent, P. (2002). Serotonin suppresses the slow
afterhyperpolarization in rat intralaminar and midline thalamic
neurones by activating 5-HT7 receptors. Journal of Physiology
(2002), 541.2, pp. 453--465
<http://jp.physoc.org/cgi/content/full/541/2/453>
- Haggard, P. & Eimer, M. (1999) On the relation between brain
potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Exp. Brain Res.
126, 128--133 (1999).
- Haggard, P. (2008) Human volition:towards a neuroscience of will.
Nature Rev Neurosci 9, 934-946
- Haynes, J., Deichmann, R. and Rees, G. (2005). Eye-specific effects
of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate nucleus. Nature
438, 496-499 (24 November 2005)
- Hughes S.W., Blethyn K.L. , Cope D.W. , & Crunelli V. (2003).
Properties and origin of spikelets in thalamocortical neurones in
vitro. Neuroscience. 2002;110(3):395-401
- Iramina, K., Maeno, T., Kowatari, Y. and Ueno, S.. (2002). Effects
of Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation on EEG Activity .IEEE
TRANSACTIONS ON MAGNETICS, VOL. 38, NO. 5, SEPTEMBER 2002
- Ishai, A., Ungerleider, L.G., Haxby, J.V.. (2000) Distributed neural
systems for the generation of visual images. Neuron 28, 979-990.
- Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1980). Mental models in cognitive science.
Cognitive Science, 4, 71-115.
<http://cognitrn.psych.indiana.edu/rgoldsto/cogsci/classics.html>
- Keller, J. & Heckhausen, H. (1990). Readiness potentials preceding
spontaneous motor acts: voluntary vs. involuntary control.
Electroencephalography and Clinical Neuropsychology, 76, 351-361.
- King, C.C. (1991). Fractal and Chaotic Dynamics in Nervous Systems.
Progress in Neurobiology, 36, pp. 279--308, 1991.
<http://citeseer.nj.nec.com/king91fractal.html>
- Klein, S.A (2002). Libet's Temporal Anomalies: A Reassessment of the
Data.
Consciousness and Cognition 11, 198--214 (2002)
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/160.pdf>
- Klein, S. (2002). Libet\'s Timing of Mental Events: Commentary on
the Commentaries. Consciousness and Cognition. 11, 326-333.
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/ccog_2002_0580-Klein-Commentary_on_the_commentaries.pdf>
- Kleinschmidt, A., Bichel, C. Zeki, S. and Frackowiak, R.S.J. (1998).
Human brain activity during spontaneously reversing perception of
ambiguous figures. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 1998 Dec
22;265(1413):2427-33
- Konishi, S., Wheeler, M.E., Donaldson, D.I., Buckner, R.L.. (2000)
Neural correlates of episodic retrieval success. NeuroImage: 12:
276-286.
- Kornhuber HH, Deecke L: Hirnpotentialänderungen beim Menschen vor
und nach Willkürbewegungen, dargestellt mit Magnetbandspeicherung
und Rückwärtsanalyse. Pflügers Arch. ges. Physiol. 281 (1964) 52.
- Kosslyn, S.M., Thompson, W.L. (2003). When is early visual cortex
activated during visual mental imagery? Psychol. Bull. 129
(2003)723-746.
- Kreiman, G., Koch, C. and Fried, I. (2000). Imagery neurons in the
human brain. Nature (2000) 408: 357-361
<http://www.cns.caltech.edu/~gabriel/publications/imagination1.html>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I., & Koch, C. (2001). Single neuron responses
in humans during binocular rivalry and flash suppression. Journal of
Vision, 1(3), 131a, <http://journalofvision.org/1/3/131>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I. And Koch, C. (2002) Single Neuron responses
in the human brain during flash suppression. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Science USA, 99:8378-8383
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031015091920/http://www.ai.mit.edu/projects/cbcl/publications/ps/kreimanetal_flash-suppression.pdf>
- Larsen, A., Madsen, K.H., Lund, T.E., and Bundesen, C. (2006).
Images of Illusory Motion in Primary Visual Cortex. Journal of
Cognitive Neuroscience. 2006;18:1174-1180.
- Laureys, S. et al. (2002). Brain function in the vegetative state.
Acta neurol. belg., 2002, 102, 177-185
<http://www.jsmf.org/meetings/2003/nov/LaureysANB2002.pdf>
- Lee. S, and Blake, R. (2002). V1 activity is reduced during
binocular rivalry. Journal of Vision (2002) 2, 618-626
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030722173225/http://journalofvision.org/2/9/4/article.pdf>
- Leopold, D.A. and Logothetis, N.K. (1999). Multistable phenomena:
changing views in perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 3:
254-264.
<http://www.kyb.tuebingen.mpg.de/publications/pdfs/pdf201.pdf>
- Libet, B., Alberts, E.W., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B.(1967).
Responses of Human Somatosensory Cortex to Stimuli Below Threshold
for Conscious Sensation. Science 158, 1597-1600.
- Libet, B., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B., and Pearl, D.(1979).
Subjective referral of the timing for a conscious sensory
experience. Brain, 102, pp. 192--224.
<http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/entrez/query.fcgi?holding=npg&cmd=Retrieve&db=PubMed&list_uids=427530&dopt=Abstract>
- Linden, D.E.J. (2005) The P300: Where in the Brain Is It Produced
and What Does It Tell Us? The Neuroscientist, Vol. 11, No. 6,
563-576 (2005) <http://nro.sagepub.com/cgi/reprint/11/6/563.pdf>
- Llinas, R., Ribary, U., Contreras, D. & Pedroarena, C. (1998). The
neuronal basis for consciousness. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London Ser.
B.353, 1841-1849
<http://big.cs.uiuc.edu/anncbt-papers/fall05/Llinas.the-neuronal-basis-of-consciousness.pdf>
- Logothetis, N.K., Leopold, D.A. and Sheinberg, D.L. (1996). What is
Rivalling During Binocular Rivalry. Nature, 380:621-624.
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nature/journal/v380/n6575/abs/380621a0.html>
- Loveblad, KO. et al. (1999). Silent functional magnetic resonance
imaging demonstrates focal activation in rapid eye movement sleep.
Neurology 1999;53:2193Z
- Luce, R.D. (1986). Response times: their role in inferring
elementary mental organization. Oxford University Press, New York.
- Lumer, E.D., Friston, K.J. & Rees, G. (1998) Neural correlates of
perceptual rivalry in the human brain. Science. 280(5371):1930-4.
- Macdonald, K.D., Fifkova, E., Jones, M.S. and Barth, D.S. (1998)
Focal Stimulation of the Thalamic Reticular Nucleus Induces Focal
Gamma Waves in Cortex. The Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 79 No. 1
January 1998, pp. 474--477
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/79/1/474>
- Maia, T.V. & Cleeremans, A. (2005). Consciousness: converging
insights from connectionist modeling and neuroscience. TRENDS in
Cognitive Sciences Vol.9 No.8 August 2005
<http://srsc.ulb.ac.be/axcWWW/papers/pdf/05-TICS.pdf>
- Marcel AJ. (1998). Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of
visual consciousness or visual function? Brain 1998, 121, 1565-1588.
<http://brain.oupjournals.org/cgi/reprint/121/8/1565.pdf>
- Marois, R., Yi, D-J., & Chun, M.M. (2004). The Neural Fate of
Consciously Perceived and Missed Events in the Attentional Blink.
Neuron, 41, 3: 465-472.
- Mashour, G.A., Tononi, G. and Massimini, M. (2005). Cognitive
Unbinding in Sleep and Anesthesia. Science 16 December 2005:
1768-1769.
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
<http://juno.ingentaselect.com/vl=6492085/cl=26/nw=1/rpsv/cgi-bin/cgi?body=linker&ini=nlm&reqidx=issn=0962-8452vl=264is=1380yr=1997mn=Marpg=393>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). Responses of Spectrally
Selective Cells in Macaque Area V2 to Wavelengths and Colors. J
Neurophysiol 87: 2104-2112, 2002.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/87/4/2104>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). The relationship between
cortical activation and perception investigated with invisible
stimuli. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA, 99(14):9527-9532.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/99/14/9527>
- Muckli, L., Singer, W., Zanella, F.E. and Goebel, R. (2002)
Integration of multiple motion vectors over space: an fMRI study of
transparent motion perception. Neuroimage. 2002 Aug;16(4):843-56.
- Munhall, K.G. (2001). Functional Imaging During Speech Production.
Acta Psychologica 107 (2001) 95-117.
<http://pavlov.psyc.queensu.ca/~munhallk/07_acta_version.pdf>
- Munk MHJ, Roelfsema PR, König P, Engel AK, and Singer W. (1996).
Role of reticular activation in the modulation of intracortical
synchronization Science. 272, 271-274.
- Newman, J. & Baars, B.J. (1993) A neural attentional model for
access to consciousness: A Global Workspace perspective. Concepts in
Neuroscience, 4:2, 255-290
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000073/>
- Nieuwenhuis S, Aston-Jones G & Cohen JD (2005). Decision making, the
P3, and the locus coeruleus-norepinephrine system. Psychological
Bulletin, 131(4), 510-532.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051117045339/http://www.csbmb.princeton.edu/conte/pdfs/project5/Proj5Pub06.pdf>
- Nørretranders, T. (1991) Consciousness: The User Illusion
(translated from Danish), Penguin Books,
; 1999 revision:
<http://www.worldcat.org/title/user-illusion-cutting-consciousness-down-to-size/oclc/41311618>.
- Pantev C (1995) Evoked and induced gamma-band activity of the human
cortex. Brain Topogr 7:321-330
- Pasley BN, Mayes LC, Schultz RT (2004) Subcortical discrimination of
unperceived objects during binocular rivalry. Neuron 2004,
42:163-172.
- Pessoa, L. (2005) To what extent are emotional visual stimuli
processed without attention and awareness? Current Opinion in
Neurobiology 2005, 15:188-196
<http://web.archive.org/web/20060623004726/http://www.brown.edu/Research/LCE/publications_files/Pessoa_CONB_2005.pdf>
- Pettigrew, J.D. (2001) Searching for the Switch: Neural Bases for
Perceptual Rivalry Alternations. Brain and Mind 2: 85-118, 2001.
<http://www.uq.edu.au/nuq/jack/searchswitch.pdf>
- Raymond, J. E, Shapiro, K. L., & Arnell, K. M. (1992). Temporary
suppression of visual processing in an RSVP task: An attentional
blink? Journal of Experimental Psychology. Human Perception and
Performance, 18 (3), 849-60.
- Rektor, I., Bares, M., Kanovsky, P. and Kukleta, M. (2001)
Intracerebral recording of readiness potential induced by a complex
motor task. Movement Disorders, Volume 16, Issue 4, Pages 698-704
- Rees, G., Kreiman, G., & Koch, C. (2002) Neural Correlates of
Consciousness in Humans. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3, 261
-270 (2002)
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nrn/journal/v3/n4/abs/nrn783_fs.html&dynoptions=doi1069842948>
- Rensink, RA. (2000). When Good Observers Go Bad: Change Blindness,
Inattentional Blindness, and Visual Experience. PSYCHE, 6(09),
August 2000.
<http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v6/psyche-6-09-rensink.html>
- Roy, J.E. & Prichep, L.S. (2005) The Anesthetic Cascade: A Theory of
How Anesthesia Suppresses Consciousness Anesthesiology: Volume
102(2) February 2005 pp 447--471
<http://www.anesthesiology.org/pt/re/anes/fulltext.00000542-200502000-00030.htm>
- Schiff, N.D., & Plum F. 1999. The Neurology of Impaired
Consciousness: Global Disorders and Implied Models. \[Target
article\]. Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness.
<http://www.phil.vt.edu/assc/niko.html>
- Schiff ND, Plum F. (2000) The Role of Arousal and \"Gating\" Systems
in the Neurology of Impaired Consciousness. Journal of
Neurophysiology. 17(5):438-452. (
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030924010953/http://www.uni-tuebingen.de/cog/lehre/ss2003/seminar_bewusstsein/epapers/SchiffPlum00.pdf>
- Sheinberg, D.L. and Logothetis, N.K. (1997). The role of temporal
cortical areas in perceptual organization. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA 94, 3408-3413. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/7/3408>
- Simons, D.J. & Rensink, RA. (2005). Change blindness: Past, present,
and future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol.9, pp16--20, No.1
January 2005.
<http://www.psych.ubc.ca/~rensink/publications/download/S&R-TICS-05a.pdf>
- Singer, W. & Gray, C.W. (1995). Visual feature integration and the
temporal correlation hypothesis. Annu. Rev. Neurosci., 18,
pp. 555--86, 1995.
- Singer, W. (2001). Consciousness and the Binding Problem. Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences 929:123-146 (2001)
- Solms, Mark (2000) DREAMING AND REM SLEEP ARE CONTROLLED BY
DIFFERENT BRAIN MECHANISMS, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23
(6): 793.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/Preprints/OldArchive/bbs.solms.html>
- Soon, C.S., Brass, M., Heinze, H-J. and Haynes, J-D. (2008).
Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain.
Nature Neuroscience 11, 543 - 545 (2008)
- Sukov, W. & Barth, D.S. (2001). Cellular Mechanisms of Thalamically
Evoked Gamma Oscillations in Auditory Cortex. J Neurophysiol 85:
1235-1245, 2001;
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/85/3/1235>
- Takeuchi, T., Miyasita, A., Inugami, M. & Yamamoto, Y. (2001).
Intrinsic dreams are not produced without REM sleep mechanisms:
evidence through elicitation of sleep onset REM periods. Journal of
Sleep Research Volume 10 Issue 1 Page 43 - March 2001
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tamás, G., Buh, E.H., Lörincz, A., and Somogyi, P. (2000).
Proximally targeted GABAergic synapses and gap junctions synchronize
cortical interneurons. Nature Neuroscience volume 3 no 4 April 2000.
<http://mrcanu.pharm.ox.ac.uk/pdfs/TamasNatureNeurosci2000.pdf>
- Tanaka, Y. & Sagi, D. (1998). A perceptual memory for low contrast
visual signals. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol 95:12729-12733.
<http://www.weizmann.ac.il/~masagi/TS98b.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2001). Competing Theories of Binocular Rivalry: A Possible
Resolution. Brain and Mind 2: 55-83, 2001
<http://web.archive.org/web/20041212094810/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_Brain&Mind2001.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual Awareness. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030723135239/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
- Tootell, R.B., Reppas, J.B., Dale, A.M., Look, R.B., Sereno, M.I.,
Malach, R., Brady, T.J. and Rosen, B.R. (1995) Visual motion
aftereffect in human cortical area MT revealed by functional
magnetic resonance imaging. Nature. 1995 May 11;375(6527):139-41.
- Tononi, G., Srinivasan, R., Russell, P.D. & Edelman, G.M. (1998).
Investigating neural correlates of conscious perception by
frequency-tagged neuromagnetic responses . Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA. Vol. 95, Issue 6, 3198-3203, March 17, 1998
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/95/6/3198>
- Thornton, I.M., Pinto, J. and Shiffrar, M. (1998).
THE VISUAL PERCEPTION OF HUMAN LOCOMOTION. COGNITIVE NEUROPSYCHOLOGY,
1998, 15 (6/7/8 ), 535-552.
<http://psychology.rutgers.edu/~mag/TPS98.pdf>
- Traub, D.R., Whittington, M.A., Buhl, E.H., Jefferys, J.G.R., &
Faulkner, H.J. (1999). On the Mechanism of the Frequency Shift in
Neuronal Oscillations Induced in Rat Hippocampal Slices by Tetanic
Stimulation. The Journal of Neuroscience, February 1, 1999,
19(3):1088-1105
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/3/1088>
- Traub, R.D. (2003). Fast Oscillations and Epilepsy. Epilepsy Curr.
2003 May; 3(3): 77-79.
<http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/articlerender.fcgi?artid=321178>
- Trevena J & Miller, J (2002) Cortical Movement Preparation before
and after a Conscious Decision to Move. Consciousness and Cognition,
Volume 11, Issue 2, June 2002, Pages 162-190
- Trevena, J & Miller, J (2009) Brain preparation before a voluntary
action: Evidence against unconscious movement initiation. Conscious
Cogn. 2009 Sep 5. \[Epub ahead of print\]
- Tse, P.U., Susana Martinez-Conde, S., Schlegel, A.A. and Macknik,
S.L. (2005). Visibility, visual awareness, and visual masking of
simple unattended targets are confined to areas in the occipital
cortex beyond human V1/V2. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA November 22,
2005 vol. 102 no. 47. 17178-17183.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/102/47/17178>
- Uchida, N., Kepecs, A. and Mainen, Z.F. (2006) Seeing at a glance,
smelling in a whiff: rapid forms of perceptual decision making.
Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 7. 485-491.
- Uchida, N & Mainen, Z.F. (2003) Speed and accuracy of olfacory
discrimination in the rat. Nature Neurosci. 6, 1224-1229.
- Vogel, E.K., Luck, S.J. & Shapiro, K.L. (1998) Electrophysiological
Evidence for a Postperceptual Locus of Suppression During the
Attentional Blink. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
Perception and Performance 1998, Vol. 24. No. 6,1656-1674
<http://web.archive.org/web/20050304211722/http://www.psychology.uiowa.edu/faculty/Luck/lucklab/pdfs/Vogel_1998_JEPHPP.pdf>
- Wehrle, R., Czisch, M., Kaufmann, C., Wetter, T.C., Holsboer, F.,
Auer, D.P., and Pollmacher, T. (2005). Rapid eye movement-related
brain activation in human sleep: a functional magnetic resonance
imaging study. NeuroReport 16:853-857
<http://www.univie.ac.at/mcogneu/lit/wehrle.pdf>
- White, NS., Alkire, MT. (2003). Impaired thalamocortical
connectivity in humans during
general-anesthetic-induced unconsciousness. NeuroImage. Volume 19, Issue
2 , June 2003, Pages 402-411. <http://smallurl.com?i=2597>
(http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/B6WNP-48GP5CG-5/1/cedb33dc0bec4301d1960c7c27cea70f)
- Wheeler, M.E., Buckner, R.L.. (2003) Functional dissociation among
components
of remembering: control, perceived oldness, and content. J. Neurosci.
23, 3869-3880.
- Williams LM, Liddell BJ, Rathjen J, Brown KJ, Shevrin H, Gray JA,
Phillips M, Young A & Gordon E (2004). Mapping the time course of
nonconscious and conscious perception of fear: An integration of
central and peripheral measures. Human Brain Mapping,21, 64 - 74
<http://psychmed.iop.kcl.ac.uk/neuroscience-and-emotion/downloads/46.pdf>
- Wunderlich, K. Schneider, K.A., & Kastner, S. (2005).Neural
correlates of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate
nucleus. Nature Neuroscience 8, 1595 - 1602 (2005)
- Yamamoto, T. & Katayama, Y. (2005). Deep brain stimulation therapy
for the vegetative state. in Neuropsychol Rehabil. 2005 Jul-Sep ;
15(3-4): 406-13
- Zeki, S., & Bartel, A. (1999). Toward a Theory of Visual
Consciousness. Consciousness & Cognition, 8, 225-259.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 2#EEG and synchronisation
*Contributors: please include full data in the references section for
all references in the text.*
```{=html}
<div class="noprint">
```
Home
```{=html}
</div>
```
## Perceptual \"filling in\"
Perceptual \"filling in\" occurs when visual properties such as
textures, colours, brightness or motion are extended in the visual field
to areas where they do not have corresponding events in the world.
The filling in of the blind spot by the properties of the field in the
contralateral eye has already been discussed. The part of the visual
field represented by the blind spot is also \"filled in\" in the case of
monocular vision.
![](Constudblindill.png "Constudblindill.png")
Shut the right eye and focus on the pink cross with the left eye, if the
head is moved towards the pink cross there is a point at which the
yellow disk disappears but the white lines are still present. In this
\"filling in\" the visual field does not appear to be distorted.
Fiorani *et al.* (1992) developed a technique for probing the cortical
blind spot using vertical and horizontal bar stimuli. Matsumoto &
komatsu (2005) used this technique on macaque monkeys. In the monocular
case they found that as a bar was moved across the visual field so that
it crossed the blind spot there was a sudden change in neural activity
in the deep layers of the neurons in the blind spot area of V1. When the
bar was moved across the same part of the visual field of the
contralateral eye the neural activity in the blind spot area increased
steadily as the bar was moved. The authors found that there were neurons
in the deep layers of blind spot cortex that had elongated receptive
fields that could respond to stimuli outside the blind spot and transfer
this activation into the blind spot cortex.
Filling in of a slightly different type occurs in \"scotoma\". In
scotoma an area of the retina is damaged and unresonsive to visual
stimuli, immediately after the damage patients report an area of visual
field that is unresponsive to stimuli. After several months patients
report that the area of field represented by the scotoma contains visual
properties related to the physical world surrounding the area that would
have formed an image on the scotoma. This results in a distortion of the
visual field. (see for instance Gilbert(1993)). Direct measurements of
activity in cortical area V1 show that the neurons that represented the
area of the scotoma become sensitive to activity in the surrounding
visual field. At the cortical level the scotoma is literally \"filled
in\".
There are many stimuli that cause \"filling in\". These stimuli are
known as \"illusions\" because they produce phenomenal experience that
has no correlate in the world outside the body. In the \"neon colour
spreading illusion\" a lightly coloured circle appears where there
should be a white background. Sasaki and Watanabe (2004) used fMRI to
show that the part of the topographic map in cortical area V1
corresponding to the light coloured circle was activated.
![](Constudneon.jpg "Constudneon.jpg")
Fiorani, M., Rosa, M.G.P., Gattas, R. & Rocha-Miranda, C.E. (1992).
Dynamic surrounds of receptive fields in primate striate cortex: a
physiological basis for perceptual completion? Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
89, 8547-8551. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/abstract/89/18/8547>
Gilbert, C.D. (1993). Circuitry, architecture and functional dynamics of
visual cortex.
Matsumoto, M & Komatsu, H. (2005). Neural responses in the macaque V1 to
bar stimuli with various lengths presented on the blind spot. J
neurophysiol. 93. 2374-2387.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/abstract/93/5/2374>
Sasaki, Y & Watanabe, T. The primary visual cortex fills in colour.
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 101, 18251-18256. (2004).
## Binocular Rivalry, Pattern Rivalry and Binocular Fusion
Sir Charles Wheatstone (1838) was the first scientist to systematically
investigate binocular rivalry. Binocular rivalry occurs when different
images are presented to the left and right eyes. The subject sees
successively one image, a combined image and then the other image. The
swapping of images can take a second or more. Binocular rivalry is of
interest in consciousness research because the parts of the brain that
contain the dominant image should also be those parts that are
contributing to conscious experience. Binocular rivalry involves at
least two components; the first switches from one image to a merged
image and then to the other image and the second permits the view to be
part of conscious experience.
![](Constudrival.png "Constudrival.png")
The switching of one image for another may involve selecting one of the
images as the percept or selecting one of the eyes. Blake *et al.*
(1979) performed an experiment in which subjects could change the image
at a given eye by pressing a button. When a particular image became
dominant they pressed a button to change the image at the eye receiving
the dominant image for the non-dominant image. They found that the
subjects immediately experienced the second image as the dominant image.
This suggests that binocular rivalry is selecting between eyes rather
than images. Lehky in 1988 proposed that the switching may be occurring
as a result of feedback between visual cortical area V1 and the Lateral
Geniculate Nucleus (a thalamic relay - see Carandini *et al.* 2002) and
Blake in 1989 also proposed that the switching occurred at the level of
area V1. (Visual cortical area V1 receives visual input direct from the
LGN.)
Tong (2001) has argued that, in humans, the switching of images in
binocular rivalry may occur at the earliest levels in the visual cortex.
In particular, Tong and Engel (2001) used an elegant technique measuring
the activity in the visual cortex that represents the blind spot of the
eye to show that almost complete switching to the dominant image occurs
at the level of visual cortical area V1. In support of this idea of
switching at the level of V1 or even before the cortex, Kreimann *et
al.* (2001, 2002) used direct electrode recordings in human cortex and
found that the activity of most neurons changed with the percept. Other
experiments have not shown a single locus in the brain where the
suppressed sensory information gets switched out (Blake & Logothetis
2002, Leopold & Logothetis 1996, Gail et al., 2004).
Functional MRI has also shown cortical activity outside of sensory
visual cortex related to both images in binocular rivalry. Lumer *et
al.* (1998) found that only the fronto-parietal areas of cortex switched
with the percept, Fang & He (2005) found that activity relating to both
suppressed and unsuppressed images were present in the dorsal stream of
the visual system. Wunderlich *et al.* (2005) and Haynes *et al.* (2005)
have both found suppression at the level of the lateral geniculate
nucleus using fMRI in humans.
Pasley *et al.* (2004) have shown that, even during suppression, fearful
faces can produce activity in the amygdala (see Pessoa (2005) for a
review).
Rivalry alternations seem to be the result of widespread activity
changes that cover large parts of the brain, including but not
necessarily originating at the earliest sensory stages of visual
processing. Most investigators have found that, once switching has
occurred, there are areas of the brain that contain activity that is
solely related to the percept but this varies from most of the cortex to
largely more frontal regions depending upon the study. The most likely
explanation for binocular rivalry is that the switching occurs at the
level of the LGN as a result of feedback from the cortex.
Pattern Rivalry is also of interest in consciousness research for the
same reasons as binocular rivalry. In pattern rivalry a figure may have
two or more forms that replace each other. Typical examples of such
figures are the Necker cube and Rubin\'s face-vase. The similarity of
the time course of the switching between percepts in binocular rivalry
and pattern rivalry has led many authors to suggest that these involve
the same mechanism. Logothetis *et al.* (1996) used novel dichoptic
stimuli (different images to each eyes) to produce a form of rivalry
that seems to involve switching at levels in the cerebral cortex that
are more distal to the sensory stimulus than V1. Leopold and Logothetis
(1999), on the basis of their work with monkeys, state that \"..many
neurons throughout the visual system, both monocular and binocular,
continue to respond to a stimulus even when it is perceptually
suppressed.\". Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998) investigated pattern rivalry
with MRI and found activity in higher order visual areas during change
of dominant pattern. Pettigrew (2001) also describes effects on rivalry
due to thought and mood that may require involvement of large areas of
cortex in the switching operation and stresses the way that V1
represents different visual fields in different hemispheres of the brain
so that inter-hemispheric switching must also be considered.
It seems likely that the change of dominant pattern or percept is
associated with higher level cortical activity but once the dominant
percept is established many of the visually responsive neurons in the
cortex are switched over to the new percept. This might account for the
similarities in timing of binocular and pattern rivalry and the
disparate results found by the various groups of authors. In the words
of Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998):
\"The transient activity fluctuations we found suggest that perceptual
metastability elicited by ambiguous stimuli is associated with rapid
redistributions of neural activity between separate specialized cortical
and subcortical structures.\"
Which permits both the idea of selecting particular eyes or percepts,
perhaps by feedback that switches a thalamic relay on the basis of
cortical processing of patterns. Once the cortex has switched the
thalamic relay most of the neurons in V1 would become exposed to the
dominant percept but there would still be a few neurons in the cortical
visual system receiving data from the non dominant image.
The investigations of binocular and pattern rivalry provide evidence
that conscious visual experience is probably distal to V1 (i.e.: cortex
or thalamus).
Perceptual rivalry may be part of complex decision making rather than
being simply a switch to blank out unwelcome input. It is clear from the
Rubin face-vase that pattern rivalry is linked to recognition and would
involve a complex delineation of forms within cortical processing. This
would suggest that many areas of cortex should be involved before a
particular percept is made dominant. Pettigrew (2001) argues that
rivalry is the result of a complex phenomenon rather than being simply a
switching event. Pettigrew\'s discovery that laughter abolishes rivalry
also points to a complex cortical system for switching percepts.
Pettigrew proposes that complex cortical processes control rivalry and
that the actual switching of percepts is performed sub-cortically in the
Ventral Tegmental Area. He concludes his review of the problem by noting
that \"Rivalry may thus reflect fundamental aspects of perceptual
decision making..\" Pettigrew (2001).
Another effect, known as \"binocular fusion\", provides further
compelling evidence for the non-conscious nature of the cerebral cortex.
In binocular fusion images from both eyes are fused together to create a
single image in experience. Moutoussis and Zeki (2002) used a form of
binocular fusion in which images of faces were flashed at 100ms
intervals to both eyes simultaneously. When both eyes received images of
the same colour the subject could see the faces but when one eye
received a green image on a red background and the other a red image on
a green background the subjects reported seeing a uniform yellow field
that contained no faces.
fMRI scans of the subject\'s brains showed that when both eyes were
exposed to images of the same colour the part of the brain that deals
with faces was active and when each eye received images of different
colours the same areas of brain showed activity. In other words the
cortex contained strong activity related to faces whether or not faces
were experienced. Moutoussis and Zeki found a similar effect when they
used images of houses instead of images of faces. The authors concluded
that: \"The present study further suggests that there are no separate
processing and perceptual areas but rather that the same cortical
regions are involved in both the processing and, when certain levels of
activation are reached and probably in combination with the activation
of other areas as well, the generation of a conscious visual percept\".
This conclusion does not seem to be supported by the data. There is no
evidence that any area of cortex contains the percept itself. The
experiment shows that the cortex contains data relating to both red and
green faces which suggests that the cortex is not the site of the
conscious percept. The percept is most likely distal to the cortex
perhaps in the thalamus or some other area that receives cortical
sensory output.
It is interesting that Fries *et al.* (1997) found that neurons that
were activated by the dominant image in binocular rivalry fired
synchronously whereas those that were activated by the non-dominant
image did not. Thalamocorticothalamic oscillations are the most likely
source for synchronising neurons over whole areas of cortex, suggesting
that the conscious percept is located in the thalamus rather than the
cortex.
## Synchronisation of Neural Processes
Our experience seems to contain entities with their attributes attached
to them at the correct places in space and time. When a dog barks we see
its jaws open at the same time as the bark and both jaws and bark are at
the same location. We take this for granted but the brain must be
engaging in some complex processing to achieve this synchronised and
appropriately positioned set of objects and events. The illustration
below shows the two basic processes that might be used to synchronise
events between the different specialised processors in the cerebral
cortex and brain in general.
![](Constudsynch.gif "Constudsynch.gif")
In the first option a complete model of sensation, dream etc. may be
created and then allowed to become part of conscious experience. In the
second model events are released into experience as fast as possible but
are synchronous when recalled, having been synchronised in a storage
buffer. There is a third option in which there is no synchronisation of
events so that the output from different processors would occur at
different times.
The \'experience buffer\' would be a volume of brain in which a
succession of events could be recorded. The buffer might either be
updated in steps, the previous content being discarded, or continuously
updated with the oldest content being lost continuously.
In the first option events from different processes would always appear
to be simultaneous unless the experience buffer were updated as a series
of steps in which case any changes at around the moment of updating
might appear in successive buffers. For instance, if change of position
were processed before change in colour a circle on a screen that changed
from green to red at the start of a motion might seem to be briefly
green during the motion and then turn red.
In the second model events from different processors might appear
asynchronous at the moment of experience but synchronous when recalled.
Colour vision and motion vision are processed in different parts of the
visual cortex and in distinct parts of visual cortical areas V1 and V2.
They are different processes and hence ideal for studying the
synchronisation of cortical activity. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997)
presented subjects with moving coloured squares on a computer screen
that changed from red to green or vice versa as they changed direction
of movement. It was found that subjects seemed to perceive changes in
colour some 70-80 msecs before they perceived a change in the direction
of motion of the squares. Further work by Arnold *et al.* (2001) and
Arnold and Clifford (2001) have confirmed that colour changes seem to be
perceived before motion. Arnold and Clifford (2001) also found a
quantitative relationship between the colour/motion asynchrony and the
direction of change of motion, complete reversals of direction giving
rise to the greatest asynchrony between the detection of colour and
motion changes.
Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) conclude by stating that the asynchrony of
neural processes shows that \"..the perception of each attribute is
solely the result of the activity in the specialised system involved in
its processing..\". It seems more likely that the experiments simply
show that slow neural processes are not synchronised before they become
percepts (the third option above). The experiments are excellent
evidence for the concept of the cortex as a set of specialised
processors that deliver their output asynchronously to some other place
where the output becomes a percept.
These experiments on colour and motion suggest that there is no
synchronisation between the processes that deal with these two aspects
of vision. Another set of experiments by Clifford *et al.* (2003)
supports this idea of processing being asynchronous. They asked subjects
to perform a variety of judgements of when visual events occurred and
found that the degree of synchrony of one visual event with another
depends on the type of judgement. Different judgements probably use
processors in different areas of cortex and the output from these
arrives asynchronously at the part of the brain that supports the
percept.
When the percept is formed there must be feedback to the cortical
processes that create its content. Otherwise it would not be possible to
report about the percept and the cortex would be unable to direct
processing to the percept in preference to other, non-conscious cortical
data.
Although slow processes (20 milliseconds to 1 second) do not seem to be
synchronised there is some evidence for very rapid synchronisation.
Andrews *et al.* (1996) revisited a problem raised by the famous
physiologist Charles Sherrington. Sherrington considered the phenomenon
of \'flicker fusion\' in which a flickering light appears to be a
continuous steady light if it flashes on and off at frequencies of about
45 Hz or higher. He reasoned that if the images from both eyes are
brought together to form a single image then the frequency at which a
flickering light appears to be steady should depend on whether one or
two eyes are used. Flicker fusion should occur if each eye receives
alternate flashes at only half the normal flicker fusion frequency. The
flicker should disappear if the left eye receives flashes at 23 pulses
per second and the right eye receives alternate flashes at 23 pulses per
second. When Sherrington performed the experiment he found that this was
not the case, using approximate figures, each eye required 46 pulses per
second for fusion to occur. Sherrington proposed that the flicker fusion
in alternate binocular presentation was occurring \"psychically\",
outside of normal physiological processes.
Andrews *et al.* duplicated Sherrington\'s result but investigated it
further. They found that when lights were flashed in each eye
alternately at low frequences (2 Hz) the experience was the same as a
light being flashed in both eyes at this rate. At frequencies of four Hz
and higher the subjects began to report that the lights being flashed
alternately in both eyes seemed to flicker at the same rate as lights
being flashed in both eyes at half the frequency. It seemed as if a
flash in one eye followed by a flash in the other eye was being
perceived as a single flash or \"conflated\" as the authors put it. The
authors explained this effect by suggesting that the brain activity
corresponding to the flashes was sampled for a short period and any
number of flashes occurring during this period became perceived as a
single flash. The maximum rate of sampling would be about 45 Hz. This
idea is similar to option (1) above, where the buffer is filled and
emptied 40 - 50 times a second.
An experience buffer that is refreshed at 40-50 times a second might
also explain the results obtained with colour and motion asynchrony
because synchronisation between processes may well happen too quickly to
affect processes that occur at very slow rates. Singer and Gray (1995),
Singer (2001) have proposed that synchronisation between neurones at
about 45 Hz is the discriminator between those neurones with activity
that contributes to conscious experience and activity in other neurones.
A rapid refresh rate in a synchronising buffer agrees with the results
found by Fries *et al.* (1997) in which visual cortical neurones that
represent a percept underwent synchronous oscillations in the gamma
frequency range (39--63 Hz). Tononi *et al.* (1998) have also found
synchronisation of neural activity in neurones that represent the
percept.
The gamma frequency oscillations are intrinsic to the cortex but are
triggered by the thalamus and are part of the \'arousal system\'.
Readers should be wary of the term \'arousal system\' because it evokes
the idea of something waking up a conscious cortex. The cortex can be
fully active during sleep and even during pathological unconsciousness
such as persistent vegetative state so it is possible that the arousal
centres themselves or nearby structures actually host phenomenal
consciousness.
## EEG and synchronisation
If electrodes are placed on the scalp varying electrical potentials of a
few tens of microvolts can be recorded between the electrodes.
Recordings of potentials from electrodes on the scalp are known as
electroencephalograms (EEGs).
The potentials recorded in the EEG are due to postsynaptic potentials in
nerve cells. The EEG is insensitive to the activity of single cells and
occurs as a result of relatively slow, **synchronised**, changes in
large areas of cells. The differences in potential between two scalp
electrodes are largely due to depolarisation and hyperpolarisation of
the dendritic trees of cortical pyramidal cells. The folding of the
cortex (gyri) is problematical for recording and interpreting EEGs
because opposing layers of cortex can cancel any net potentials.
The EEG shows rhythmic activity. This is conventionally divided into the
following frequency bands:
Delta waves 0--4 Hz
Theta waves 4--8 Hz
Alpha waves 8--12 Hz
Beta waves \>10 Hz
Gamma waves (also called fast beta) 25--100 Hz
EEGs also contain short bursts of activity called spindles and very fast
oscillations (VFOs). Spindles last for 1--2 seconds and contain rhythmic
activity at 7--14 Hz. They are associated with the onset of sleep. The
VFOs consist of short bursts at frequencies of over 80 Hz.
When the eyes are closed the amplitude of activity from most pairs of
electrodes is increased compared with when the eyes are open. When
subjects are awake the EEG consists mainly of alpha and beta activity
with considerable low amplitude gamma when the eyes are open. In stage 1
sleep the EEG consists of theta waves, in stage 2 sleep of varied
activity and spindles, in stage 4 sleep of delta and during REM sleep of
beta and theta activity. In epileptic seizures there tends to be high
amplitude activity with pronounced synchronisation between many pairs of
electrodes.
The rhythmic electrical activity is due to cortical feedback loops,
cortico-cortical synchronisation, thalamic pacemakers and
thalamo-cortical synchronisation. VFOs have been attributed to the
activity of electrical connections between cells (dendro-dendritic gap
junctions) (Traub (2003)).
The gamma activity, centred on a frequency of 40 Hz appears to be
related to activity in cortical interneurons that form electrical
connections between their dendrites (Tamas *et al.* 2000). These
oscillations can be triggered by high frequency stimulation of the
posterior intralaminar nuclei of the thalamus (Barth and MacDonald 1996,
Sukov and Barth 2001) and as a result of activation of the reticular
system (Munk *et al.* 1996). This suggests that stimulation of cortex by
thalamic sensory relays triggers gamma band activity in the cortex. A
shift from gamma to beta waves can occur in human event related
potentials after about 0.2 secs (Pantev 1995, Traub *et al.* 1999).
The alpha activity is related to thalamic pacemakers, perhaps as a
result of intrinsic oscillatory activity in thalamic sensory relays (see
Roy & Prichep 2005 for a brief review). Theta activity, which occurs
during some cognitive tasks and mental arithmetic involves a loop from
the cortex to the non-specific thalamic nuclei. Delta activity seems to
be endogenous to cortex when input is suppressed during sleep. Beta
activity is due to cortico-cortical interactions, often after a brief
period of gamma activation. It should be noted that gamma and beta
activity can be expressed as impulses in cortico-thalamic pathways and
that when cortical and thalamic activity is correlated there is a
conscious state. In other words gamma or beta waves in the cortex are
not correlates of consciousness on their own - see for instance Laureys
*et al.* (2002).
## Event related potentials
After a sudden event there are a characteristic set of changes in EEG
activity known as **event related potentials** or ERPs. The time course
of the ERP is shown in the diagram below.
![](Constudevent.png "Constudevent.png")
ERPs occur in response to novel stimuli and are also produced by brief
transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS)(Iramina *et al.* 2002). The slow
component is known as the P3 or P300 phase of the ERP. It is due to
activation of areas of the brain that are relatively remote from the
primary sensory areas of brain.
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) have reviewed the origin of the P300 ERP:
\"To summarize, convergent evidence suggests that P3-like activity can
be recorded in several, widely separated brain areas. These include some
medial temporal and subcortical structures (e.g., the hippocampal
formation, amygdala, and thalamus), but these structures are unlikely to
contribute directly to the scalp-recorded P3.\". According to
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) the recorded P300 may be due to
temporo-parietal and prefrontal cortical activity. Linden (2005) has
also concluded that widespread, but specific, cortical activation is
correlated with the recorded P300 ERP.
The generator of the P300 is still obscure. Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005)
consider that the Locus coeruleus, a nucleus in the pons that regulates
task related attention and part of the sleep-wake cycle, may be
responsible. In line with this, Mashour *et al.* (2005) have discovered
that TMS induced P300 activity is reduced in unconscious states.
Whether the P300 is related to Libet\'s 0.5 second delay is still
obscure but the discovery that the P300 occurs in association with
subliminal stimuli (stimuli that do not enter awareness)(Bernat *et al.*
2001) suggests that it is associated with non-conscious cortical
processing. Williams *et al.* (2004), in an investigation of subliminal
and supraliminal fear perception, found that \"conscious fear perception
was distinguished by a more prominent N4, peaking around 400 msec\"; the
N4 component follows the P300 component in the succession of phases of
the ERP. Williams *et al.* considered that the earlier phases in the ERP
are probably related to non-conscious processing. In contrast Vogel *et
al.* (1998) found that suppression of the P300 was associated with
suppression of awareness.
## The integration delay
Psychological experiments often involve binary decisions where subjects
give one of two outputs in response to stimuli. It is found that if the
stimuli are made increasingly noisy or complex the response time tends
to increase. Psychophyicists have developed various mathematical models
to explain the increased response times due to noise such as the
Integrator and Accumulator models (cf: Luce(1986)). These models have
been fairly successful when explaining experiments such as judging the
net direction of movement of sets of dots on a screen when the dots are
given semi-random paths and different brightness etc. In these
circumstances it can take up to 2 seconds for an accurate decision.
There are many tasks however where the accuracy of decision making does
not improve after about 300 milliseconds. The accuracy of the
performance of rats when choosing between two alternatives when reacting
to odours peaks at about 300 ms (Uchida and Mainen(2003), Abraham *et
al.* (2004)). The accuracy of humans when performing vernier acuity
tasks, line detection, contrast sensitivity, motion velocity
discrimination and stereoscopic depth discrimination seems to peak at
300ms (Uchida *et al.* 2006).
Uchida, Kepecs and Mainen (2006) suggest that \"rapid and short
integration time is a sensible strategy for rapid processing of
low-level sensory information in order to form more complex sensory
images, both in vision and olfaction.\" Whether these authors regard
these derived sensory images as the content of consciousness is not
mentioned. The authors propose that the 300ms optimal integration time
may be partly due to the mechanics of sniffing (a sniff takes about
125-200ms) and the nature of optical fixation (inter-saccade intervals
are typically 200-400 ms ). The authors note that the animal or human
could, in principle, choose to integrate over longer intervals but if it
is moving this may not lead to information that is current for changed
circumstances.
An optimal processing time of about 300 ms would be consistent with the
delays observed before conscious awareness occurs in response to a
stimulus - an interval required to form \"more complex sensory images\".
## Global Workspace Theory
Global Workspace Theory is the idea that somewhere in the brain there is
a facility that integrates the processes that occur in the various
separate areas of the brain. The theory was first proposed by Descartes
as the *sensus communis*, the common sense, but the modern form of the
theory dispenses with the idea of a point soul looking at the brain. In
modern Global Workspace theory it is proposed that an area of brain
receives input from most of the cerebral cortex and broadcasts its
outputs to all of the unconscious modular information processors in the
brain.
Modern Global Workspace Theory has been championed by Baars (1983,
1988).
There is increasing evidence for a Global Workspace or Global Workspaces
in the brain. Much of this evidence comes from fMRI, single unit and
magnetoencephalography studies in which it is shown that non-conscious
or subliminal processing mainly occupies primary, sensory cortex whereas
conscious processing occupies large areas of cerebral cortex.
In binocular rivalry the stimulus that is consciously perceived is
responsible for relatively intense activation of large areas of brain
whereas the non-conscious stimulus is often suppressed (see above and
Sheinberg & Logothetis (1997), Tononi *et al.* (1998)). The suppression
is likely to occur in the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei which suggests a
role for the Thalamic Reticular Nuclei, which modulate LGN activity, in
the control of the percept.
### Masking and visual awareness
Word masking has also been used to investigate the idea of a Global
Workspace. When a word is presented on its own for a few tens of
milliseconds it remains readable but if it is immediately succeeded by,
or accompanied by, another word it becomes indistinct or invisible. This
effect is known as \"word masking\". Vogel *et al.* (1998) have
investigated a version of word masking known as the \"attentional
blink\". They found that when stimuli became invisible the P3 component
of the Event Related Potential, which peaks at around 300-500 millisecs
after a stimulus, was completely suppressed. The P3 component of the ERP
has been related to the lodging of data in working memory and also to
gamma band activity in the EEG. This strongly suggests the involvement
of a cortico-thalamic loop in the \"attentional blink\". The delay of
0.3 to 0.5 secs is typical of the time required for conscious awareness
(see above).
Word masking in conjunction with fMRI and Event Related Potential (ERP)
recordings has been used by Dehaene *et al.* (2001) to expose control by
a central mechanism. It was found that masked words activate mainly the
visual cortex and ventral stream (inferior temporal lobe) whereas
visible words also activated distant parietal, prefrontal and cingulate
sites.
Dehaene *et al.* (2003) and found that the dynamics of the loss of
visibility of words in an attentional blink experiment could be modelled
by a simulated cortico-thalamic loop. In their simulation a distributed
cortical process determined which events would receive attention and the
system used the thalamic gating systems to exclude those that did not
receive attention.
Tse *et al.* (2005) have used purely visual stimuli in masking
experiments and concluded that, in the case of purely visual stimuli,
the neural correlates of awareness were limited to the occipital cortex:
\"We suggest that there are both lower and upper bounds within the
visual hierarchy for the processing of visual masking and the
maintenance of visual awareness of simple unattended targets; the lower
bound is at least as high as the border between V2 and V3, and the upper
bound is within the occipital lobe, possibly somewhere downstream of
V4.\"
This discovery would mean that activation of large areas of cortex are
unnecessary for awareness.
Melloni *et al.* (2007) compared compared the electrophysiological
responses related to the processing of visible and invisible words in a
delayed matching to sample task. Both perceived and nonperceived words
caused a similar increase of local (gamma) oscillations in the EEG, but
only perceived words induced a transient long-distance synchronization
of gamma oscillations across widely separated regions of the brain.
After this transient period of temporal coordination, the electrographic
signatures of conscious and unconscious processes continue to diverge.
Only words reported as perceivedinduced (1) enhanced theta oscillations
over frontal regions during the maintenance interval, (2) an increase of
the P300 component of the event-related potential, and (3) an increase
in power and phase synchrony of gamma oscillationsbefore the anticipated
presentation of the test word. We propose that the critical process
mediating the access to conscious perception is the earlytransient
global increase of phase synchrony of oscillatory activity in the
gammafrequency.
Melloni L, Molina C, Pena M, Torres D, Singer W, Rodriguez E. (2007).
Synchronization of neural activity across cortical areas correlates
withconscious perception.J Neurosci. 2007 Mar 14;27(11):2858-65.
### Attention and the global workspace
Baars (2002) in his review of evidence for the Global Workspace Theory
quotes many other experiments that show activation of larger areas of
cortex in response to conscious stimuli compared with unconscious or
subliminal stimuli.The effect is also seen in change blindness, learning
and attention. Newman and Baars (1993) consider that the \"workspace\"
is fairly global in the brain:
\"This Neural Global Workspace (NGW) model views conscious processes in
terms of a globally integrative brain system. The neural circuitry
contributing to this system is not only widely distributed across the
neocortex, but includes key corticothalamic and midbrain circuits as
well. These cortico-subcortical circuits are hypothesized to be critical
to understanding the mechanisms of attentional control that provide an
essential basis for the conscious processing of information\".
However they focus particularly on the role of the thalamic Reticular
Nucleus and cortico-thalamic connectivity in the control of attention.
Other ideas for the location of the Global Workspace are the idea of
Singer et al. that gamma synchrony controls access to the content of
consciousness and Llinas et al. (1998) that the thalamus is the hub
through which communication occurs between areas of cortex.
One of the problems with Global Workspace theory is that it suggests
that attention, working memory, cognitive control and consciousness may
all be in the same area of the brain. It is likely that the mechanisms
of attention, working memory, and cognitive control may involve several,
interlinked systems perhaps co-opting the basal ganglia in the process.
In view of this Maia and Cleeremans (2005) propose that \".. attention,
working memory, cognitive control and consciousness are not distinct
functions implemented by separate brain systems. Attempting to find
separate neural correlates for each may therefore be the wrong approach.
Instead, we suggest that they should be understood in terms of the
dynamics of global competition, with biasing from PFC (prefrontal
cortex).\". The inclusion by Maia and Cleeremans of consciousness with
distributed attention, working memory and cognitive control is
reminiscent of Zeki & Bartel\'s idea of microconsciousness.
It should be noted that, in common with Libet\'s data, the percept seems
to be available to phenomenal consciousness some 0.3 to 0.5 secs after a
stimulus; this suggests that whatever determines the content of
phenomenal consciousness operates before events become part of
phenomenal consciousness. This relegates phenomenal consciousness from
being a controller of attention to being the recipient of content that
is the subject of attention. This finding is consistent with the
philosophical problem of the **apparently** epiphenomenal nature of
phenomenal consciousness.
Given the data on the timing of conscious awareness it seems that there
may be two \"workspaces\", an active workspace that models the world,
discarding and suppressing data during rivalry, and a passive workspace
that receives the final, edited product. The active workspace would
correlate with the cortical systems stressed by Dehaene *et al.* and
Maia and Cleermans although, given the results of Tse et al., the
workspace would be limited to small zones of cortex. The loading of the
passive workspace with the output of the active workspace would
correlate with thalamo-cortical activity during component P3 of the ERP
in which data is transferred from the cortex to the thalamus. This
workspace might constitute the source for reports of the content of
phenomenal consciousness.
Llinas *et al.* (1998) have proposed two parallel cortico-thalamic
attentional systems, one of which is related to the thalamic specific
nuclei and the other to the thalamic non-specific nuclei, especially the
ILN. The non-specific system would be related to consciousness itself.
## The \"cognitive map\" and the neural basis of perceptual space
Our bodies appear to be mobile within a constant space. We walk around a
room; the room does not rotate around us. The constancy of the location
of things gives us the feeling that we are directly viewing a constant
world. But how does the brain provide a constant world rather than a
world that rotates with the movement of the sense organs? Why is our
view of the world when we move our eyes so different from the disturbing
flow of images that occur when a video camera is waved around? Do our
brains contain a constant \"cognitive map\" (O\'Keefe and Nadel 1978) of
our surroundings?
Mittelstaedt & Mittelstaedt (1980, 1982) discovered that female gerbils
were able to recover their pups in darkened surroundings by searching in
a semi random fashion on the outbound journey and then proceeding
directly back to the nest on the inbound journey. The direct journey
back to the nest seemed to be due to an integration of the various
directions taken on the outward journey (**path integration**). If the
equipment being explored by the mother gerbil was rotated very slowly
the mother would make an error equivalent to the amount of rotation.
More rapid rotations that activated the vestibular system of the rat
(acceleration measurement) did not cause errors in navigation. This
demonstration that rodents could navigate accurately on the basis of
**idiothetic** cues (cues that are due to internal senses) led to
research on the neural basis of the navigation.
As early as 1971 O\'Keefe and Dostrovsky had discovered that there are
particular cells in the hippocampus that fire according to the position
of an animal in the environment. This has been complimented by research
that showed that changes in visual cues within the environment caused
changes in the firing rate of place cells in hippocampal area CA3 (.
![](Gray717.png "Gray717.png")
![](HippocampalRegions.jpg "HippocampalRegions.jpg")
!Entorhinal cortex approximately maps to areas 28 and
34{width="500"}
F. P. Battaglia and A. Treves. 1998 Attractor neural networks storing
multiple space representations: A model for hippocampal place fields.
PHYSICAL REVIEW E DECEMBER 1998 VOLUME 58, NUMBER 6
<http://www.sissa.it/~ale/Bat+98b.pdf>
Leutgeb, S., Leutgeb, J.K., Moser, M-B, and Moser, E.I. 2005. Place
cells, spatial maps and the population code for memory. Current Opinion
in Neurobiology 2005, 15:738--746.
<http://instruct1.cit.cornell.edu/courses/bionb720nejc/reprints/LeutgebEtAl2005.pdf>
Mittelstaedt, H. & Mittelstaedt, M-L. 1982. Avian Navigation. (ed. Papi,
F. & Wallraff, H.) 290-297. Springer, Berlin.
Mittelstaedt, M-L & Glasauer, S. 1991. Idiothetic Navigation in Gerbils
and Humans. Zool. Jb. Physiol. 95 (1991), 427-435
<http://web.archive.org/web/20110125132449/http://www.nefo.med.uni-muenchen.de/~sglasauer/MittelstaedtGlasauer1991.pdf>
O\'Keefe, J. & Dostrovsky, J. (1971). The hippocampus as a spatial map:
preliminary evidence from unit activity in the freely moving rat. Brain
Res. 34, 171-175.
O\'Keefe, J. & Nadel, L. (1978). The Hippocampus as a cognitive map.
(Oxford)
## Bibliography
Defining the States of Consciousness. Tassi, P., Muzet, A. (2001)
Neuroscience and Behavioural Reviews 25(2001) 175-191.
Neuroanatomy: \"Digital Slice of Life\" by Stensaas and Millhouse
<http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/subj2.html>
See also: <http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/index.html>
EEG\'s: Coles, M.G.H., Rugg, M.D. Event Related Brain Potentials: An
Introduction.
<http://whalen.psych.udel.edu/667/1.What_is_ERP/ColesRugg1995chpt1.pdf>
Visual System: Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual
Awareness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
Professor Bogen\'s Consciousness Page
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/toccons.htm>
Demonstrations of Auditory Illusions and Tricks. Yoshitaka Nakajima
<http://www.kyushu-id.ac.jp/~ynhome/ENG/Demo/illusions2nd.html>
## References
- Abraham, N.M. (2004) Maintaining accuracy at the expense of speed:
stimulus similarity defines odor discrimination time in mice. Neuron
44, 865-876.
- Aleman, A., Ramsey, N., Van Honk, J.E., Kessels, R.P.C., Hoogduin,
J., Schutter, D.L.G., Postma, A., Kahn, R.S., De Haan, E.H.F.
(submitted). Parietal cortex mediates visuospatial imagery: evidence
from fMRI and rTMS.
<http://igitur-archive.library.uu.nl/dissertations/1954455/c10.pdf>
- Alkire, M.T., Haier, R.J., Fallon, J.H., and Barker, S.J.(1996). PET
imaging of conscious and unconscious verbal memory. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, 3 ( 5-6) 1996 , pp. 448--462
<http://www.imprint.co.uk/jcs_3_5-6.html>
- Anderson, J. & Anderson, B. (1993). \"The Myth of Persistence of
Vision Revisited,\" Journal of Film and Video, Vol. 45, No. 1
(Spring 1993): 3-12.
<http://www.uca.edu/org/ccsmi/ccsmi/classicwork/Myth%20Revisited.htm>
- Andrews, T.J., White, L.E., Binder, D. & Purves, D. (1996). Temporal
events in cyclopean vision. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 93,
pp. 3689--3692, April 1996. Neurobiology.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030510095149/http://www.dur.ac.uk/tim.andrews/PNAS_93_3689.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G. (2001) Determinants of asynchronous
processing in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London,
Series B: Biological Sciences, 269, 579 - 583.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031205165920/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/AC02.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G, Wenderoth, P. (2001). Asynchronous
processing in vision: Color leads motion. Current Biology, 11,
596 - 600.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030617120017/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/ACW01.pdf>
- Austin, G.M. & Grant, F.C. (1958). Physiologic observations
following total hemispherectomy in man. Surgery 38, 239-258.
- Baars, B.J. (1983) Conscious contents provide the nervous system
with coherent, global information. In Consciousness and
Self-Regulation (Vol 3). Davidson, R.J. et al., editors. Plenum
Press.
- Baars, B.J. (1988) A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness, Cambridge
University Press.
- Baars, B., Newman, J., & Taylor, J. (1998) Neuronal mechanisms of
consciousness: A Relational Global Workspace framework., in
Hameroff, Stuart and Kaszniak, Al and Laukes, James, Eds. Toward a
Science of Consciousness II: The second Tucson discussions and
debates., chapter 24, pages 269-278. MIT Press.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000946/>
- Baars, B.J. (2002) The conscious access hypothesis: origins and
recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. Vol 6, No 1,
47-52. 2002. <http://www.cs.memphis.edu/~wrcm/BaarsTICS2002.pdf>
- Barth, D. S. and MacDonald, K. D. (1996) Thalamic modulation of
high-frequency oscillating potentials in auditory cortex. Nature.
383, 78-81.
- Bernat E, Shevrin H, Snodgrass M. (2001). Subliminal visual oddball
stimuli evoke a P300 component. Clin Neurophysiol. 2001
Jan;112(1):159-71.
- Blake, R., Westendorf, D. and Overton, R. (1979) What is suppressed
during binocular rivalry? Perception 9: 223-231.
- Blake, R. and Lee, S.-H. (1999). Rival ideas about binocular
rivalry. Vision Research. 39: 1447-1454
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/faculty/blake/PDFs/Lee_Blake_99VR.pdf>
- Blankenburg, F., Ruff, C.C., Deichmann, R., Rees, G. and
Driver, J. (2006) The cutaneous rabbit illusion affects human
primary sensory cortex somatotopically, PLoS Biol 2006;4(3):e69.
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness: I. An
overview. Consciousness and Cognition, 4, 52-62.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/bogen-95.pdf>
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness:
Part II. Constraining the semantic problem. Consciousness and
Cognition, 4, 137-158.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/concog95.htm>
- Bregman, A.S. (1990). Auditory scene analysis: The perceptual
organization of sound. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Budka, H. (1998). Fatal Familial Insomnia Around the World. Brain
Pathology, 8: 553-570.
<http://brainpath.medsch.ucla.edu/pdfs/0803pdf/budka.pdf>
- Carandini M, Heeger DJ, & Senn W, (2002). A synaptic explanation of
suppression in visual cortex, Journal of Neuroscience,
22:10053-10065, 2002.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031031214953/http://www.cns.nyu.edu/~david/ftp/reprints/Carandini-JNeurosci2002.pdf>
- Cariani, P. (2000). Anesthesia, Neural Information Processing, And
Conscious Awareness. Consciousness And Cognition Vol. 9, No. 3,
September 2000 p. 387-395
- Castro-Alamancos, M.A., Connors, B.W. (1997). Thalamo-cortical
synapses. Progress in Neurobiology, Vol.51, pp. 581 to 606, 1997
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051025163047/http://neurobio.drexel.edu/castroweb/progneurobio1.pdf>
- Christmann, C. & Leuthold, H. (2004). The Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Section A. Volume 57, Number 2 /
February 2004. 357-381.
- Claus, R. & Nel, W. (2006). Drug induced arousal from the permanent
vegetative state. NeuroRehabilitation. 2006;21(1):23-8.
- Clifford, C.W.G., Arnold, D.H., Pearson, J. (2003). A paradox of
temporal perception revealed by a stimulus oscillating in colour and
orientation. Vision Research 43 (2003) 2245-2253.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031102125210/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/CAP03.pdf>
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of
consciousness Seminars in the Neurosciences (1990) 2, 263-275
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1998). Consciousness and Neuroscience.
Cerebral Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
- Culham, J.C., Dukelow, S.P., Vilis, T., Hassard, F.A., Gati, J.S.,
Menon, R.S. and Goodale, M.A. (1999). Recovery of fMRI Activation in
Motion Area MT Following Storage of the Motion Aftereffect. The
Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 81 No. 1 January 1999, pp. 388--393.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/81/1/388>
- Deecke, L. (1996) Planning, preparation, execution, and imagery of
volitional action, (Introduction / Editorial) in: L. Deecke W.
Lang, A. Berthoz (Eds) Mental Representations of Motor Acts.
Cognitive Brain Res 3 / Special Issue (2) 59-64.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000015/00/COGBRAIN.html>
- Dehaene, S., Sergent, C., and Changeux, J. (2003) A neuronal network
model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data
during conscious perception. PNAS July 8, 2003 vol. 100 no. 14
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/DehaeneSergentChangeux_BlinkModel_PNAS2003.pdf>
- Dehaene, S. et al. (2001) Cerebral mechanisms of word masking and
unconscious repetition priming. Nat. Neurosci, 4, 752-758.
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/Dehaene_MaskedWords_NatureNeuroscience2001.pdf>
- Dennett, D. and Kinsbourne, M. (1992) Time and the Observer: the
Where and When of Consciousness in the Brain. (1992) Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 15, 183-247, 1992. Reprinted in The Philosopher\'s
Annual, Grim, Mar and Williams, eds., vol. XV-1992, 1994,
pp. 23--68; Noel Sheehy and Tony Chapman, eds., Cognitive Science,
Vol. I, Elgar, 1995,
pp. 210--274.http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/time&obs.htm
- Destexhe, A. (2000). Modelling corticothalamic feedback and the
gating of the thalamus by the cerebral cortex. J. Physiol (Paris),
94 (2000) 391-410. <http://cns.iaf.cnrs-gif.fr/files/Brem2000.pdf>
- Fang, F. & He, S. (2005).Cortical responses to invisible objects in
the human dorsal and ventral pathways. Nat Neurosci. 2005
Oct;8(10):1380-5. Epub 2005 Sep 4.
- Ffytche, D. H., Howard, R. J., Brammer, M. J., David, A., Woodruff,
P., & Williams, S. (1998). The anatomy of conscious vision: an fMRI
study of visual hallucinations. Nature Neuroscience, 1, 738--742.
- Fiset, P., Paus, T., Daloze, T., Plourde, G., Meuret, P., Bonhomme,
V., Hajj-Ali, N., Backman, S.B., and Evans, A.C. (1999). Brain
Mechanisms of Propofol-Induced Loss of Consciousness in Humans: a
Positron Emission Tomographic Study. The Journal of Neuroscience,
July 1, 1999, 19(13):5506-5513.
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/13/5506>
- Fu, C.H.Y., Morgan, K., Suckling, J., Williams, S.C.R., Andrew, C.,
Vythelingum, G.N., McGuire, P.K. (2002). A Functional Magnetic
Resonance Imaging Study of Overt Letter Verbal Fluency Using a
Clustered Acquisition Sequence: Greater Anterior Cingulate
Activation with Increased Task Demand. NeuroImage 17, 871-
879 (2002)
<http://www-bmu.psychiatry.cam.ac.uk/PUBLICATION_STORE/fu02fun.pdf>
- Ganis, G., Thomson, W.L. and Kosslyn, S.M. (2004). Brain areas
underlying visual mental imagery and visual perception: an fMRI
study. Cognitive Brain Research 20 (2004) 226--241
<http://www.wjh.harvard.edu/~kwn/Kosslyn_pdfs/2004Ganis_CogBrainRes20_BrainAreas.pdf>
- Hultin, L. (1997). On Neuromagnetic Assessment of the Contingent
Negative Variation.
<http://www2.lib.chalmers.se/cth/diss/doc/9697/HultinLeif.html>
- Fries, P.. Roelfsema, P.R., Engel, A.K., König, P. and Singer, W.
(1997). Synchronization of oscillatory responses in visual cortex
correlates with perception in interocular rivalry. Proc. Natl. Acad.
Sci. USA, Vol. 94, pp. 12699--12704, November 1997.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/23/12699>
- Fuentealba, P., Crochet, S., Timofeev, I., Bazhenov, M., Sejnowski,
T.J. and Steriade, M. (2004). European Journal of Neuroscience
20(1):111-119. <http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2004/22126/ch03.html>
- Goaillard, J. & Vincent, P. (2002). Serotonin suppresses the slow
afterhyperpolarization in rat intralaminar and midline thalamic
neurones by activating 5-HT7 receptors. Journal of Physiology
(2002), 541.2, pp. 453--465
<http://jp.physoc.org/cgi/content/full/541/2/453>
- Haggard, P. & Eimer, M. (1999) On the relation between brain
potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Exp. Brain Res.
126, 128--133 (1999).
- Haggard, P. (2008) Human volition:towards a neuroscience of will.
Nature Rev Neurosci 9, 934-946
- Haynes, J., Deichmann, R. and Rees, G. (2005). Eye-specific effects
of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate nucleus. Nature
438, 496-499 (24 November 2005)
- Hughes S.W., Blethyn K.L. , Cope D.W. , & Crunelli V. (2003).
Properties and origin of spikelets in thalamocortical neurones in
vitro. Neuroscience. 2002;110(3):395-401
- Iramina, K., Maeno, T., Kowatari, Y. and Ueno, S.. (2002). Effects
of Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation on EEG Activity .IEEE
TRANSACTIONS ON MAGNETICS, VOL. 38, NO. 5, SEPTEMBER 2002
- Ishai, A., Ungerleider, L.G., Haxby, J.V.. (2000) Distributed neural
systems for the generation of visual images. Neuron 28, 979-990.
- Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1980). Mental models in cognitive science.
Cognitive Science, 4, 71-115.
<http://cognitrn.psych.indiana.edu/rgoldsto/cogsci/classics.html>
- Keller, J. & Heckhausen, H. (1990). Readiness potentials preceding
spontaneous motor acts: voluntary vs. involuntary control.
Electroencephalography and Clinical Neuropsychology, 76, 351-361.
- King, C.C. (1991). Fractal and Chaotic Dynamics in Nervous Systems.
Progress in Neurobiology, 36, pp. 279--308, 1991.
<http://citeseer.nj.nec.com/king91fractal.html>
- Klein, S.A (2002). Libet's Temporal Anomalies: A Reassessment of the
Data.
Consciousness and Cognition 11, 198--214 (2002)
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/160.pdf>
- Klein, S. (2002). Libet\'s Timing of Mental Events: Commentary on
the Commentaries. Consciousness and Cognition. 11, 326-333.
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/ccog_2002_0580-Klein-Commentary_on_the_commentaries.pdf>
- Kleinschmidt, A., Bichel, C. Zeki, S. and Frackowiak, R.S.J. (1998).
Human brain activity during spontaneously reversing perception of
ambiguous figures. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 1998 Dec
22;265(1413):2427-33
- Konishi, S., Wheeler, M.E., Donaldson, D.I., Buckner, R.L.. (2000)
Neural correlates of episodic retrieval success. NeuroImage: 12:
276-286.
- Kornhuber HH, Deecke L: Hirnpotentialänderungen beim Menschen vor
und nach Willkürbewegungen, dargestellt mit Magnetbandspeicherung
und Rückwärtsanalyse. Pflügers Arch. ges. Physiol. 281 (1964) 52.
- Kosslyn, S.M., Thompson, W.L. (2003). When is early visual cortex
activated during visual mental imagery? Psychol. Bull. 129
(2003)723-746.
- Kreiman, G., Koch, C. and Fried, I. (2000). Imagery neurons in the
human brain. Nature (2000) 408: 357-361
<http://www.cns.caltech.edu/~gabriel/publications/imagination1.html>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I., & Koch, C. (2001). Single neuron responses
in humans during binocular rivalry and flash suppression. Journal of
Vision, 1(3), 131a, <http://journalofvision.org/1/3/131>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I. And Koch, C. (2002) Single Neuron responses
in the human brain during flash suppression. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Science USA, 99:8378-8383
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031015091920/http://www.ai.mit.edu/projects/cbcl/publications/ps/kreimanetal_flash-suppression.pdf>
- Larsen, A., Madsen, K.H., Lund, T.E., and Bundesen, C. (2006).
Images of Illusory Motion in Primary Visual Cortex. Journal of
Cognitive Neuroscience. 2006;18:1174-1180.
- Laureys, S. et al. (2002). Brain function in the vegetative state.
Acta neurol. belg., 2002, 102, 177-185
<http://www.jsmf.org/meetings/2003/nov/LaureysANB2002.pdf>
- Lee. S, and Blake, R. (2002). V1 activity is reduced during
binocular rivalry. Journal of Vision (2002) 2, 618-626
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030722173225/http://journalofvision.org/2/9/4/article.pdf>
- Leopold, D.A. and Logothetis, N.K. (1999). Multistable phenomena:
changing views in perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 3:
254-264.
<http://www.kyb.tuebingen.mpg.de/publications/pdfs/pdf201.pdf>
- Libet, B., Alberts, E.W., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B.(1967).
Responses of Human Somatosensory Cortex to Stimuli Below Threshold
for Conscious Sensation. Science 158, 1597-1600.
- Libet, B., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B., and Pearl, D.(1979).
Subjective referral of the timing for a conscious sensory
experience. Brain, 102, pp. 192--224.
<http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/entrez/query.fcgi?holding=npg&cmd=Retrieve&db=PubMed&list_uids=427530&dopt=Abstract>
- Linden, D.E.J. (2005) The P300: Where in the Brain Is It Produced
and What Does It Tell Us? The Neuroscientist, Vol. 11, No. 6,
563-576 (2005) <http://nro.sagepub.com/cgi/reprint/11/6/563.pdf>
- Llinas, R., Ribary, U., Contreras, D. & Pedroarena, C. (1998). The
neuronal basis for consciousness. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London Ser.
B.353, 1841-1849
<http://big.cs.uiuc.edu/anncbt-papers/fall05/Llinas.the-neuronal-basis-of-consciousness.pdf>
- Logothetis, N.K., Leopold, D.A. and Sheinberg, D.L. (1996). What is
Rivalling During Binocular Rivalry. Nature, 380:621-624.
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nature/journal/v380/n6575/abs/380621a0.html>
- Loveblad, KO. et al. (1999). Silent functional magnetic resonance
imaging demonstrates focal activation in rapid eye movement sleep.
Neurology 1999;53:2193Z
- Luce, R.D. (1986). Response times: their role in inferring
elementary mental organization. Oxford University Press, New York.
- Lumer, E.D., Friston, K.J. & Rees, G. (1998) Neural correlates of
perceptual rivalry in the human brain. Science. 280(5371):1930-4.
- Macdonald, K.D., Fifkova, E., Jones, M.S. and Barth, D.S. (1998)
Focal Stimulation of the Thalamic Reticular Nucleus Induces Focal
Gamma Waves in Cortex. The Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 79 No. 1
January 1998, pp. 474--477
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/79/1/474>
- Maia, T.V. & Cleeremans, A. (2005). Consciousness: converging
insights from connectionist modeling and neuroscience. TRENDS in
Cognitive Sciences Vol.9 No.8 August 2005
<http://srsc.ulb.ac.be/axcWWW/papers/pdf/05-TICS.pdf>
- Marcel AJ. (1998). Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of
visual consciousness or visual function? Brain 1998, 121, 1565-1588.
<http://brain.oupjournals.org/cgi/reprint/121/8/1565.pdf>
- Marois, R., Yi, D-J., & Chun, M.M. (2004). The Neural Fate of
Consciously Perceived and Missed Events in the Attentional Blink.
Neuron, 41, 3: 465-472.
- Mashour, G.A., Tononi, G. and Massimini, M. (2005). Cognitive
Unbinding in Sleep and Anesthesia. Science 16 December 2005:
1768-1769.
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
<http://juno.ingentaselect.com/vl=6492085/cl=26/nw=1/rpsv/cgi-bin/cgi?body=linker&ini=nlm&reqidx=issn=0962-8452vl=264is=1380yr=1997mn=Marpg=393>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). Responses of Spectrally
Selective Cells in Macaque Area V2 to Wavelengths and Colors. J
Neurophysiol 87: 2104-2112, 2002.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/87/4/2104>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). The relationship between
cortical activation and perception investigated with invisible
stimuli. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA, 99(14):9527-9532.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/99/14/9527>
- Muckli, L., Singer, W., Zanella, F.E. and Goebel, R. (2002)
Integration of multiple motion vectors over space: an fMRI study of
transparent motion perception. Neuroimage. 2002 Aug;16(4):843-56.
- Munhall, K.G. (2001). Functional Imaging During Speech Production.
Acta Psychologica 107 (2001) 95-117.
<http://pavlov.psyc.queensu.ca/~munhallk/07_acta_version.pdf>
- Munk MHJ, Roelfsema PR, König P, Engel AK, and Singer W. (1996).
Role of reticular activation in the modulation of intracortical
synchronization Science. 272, 271-274.
- Newman, J. & Baars, B.J. (1993) A neural attentional model for
access to consciousness: A Global Workspace perspective. Concepts in
Neuroscience, 4:2, 255-290
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000073/>
- Nieuwenhuis S, Aston-Jones G & Cohen JD (2005). Decision making, the
P3, and the locus coeruleus-norepinephrine system. Psychological
Bulletin, 131(4), 510-532.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051117045339/http://www.csbmb.princeton.edu/conte/pdfs/project5/Proj5Pub06.pdf>
- Nørretranders, T. (1991) Consciousness: The User Illusion
(translated from Danish), Penguin Books,
; 1999 revision:
<http://www.worldcat.org/title/user-illusion-cutting-consciousness-down-to-size/oclc/41311618>.
- Pantev C (1995) Evoked and induced gamma-band activity of the human
cortex. Brain Topogr 7:321-330
- Pasley BN, Mayes LC, Schultz RT (2004) Subcortical discrimination of
unperceived objects during binocular rivalry. Neuron 2004,
42:163-172.
- Pessoa, L. (2005) To what extent are emotional visual stimuli
processed without attention and awareness? Current Opinion in
Neurobiology 2005, 15:188-196
<http://web.archive.org/web/20060623004726/http://www.brown.edu/Research/LCE/publications_files/Pessoa_CONB_2005.pdf>
- Pettigrew, J.D. (2001) Searching for the Switch: Neural Bases for
Perceptual Rivalry Alternations. Brain and Mind 2: 85-118, 2001.
<http://www.uq.edu.au/nuq/jack/searchswitch.pdf>
- Raymond, J. E, Shapiro, K. L., & Arnell, K. M. (1992). Temporary
suppression of visual processing in an RSVP task: An attentional
blink? Journal of Experimental Psychology. Human Perception and
Performance, 18 (3), 849-60.
- Rektor, I., Bares, M., Kanovsky, P. and Kukleta, M. (2001)
Intracerebral recording of readiness potential induced by a complex
motor task. Movement Disorders, Volume 16, Issue 4, Pages 698-704
- Rees, G., Kreiman, G., & Koch, C. (2002) Neural Correlates of
Consciousness in Humans. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3, 261
-270 (2002)
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nrn/journal/v3/n4/abs/nrn783_fs.html&dynoptions=doi1069842948>
- Rensink, RA. (2000). When Good Observers Go Bad: Change Blindness,
Inattentional Blindness, and Visual Experience. PSYCHE, 6(09),
August 2000.
<http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v6/psyche-6-09-rensink.html>
- Roy, J.E. & Prichep, L.S. (2005) The Anesthetic Cascade: A Theory of
How Anesthesia Suppresses Consciousness Anesthesiology: Volume
102(2) February 2005 pp 447--471
<http://www.anesthesiology.org/pt/re/anes/fulltext.00000542-200502000-00030.htm>
- Schiff, N.D., & Plum F. 1999. The Neurology of Impaired
Consciousness: Global Disorders and Implied Models. \[Target
article\]. Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness.
<http://www.phil.vt.edu/assc/niko.html>
- Schiff ND, Plum F. (2000) The Role of Arousal and \"Gating\" Systems
in the Neurology of Impaired Consciousness. Journal of
Neurophysiology. 17(5):438-452. (
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030924010953/http://www.uni-tuebingen.de/cog/lehre/ss2003/seminar_bewusstsein/epapers/SchiffPlum00.pdf>
- Sheinberg, D.L. and Logothetis, N.K. (1997). The role of temporal
cortical areas in perceptual organization. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA 94, 3408-3413. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/7/3408>
- Simons, D.J. & Rensink, RA. (2005). Change blindness: Past, present,
and future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol.9, pp16--20, No.1
January 2005.
<http://www.psych.ubc.ca/~rensink/publications/download/S&R-TICS-05a.pdf>
- Singer, W. & Gray, C.W. (1995). Visual feature integration and the
temporal correlation hypothesis. Annu. Rev. Neurosci., 18,
pp. 555--86, 1995.
- Singer, W. (2001). Consciousness and the Binding Problem. Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences 929:123-146 (2001)
- Solms, Mark (2000) DREAMING AND REM SLEEP ARE CONTROLLED BY
DIFFERENT BRAIN MECHANISMS, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23
(6): 793.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/Preprints/OldArchive/bbs.solms.html>
- Soon, C.S., Brass, M., Heinze, H-J. and Haynes, J-D. (2008).
Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain.
Nature Neuroscience 11, 543 - 545 (2008)
- Sukov, W. & Barth, D.S. (2001). Cellular Mechanisms of Thalamically
Evoked Gamma Oscillations in Auditory Cortex. J Neurophysiol 85:
1235-1245, 2001;
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/85/3/1235>
- Takeuchi, T., Miyasita, A., Inugami, M. & Yamamoto, Y. (2001).
Intrinsic dreams are not produced without REM sleep mechanisms:
evidence through elicitation of sleep onset REM periods. Journal of
Sleep Research Volume 10 Issue 1 Page 43 - March 2001
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tamás, G., Buh, E.H., Lörincz, A., and Somogyi, P. (2000).
Proximally targeted GABAergic synapses and gap junctions synchronize
cortical interneurons. Nature Neuroscience volume 3 no 4 April 2000.
<http://mrcanu.pharm.ox.ac.uk/pdfs/TamasNatureNeurosci2000.pdf>
- Tanaka, Y. & Sagi, D. (1998). A perceptual memory for low contrast
visual signals. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol 95:12729-12733.
<http://www.weizmann.ac.il/~masagi/TS98b.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2001). Competing Theories of Binocular Rivalry: A Possible
Resolution. Brain and Mind 2: 55-83, 2001
<http://web.archive.org/web/20041212094810/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_Brain&Mind2001.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual Awareness. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030723135239/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
- Tootell, R.B., Reppas, J.B., Dale, A.M., Look, R.B., Sereno, M.I.,
Malach, R., Brady, T.J. and Rosen, B.R. (1995) Visual motion
aftereffect in human cortical area MT revealed by functional
magnetic resonance imaging. Nature. 1995 May 11;375(6527):139-41.
- Tononi, G., Srinivasan, R., Russell, P.D. & Edelman, G.M. (1998).
Investigating neural correlates of conscious perception by
frequency-tagged neuromagnetic responses . Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA. Vol. 95, Issue 6, 3198-3203, March 17, 1998
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/95/6/3198>
- Thornton, I.M., Pinto, J. and Shiffrar, M. (1998).
THE VISUAL PERCEPTION OF HUMAN LOCOMOTION. COGNITIVE NEUROPSYCHOLOGY,
1998, 15 (6/7/8 ), 535-552.
<http://psychology.rutgers.edu/~mag/TPS98.pdf>
- Traub, D.R., Whittington, M.A., Buhl, E.H., Jefferys, J.G.R., &
Faulkner, H.J. (1999). On the Mechanism of the Frequency Shift in
Neuronal Oscillations Induced in Rat Hippocampal Slices by Tetanic
Stimulation. The Journal of Neuroscience, February 1, 1999,
19(3):1088-1105
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/3/1088>
- Traub, R.D. (2003). Fast Oscillations and Epilepsy. Epilepsy Curr.
2003 May; 3(3): 77-79.
<http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/articlerender.fcgi?artid=321178>
- Trevena J & Miller, J (2002) Cortical Movement Preparation before
and after a Conscious Decision to Move. Consciousness and Cognition,
Volume 11, Issue 2, June 2002, Pages 162-190
- Trevena, J & Miller, J (2009) Brain preparation before a voluntary
action: Evidence against unconscious movement initiation. Conscious
Cogn. 2009 Sep 5. \[Epub ahead of print\]
- Tse, P.U., Susana Martinez-Conde, S., Schlegel, A.A. and Macknik,
S.L. (2005). Visibility, visual awareness, and visual masking of
simple unattended targets are confined to areas in the occipital
cortex beyond human V1/V2. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA November 22,
2005 vol. 102 no. 47. 17178-17183.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/102/47/17178>
- Uchida, N., Kepecs, A. and Mainen, Z.F. (2006) Seeing at a glance,
smelling in a whiff: rapid forms of perceptual decision making.
Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 7. 485-491.
- Uchida, N & Mainen, Z.F. (2003) Speed and accuracy of olfacory
discrimination in the rat. Nature Neurosci. 6, 1224-1229.
- Vogel, E.K., Luck, S.J. & Shapiro, K.L. (1998) Electrophysiological
Evidence for a Postperceptual Locus of Suppression During the
Attentional Blink. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
Perception and Performance 1998, Vol. 24. No. 6,1656-1674
<http://web.archive.org/web/20050304211722/http://www.psychology.uiowa.edu/faculty/Luck/lucklab/pdfs/Vogel_1998_JEPHPP.pdf>
- Wehrle, R., Czisch, M., Kaufmann, C., Wetter, T.C., Holsboer, F.,
Auer, D.P., and Pollmacher, T. (2005). Rapid eye movement-related
brain activation in human sleep: a functional magnetic resonance
imaging study. NeuroReport 16:853-857
<http://www.univie.ac.at/mcogneu/lit/wehrle.pdf>
- White, NS., Alkire, MT. (2003). Impaired thalamocortical
connectivity in humans during
general-anesthetic-induced unconsciousness. NeuroImage. Volume 19, Issue
2 , June 2003, Pages 402-411. <http://smallurl.com?i=2597>
(http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/B6WNP-48GP5CG-5/1/cedb33dc0bec4301d1960c7c27cea70f)
- Wheeler, M.E., Buckner, R.L.. (2003) Functional dissociation among
components
of remembering: control, perceived oldness, and content. J. Neurosci.
23, 3869-3880.
- Williams LM, Liddell BJ, Rathjen J, Brown KJ, Shevrin H, Gray JA,
Phillips M, Young A & Gordon E (2004). Mapping the time course of
nonconscious and conscious perception of fear: An integration of
central and peripheral measures. Human Brain Mapping,21, 64 - 74
<http://psychmed.iop.kcl.ac.uk/neuroscience-and-emotion/downloads/46.pdf>
- Wunderlich, K. Schneider, K.A., & Kastner, S. (2005).Neural
correlates of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate
nucleus. Nature Neuroscience 8, 1595 - 1602 (2005)
- Yamamoto, T. & Katayama, Y. (2005). Deep brain stimulation therapy
for the vegetative state. in Neuropsychol Rehabil. 2005 Jul-Sep ;
15(3-4): 406-13
- Zeki, S., & Bartel, A. (1999). Toward a Theory of Visual
Consciousness. Consciousness & Cognition, 8, 225-259.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 2#Event related potentials
*Contributors: please include full data in the references section for
all references in the text.*
```{=html}
<div class="noprint">
```
Home
```{=html}
</div>
```
## Perceptual \"filling in\"
Perceptual \"filling in\" occurs when visual properties such as
textures, colours, brightness or motion are extended in the visual field
to areas where they do not have corresponding events in the world.
The filling in of the blind spot by the properties of the field in the
contralateral eye has already been discussed. The part of the visual
field represented by the blind spot is also \"filled in\" in the case of
monocular vision.
![](Constudblindill.png "Constudblindill.png")
Shut the right eye and focus on the pink cross with the left eye, if the
head is moved towards the pink cross there is a point at which the
yellow disk disappears but the white lines are still present. In this
\"filling in\" the visual field does not appear to be distorted.
Fiorani *et al.* (1992) developed a technique for probing the cortical
blind spot using vertical and horizontal bar stimuli. Matsumoto &
komatsu (2005) used this technique on macaque monkeys. In the monocular
case they found that as a bar was moved across the visual field so that
it crossed the blind spot there was a sudden change in neural activity
in the deep layers of the neurons in the blind spot area of V1. When the
bar was moved across the same part of the visual field of the
contralateral eye the neural activity in the blind spot area increased
steadily as the bar was moved. The authors found that there were neurons
in the deep layers of blind spot cortex that had elongated receptive
fields that could respond to stimuli outside the blind spot and transfer
this activation into the blind spot cortex.
Filling in of a slightly different type occurs in \"scotoma\". In
scotoma an area of the retina is damaged and unresonsive to visual
stimuli, immediately after the damage patients report an area of visual
field that is unresponsive to stimuli. After several months patients
report that the area of field represented by the scotoma contains visual
properties related to the physical world surrounding the area that would
have formed an image on the scotoma. This results in a distortion of the
visual field. (see for instance Gilbert(1993)). Direct measurements of
activity in cortical area V1 show that the neurons that represented the
area of the scotoma become sensitive to activity in the surrounding
visual field. At the cortical level the scotoma is literally \"filled
in\".
There are many stimuli that cause \"filling in\". These stimuli are
known as \"illusions\" because they produce phenomenal experience that
has no correlate in the world outside the body. In the \"neon colour
spreading illusion\" a lightly coloured circle appears where there
should be a white background. Sasaki and Watanabe (2004) used fMRI to
show that the part of the topographic map in cortical area V1
corresponding to the light coloured circle was activated.
![](Constudneon.jpg "Constudneon.jpg")
Fiorani, M., Rosa, M.G.P., Gattas, R. & Rocha-Miranda, C.E. (1992).
Dynamic surrounds of receptive fields in primate striate cortex: a
physiological basis for perceptual completion? Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
89, 8547-8551. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/abstract/89/18/8547>
Gilbert, C.D. (1993). Circuitry, architecture and functional dynamics of
visual cortex.
Matsumoto, M & Komatsu, H. (2005). Neural responses in the macaque V1 to
bar stimuli with various lengths presented on the blind spot. J
neurophysiol. 93. 2374-2387.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/abstract/93/5/2374>
Sasaki, Y & Watanabe, T. The primary visual cortex fills in colour.
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 101, 18251-18256. (2004).
## Binocular Rivalry, Pattern Rivalry and Binocular Fusion
Sir Charles Wheatstone (1838) was the first scientist to systematically
investigate binocular rivalry. Binocular rivalry occurs when different
images are presented to the left and right eyes. The subject sees
successively one image, a combined image and then the other image. The
swapping of images can take a second or more. Binocular rivalry is of
interest in consciousness research because the parts of the brain that
contain the dominant image should also be those parts that are
contributing to conscious experience. Binocular rivalry involves at
least two components; the first switches from one image to a merged
image and then to the other image and the second permits the view to be
part of conscious experience.
![](Constudrival.png "Constudrival.png")
The switching of one image for another may involve selecting one of the
images as the percept or selecting one of the eyes. Blake *et al.*
(1979) performed an experiment in which subjects could change the image
at a given eye by pressing a button. When a particular image became
dominant they pressed a button to change the image at the eye receiving
the dominant image for the non-dominant image. They found that the
subjects immediately experienced the second image as the dominant image.
This suggests that binocular rivalry is selecting between eyes rather
than images. Lehky in 1988 proposed that the switching may be occurring
as a result of feedback between visual cortical area V1 and the Lateral
Geniculate Nucleus (a thalamic relay - see Carandini *et al.* 2002) and
Blake in 1989 also proposed that the switching occurred at the level of
area V1. (Visual cortical area V1 receives visual input direct from the
LGN.)
Tong (2001) has argued that, in humans, the switching of images in
binocular rivalry may occur at the earliest levels in the visual cortex.
In particular, Tong and Engel (2001) used an elegant technique measuring
the activity in the visual cortex that represents the blind spot of the
eye to show that almost complete switching to the dominant image occurs
at the level of visual cortical area V1. In support of this idea of
switching at the level of V1 or even before the cortex, Kreimann *et
al.* (2001, 2002) used direct electrode recordings in human cortex and
found that the activity of most neurons changed with the percept. Other
experiments have not shown a single locus in the brain where the
suppressed sensory information gets switched out (Blake & Logothetis
2002, Leopold & Logothetis 1996, Gail et al., 2004).
Functional MRI has also shown cortical activity outside of sensory
visual cortex related to both images in binocular rivalry. Lumer *et
al.* (1998) found that only the fronto-parietal areas of cortex switched
with the percept, Fang & He (2005) found that activity relating to both
suppressed and unsuppressed images were present in the dorsal stream of
the visual system. Wunderlich *et al.* (2005) and Haynes *et al.* (2005)
have both found suppression at the level of the lateral geniculate
nucleus using fMRI in humans.
Pasley *et al.* (2004) have shown that, even during suppression, fearful
faces can produce activity in the amygdala (see Pessoa (2005) for a
review).
Rivalry alternations seem to be the result of widespread activity
changes that cover large parts of the brain, including but not
necessarily originating at the earliest sensory stages of visual
processing. Most investigators have found that, once switching has
occurred, there are areas of the brain that contain activity that is
solely related to the percept but this varies from most of the cortex to
largely more frontal regions depending upon the study. The most likely
explanation for binocular rivalry is that the switching occurs at the
level of the LGN as a result of feedback from the cortex.
Pattern Rivalry is also of interest in consciousness research for the
same reasons as binocular rivalry. In pattern rivalry a figure may have
two or more forms that replace each other. Typical examples of such
figures are the Necker cube and Rubin\'s face-vase. The similarity of
the time course of the switching between percepts in binocular rivalry
and pattern rivalry has led many authors to suggest that these involve
the same mechanism. Logothetis *et al.* (1996) used novel dichoptic
stimuli (different images to each eyes) to produce a form of rivalry
that seems to involve switching at levels in the cerebral cortex that
are more distal to the sensory stimulus than V1. Leopold and Logothetis
(1999), on the basis of their work with monkeys, state that \"..many
neurons throughout the visual system, both monocular and binocular,
continue to respond to a stimulus even when it is perceptually
suppressed.\". Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998) investigated pattern rivalry
with MRI and found activity in higher order visual areas during change
of dominant pattern. Pettigrew (2001) also describes effects on rivalry
due to thought and mood that may require involvement of large areas of
cortex in the switching operation and stresses the way that V1
represents different visual fields in different hemispheres of the brain
so that inter-hemispheric switching must also be considered.
It seems likely that the change of dominant pattern or percept is
associated with higher level cortical activity but once the dominant
percept is established many of the visually responsive neurons in the
cortex are switched over to the new percept. This might account for the
similarities in timing of binocular and pattern rivalry and the
disparate results found by the various groups of authors. In the words
of Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998):
\"The transient activity fluctuations we found suggest that perceptual
metastability elicited by ambiguous stimuli is associated with rapid
redistributions of neural activity between separate specialized cortical
and subcortical structures.\"
Which permits both the idea of selecting particular eyes or percepts,
perhaps by feedback that switches a thalamic relay on the basis of
cortical processing of patterns. Once the cortex has switched the
thalamic relay most of the neurons in V1 would become exposed to the
dominant percept but there would still be a few neurons in the cortical
visual system receiving data from the non dominant image.
The investigations of binocular and pattern rivalry provide evidence
that conscious visual experience is probably distal to V1 (i.e.: cortex
or thalamus).
Perceptual rivalry may be part of complex decision making rather than
being simply a switch to blank out unwelcome input. It is clear from the
Rubin face-vase that pattern rivalry is linked to recognition and would
involve a complex delineation of forms within cortical processing. This
would suggest that many areas of cortex should be involved before a
particular percept is made dominant. Pettigrew (2001) argues that
rivalry is the result of a complex phenomenon rather than being simply a
switching event. Pettigrew\'s discovery that laughter abolishes rivalry
also points to a complex cortical system for switching percepts.
Pettigrew proposes that complex cortical processes control rivalry and
that the actual switching of percepts is performed sub-cortically in the
Ventral Tegmental Area. He concludes his review of the problem by noting
that \"Rivalry may thus reflect fundamental aspects of perceptual
decision making..\" Pettigrew (2001).
Another effect, known as \"binocular fusion\", provides further
compelling evidence for the non-conscious nature of the cerebral cortex.
In binocular fusion images from both eyes are fused together to create a
single image in experience. Moutoussis and Zeki (2002) used a form of
binocular fusion in which images of faces were flashed at 100ms
intervals to both eyes simultaneously. When both eyes received images of
the same colour the subject could see the faces but when one eye
received a green image on a red background and the other a red image on
a green background the subjects reported seeing a uniform yellow field
that contained no faces.
fMRI scans of the subject\'s brains showed that when both eyes were
exposed to images of the same colour the part of the brain that deals
with faces was active and when each eye received images of different
colours the same areas of brain showed activity. In other words the
cortex contained strong activity related to faces whether or not faces
were experienced. Moutoussis and Zeki found a similar effect when they
used images of houses instead of images of faces. The authors concluded
that: \"The present study further suggests that there are no separate
processing and perceptual areas but rather that the same cortical
regions are involved in both the processing and, when certain levels of
activation are reached and probably in combination with the activation
of other areas as well, the generation of a conscious visual percept\".
This conclusion does not seem to be supported by the data. There is no
evidence that any area of cortex contains the percept itself. The
experiment shows that the cortex contains data relating to both red and
green faces which suggests that the cortex is not the site of the
conscious percept. The percept is most likely distal to the cortex
perhaps in the thalamus or some other area that receives cortical
sensory output.
It is interesting that Fries *et al.* (1997) found that neurons that
were activated by the dominant image in binocular rivalry fired
synchronously whereas those that were activated by the non-dominant
image did not. Thalamocorticothalamic oscillations are the most likely
source for synchronising neurons over whole areas of cortex, suggesting
that the conscious percept is located in the thalamus rather than the
cortex.
## Synchronisation of Neural Processes
Our experience seems to contain entities with their attributes attached
to them at the correct places in space and time. When a dog barks we see
its jaws open at the same time as the bark and both jaws and bark are at
the same location. We take this for granted but the brain must be
engaging in some complex processing to achieve this synchronised and
appropriately positioned set of objects and events. The illustration
below shows the two basic processes that might be used to synchronise
events between the different specialised processors in the cerebral
cortex and brain in general.
![](Constudsynch.gif "Constudsynch.gif")
In the first option a complete model of sensation, dream etc. may be
created and then allowed to become part of conscious experience. In the
second model events are released into experience as fast as possible but
are synchronous when recalled, having been synchronised in a storage
buffer. There is a third option in which there is no synchronisation of
events so that the output from different processors would occur at
different times.
The \'experience buffer\' would be a volume of brain in which a
succession of events could be recorded. The buffer might either be
updated in steps, the previous content being discarded, or continuously
updated with the oldest content being lost continuously.
In the first option events from different processes would always appear
to be simultaneous unless the experience buffer were updated as a series
of steps in which case any changes at around the moment of updating
might appear in successive buffers. For instance, if change of position
were processed before change in colour a circle on a screen that changed
from green to red at the start of a motion might seem to be briefly
green during the motion and then turn red.
In the second model events from different processors might appear
asynchronous at the moment of experience but synchronous when recalled.
Colour vision and motion vision are processed in different parts of the
visual cortex and in distinct parts of visual cortical areas V1 and V2.
They are different processes and hence ideal for studying the
synchronisation of cortical activity. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997)
presented subjects with moving coloured squares on a computer screen
that changed from red to green or vice versa as they changed direction
of movement. It was found that subjects seemed to perceive changes in
colour some 70-80 msecs before they perceived a change in the direction
of motion of the squares. Further work by Arnold *et al.* (2001) and
Arnold and Clifford (2001) have confirmed that colour changes seem to be
perceived before motion. Arnold and Clifford (2001) also found a
quantitative relationship between the colour/motion asynchrony and the
direction of change of motion, complete reversals of direction giving
rise to the greatest asynchrony between the detection of colour and
motion changes.
Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) conclude by stating that the asynchrony of
neural processes shows that \"..the perception of each attribute is
solely the result of the activity in the specialised system involved in
its processing..\". It seems more likely that the experiments simply
show that slow neural processes are not synchronised before they become
percepts (the third option above). The experiments are excellent
evidence for the concept of the cortex as a set of specialised
processors that deliver their output asynchronously to some other place
where the output becomes a percept.
These experiments on colour and motion suggest that there is no
synchronisation between the processes that deal with these two aspects
of vision. Another set of experiments by Clifford *et al.* (2003)
supports this idea of processing being asynchronous. They asked subjects
to perform a variety of judgements of when visual events occurred and
found that the degree of synchrony of one visual event with another
depends on the type of judgement. Different judgements probably use
processors in different areas of cortex and the output from these
arrives asynchronously at the part of the brain that supports the
percept.
When the percept is formed there must be feedback to the cortical
processes that create its content. Otherwise it would not be possible to
report about the percept and the cortex would be unable to direct
processing to the percept in preference to other, non-conscious cortical
data.
Although slow processes (20 milliseconds to 1 second) do not seem to be
synchronised there is some evidence for very rapid synchronisation.
Andrews *et al.* (1996) revisited a problem raised by the famous
physiologist Charles Sherrington. Sherrington considered the phenomenon
of \'flicker fusion\' in which a flickering light appears to be a
continuous steady light if it flashes on and off at frequencies of about
45 Hz or higher. He reasoned that if the images from both eyes are
brought together to form a single image then the frequency at which a
flickering light appears to be steady should depend on whether one or
two eyes are used. Flicker fusion should occur if each eye receives
alternate flashes at only half the normal flicker fusion frequency. The
flicker should disappear if the left eye receives flashes at 23 pulses
per second and the right eye receives alternate flashes at 23 pulses per
second. When Sherrington performed the experiment he found that this was
not the case, using approximate figures, each eye required 46 pulses per
second for fusion to occur. Sherrington proposed that the flicker fusion
in alternate binocular presentation was occurring \"psychically\",
outside of normal physiological processes.
Andrews *et al.* duplicated Sherrington\'s result but investigated it
further. They found that when lights were flashed in each eye
alternately at low frequences (2 Hz) the experience was the same as a
light being flashed in both eyes at this rate. At frequencies of four Hz
and higher the subjects began to report that the lights being flashed
alternately in both eyes seemed to flicker at the same rate as lights
being flashed in both eyes at half the frequency. It seemed as if a
flash in one eye followed by a flash in the other eye was being
perceived as a single flash or \"conflated\" as the authors put it. The
authors explained this effect by suggesting that the brain activity
corresponding to the flashes was sampled for a short period and any
number of flashes occurring during this period became perceived as a
single flash. The maximum rate of sampling would be about 45 Hz. This
idea is similar to option (1) above, where the buffer is filled and
emptied 40 - 50 times a second.
An experience buffer that is refreshed at 40-50 times a second might
also explain the results obtained with colour and motion asynchrony
because synchronisation between processes may well happen too quickly to
affect processes that occur at very slow rates. Singer and Gray (1995),
Singer (2001) have proposed that synchronisation between neurones at
about 45 Hz is the discriminator between those neurones with activity
that contributes to conscious experience and activity in other neurones.
A rapid refresh rate in a synchronising buffer agrees with the results
found by Fries *et al.* (1997) in which visual cortical neurones that
represent a percept underwent synchronous oscillations in the gamma
frequency range (39--63 Hz). Tononi *et al.* (1998) have also found
synchronisation of neural activity in neurones that represent the
percept.
The gamma frequency oscillations are intrinsic to the cortex but are
triggered by the thalamus and are part of the \'arousal system\'.
Readers should be wary of the term \'arousal system\' because it evokes
the idea of something waking up a conscious cortex. The cortex can be
fully active during sleep and even during pathological unconsciousness
such as persistent vegetative state so it is possible that the arousal
centres themselves or nearby structures actually host phenomenal
consciousness.
## EEG and synchronisation
If electrodes are placed on the scalp varying electrical potentials of a
few tens of microvolts can be recorded between the electrodes.
Recordings of potentials from electrodes on the scalp are known as
electroencephalograms (EEGs).
The potentials recorded in the EEG are due to postsynaptic potentials in
nerve cells. The EEG is insensitive to the activity of single cells and
occurs as a result of relatively slow, **synchronised**, changes in
large areas of cells. The differences in potential between two scalp
electrodes are largely due to depolarisation and hyperpolarisation of
the dendritic trees of cortical pyramidal cells. The folding of the
cortex (gyri) is problematical for recording and interpreting EEGs
because opposing layers of cortex can cancel any net potentials.
The EEG shows rhythmic activity. This is conventionally divided into the
following frequency bands:
Delta waves 0--4 Hz
Theta waves 4--8 Hz
Alpha waves 8--12 Hz
Beta waves \>10 Hz
Gamma waves (also called fast beta) 25--100 Hz
EEGs also contain short bursts of activity called spindles and very fast
oscillations (VFOs). Spindles last for 1--2 seconds and contain rhythmic
activity at 7--14 Hz. They are associated with the onset of sleep. The
VFOs consist of short bursts at frequencies of over 80 Hz.
When the eyes are closed the amplitude of activity from most pairs of
electrodes is increased compared with when the eyes are open. When
subjects are awake the EEG consists mainly of alpha and beta activity
with considerable low amplitude gamma when the eyes are open. In stage 1
sleep the EEG consists of theta waves, in stage 2 sleep of varied
activity and spindles, in stage 4 sleep of delta and during REM sleep of
beta and theta activity. In epileptic seizures there tends to be high
amplitude activity with pronounced synchronisation between many pairs of
electrodes.
The rhythmic electrical activity is due to cortical feedback loops,
cortico-cortical synchronisation, thalamic pacemakers and
thalamo-cortical synchronisation. VFOs have been attributed to the
activity of electrical connections between cells (dendro-dendritic gap
junctions) (Traub (2003)).
The gamma activity, centred on a frequency of 40 Hz appears to be
related to activity in cortical interneurons that form electrical
connections between their dendrites (Tamas *et al.* 2000). These
oscillations can be triggered by high frequency stimulation of the
posterior intralaminar nuclei of the thalamus (Barth and MacDonald 1996,
Sukov and Barth 2001) and as a result of activation of the reticular
system (Munk *et al.* 1996). This suggests that stimulation of cortex by
thalamic sensory relays triggers gamma band activity in the cortex. A
shift from gamma to beta waves can occur in human event related
potentials after about 0.2 secs (Pantev 1995, Traub *et al.* 1999).
The alpha activity is related to thalamic pacemakers, perhaps as a
result of intrinsic oscillatory activity in thalamic sensory relays (see
Roy & Prichep 2005 for a brief review). Theta activity, which occurs
during some cognitive tasks and mental arithmetic involves a loop from
the cortex to the non-specific thalamic nuclei. Delta activity seems to
be endogenous to cortex when input is suppressed during sleep. Beta
activity is due to cortico-cortical interactions, often after a brief
period of gamma activation. It should be noted that gamma and beta
activity can be expressed as impulses in cortico-thalamic pathways and
that when cortical and thalamic activity is correlated there is a
conscious state. In other words gamma or beta waves in the cortex are
not correlates of consciousness on their own - see for instance Laureys
*et al.* (2002).
## Event related potentials
After a sudden event there are a characteristic set of changes in EEG
activity known as **event related potentials** or ERPs. The time course
of the ERP is shown in the diagram below.
![](Constudevent.png "Constudevent.png")
ERPs occur in response to novel stimuli and are also produced by brief
transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS)(Iramina *et al.* 2002). The slow
component is known as the P3 or P300 phase of the ERP. It is due to
activation of areas of the brain that are relatively remote from the
primary sensory areas of brain.
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) have reviewed the origin of the P300 ERP:
\"To summarize, convergent evidence suggests that P3-like activity can
be recorded in several, widely separated brain areas. These include some
medial temporal and subcortical structures (e.g., the hippocampal
formation, amygdala, and thalamus), but these structures are unlikely to
contribute directly to the scalp-recorded P3.\". According to
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) the recorded P300 may be due to
temporo-parietal and prefrontal cortical activity. Linden (2005) has
also concluded that widespread, but specific, cortical activation is
correlated with the recorded P300 ERP.
The generator of the P300 is still obscure. Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005)
consider that the Locus coeruleus, a nucleus in the pons that regulates
task related attention and part of the sleep-wake cycle, may be
responsible. In line with this, Mashour *et al.* (2005) have discovered
that TMS induced P300 activity is reduced in unconscious states.
Whether the P300 is related to Libet\'s 0.5 second delay is still
obscure but the discovery that the P300 occurs in association with
subliminal stimuli (stimuli that do not enter awareness)(Bernat *et al.*
2001) suggests that it is associated with non-conscious cortical
processing. Williams *et al.* (2004), in an investigation of subliminal
and supraliminal fear perception, found that \"conscious fear perception
was distinguished by a more prominent N4, peaking around 400 msec\"; the
N4 component follows the P300 component in the succession of phases of
the ERP. Williams *et al.* considered that the earlier phases in the ERP
are probably related to non-conscious processing. In contrast Vogel *et
al.* (1998) found that suppression of the P300 was associated with
suppression of awareness.
## The integration delay
Psychological experiments often involve binary decisions where subjects
give one of two outputs in response to stimuli. It is found that if the
stimuli are made increasingly noisy or complex the response time tends
to increase. Psychophyicists have developed various mathematical models
to explain the increased response times due to noise such as the
Integrator and Accumulator models (cf: Luce(1986)). These models have
been fairly successful when explaining experiments such as judging the
net direction of movement of sets of dots on a screen when the dots are
given semi-random paths and different brightness etc. In these
circumstances it can take up to 2 seconds for an accurate decision.
There are many tasks however where the accuracy of decision making does
not improve after about 300 milliseconds. The accuracy of the
performance of rats when choosing between two alternatives when reacting
to odours peaks at about 300 ms (Uchida and Mainen(2003), Abraham *et
al.* (2004)). The accuracy of humans when performing vernier acuity
tasks, line detection, contrast sensitivity, motion velocity
discrimination and stereoscopic depth discrimination seems to peak at
300ms (Uchida *et al.* 2006).
Uchida, Kepecs and Mainen (2006) suggest that \"rapid and short
integration time is a sensible strategy for rapid processing of
low-level sensory information in order to form more complex sensory
images, both in vision and olfaction.\" Whether these authors regard
these derived sensory images as the content of consciousness is not
mentioned. The authors propose that the 300ms optimal integration time
may be partly due to the mechanics of sniffing (a sniff takes about
125-200ms) and the nature of optical fixation (inter-saccade intervals
are typically 200-400 ms ). The authors note that the animal or human
could, in principle, choose to integrate over longer intervals but if it
is moving this may not lead to information that is current for changed
circumstances.
An optimal processing time of about 300 ms would be consistent with the
delays observed before conscious awareness occurs in response to a
stimulus - an interval required to form \"more complex sensory images\".
## Global Workspace Theory
Global Workspace Theory is the idea that somewhere in the brain there is
a facility that integrates the processes that occur in the various
separate areas of the brain. The theory was first proposed by Descartes
as the *sensus communis*, the common sense, but the modern form of the
theory dispenses with the idea of a point soul looking at the brain. In
modern Global Workspace theory it is proposed that an area of brain
receives input from most of the cerebral cortex and broadcasts its
outputs to all of the unconscious modular information processors in the
brain.
Modern Global Workspace Theory has been championed by Baars (1983,
1988).
There is increasing evidence for a Global Workspace or Global Workspaces
in the brain. Much of this evidence comes from fMRI, single unit and
magnetoencephalography studies in which it is shown that non-conscious
or subliminal processing mainly occupies primary, sensory cortex whereas
conscious processing occupies large areas of cerebral cortex.
In binocular rivalry the stimulus that is consciously perceived is
responsible for relatively intense activation of large areas of brain
whereas the non-conscious stimulus is often suppressed (see above and
Sheinberg & Logothetis (1997), Tononi *et al.* (1998)). The suppression
is likely to occur in the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei which suggests a
role for the Thalamic Reticular Nuclei, which modulate LGN activity, in
the control of the percept.
### Masking and visual awareness
Word masking has also been used to investigate the idea of a Global
Workspace. When a word is presented on its own for a few tens of
milliseconds it remains readable but if it is immediately succeeded by,
or accompanied by, another word it becomes indistinct or invisible. This
effect is known as \"word masking\". Vogel *et al.* (1998) have
investigated a version of word masking known as the \"attentional
blink\". They found that when stimuli became invisible the P3 component
of the Event Related Potential, which peaks at around 300-500 millisecs
after a stimulus, was completely suppressed. The P3 component of the ERP
has been related to the lodging of data in working memory and also to
gamma band activity in the EEG. This strongly suggests the involvement
of a cortico-thalamic loop in the \"attentional blink\". The delay of
0.3 to 0.5 secs is typical of the time required for conscious awareness
(see above).
Word masking in conjunction with fMRI and Event Related Potential (ERP)
recordings has been used by Dehaene *et al.* (2001) to expose control by
a central mechanism. It was found that masked words activate mainly the
visual cortex and ventral stream (inferior temporal lobe) whereas
visible words also activated distant parietal, prefrontal and cingulate
sites.
Dehaene *et al.* (2003) and found that the dynamics of the loss of
visibility of words in an attentional blink experiment could be modelled
by a simulated cortico-thalamic loop. In their simulation a distributed
cortical process determined which events would receive attention and the
system used the thalamic gating systems to exclude those that did not
receive attention.
Tse *et al.* (2005) have used purely visual stimuli in masking
experiments and concluded that, in the case of purely visual stimuli,
the neural correlates of awareness were limited to the occipital cortex:
\"We suggest that there are both lower and upper bounds within the
visual hierarchy for the processing of visual masking and the
maintenance of visual awareness of simple unattended targets; the lower
bound is at least as high as the border between V2 and V3, and the upper
bound is within the occipital lobe, possibly somewhere downstream of
V4.\"
This discovery would mean that activation of large areas of cortex are
unnecessary for awareness.
Melloni *et al.* (2007) compared compared the electrophysiological
responses related to the processing of visible and invisible words in a
delayed matching to sample task. Both perceived and nonperceived words
caused a similar increase of local (gamma) oscillations in the EEG, but
only perceived words induced a transient long-distance synchronization
of gamma oscillations across widely separated regions of the brain.
After this transient period of temporal coordination, the electrographic
signatures of conscious and unconscious processes continue to diverge.
Only words reported as perceivedinduced (1) enhanced theta oscillations
over frontal regions during the maintenance interval, (2) an increase of
the P300 component of the event-related potential, and (3) an increase
in power and phase synchrony of gamma oscillationsbefore the anticipated
presentation of the test word. We propose that the critical process
mediating the access to conscious perception is the earlytransient
global increase of phase synchrony of oscillatory activity in the
gammafrequency.
Melloni L, Molina C, Pena M, Torres D, Singer W, Rodriguez E. (2007).
Synchronization of neural activity across cortical areas correlates
withconscious perception.J Neurosci. 2007 Mar 14;27(11):2858-65.
### Attention and the global workspace
Baars (2002) in his review of evidence for the Global Workspace Theory
quotes many other experiments that show activation of larger areas of
cortex in response to conscious stimuli compared with unconscious or
subliminal stimuli.The effect is also seen in change blindness, learning
and attention. Newman and Baars (1993) consider that the \"workspace\"
is fairly global in the brain:
\"This Neural Global Workspace (NGW) model views conscious processes in
terms of a globally integrative brain system. The neural circuitry
contributing to this system is not only widely distributed across the
neocortex, but includes key corticothalamic and midbrain circuits as
well. These cortico-subcortical circuits are hypothesized to be critical
to understanding the mechanisms of attentional control that provide an
essential basis for the conscious processing of information\".
However they focus particularly on the role of the thalamic Reticular
Nucleus and cortico-thalamic connectivity in the control of attention.
Other ideas for the location of the Global Workspace are the idea of
Singer et al. that gamma synchrony controls access to the content of
consciousness and Llinas et al. (1998) that the thalamus is the hub
through which communication occurs between areas of cortex.
One of the problems with Global Workspace theory is that it suggests
that attention, working memory, cognitive control and consciousness may
all be in the same area of the brain. It is likely that the mechanisms
of attention, working memory, and cognitive control may involve several,
interlinked systems perhaps co-opting the basal ganglia in the process.
In view of this Maia and Cleeremans (2005) propose that \".. attention,
working memory, cognitive control and consciousness are not distinct
functions implemented by separate brain systems. Attempting to find
separate neural correlates for each may therefore be the wrong approach.
Instead, we suggest that they should be understood in terms of the
dynamics of global competition, with biasing from PFC (prefrontal
cortex).\". The inclusion by Maia and Cleeremans of consciousness with
distributed attention, working memory and cognitive control is
reminiscent of Zeki & Bartel\'s idea of microconsciousness.
It should be noted that, in common with Libet\'s data, the percept seems
to be available to phenomenal consciousness some 0.3 to 0.5 secs after a
stimulus; this suggests that whatever determines the content of
phenomenal consciousness operates before events become part of
phenomenal consciousness. This relegates phenomenal consciousness from
being a controller of attention to being the recipient of content that
is the subject of attention. This finding is consistent with the
philosophical problem of the **apparently** epiphenomenal nature of
phenomenal consciousness.
Given the data on the timing of conscious awareness it seems that there
may be two \"workspaces\", an active workspace that models the world,
discarding and suppressing data during rivalry, and a passive workspace
that receives the final, edited product. The active workspace would
correlate with the cortical systems stressed by Dehaene *et al.* and
Maia and Cleermans although, given the results of Tse et al., the
workspace would be limited to small zones of cortex. The loading of the
passive workspace with the output of the active workspace would
correlate with thalamo-cortical activity during component P3 of the ERP
in which data is transferred from the cortex to the thalamus. This
workspace might constitute the source for reports of the content of
phenomenal consciousness.
Llinas *et al.* (1998) have proposed two parallel cortico-thalamic
attentional systems, one of which is related to the thalamic specific
nuclei and the other to the thalamic non-specific nuclei, especially the
ILN. The non-specific system would be related to consciousness itself.
## The \"cognitive map\" and the neural basis of perceptual space
Our bodies appear to be mobile within a constant space. We walk around a
room; the room does not rotate around us. The constancy of the location
of things gives us the feeling that we are directly viewing a constant
world. But how does the brain provide a constant world rather than a
world that rotates with the movement of the sense organs? Why is our
view of the world when we move our eyes so different from the disturbing
flow of images that occur when a video camera is waved around? Do our
brains contain a constant \"cognitive map\" (O\'Keefe and Nadel 1978) of
our surroundings?
Mittelstaedt & Mittelstaedt (1980, 1982) discovered that female gerbils
were able to recover their pups in darkened surroundings by searching in
a semi random fashion on the outbound journey and then proceeding
directly back to the nest on the inbound journey. The direct journey
back to the nest seemed to be due to an integration of the various
directions taken on the outward journey (**path integration**). If the
equipment being explored by the mother gerbil was rotated very slowly
the mother would make an error equivalent to the amount of rotation.
More rapid rotations that activated the vestibular system of the rat
(acceleration measurement) did not cause errors in navigation. This
demonstration that rodents could navigate accurately on the basis of
**idiothetic** cues (cues that are due to internal senses) led to
research on the neural basis of the navigation.
As early as 1971 O\'Keefe and Dostrovsky had discovered that there are
particular cells in the hippocampus that fire according to the position
of an animal in the environment. This has been complimented by research
that showed that changes in visual cues within the environment caused
changes in the firing rate of place cells in hippocampal area CA3 (.
![](Gray717.png "Gray717.png")
![](HippocampalRegions.jpg "HippocampalRegions.jpg")
!Entorhinal cortex approximately maps to areas 28 and
34{width="500"}
F. P. Battaglia and A. Treves. 1998 Attractor neural networks storing
multiple space representations: A model for hippocampal place fields.
PHYSICAL REVIEW E DECEMBER 1998 VOLUME 58, NUMBER 6
<http://www.sissa.it/~ale/Bat+98b.pdf>
Leutgeb, S., Leutgeb, J.K., Moser, M-B, and Moser, E.I. 2005. Place
cells, spatial maps and the population code for memory. Current Opinion
in Neurobiology 2005, 15:738--746.
<http://instruct1.cit.cornell.edu/courses/bionb720nejc/reprints/LeutgebEtAl2005.pdf>
Mittelstaedt, H. & Mittelstaedt, M-L. 1982. Avian Navigation. (ed. Papi,
F. & Wallraff, H.) 290-297. Springer, Berlin.
Mittelstaedt, M-L & Glasauer, S. 1991. Idiothetic Navigation in Gerbils
and Humans. Zool. Jb. Physiol. 95 (1991), 427-435
<http://web.archive.org/web/20110125132449/http://www.nefo.med.uni-muenchen.de/~sglasauer/MittelstaedtGlasauer1991.pdf>
O\'Keefe, J. & Dostrovsky, J. (1971). The hippocampus as a spatial map:
preliminary evidence from unit activity in the freely moving rat. Brain
Res. 34, 171-175.
O\'Keefe, J. & Nadel, L. (1978). The Hippocampus as a cognitive map.
(Oxford)
## Bibliography
Defining the States of Consciousness. Tassi, P., Muzet, A. (2001)
Neuroscience and Behavioural Reviews 25(2001) 175-191.
Neuroanatomy: \"Digital Slice of Life\" by Stensaas and Millhouse
<http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/subj2.html>
See also: <http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/index.html>
EEG\'s: Coles, M.G.H., Rugg, M.D. Event Related Brain Potentials: An
Introduction.
<http://whalen.psych.udel.edu/667/1.What_is_ERP/ColesRugg1995chpt1.pdf>
Visual System: Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual
Awareness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
Professor Bogen\'s Consciousness Page
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/toccons.htm>
Demonstrations of Auditory Illusions and Tricks. Yoshitaka Nakajima
<http://www.kyushu-id.ac.jp/~ynhome/ENG/Demo/illusions2nd.html>
## References
- Abraham, N.M. (2004) Maintaining accuracy at the expense of speed:
stimulus similarity defines odor discrimination time in mice. Neuron
44, 865-876.
- Aleman, A., Ramsey, N., Van Honk, J.E., Kessels, R.P.C., Hoogduin,
J., Schutter, D.L.G., Postma, A., Kahn, R.S., De Haan, E.H.F.
(submitted). Parietal cortex mediates visuospatial imagery: evidence
from fMRI and rTMS.
<http://igitur-archive.library.uu.nl/dissertations/1954455/c10.pdf>
- Alkire, M.T., Haier, R.J., Fallon, J.H., and Barker, S.J.(1996). PET
imaging of conscious and unconscious verbal memory. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, 3 ( 5-6) 1996 , pp. 448--462
<http://www.imprint.co.uk/jcs_3_5-6.html>
- Anderson, J. & Anderson, B. (1993). \"The Myth of Persistence of
Vision Revisited,\" Journal of Film and Video, Vol. 45, No. 1
(Spring 1993): 3-12.
<http://www.uca.edu/org/ccsmi/ccsmi/classicwork/Myth%20Revisited.htm>
- Andrews, T.J., White, L.E., Binder, D. & Purves, D. (1996). Temporal
events in cyclopean vision. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 93,
pp. 3689--3692, April 1996. Neurobiology.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030510095149/http://www.dur.ac.uk/tim.andrews/PNAS_93_3689.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G. (2001) Determinants of asynchronous
processing in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London,
Series B: Biological Sciences, 269, 579 - 583.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031205165920/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/AC02.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G, Wenderoth, P. (2001). Asynchronous
processing in vision: Color leads motion. Current Biology, 11,
596 - 600.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030617120017/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/ACW01.pdf>
- Austin, G.M. & Grant, F.C. (1958). Physiologic observations
following total hemispherectomy in man. Surgery 38, 239-258.
- Baars, B.J. (1983) Conscious contents provide the nervous system
with coherent, global information. In Consciousness and
Self-Regulation (Vol 3). Davidson, R.J. et al., editors. Plenum
Press.
- Baars, B.J. (1988) A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness, Cambridge
University Press.
- Baars, B., Newman, J., & Taylor, J. (1998) Neuronal mechanisms of
consciousness: A Relational Global Workspace framework., in
Hameroff, Stuart and Kaszniak, Al and Laukes, James, Eds. Toward a
Science of Consciousness II: The second Tucson discussions and
debates., chapter 24, pages 269-278. MIT Press.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000946/>
- Baars, B.J. (2002) The conscious access hypothesis: origins and
recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. Vol 6, No 1,
47-52. 2002. <http://www.cs.memphis.edu/~wrcm/BaarsTICS2002.pdf>
- Barth, D. S. and MacDonald, K. D. (1996) Thalamic modulation of
high-frequency oscillating potentials in auditory cortex. Nature.
383, 78-81.
- Bernat E, Shevrin H, Snodgrass M. (2001). Subliminal visual oddball
stimuli evoke a P300 component. Clin Neurophysiol. 2001
Jan;112(1):159-71.
- Blake, R., Westendorf, D. and Overton, R. (1979) What is suppressed
during binocular rivalry? Perception 9: 223-231.
- Blake, R. and Lee, S.-H. (1999). Rival ideas about binocular
rivalry. Vision Research. 39: 1447-1454
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/faculty/blake/PDFs/Lee_Blake_99VR.pdf>
- Blankenburg, F., Ruff, C.C., Deichmann, R., Rees, G. and
Driver, J. (2006) The cutaneous rabbit illusion affects human
primary sensory cortex somatotopically, PLoS Biol 2006;4(3):e69.
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness: I. An
overview. Consciousness and Cognition, 4, 52-62.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/bogen-95.pdf>
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness:
Part II. Constraining the semantic problem. Consciousness and
Cognition, 4, 137-158.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/concog95.htm>
- Bregman, A.S. (1990). Auditory scene analysis: The perceptual
organization of sound. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Budka, H. (1998). Fatal Familial Insomnia Around the World. Brain
Pathology, 8: 553-570.
<http://brainpath.medsch.ucla.edu/pdfs/0803pdf/budka.pdf>
- Carandini M, Heeger DJ, & Senn W, (2002). A synaptic explanation of
suppression in visual cortex, Journal of Neuroscience,
22:10053-10065, 2002.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031031214953/http://www.cns.nyu.edu/~david/ftp/reprints/Carandini-JNeurosci2002.pdf>
- Cariani, P. (2000). Anesthesia, Neural Information Processing, And
Conscious Awareness. Consciousness And Cognition Vol. 9, No. 3,
September 2000 p. 387-395
- Castro-Alamancos, M.A., Connors, B.W. (1997). Thalamo-cortical
synapses. Progress in Neurobiology, Vol.51, pp. 581 to 606, 1997
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051025163047/http://neurobio.drexel.edu/castroweb/progneurobio1.pdf>
- Christmann, C. & Leuthold, H. (2004). The Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Section A. Volume 57, Number 2 /
February 2004. 357-381.
- Claus, R. & Nel, W. (2006). Drug induced arousal from the permanent
vegetative state. NeuroRehabilitation. 2006;21(1):23-8.
- Clifford, C.W.G., Arnold, D.H., Pearson, J. (2003). A paradox of
temporal perception revealed by a stimulus oscillating in colour and
orientation. Vision Research 43 (2003) 2245-2253.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031102125210/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/CAP03.pdf>
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of
consciousness Seminars in the Neurosciences (1990) 2, 263-275
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1998). Consciousness and Neuroscience.
Cerebral Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
- Culham, J.C., Dukelow, S.P., Vilis, T., Hassard, F.A., Gati, J.S.,
Menon, R.S. and Goodale, M.A. (1999). Recovery of fMRI Activation in
Motion Area MT Following Storage of the Motion Aftereffect. The
Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 81 No. 1 January 1999, pp. 388--393.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/81/1/388>
- Deecke, L. (1996) Planning, preparation, execution, and imagery of
volitional action, (Introduction / Editorial) in: L. Deecke W.
Lang, A. Berthoz (Eds) Mental Representations of Motor Acts.
Cognitive Brain Res 3 / Special Issue (2) 59-64.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000015/00/COGBRAIN.html>
- Dehaene, S., Sergent, C., and Changeux, J. (2003) A neuronal network
model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data
during conscious perception. PNAS July 8, 2003 vol. 100 no. 14
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/DehaeneSergentChangeux_BlinkModel_PNAS2003.pdf>
- Dehaene, S. et al. (2001) Cerebral mechanisms of word masking and
unconscious repetition priming. Nat. Neurosci, 4, 752-758.
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/Dehaene_MaskedWords_NatureNeuroscience2001.pdf>
- Dennett, D. and Kinsbourne, M. (1992) Time and the Observer: the
Where and When of Consciousness in the Brain. (1992) Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 15, 183-247, 1992. Reprinted in The Philosopher\'s
Annual, Grim, Mar and Williams, eds., vol. XV-1992, 1994,
pp. 23--68; Noel Sheehy and Tony Chapman, eds., Cognitive Science,
Vol. I, Elgar, 1995,
pp. 210--274.http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/time&obs.htm
- Destexhe, A. (2000). Modelling corticothalamic feedback and the
gating of the thalamus by the cerebral cortex. J. Physiol (Paris),
94 (2000) 391-410. <http://cns.iaf.cnrs-gif.fr/files/Brem2000.pdf>
- Fang, F. & He, S. (2005).Cortical responses to invisible objects in
the human dorsal and ventral pathways. Nat Neurosci. 2005
Oct;8(10):1380-5. Epub 2005 Sep 4.
- Ffytche, D. H., Howard, R. J., Brammer, M. J., David, A., Woodruff,
P., & Williams, S. (1998). The anatomy of conscious vision: an fMRI
study of visual hallucinations. Nature Neuroscience, 1, 738--742.
- Fiset, P., Paus, T., Daloze, T., Plourde, G., Meuret, P., Bonhomme,
V., Hajj-Ali, N., Backman, S.B., and Evans, A.C. (1999). Brain
Mechanisms of Propofol-Induced Loss of Consciousness in Humans: a
Positron Emission Tomographic Study. The Journal of Neuroscience,
July 1, 1999, 19(13):5506-5513.
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/13/5506>
- Fu, C.H.Y., Morgan, K., Suckling, J., Williams, S.C.R., Andrew, C.,
Vythelingum, G.N., McGuire, P.K. (2002). A Functional Magnetic
Resonance Imaging Study of Overt Letter Verbal Fluency Using a
Clustered Acquisition Sequence: Greater Anterior Cingulate
Activation with Increased Task Demand. NeuroImage 17, 871-
879 (2002)
<http://www-bmu.psychiatry.cam.ac.uk/PUBLICATION_STORE/fu02fun.pdf>
- Ganis, G., Thomson, W.L. and Kosslyn, S.M. (2004). Brain areas
underlying visual mental imagery and visual perception: an fMRI
study. Cognitive Brain Research 20 (2004) 226--241
<http://www.wjh.harvard.edu/~kwn/Kosslyn_pdfs/2004Ganis_CogBrainRes20_BrainAreas.pdf>
- Hultin, L. (1997). On Neuromagnetic Assessment of the Contingent
Negative Variation.
<http://www2.lib.chalmers.se/cth/diss/doc/9697/HultinLeif.html>
- Fries, P.. Roelfsema, P.R., Engel, A.K., König, P. and Singer, W.
(1997). Synchronization of oscillatory responses in visual cortex
correlates with perception in interocular rivalry. Proc. Natl. Acad.
Sci. USA, Vol. 94, pp. 12699--12704, November 1997.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/23/12699>
- Fuentealba, P., Crochet, S., Timofeev, I., Bazhenov, M., Sejnowski,
T.J. and Steriade, M. (2004). European Journal of Neuroscience
20(1):111-119. <http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2004/22126/ch03.html>
- Goaillard, J. & Vincent, P. (2002). Serotonin suppresses the slow
afterhyperpolarization in rat intralaminar and midline thalamic
neurones by activating 5-HT7 receptors. Journal of Physiology
(2002), 541.2, pp. 453--465
<http://jp.physoc.org/cgi/content/full/541/2/453>
- Haggard, P. & Eimer, M. (1999) On the relation between brain
potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Exp. Brain Res.
126, 128--133 (1999).
- Haggard, P. (2008) Human volition:towards a neuroscience of will.
Nature Rev Neurosci 9, 934-946
- Haynes, J., Deichmann, R. and Rees, G. (2005). Eye-specific effects
of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate nucleus. Nature
438, 496-499 (24 November 2005)
- Hughes S.W., Blethyn K.L. , Cope D.W. , & Crunelli V. (2003).
Properties and origin of spikelets in thalamocortical neurones in
vitro. Neuroscience. 2002;110(3):395-401
- Iramina, K., Maeno, T., Kowatari, Y. and Ueno, S.. (2002). Effects
of Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation on EEG Activity .IEEE
TRANSACTIONS ON MAGNETICS, VOL. 38, NO. 5, SEPTEMBER 2002
- Ishai, A., Ungerleider, L.G., Haxby, J.V.. (2000) Distributed neural
systems for the generation of visual images. Neuron 28, 979-990.
- Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1980). Mental models in cognitive science.
Cognitive Science, 4, 71-115.
<http://cognitrn.psych.indiana.edu/rgoldsto/cogsci/classics.html>
- Keller, J. & Heckhausen, H. (1990). Readiness potentials preceding
spontaneous motor acts: voluntary vs. involuntary control.
Electroencephalography and Clinical Neuropsychology, 76, 351-361.
- King, C.C. (1991). Fractal and Chaotic Dynamics in Nervous Systems.
Progress in Neurobiology, 36, pp. 279--308, 1991.
<http://citeseer.nj.nec.com/king91fractal.html>
- Klein, S.A (2002). Libet's Temporal Anomalies: A Reassessment of the
Data.
Consciousness and Cognition 11, 198--214 (2002)
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/160.pdf>
- Klein, S. (2002). Libet\'s Timing of Mental Events: Commentary on
the Commentaries. Consciousness and Cognition. 11, 326-333.
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/ccog_2002_0580-Klein-Commentary_on_the_commentaries.pdf>
- Kleinschmidt, A., Bichel, C. Zeki, S. and Frackowiak, R.S.J. (1998).
Human brain activity during spontaneously reversing perception of
ambiguous figures. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 1998 Dec
22;265(1413):2427-33
- Konishi, S., Wheeler, M.E., Donaldson, D.I., Buckner, R.L.. (2000)
Neural correlates of episodic retrieval success. NeuroImage: 12:
276-286.
- Kornhuber HH, Deecke L: Hirnpotentialänderungen beim Menschen vor
und nach Willkürbewegungen, dargestellt mit Magnetbandspeicherung
und Rückwärtsanalyse. Pflügers Arch. ges. Physiol. 281 (1964) 52.
- Kosslyn, S.M., Thompson, W.L. (2003). When is early visual cortex
activated during visual mental imagery? Psychol. Bull. 129
(2003)723-746.
- Kreiman, G., Koch, C. and Fried, I. (2000). Imagery neurons in the
human brain. Nature (2000) 408: 357-361
<http://www.cns.caltech.edu/~gabriel/publications/imagination1.html>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I., & Koch, C. (2001). Single neuron responses
in humans during binocular rivalry and flash suppression. Journal of
Vision, 1(3), 131a, <http://journalofvision.org/1/3/131>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I. And Koch, C. (2002) Single Neuron responses
in the human brain during flash suppression. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Science USA, 99:8378-8383
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031015091920/http://www.ai.mit.edu/projects/cbcl/publications/ps/kreimanetal_flash-suppression.pdf>
- Larsen, A., Madsen, K.H., Lund, T.E., and Bundesen, C. (2006).
Images of Illusory Motion in Primary Visual Cortex. Journal of
Cognitive Neuroscience. 2006;18:1174-1180.
- Laureys, S. et al. (2002). Brain function in the vegetative state.
Acta neurol. belg., 2002, 102, 177-185
<http://www.jsmf.org/meetings/2003/nov/LaureysANB2002.pdf>
- Lee. S, and Blake, R. (2002). V1 activity is reduced during
binocular rivalry. Journal of Vision (2002) 2, 618-626
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030722173225/http://journalofvision.org/2/9/4/article.pdf>
- Leopold, D.A. and Logothetis, N.K. (1999). Multistable phenomena:
changing views in perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 3:
254-264.
<http://www.kyb.tuebingen.mpg.de/publications/pdfs/pdf201.pdf>
- Libet, B., Alberts, E.W., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B.(1967).
Responses of Human Somatosensory Cortex to Stimuli Below Threshold
for Conscious Sensation. Science 158, 1597-1600.
- Libet, B., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B., and Pearl, D.(1979).
Subjective referral of the timing for a conscious sensory
experience. Brain, 102, pp. 192--224.
<http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/entrez/query.fcgi?holding=npg&cmd=Retrieve&db=PubMed&list_uids=427530&dopt=Abstract>
- Linden, D.E.J. (2005) The P300: Where in the Brain Is It Produced
and What Does It Tell Us? The Neuroscientist, Vol. 11, No. 6,
563-576 (2005) <http://nro.sagepub.com/cgi/reprint/11/6/563.pdf>
- Llinas, R., Ribary, U., Contreras, D. & Pedroarena, C. (1998). The
neuronal basis for consciousness. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London Ser.
B.353, 1841-1849
<http://big.cs.uiuc.edu/anncbt-papers/fall05/Llinas.the-neuronal-basis-of-consciousness.pdf>
- Logothetis, N.K., Leopold, D.A. and Sheinberg, D.L. (1996). What is
Rivalling During Binocular Rivalry. Nature, 380:621-624.
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nature/journal/v380/n6575/abs/380621a0.html>
- Loveblad, KO. et al. (1999). Silent functional magnetic resonance
imaging demonstrates focal activation in rapid eye movement sleep.
Neurology 1999;53:2193Z
- Luce, R.D. (1986). Response times: their role in inferring
elementary mental organization. Oxford University Press, New York.
- Lumer, E.D., Friston, K.J. & Rees, G. (1998) Neural correlates of
perceptual rivalry in the human brain. Science. 280(5371):1930-4.
- Macdonald, K.D., Fifkova, E., Jones, M.S. and Barth, D.S. (1998)
Focal Stimulation of the Thalamic Reticular Nucleus Induces Focal
Gamma Waves in Cortex. The Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 79 No. 1
January 1998, pp. 474--477
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/79/1/474>
- Maia, T.V. & Cleeremans, A. (2005). Consciousness: converging
insights from connectionist modeling and neuroscience. TRENDS in
Cognitive Sciences Vol.9 No.8 August 2005
<http://srsc.ulb.ac.be/axcWWW/papers/pdf/05-TICS.pdf>
- Marcel AJ. (1998). Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of
visual consciousness or visual function? Brain 1998, 121, 1565-1588.
<http://brain.oupjournals.org/cgi/reprint/121/8/1565.pdf>
- Marois, R., Yi, D-J., & Chun, M.M. (2004). The Neural Fate of
Consciously Perceived and Missed Events in the Attentional Blink.
Neuron, 41, 3: 465-472.
- Mashour, G.A., Tononi, G. and Massimini, M. (2005). Cognitive
Unbinding in Sleep and Anesthesia. Science 16 December 2005:
1768-1769.
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
<http://juno.ingentaselect.com/vl=6492085/cl=26/nw=1/rpsv/cgi-bin/cgi?body=linker&ini=nlm&reqidx=issn=0962-8452vl=264is=1380yr=1997mn=Marpg=393>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). Responses of Spectrally
Selective Cells in Macaque Area V2 to Wavelengths and Colors. J
Neurophysiol 87: 2104-2112, 2002.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/87/4/2104>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). The relationship between
cortical activation and perception investigated with invisible
stimuli. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA, 99(14):9527-9532.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/99/14/9527>
- Muckli, L., Singer, W., Zanella, F.E. and Goebel, R. (2002)
Integration of multiple motion vectors over space: an fMRI study of
transparent motion perception. Neuroimage. 2002 Aug;16(4):843-56.
- Munhall, K.G. (2001). Functional Imaging During Speech Production.
Acta Psychologica 107 (2001) 95-117.
<http://pavlov.psyc.queensu.ca/~munhallk/07_acta_version.pdf>
- Munk MHJ, Roelfsema PR, König P, Engel AK, and Singer W. (1996).
Role of reticular activation in the modulation of intracortical
synchronization Science. 272, 271-274.
- Newman, J. & Baars, B.J. (1993) A neural attentional model for
access to consciousness: A Global Workspace perspective. Concepts in
Neuroscience, 4:2, 255-290
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000073/>
- Nieuwenhuis S, Aston-Jones G & Cohen JD (2005). Decision making, the
P3, and the locus coeruleus-norepinephrine system. Psychological
Bulletin, 131(4), 510-532.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051117045339/http://www.csbmb.princeton.edu/conte/pdfs/project5/Proj5Pub06.pdf>
- Nørretranders, T. (1991) Consciousness: The User Illusion
(translated from Danish), Penguin Books,
; 1999 revision:
<http://www.worldcat.org/title/user-illusion-cutting-consciousness-down-to-size/oclc/41311618>.
- Pantev C (1995) Evoked and induced gamma-band activity of the human
cortex. Brain Topogr 7:321-330
- Pasley BN, Mayes LC, Schultz RT (2004) Subcortical discrimination of
unperceived objects during binocular rivalry. Neuron 2004,
42:163-172.
- Pessoa, L. (2005) To what extent are emotional visual stimuli
processed without attention and awareness? Current Opinion in
Neurobiology 2005, 15:188-196
<http://web.archive.org/web/20060623004726/http://www.brown.edu/Research/LCE/publications_files/Pessoa_CONB_2005.pdf>
- Pettigrew, J.D. (2001) Searching for the Switch: Neural Bases for
Perceptual Rivalry Alternations. Brain and Mind 2: 85-118, 2001.
<http://www.uq.edu.au/nuq/jack/searchswitch.pdf>
- Raymond, J. E, Shapiro, K. L., & Arnell, K. M. (1992). Temporary
suppression of visual processing in an RSVP task: An attentional
blink? Journal of Experimental Psychology. Human Perception and
Performance, 18 (3), 849-60.
- Rektor, I., Bares, M., Kanovsky, P. and Kukleta, M. (2001)
Intracerebral recording of readiness potential induced by a complex
motor task. Movement Disorders, Volume 16, Issue 4, Pages 698-704
- Rees, G., Kreiman, G., & Koch, C. (2002) Neural Correlates of
Consciousness in Humans. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3, 261
-270 (2002)
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nrn/journal/v3/n4/abs/nrn783_fs.html&dynoptions=doi1069842948>
- Rensink, RA. (2000). When Good Observers Go Bad: Change Blindness,
Inattentional Blindness, and Visual Experience. PSYCHE, 6(09),
August 2000.
<http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v6/psyche-6-09-rensink.html>
- Roy, J.E. & Prichep, L.S. (2005) The Anesthetic Cascade: A Theory of
How Anesthesia Suppresses Consciousness Anesthesiology: Volume
102(2) February 2005 pp 447--471
<http://www.anesthesiology.org/pt/re/anes/fulltext.00000542-200502000-00030.htm>
- Schiff, N.D., & Plum F. 1999. The Neurology of Impaired
Consciousness: Global Disorders and Implied Models. \[Target
article\]. Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness.
<http://www.phil.vt.edu/assc/niko.html>
- Schiff ND, Plum F. (2000) The Role of Arousal and \"Gating\" Systems
in the Neurology of Impaired Consciousness. Journal of
Neurophysiology. 17(5):438-452. (
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030924010953/http://www.uni-tuebingen.de/cog/lehre/ss2003/seminar_bewusstsein/epapers/SchiffPlum00.pdf>
- Sheinberg, D.L. and Logothetis, N.K. (1997). The role of temporal
cortical areas in perceptual organization. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA 94, 3408-3413. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/7/3408>
- Simons, D.J. & Rensink, RA. (2005). Change blindness: Past, present,
and future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol.9, pp16--20, No.1
January 2005.
<http://www.psych.ubc.ca/~rensink/publications/download/S&R-TICS-05a.pdf>
- Singer, W. & Gray, C.W. (1995). Visual feature integration and the
temporal correlation hypothesis. Annu. Rev. Neurosci., 18,
pp. 555--86, 1995.
- Singer, W. (2001). Consciousness and the Binding Problem. Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences 929:123-146 (2001)
- Solms, Mark (2000) DREAMING AND REM SLEEP ARE CONTROLLED BY
DIFFERENT BRAIN MECHANISMS, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23
(6): 793.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/Preprints/OldArchive/bbs.solms.html>
- Soon, C.S., Brass, M., Heinze, H-J. and Haynes, J-D. (2008).
Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain.
Nature Neuroscience 11, 543 - 545 (2008)
- Sukov, W. & Barth, D.S. (2001). Cellular Mechanisms of Thalamically
Evoked Gamma Oscillations in Auditory Cortex. J Neurophysiol 85:
1235-1245, 2001;
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/85/3/1235>
- Takeuchi, T., Miyasita, A., Inugami, M. & Yamamoto, Y. (2001).
Intrinsic dreams are not produced without REM sleep mechanisms:
evidence through elicitation of sleep onset REM periods. Journal of
Sleep Research Volume 10 Issue 1 Page 43 - March 2001
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tamás, G., Buh, E.H., Lörincz, A., and Somogyi, P. (2000).
Proximally targeted GABAergic synapses and gap junctions synchronize
cortical interneurons. Nature Neuroscience volume 3 no 4 April 2000.
<http://mrcanu.pharm.ox.ac.uk/pdfs/TamasNatureNeurosci2000.pdf>
- Tanaka, Y. & Sagi, D. (1998). A perceptual memory for low contrast
visual signals. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol 95:12729-12733.
<http://www.weizmann.ac.il/~masagi/TS98b.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2001). Competing Theories of Binocular Rivalry: A Possible
Resolution. Brain and Mind 2: 55-83, 2001
<http://web.archive.org/web/20041212094810/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_Brain&Mind2001.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual Awareness. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030723135239/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
- Tootell, R.B., Reppas, J.B., Dale, A.M., Look, R.B., Sereno, M.I.,
Malach, R., Brady, T.J. and Rosen, B.R. (1995) Visual motion
aftereffect in human cortical area MT revealed by functional
magnetic resonance imaging. Nature. 1995 May 11;375(6527):139-41.
- Tononi, G., Srinivasan, R., Russell, P.D. & Edelman, G.M. (1998).
Investigating neural correlates of conscious perception by
frequency-tagged neuromagnetic responses . Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA. Vol. 95, Issue 6, 3198-3203, March 17, 1998
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/95/6/3198>
- Thornton, I.M., Pinto, J. and Shiffrar, M. (1998).
THE VISUAL PERCEPTION OF HUMAN LOCOMOTION. COGNITIVE NEUROPSYCHOLOGY,
1998, 15 (6/7/8 ), 535-552.
<http://psychology.rutgers.edu/~mag/TPS98.pdf>
- Traub, D.R., Whittington, M.A., Buhl, E.H., Jefferys, J.G.R., &
Faulkner, H.J. (1999). On the Mechanism of the Frequency Shift in
Neuronal Oscillations Induced in Rat Hippocampal Slices by Tetanic
Stimulation. The Journal of Neuroscience, February 1, 1999,
19(3):1088-1105
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/3/1088>
- Traub, R.D. (2003). Fast Oscillations and Epilepsy. Epilepsy Curr.
2003 May; 3(3): 77-79.
<http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/articlerender.fcgi?artid=321178>
- Trevena J & Miller, J (2002) Cortical Movement Preparation before
and after a Conscious Decision to Move. Consciousness and Cognition,
Volume 11, Issue 2, June 2002, Pages 162-190
- Trevena, J & Miller, J (2009) Brain preparation before a voluntary
action: Evidence against unconscious movement initiation. Conscious
Cogn. 2009 Sep 5. \[Epub ahead of print\]
- Tse, P.U., Susana Martinez-Conde, S., Schlegel, A.A. and Macknik,
S.L. (2005). Visibility, visual awareness, and visual masking of
simple unattended targets are confined to areas in the occipital
cortex beyond human V1/V2. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA November 22,
2005 vol. 102 no. 47. 17178-17183.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/102/47/17178>
- Uchida, N., Kepecs, A. and Mainen, Z.F. (2006) Seeing at a glance,
smelling in a whiff: rapid forms of perceptual decision making.
Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 7. 485-491.
- Uchida, N & Mainen, Z.F. (2003) Speed and accuracy of olfacory
discrimination in the rat. Nature Neurosci. 6, 1224-1229.
- Vogel, E.K., Luck, S.J. & Shapiro, K.L. (1998) Electrophysiological
Evidence for a Postperceptual Locus of Suppression During the
Attentional Blink. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
Perception and Performance 1998, Vol. 24. No. 6,1656-1674
<http://web.archive.org/web/20050304211722/http://www.psychology.uiowa.edu/faculty/Luck/lucklab/pdfs/Vogel_1998_JEPHPP.pdf>
- Wehrle, R., Czisch, M., Kaufmann, C., Wetter, T.C., Holsboer, F.,
Auer, D.P., and Pollmacher, T. (2005). Rapid eye movement-related
brain activation in human sleep: a functional magnetic resonance
imaging study. NeuroReport 16:853-857
<http://www.univie.ac.at/mcogneu/lit/wehrle.pdf>
- White, NS., Alkire, MT. (2003). Impaired thalamocortical
connectivity in humans during
general-anesthetic-induced unconsciousness. NeuroImage. Volume 19, Issue
2 , June 2003, Pages 402-411. <http://smallurl.com?i=2597>
(http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/B6WNP-48GP5CG-5/1/cedb33dc0bec4301d1960c7c27cea70f)
- Wheeler, M.E., Buckner, R.L.. (2003) Functional dissociation among
components
of remembering: control, perceived oldness, and content. J. Neurosci.
23, 3869-3880.
- Williams LM, Liddell BJ, Rathjen J, Brown KJ, Shevrin H, Gray JA,
Phillips M, Young A & Gordon E (2004). Mapping the time course of
nonconscious and conscious perception of fear: An integration of
central and peripheral measures. Human Brain Mapping,21, 64 - 74
<http://psychmed.iop.kcl.ac.uk/neuroscience-and-emotion/downloads/46.pdf>
- Wunderlich, K. Schneider, K.A., & Kastner, S. (2005).Neural
correlates of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate
nucleus. Nature Neuroscience 8, 1595 - 1602 (2005)
- Yamamoto, T. & Katayama, Y. (2005). Deep brain stimulation therapy
for the vegetative state. in Neuropsychol Rehabil. 2005 Jul-Sep ;
15(3-4): 406-13
- Zeki, S., & Bartel, A. (1999). Toward a Theory of Visual
Consciousness. Consciousness & Cognition, 8, 225-259.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 2#The integration delay
*Contributors: please include full data in the references section for
all references in the text.*
```{=html}
<div class="noprint">
```
Home
```{=html}
</div>
```
## Perceptual \"filling in\"
Perceptual \"filling in\" occurs when visual properties such as
textures, colours, brightness or motion are extended in the visual field
to areas where they do not have corresponding events in the world.
The filling in of the blind spot by the properties of the field in the
contralateral eye has already been discussed. The part of the visual
field represented by the blind spot is also \"filled in\" in the case of
monocular vision.
![](Constudblindill.png "Constudblindill.png")
Shut the right eye and focus on the pink cross with the left eye, if the
head is moved towards the pink cross there is a point at which the
yellow disk disappears but the white lines are still present. In this
\"filling in\" the visual field does not appear to be distorted.
Fiorani *et al.* (1992) developed a technique for probing the cortical
blind spot using vertical and horizontal bar stimuli. Matsumoto &
komatsu (2005) used this technique on macaque monkeys. In the monocular
case they found that as a bar was moved across the visual field so that
it crossed the blind spot there was a sudden change in neural activity
in the deep layers of the neurons in the blind spot area of V1. When the
bar was moved across the same part of the visual field of the
contralateral eye the neural activity in the blind spot area increased
steadily as the bar was moved. The authors found that there were neurons
in the deep layers of blind spot cortex that had elongated receptive
fields that could respond to stimuli outside the blind spot and transfer
this activation into the blind spot cortex.
Filling in of a slightly different type occurs in \"scotoma\". In
scotoma an area of the retina is damaged and unresonsive to visual
stimuli, immediately after the damage patients report an area of visual
field that is unresponsive to stimuli. After several months patients
report that the area of field represented by the scotoma contains visual
properties related to the physical world surrounding the area that would
have formed an image on the scotoma. This results in a distortion of the
visual field. (see for instance Gilbert(1993)). Direct measurements of
activity in cortical area V1 show that the neurons that represented the
area of the scotoma become sensitive to activity in the surrounding
visual field. At the cortical level the scotoma is literally \"filled
in\".
There are many stimuli that cause \"filling in\". These stimuli are
known as \"illusions\" because they produce phenomenal experience that
has no correlate in the world outside the body. In the \"neon colour
spreading illusion\" a lightly coloured circle appears where there
should be a white background. Sasaki and Watanabe (2004) used fMRI to
show that the part of the topographic map in cortical area V1
corresponding to the light coloured circle was activated.
![](Constudneon.jpg "Constudneon.jpg")
Fiorani, M., Rosa, M.G.P., Gattas, R. & Rocha-Miranda, C.E. (1992).
Dynamic surrounds of receptive fields in primate striate cortex: a
physiological basis for perceptual completion? Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
89, 8547-8551. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/abstract/89/18/8547>
Gilbert, C.D. (1993). Circuitry, architecture and functional dynamics of
visual cortex.
Matsumoto, M & Komatsu, H. (2005). Neural responses in the macaque V1 to
bar stimuli with various lengths presented on the blind spot. J
neurophysiol. 93. 2374-2387.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/abstract/93/5/2374>
Sasaki, Y & Watanabe, T. The primary visual cortex fills in colour.
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 101, 18251-18256. (2004).
## Binocular Rivalry, Pattern Rivalry and Binocular Fusion
Sir Charles Wheatstone (1838) was the first scientist to systematically
investigate binocular rivalry. Binocular rivalry occurs when different
images are presented to the left and right eyes. The subject sees
successively one image, a combined image and then the other image. The
swapping of images can take a second or more. Binocular rivalry is of
interest in consciousness research because the parts of the brain that
contain the dominant image should also be those parts that are
contributing to conscious experience. Binocular rivalry involves at
least two components; the first switches from one image to a merged
image and then to the other image and the second permits the view to be
part of conscious experience.
![](Constudrival.png "Constudrival.png")
The switching of one image for another may involve selecting one of the
images as the percept or selecting one of the eyes. Blake *et al.*
(1979) performed an experiment in which subjects could change the image
at a given eye by pressing a button. When a particular image became
dominant they pressed a button to change the image at the eye receiving
the dominant image for the non-dominant image. They found that the
subjects immediately experienced the second image as the dominant image.
This suggests that binocular rivalry is selecting between eyes rather
than images. Lehky in 1988 proposed that the switching may be occurring
as a result of feedback between visual cortical area V1 and the Lateral
Geniculate Nucleus (a thalamic relay - see Carandini *et al.* 2002) and
Blake in 1989 also proposed that the switching occurred at the level of
area V1. (Visual cortical area V1 receives visual input direct from the
LGN.)
Tong (2001) has argued that, in humans, the switching of images in
binocular rivalry may occur at the earliest levels in the visual cortex.
In particular, Tong and Engel (2001) used an elegant technique measuring
the activity in the visual cortex that represents the blind spot of the
eye to show that almost complete switching to the dominant image occurs
at the level of visual cortical area V1. In support of this idea of
switching at the level of V1 or even before the cortex, Kreimann *et
al.* (2001, 2002) used direct electrode recordings in human cortex and
found that the activity of most neurons changed with the percept. Other
experiments have not shown a single locus in the brain where the
suppressed sensory information gets switched out (Blake & Logothetis
2002, Leopold & Logothetis 1996, Gail et al., 2004).
Functional MRI has also shown cortical activity outside of sensory
visual cortex related to both images in binocular rivalry. Lumer *et
al.* (1998) found that only the fronto-parietal areas of cortex switched
with the percept, Fang & He (2005) found that activity relating to both
suppressed and unsuppressed images were present in the dorsal stream of
the visual system. Wunderlich *et al.* (2005) and Haynes *et al.* (2005)
have both found suppression at the level of the lateral geniculate
nucleus using fMRI in humans.
Pasley *et al.* (2004) have shown that, even during suppression, fearful
faces can produce activity in the amygdala (see Pessoa (2005) for a
review).
Rivalry alternations seem to be the result of widespread activity
changes that cover large parts of the brain, including but not
necessarily originating at the earliest sensory stages of visual
processing. Most investigators have found that, once switching has
occurred, there are areas of the brain that contain activity that is
solely related to the percept but this varies from most of the cortex to
largely more frontal regions depending upon the study. The most likely
explanation for binocular rivalry is that the switching occurs at the
level of the LGN as a result of feedback from the cortex.
Pattern Rivalry is also of interest in consciousness research for the
same reasons as binocular rivalry. In pattern rivalry a figure may have
two or more forms that replace each other. Typical examples of such
figures are the Necker cube and Rubin\'s face-vase. The similarity of
the time course of the switching between percepts in binocular rivalry
and pattern rivalry has led many authors to suggest that these involve
the same mechanism. Logothetis *et al.* (1996) used novel dichoptic
stimuli (different images to each eyes) to produce a form of rivalry
that seems to involve switching at levels in the cerebral cortex that
are more distal to the sensory stimulus than V1. Leopold and Logothetis
(1999), on the basis of their work with monkeys, state that \"..many
neurons throughout the visual system, both monocular and binocular,
continue to respond to a stimulus even when it is perceptually
suppressed.\". Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998) investigated pattern rivalry
with MRI and found activity in higher order visual areas during change
of dominant pattern. Pettigrew (2001) also describes effects on rivalry
due to thought and mood that may require involvement of large areas of
cortex in the switching operation and stresses the way that V1
represents different visual fields in different hemispheres of the brain
so that inter-hemispheric switching must also be considered.
It seems likely that the change of dominant pattern or percept is
associated with higher level cortical activity but once the dominant
percept is established many of the visually responsive neurons in the
cortex are switched over to the new percept. This might account for the
similarities in timing of binocular and pattern rivalry and the
disparate results found by the various groups of authors. In the words
of Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998):
\"The transient activity fluctuations we found suggest that perceptual
metastability elicited by ambiguous stimuli is associated with rapid
redistributions of neural activity between separate specialized cortical
and subcortical structures.\"
Which permits both the idea of selecting particular eyes or percepts,
perhaps by feedback that switches a thalamic relay on the basis of
cortical processing of patterns. Once the cortex has switched the
thalamic relay most of the neurons in V1 would become exposed to the
dominant percept but there would still be a few neurons in the cortical
visual system receiving data from the non dominant image.
The investigations of binocular and pattern rivalry provide evidence
that conscious visual experience is probably distal to V1 (i.e.: cortex
or thalamus).
Perceptual rivalry may be part of complex decision making rather than
being simply a switch to blank out unwelcome input. It is clear from the
Rubin face-vase that pattern rivalry is linked to recognition and would
involve a complex delineation of forms within cortical processing. This
would suggest that many areas of cortex should be involved before a
particular percept is made dominant. Pettigrew (2001) argues that
rivalry is the result of a complex phenomenon rather than being simply a
switching event. Pettigrew\'s discovery that laughter abolishes rivalry
also points to a complex cortical system for switching percepts.
Pettigrew proposes that complex cortical processes control rivalry and
that the actual switching of percepts is performed sub-cortically in the
Ventral Tegmental Area. He concludes his review of the problem by noting
that \"Rivalry may thus reflect fundamental aspects of perceptual
decision making..\" Pettigrew (2001).
Another effect, known as \"binocular fusion\", provides further
compelling evidence for the non-conscious nature of the cerebral cortex.
In binocular fusion images from both eyes are fused together to create a
single image in experience. Moutoussis and Zeki (2002) used a form of
binocular fusion in which images of faces were flashed at 100ms
intervals to both eyes simultaneously. When both eyes received images of
the same colour the subject could see the faces but when one eye
received a green image on a red background and the other a red image on
a green background the subjects reported seeing a uniform yellow field
that contained no faces.
fMRI scans of the subject\'s brains showed that when both eyes were
exposed to images of the same colour the part of the brain that deals
with faces was active and when each eye received images of different
colours the same areas of brain showed activity. In other words the
cortex contained strong activity related to faces whether or not faces
were experienced. Moutoussis and Zeki found a similar effect when they
used images of houses instead of images of faces. The authors concluded
that: \"The present study further suggests that there are no separate
processing and perceptual areas but rather that the same cortical
regions are involved in both the processing and, when certain levels of
activation are reached and probably in combination with the activation
of other areas as well, the generation of a conscious visual percept\".
This conclusion does not seem to be supported by the data. There is no
evidence that any area of cortex contains the percept itself. The
experiment shows that the cortex contains data relating to both red and
green faces which suggests that the cortex is not the site of the
conscious percept. The percept is most likely distal to the cortex
perhaps in the thalamus or some other area that receives cortical
sensory output.
It is interesting that Fries *et al.* (1997) found that neurons that
were activated by the dominant image in binocular rivalry fired
synchronously whereas those that were activated by the non-dominant
image did not. Thalamocorticothalamic oscillations are the most likely
source for synchronising neurons over whole areas of cortex, suggesting
that the conscious percept is located in the thalamus rather than the
cortex.
## Synchronisation of Neural Processes
Our experience seems to contain entities with their attributes attached
to them at the correct places in space and time. When a dog barks we see
its jaws open at the same time as the bark and both jaws and bark are at
the same location. We take this for granted but the brain must be
engaging in some complex processing to achieve this synchronised and
appropriately positioned set of objects and events. The illustration
below shows the two basic processes that might be used to synchronise
events between the different specialised processors in the cerebral
cortex and brain in general.
![](Constudsynch.gif "Constudsynch.gif")
In the first option a complete model of sensation, dream etc. may be
created and then allowed to become part of conscious experience. In the
second model events are released into experience as fast as possible but
are synchronous when recalled, having been synchronised in a storage
buffer. There is a third option in which there is no synchronisation of
events so that the output from different processors would occur at
different times.
The \'experience buffer\' would be a volume of brain in which a
succession of events could be recorded. The buffer might either be
updated in steps, the previous content being discarded, or continuously
updated with the oldest content being lost continuously.
In the first option events from different processes would always appear
to be simultaneous unless the experience buffer were updated as a series
of steps in which case any changes at around the moment of updating
might appear in successive buffers. For instance, if change of position
were processed before change in colour a circle on a screen that changed
from green to red at the start of a motion might seem to be briefly
green during the motion and then turn red.
In the second model events from different processors might appear
asynchronous at the moment of experience but synchronous when recalled.
Colour vision and motion vision are processed in different parts of the
visual cortex and in distinct parts of visual cortical areas V1 and V2.
They are different processes and hence ideal for studying the
synchronisation of cortical activity. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997)
presented subjects with moving coloured squares on a computer screen
that changed from red to green or vice versa as they changed direction
of movement. It was found that subjects seemed to perceive changes in
colour some 70-80 msecs before they perceived a change in the direction
of motion of the squares. Further work by Arnold *et al.* (2001) and
Arnold and Clifford (2001) have confirmed that colour changes seem to be
perceived before motion. Arnold and Clifford (2001) also found a
quantitative relationship between the colour/motion asynchrony and the
direction of change of motion, complete reversals of direction giving
rise to the greatest asynchrony between the detection of colour and
motion changes.
Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) conclude by stating that the asynchrony of
neural processes shows that \"..the perception of each attribute is
solely the result of the activity in the specialised system involved in
its processing..\". It seems more likely that the experiments simply
show that slow neural processes are not synchronised before they become
percepts (the third option above). The experiments are excellent
evidence for the concept of the cortex as a set of specialised
processors that deliver their output asynchronously to some other place
where the output becomes a percept.
These experiments on colour and motion suggest that there is no
synchronisation between the processes that deal with these two aspects
of vision. Another set of experiments by Clifford *et al.* (2003)
supports this idea of processing being asynchronous. They asked subjects
to perform a variety of judgements of when visual events occurred and
found that the degree of synchrony of one visual event with another
depends on the type of judgement. Different judgements probably use
processors in different areas of cortex and the output from these
arrives asynchronously at the part of the brain that supports the
percept.
When the percept is formed there must be feedback to the cortical
processes that create its content. Otherwise it would not be possible to
report about the percept and the cortex would be unable to direct
processing to the percept in preference to other, non-conscious cortical
data.
Although slow processes (20 milliseconds to 1 second) do not seem to be
synchronised there is some evidence for very rapid synchronisation.
Andrews *et al.* (1996) revisited a problem raised by the famous
physiologist Charles Sherrington. Sherrington considered the phenomenon
of \'flicker fusion\' in which a flickering light appears to be a
continuous steady light if it flashes on and off at frequencies of about
45 Hz or higher. He reasoned that if the images from both eyes are
brought together to form a single image then the frequency at which a
flickering light appears to be steady should depend on whether one or
two eyes are used. Flicker fusion should occur if each eye receives
alternate flashes at only half the normal flicker fusion frequency. The
flicker should disappear if the left eye receives flashes at 23 pulses
per second and the right eye receives alternate flashes at 23 pulses per
second. When Sherrington performed the experiment he found that this was
not the case, using approximate figures, each eye required 46 pulses per
second for fusion to occur. Sherrington proposed that the flicker fusion
in alternate binocular presentation was occurring \"psychically\",
outside of normal physiological processes.
Andrews *et al.* duplicated Sherrington\'s result but investigated it
further. They found that when lights were flashed in each eye
alternately at low frequences (2 Hz) the experience was the same as a
light being flashed in both eyes at this rate. At frequencies of four Hz
and higher the subjects began to report that the lights being flashed
alternately in both eyes seemed to flicker at the same rate as lights
being flashed in both eyes at half the frequency. It seemed as if a
flash in one eye followed by a flash in the other eye was being
perceived as a single flash or \"conflated\" as the authors put it. The
authors explained this effect by suggesting that the brain activity
corresponding to the flashes was sampled for a short period and any
number of flashes occurring during this period became perceived as a
single flash. The maximum rate of sampling would be about 45 Hz. This
idea is similar to option (1) above, where the buffer is filled and
emptied 40 - 50 times a second.
An experience buffer that is refreshed at 40-50 times a second might
also explain the results obtained with colour and motion asynchrony
because synchronisation between processes may well happen too quickly to
affect processes that occur at very slow rates. Singer and Gray (1995),
Singer (2001) have proposed that synchronisation between neurones at
about 45 Hz is the discriminator between those neurones with activity
that contributes to conscious experience and activity in other neurones.
A rapid refresh rate in a synchronising buffer agrees with the results
found by Fries *et al.* (1997) in which visual cortical neurones that
represent a percept underwent synchronous oscillations in the gamma
frequency range (39--63 Hz). Tononi *et al.* (1998) have also found
synchronisation of neural activity in neurones that represent the
percept.
The gamma frequency oscillations are intrinsic to the cortex but are
triggered by the thalamus and are part of the \'arousal system\'.
Readers should be wary of the term \'arousal system\' because it evokes
the idea of something waking up a conscious cortex. The cortex can be
fully active during sleep and even during pathological unconsciousness
such as persistent vegetative state so it is possible that the arousal
centres themselves or nearby structures actually host phenomenal
consciousness.
## EEG and synchronisation
If electrodes are placed on the scalp varying electrical potentials of a
few tens of microvolts can be recorded between the electrodes.
Recordings of potentials from electrodes on the scalp are known as
electroencephalograms (EEGs).
The potentials recorded in the EEG are due to postsynaptic potentials in
nerve cells. The EEG is insensitive to the activity of single cells and
occurs as a result of relatively slow, **synchronised**, changes in
large areas of cells. The differences in potential between two scalp
electrodes are largely due to depolarisation and hyperpolarisation of
the dendritic trees of cortical pyramidal cells. The folding of the
cortex (gyri) is problematical for recording and interpreting EEGs
because opposing layers of cortex can cancel any net potentials.
The EEG shows rhythmic activity. This is conventionally divided into the
following frequency bands:
Delta waves 0--4 Hz
Theta waves 4--8 Hz
Alpha waves 8--12 Hz
Beta waves \>10 Hz
Gamma waves (also called fast beta) 25--100 Hz
EEGs also contain short bursts of activity called spindles and very fast
oscillations (VFOs). Spindles last for 1--2 seconds and contain rhythmic
activity at 7--14 Hz. They are associated with the onset of sleep. The
VFOs consist of short bursts at frequencies of over 80 Hz.
When the eyes are closed the amplitude of activity from most pairs of
electrodes is increased compared with when the eyes are open. When
subjects are awake the EEG consists mainly of alpha and beta activity
with considerable low amplitude gamma when the eyes are open. In stage 1
sleep the EEG consists of theta waves, in stage 2 sleep of varied
activity and spindles, in stage 4 sleep of delta and during REM sleep of
beta and theta activity. In epileptic seizures there tends to be high
amplitude activity with pronounced synchronisation between many pairs of
electrodes.
The rhythmic electrical activity is due to cortical feedback loops,
cortico-cortical synchronisation, thalamic pacemakers and
thalamo-cortical synchronisation. VFOs have been attributed to the
activity of electrical connections between cells (dendro-dendritic gap
junctions) (Traub (2003)).
The gamma activity, centred on a frequency of 40 Hz appears to be
related to activity in cortical interneurons that form electrical
connections between their dendrites (Tamas *et al.* 2000). These
oscillations can be triggered by high frequency stimulation of the
posterior intralaminar nuclei of the thalamus (Barth and MacDonald 1996,
Sukov and Barth 2001) and as a result of activation of the reticular
system (Munk *et al.* 1996). This suggests that stimulation of cortex by
thalamic sensory relays triggers gamma band activity in the cortex. A
shift from gamma to beta waves can occur in human event related
potentials after about 0.2 secs (Pantev 1995, Traub *et al.* 1999).
The alpha activity is related to thalamic pacemakers, perhaps as a
result of intrinsic oscillatory activity in thalamic sensory relays (see
Roy & Prichep 2005 for a brief review). Theta activity, which occurs
during some cognitive tasks and mental arithmetic involves a loop from
the cortex to the non-specific thalamic nuclei. Delta activity seems to
be endogenous to cortex when input is suppressed during sleep. Beta
activity is due to cortico-cortical interactions, often after a brief
period of gamma activation. It should be noted that gamma and beta
activity can be expressed as impulses in cortico-thalamic pathways and
that when cortical and thalamic activity is correlated there is a
conscious state. In other words gamma or beta waves in the cortex are
not correlates of consciousness on their own - see for instance Laureys
*et al.* (2002).
## Event related potentials
After a sudden event there are a characteristic set of changes in EEG
activity known as **event related potentials** or ERPs. The time course
of the ERP is shown in the diagram below.
![](Constudevent.png "Constudevent.png")
ERPs occur in response to novel stimuli and are also produced by brief
transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS)(Iramina *et al.* 2002). The slow
component is known as the P3 or P300 phase of the ERP. It is due to
activation of areas of the brain that are relatively remote from the
primary sensory areas of brain.
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) have reviewed the origin of the P300 ERP:
\"To summarize, convergent evidence suggests that P3-like activity can
be recorded in several, widely separated brain areas. These include some
medial temporal and subcortical structures (e.g., the hippocampal
formation, amygdala, and thalamus), but these structures are unlikely to
contribute directly to the scalp-recorded P3.\". According to
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) the recorded P300 may be due to
temporo-parietal and prefrontal cortical activity. Linden (2005) has
also concluded that widespread, but specific, cortical activation is
correlated with the recorded P300 ERP.
The generator of the P300 is still obscure. Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005)
consider that the Locus coeruleus, a nucleus in the pons that regulates
task related attention and part of the sleep-wake cycle, may be
responsible. In line with this, Mashour *et al.* (2005) have discovered
that TMS induced P300 activity is reduced in unconscious states.
Whether the P300 is related to Libet\'s 0.5 second delay is still
obscure but the discovery that the P300 occurs in association with
subliminal stimuli (stimuli that do not enter awareness)(Bernat *et al.*
2001) suggests that it is associated with non-conscious cortical
processing. Williams *et al.* (2004), in an investigation of subliminal
and supraliminal fear perception, found that \"conscious fear perception
was distinguished by a more prominent N4, peaking around 400 msec\"; the
N4 component follows the P300 component in the succession of phases of
the ERP. Williams *et al.* considered that the earlier phases in the ERP
are probably related to non-conscious processing. In contrast Vogel *et
al.* (1998) found that suppression of the P300 was associated with
suppression of awareness.
## The integration delay
Psychological experiments often involve binary decisions where subjects
give one of two outputs in response to stimuli. It is found that if the
stimuli are made increasingly noisy or complex the response time tends
to increase. Psychophyicists have developed various mathematical models
to explain the increased response times due to noise such as the
Integrator and Accumulator models (cf: Luce(1986)). These models have
been fairly successful when explaining experiments such as judging the
net direction of movement of sets of dots on a screen when the dots are
given semi-random paths and different brightness etc. In these
circumstances it can take up to 2 seconds for an accurate decision.
There are many tasks however where the accuracy of decision making does
not improve after about 300 milliseconds. The accuracy of the
performance of rats when choosing between two alternatives when reacting
to odours peaks at about 300 ms (Uchida and Mainen(2003), Abraham *et
al.* (2004)). The accuracy of humans when performing vernier acuity
tasks, line detection, contrast sensitivity, motion velocity
discrimination and stereoscopic depth discrimination seems to peak at
300ms (Uchida *et al.* 2006).
Uchida, Kepecs and Mainen (2006) suggest that \"rapid and short
integration time is a sensible strategy for rapid processing of
low-level sensory information in order to form more complex sensory
images, both in vision and olfaction.\" Whether these authors regard
these derived sensory images as the content of consciousness is not
mentioned. The authors propose that the 300ms optimal integration time
may be partly due to the mechanics of sniffing (a sniff takes about
125-200ms) and the nature of optical fixation (inter-saccade intervals
are typically 200-400 ms ). The authors note that the animal or human
could, in principle, choose to integrate over longer intervals but if it
is moving this may not lead to information that is current for changed
circumstances.
An optimal processing time of about 300 ms would be consistent with the
delays observed before conscious awareness occurs in response to a
stimulus - an interval required to form \"more complex sensory images\".
## Global Workspace Theory
Global Workspace Theory is the idea that somewhere in the brain there is
a facility that integrates the processes that occur in the various
separate areas of the brain. The theory was first proposed by Descartes
as the *sensus communis*, the common sense, but the modern form of the
theory dispenses with the idea of a point soul looking at the brain. In
modern Global Workspace theory it is proposed that an area of brain
receives input from most of the cerebral cortex and broadcasts its
outputs to all of the unconscious modular information processors in the
brain.
Modern Global Workspace Theory has been championed by Baars (1983,
1988).
There is increasing evidence for a Global Workspace or Global Workspaces
in the brain. Much of this evidence comes from fMRI, single unit and
magnetoencephalography studies in which it is shown that non-conscious
or subliminal processing mainly occupies primary, sensory cortex whereas
conscious processing occupies large areas of cerebral cortex.
In binocular rivalry the stimulus that is consciously perceived is
responsible for relatively intense activation of large areas of brain
whereas the non-conscious stimulus is often suppressed (see above and
Sheinberg & Logothetis (1997), Tononi *et al.* (1998)). The suppression
is likely to occur in the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei which suggests a
role for the Thalamic Reticular Nuclei, which modulate LGN activity, in
the control of the percept.
### Masking and visual awareness
Word masking has also been used to investigate the idea of a Global
Workspace. When a word is presented on its own for a few tens of
milliseconds it remains readable but if it is immediately succeeded by,
or accompanied by, another word it becomes indistinct or invisible. This
effect is known as \"word masking\". Vogel *et al.* (1998) have
investigated a version of word masking known as the \"attentional
blink\". They found that when stimuli became invisible the P3 component
of the Event Related Potential, which peaks at around 300-500 millisecs
after a stimulus, was completely suppressed. The P3 component of the ERP
has been related to the lodging of data in working memory and also to
gamma band activity in the EEG. This strongly suggests the involvement
of a cortico-thalamic loop in the \"attentional blink\". The delay of
0.3 to 0.5 secs is typical of the time required for conscious awareness
(see above).
Word masking in conjunction with fMRI and Event Related Potential (ERP)
recordings has been used by Dehaene *et al.* (2001) to expose control by
a central mechanism. It was found that masked words activate mainly the
visual cortex and ventral stream (inferior temporal lobe) whereas
visible words also activated distant parietal, prefrontal and cingulate
sites.
Dehaene *et al.* (2003) and found that the dynamics of the loss of
visibility of words in an attentional blink experiment could be modelled
by a simulated cortico-thalamic loop. In their simulation a distributed
cortical process determined which events would receive attention and the
system used the thalamic gating systems to exclude those that did not
receive attention.
Tse *et al.* (2005) have used purely visual stimuli in masking
experiments and concluded that, in the case of purely visual stimuli,
the neural correlates of awareness were limited to the occipital cortex:
\"We suggest that there are both lower and upper bounds within the
visual hierarchy for the processing of visual masking and the
maintenance of visual awareness of simple unattended targets; the lower
bound is at least as high as the border between V2 and V3, and the upper
bound is within the occipital lobe, possibly somewhere downstream of
V4.\"
This discovery would mean that activation of large areas of cortex are
unnecessary for awareness.
Melloni *et al.* (2007) compared compared the electrophysiological
responses related to the processing of visible and invisible words in a
delayed matching to sample task. Both perceived and nonperceived words
caused a similar increase of local (gamma) oscillations in the EEG, but
only perceived words induced a transient long-distance synchronization
of gamma oscillations across widely separated regions of the brain.
After this transient period of temporal coordination, the electrographic
signatures of conscious and unconscious processes continue to diverge.
Only words reported as perceivedinduced (1) enhanced theta oscillations
over frontal regions during the maintenance interval, (2) an increase of
the P300 component of the event-related potential, and (3) an increase
in power and phase synchrony of gamma oscillationsbefore the anticipated
presentation of the test word. We propose that the critical process
mediating the access to conscious perception is the earlytransient
global increase of phase synchrony of oscillatory activity in the
gammafrequency.
Melloni L, Molina C, Pena M, Torres D, Singer W, Rodriguez E. (2007).
Synchronization of neural activity across cortical areas correlates
withconscious perception.J Neurosci. 2007 Mar 14;27(11):2858-65.
### Attention and the global workspace
Baars (2002) in his review of evidence for the Global Workspace Theory
quotes many other experiments that show activation of larger areas of
cortex in response to conscious stimuli compared with unconscious or
subliminal stimuli.The effect is also seen in change blindness, learning
and attention. Newman and Baars (1993) consider that the \"workspace\"
is fairly global in the brain:
\"This Neural Global Workspace (NGW) model views conscious processes in
terms of a globally integrative brain system. The neural circuitry
contributing to this system is not only widely distributed across the
neocortex, but includes key corticothalamic and midbrain circuits as
well. These cortico-subcortical circuits are hypothesized to be critical
to understanding the mechanisms of attentional control that provide an
essential basis for the conscious processing of information\".
However they focus particularly on the role of the thalamic Reticular
Nucleus and cortico-thalamic connectivity in the control of attention.
Other ideas for the location of the Global Workspace are the idea of
Singer et al. that gamma synchrony controls access to the content of
consciousness and Llinas et al. (1998) that the thalamus is the hub
through which communication occurs between areas of cortex.
One of the problems with Global Workspace theory is that it suggests
that attention, working memory, cognitive control and consciousness may
all be in the same area of the brain. It is likely that the mechanisms
of attention, working memory, and cognitive control may involve several,
interlinked systems perhaps co-opting the basal ganglia in the process.
In view of this Maia and Cleeremans (2005) propose that \".. attention,
working memory, cognitive control and consciousness are not distinct
functions implemented by separate brain systems. Attempting to find
separate neural correlates for each may therefore be the wrong approach.
Instead, we suggest that they should be understood in terms of the
dynamics of global competition, with biasing from PFC (prefrontal
cortex).\". The inclusion by Maia and Cleeremans of consciousness with
distributed attention, working memory and cognitive control is
reminiscent of Zeki & Bartel\'s idea of microconsciousness.
It should be noted that, in common with Libet\'s data, the percept seems
to be available to phenomenal consciousness some 0.3 to 0.5 secs after a
stimulus; this suggests that whatever determines the content of
phenomenal consciousness operates before events become part of
phenomenal consciousness. This relegates phenomenal consciousness from
being a controller of attention to being the recipient of content that
is the subject of attention. This finding is consistent with the
philosophical problem of the **apparently** epiphenomenal nature of
phenomenal consciousness.
Given the data on the timing of conscious awareness it seems that there
may be two \"workspaces\", an active workspace that models the world,
discarding and suppressing data during rivalry, and a passive workspace
that receives the final, edited product. The active workspace would
correlate with the cortical systems stressed by Dehaene *et al.* and
Maia and Cleermans although, given the results of Tse et al., the
workspace would be limited to small zones of cortex. The loading of the
passive workspace with the output of the active workspace would
correlate with thalamo-cortical activity during component P3 of the ERP
in which data is transferred from the cortex to the thalamus. This
workspace might constitute the source for reports of the content of
phenomenal consciousness.
Llinas *et al.* (1998) have proposed two parallel cortico-thalamic
attentional systems, one of which is related to the thalamic specific
nuclei and the other to the thalamic non-specific nuclei, especially the
ILN. The non-specific system would be related to consciousness itself.
## The \"cognitive map\" and the neural basis of perceptual space
Our bodies appear to be mobile within a constant space. We walk around a
room; the room does not rotate around us. The constancy of the location
of things gives us the feeling that we are directly viewing a constant
world. But how does the brain provide a constant world rather than a
world that rotates with the movement of the sense organs? Why is our
view of the world when we move our eyes so different from the disturbing
flow of images that occur when a video camera is waved around? Do our
brains contain a constant \"cognitive map\" (O\'Keefe and Nadel 1978) of
our surroundings?
Mittelstaedt & Mittelstaedt (1980, 1982) discovered that female gerbils
were able to recover their pups in darkened surroundings by searching in
a semi random fashion on the outbound journey and then proceeding
directly back to the nest on the inbound journey. The direct journey
back to the nest seemed to be due to an integration of the various
directions taken on the outward journey (**path integration**). If the
equipment being explored by the mother gerbil was rotated very slowly
the mother would make an error equivalent to the amount of rotation.
More rapid rotations that activated the vestibular system of the rat
(acceleration measurement) did not cause errors in navigation. This
demonstration that rodents could navigate accurately on the basis of
**idiothetic** cues (cues that are due to internal senses) led to
research on the neural basis of the navigation.
As early as 1971 O\'Keefe and Dostrovsky had discovered that there are
particular cells in the hippocampus that fire according to the position
of an animal in the environment. This has been complimented by research
that showed that changes in visual cues within the environment caused
changes in the firing rate of place cells in hippocampal area CA3 (.
![](Gray717.png "Gray717.png")
![](HippocampalRegions.jpg "HippocampalRegions.jpg")
!Entorhinal cortex approximately maps to areas 28 and
34{width="500"}
F. P. Battaglia and A. Treves. 1998 Attractor neural networks storing
multiple space representations: A model for hippocampal place fields.
PHYSICAL REVIEW E DECEMBER 1998 VOLUME 58, NUMBER 6
<http://www.sissa.it/~ale/Bat+98b.pdf>
Leutgeb, S., Leutgeb, J.K., Moser, M-B, and Moser, E.I. 2005. Place
cells, spatial maps and the population code for memory. Current Opinion
in Neurobiology 2005, 15:738--746.
<http://instruct1.cit.cornell.edu/courses/bionb720nejc/reprints/LeutgebEtAl2005.pdf>
Mittelstaedt, H. & Mittelstaedt, M-L. 1982. Avian Navigation. (ed. Papi,
F. & Wallraff, H.) 290-297. Springer, Berlin.
Mittelstaedt, M-L & Glasauer, S. 1991. Idiothetic Navigation in Gerbils
and Humans. Zool. Jb. Physiol. 95 (1991), 427-435
<http://web.archive.org/web/20110125132449/http://www.nefo.med.uni-muenchen.de/~sglasauer/MittelstaedtGlasauer1991.pdf>
O\'Keefe, J. & Dostrovsky, J. (1971). The hippocampus as a spatial map:
preliminary evidence from unit activity in the freely moving rat. Brain
Res. 34, 171-175.
O\'Keefe, J. & Nadel, L. (1978). The Hippocampus as a cognitive map.
(Oxford)
## Bibliography
Defining the States of Consciousness. Tassi, P., Muzet, A. (2001)
Neuroscience and Behavioural Reviews 25(2001) 175-191.
Neuroanatomy: \"Digital Slice of Life\" by Stensaas and Millhouse
<http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/subj2.html>
See also: <http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/index.html>
EEG\'s: Coles, M.G.H., Rugg, M.D. Event Related Brain Potentials: An
Introduction.
<http://whalen.psych.udel.edu/667/1.What_is_ERP/ColesRugg1995chpt1.pdf>
Visual System: Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual
Awareness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
Professor Bogen\'s Consciousness Page
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/toccons.htm>
Demonstrations of Auditory Illusions and Tricks. Yoshitaka Nakajima
<http://www.kyushu-id.ac.jp/~ynhome/ENG/Demo/illusions2nd.html>
## References
- Abraham, N.M. (2004) Maintaining accuracy at the expense of speed:
stimulus similarity defines odor discrimination time in mice. Neuron
44, 865-876.
- Aleman, A., Ramsey, N., Van Honk, J.E., Kessels, R.P.C., Hoogduin,
J., Schutter, D.L.G., Postma, A., Kahn, R.S., De Haan, E.H.F.
(submitted). Parietal cortex mediates visuospatial imagery: evidence
from fMRI and rTMS.
<http://igitur-archive.library.uu.nl/dissertations/1954455/c10.pdf>
- Alkire, M.T., Haier, R.J., Fallon, J.H., and Barker, S.J.(1996). PET
imaging of conscious and unconscious verbal memory. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, 3 ( 5-6) 1996 , pp. 448--462
<http://www.imprint.co.uk/jcs_3_5-6.html>
- Anderson, J. & Anderson, B. (1993). \"The Myth of Persistence of
Vision Revisited,\" Journal of Film and Video, Vol. 45, No. 1
(Spring 1993): 3-12.
<http://www.uca.edu/org/ccsmi/ccsmi/classicwork/Myth%20Revisited.htm>
- Andrews, T.J., White, L.E., Binder, D. & Purves, D. (1996). Temporal
events in cyclopean vision. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 93,
pp. 3689--3692, April 1996. Neurobiology.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030510095149/http://www.dur.ac.uk/tim.andrews/PNAS_93_3689.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G. (2001) Determinants of asynchronous
processing in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London,
Series B: Biological Sciences, 269, 579 - 583.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031205165920/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/AC02.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G, Wenderoth, P. (2001). Asynchronous
processing in vision: Color leads motion. Current Biology, 11,
596 - 600.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030617120017/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/ACW01.pdf>
- Austin, G.M. & Grant, F.C. (1958). Physiologic observations
following total hemispherectomy in man. Surgery 38, 239-258.
- Baars, B.J. (1983) Conscious contents provide the nervous system
with coherent, global information. In Consciousness and
Self-Regulation (Vol 3). Davidson, R.J. et al., editors. Plenum
Press.
- Baars, B.J. (1988) A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness, Cambridge
University Press.
- Baars, B., Newman, J., & Taylor, J. (1998) Neuronal mechanisms of
consciousness: A Relational Global Workspace framework., in
Hameroff, Stuart and Kaszniak, Al and Laukes, James, Eds. Toward a
Science of Consciousness II: The second Tucson discussions and
debates., chapter 24, pages 269-278. MIT Press.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000946/>
- Baars, B.J. (2002) The conscious access hypothesis: origins and
recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. Vol 6, No 1,
47-52. 2002. <http://www.cs.memphis.edu/~wrcm/BaarsTICS2002.pdf>
- Barth, D. S. and MacDonald, K. D. (1996) Thalamic modulation of
high-frequency oscillating potentials in auditory cortex. Nature.
383, 78-81.
- Bernat E, Shevrin H, Snodgrass M. (2001). Subliminal visual oddball
stimuli evoke a P300 component. Clin Neurophysiol. 2001
Jan;112(1):159-71.
- Blake, R., Westendorf, D. and Overton, R. (1979) What is suppressed
during binocular rivalry? Perception 9: 223-231.
- Blake, R. and Lee, S.-H. (1999). Rival ideas about binocular
rivalry. Vision Research. 39: 1447-1454
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/faculty/blake/PDFs/Lee_Blake_99VR.pdf>
- Blankenburg, F., Ruff, C.C., Deichmann, R., Rees, G. and
Driver, J. (2006) The cutaneous rabbit illusion affects human
primary sensory cortex somatotopically, PLoS Biol 2006;4(3):e69.
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness: I. An
overview. Consciousness and Cognition, 4, 52-62.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/bogen-95.pdf>
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness:
Part II. Constraining the semantic problem. Consciousness and
Cognition, 4, 137-158.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/concog95.htm>
- Bregman, A.S. (1990). Auditory scene analysis: The perceptual
organization of sound. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Budka, H. (1998). Fatal Familial Insomnia Around the World. Brain
Pathology, 8: 553-570.
<http://brainpath.medsch.ucla.edu/pdfs/0803pdf/budka.pdf>
- Carandini M, Heeger DJ, & Senn W, (2002). A synaptic explanation of
suppression in visual cortex, Journal of Neuroscience,
22:10053-10065, 2002.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031031214953/http://www.cns.nyu.edu/~david/ftp/reprints/Carandini-JNeurosci2002.pdf>
- Cariani, P. (2000). Anesthesia, Neural Information Processing, And
Conscious Awareness. Consciousness And Cognition Vol. 9, No. 3,
September 2000 p. 387-395
- Castro-Alamancos, M.A., Connors, B.W. (1997). Thalamo-cortical
synapses. Progress in Neurobiology, Vol.51, pp. 581 to 606, 1997
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051025163047/http://neurobio.drexel.edu/castroweb/progneurobio1.pdf>
- Christmann, C. & Leuthold, H. (2004). The Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Section A. Volume 57, Number 2 /
February 2004. 357-381.
- Claus, R. & Nel, W. (2006). Drug induced arousal from the permanent
vegetative state. NeuroRehabilitation. 2006;21(1):23-8.
- Clifford, C.W.G., Arnold, D.H., Pearson, J. (2003). A paradox of
temporal perception revealed by a stimulus oscillating in colour and
orientation. Vision Research 43 (2003) 2245-2253.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031102125210/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/CAP03.pdf>
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of
consciousness Seminars in the Neurosciences (1990) 2, 263-275
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1998). Consciousness and Neuroscience.
Cerebral Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
- Culham, J.C., Dukelow, S.P., Vilis, T., Hassard, F.A., Gati, J.S.,
Menon, R.S. and Goodale, M.A. (1999). Recovery of fMRI Activation in
Motion Area MT Following Storage of the Motion Aftereffect. The
Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 81 No. 1 January 1999, pp. 388--393.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/81/1/388>
- Deecke, L. (1996) Planning, preparation, execution, and imagery of
volitional action, (Introduction / Editorial) in: L. Deecke W.
Lang, A. Berthoz (Eds) Mental Representations of Motor Acts.
Cognitive Brain Res 3 / Special Issue (2) 59-64.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000015/00/COGBRAIN.html>
- Dehaene, S., Sergent, C., and Changeux, J. (2003) A neuronal network
model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data
during conscious perception. PNAS July 8, 2003 vol. 100 no. 14
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/DehaeneSergentChangeux_BlinkModel_PNAS2003.pdf>
- Dehaene, S. et al. (2001) Cerebral mechanisms of word masking and
unconscious repetition priming. Nat. Neurosci, 4, 752-758.
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/Dehaene_MaskedWords_NatureNeuroscience2001.pdf>
- Dennett, D. and Kinsbourne, M. (1992) Time and the Observer: the
Where and When of Consciousness in the Brain. (1992) Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 15, 183-247, 1992. Reprinted in The Philosopher\'s
Annual, Grim, Mar and Williams, eds., vol. XV-1992, 1994,
pp. 23--68; Noel Sheehy and Tony Chapman, eds., Cognitive Science,
Vol. I, Elgar, 1995,
pp. 210--274.http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/time&obs.htm
- Destexhe, A. (2000). Modelling corticothalamic feedback and the
gating of the thalamus by the cerebral cortex. J. Physiol (Paris),
94 (2000) 391-410. <http://cns.iaf.cnrs-gif.fr/files/Brem2000.pdf>
- Fang, F. & He, S. (2005).Cortical responses to invisible objects in
the human dorsal and ventral pathways. Nat Neurosci. 2005
Oct;8(10):1380-5. Epub 2005 Sep 4.
- Ffytche, D. H., Howard, R. J., Brammer, M. J., David, A., Woodruff,
P., & Williams, S. (1998). The anatomy of conscious vision: an fMRI
study of visual hallucinations. Nature Neuroscience, 1, 738--742.
- Fiset, P., Paus, T., Daloze, T., Plourde, G., Meuret, P., Bonhomme,
V., Hajj-Ali, N., Backman, S.B., and Evans, A.C. (1999). Brain
Mechanisms of Propofol-Induced Loss of Consciousness in Humans: a
Positron Emission Tomographic Study. The Journal of Neuroscience,
July 1, 1999, 19(13):5506-5513.
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/13/5506>
- Fu, C.H.Y., Morgan, K., Suckling, J., Williams, S.C.R., Andrew, C.,
Vythelingum, G.N., McGuire, P.K. (2002). A Functional Magnetic
Resonance Imaging Study of Overt Letter Verbal Fluency Using a
Clustered Acquisition Sequence: Greater Anterior Cingulate
Activation with Increased Task Demand. NeuroImage 17, 871-
879 (2002)
<http://www-bmu.psychiatry.cam.ac.uk/PUBLICATION_STORE/fu02fun.pdf>
- Ganis, G., Thomson, W.L. and Kosslyn, S.M. (2004). Brain areas
underlying visual mental imagery and visual perception: an fMRI
study. Cognitive Brain Research 20 (2004) 226--241
<http://www.wjh.harvard.edu/~kwn/Kosslyn_pdfs/2004Ganis_CogBrainRes20_BrainAreas.pdf>
- Hultin, L. (1997). On Neuromagnetic Assessment of the Contingent
Negative Variation.
<http://www2.lib.chalmers.se/cth/diss/doc/9697/HultinLeif.html>
- Fries, P.. Roelfsema, P.R., Engel, A.K., König, P. and Singer, W.
(1997). Synchronization of oscillatory responses in visual cortex
correlates with perception in interocular rivalry. Proc. Natl. Acad.
Sci. USA, Vol. 94, pp. 12699--12704, November 1997.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/23/12699>
- Fuentealba, P., Crochet, S., Timofeev, I., Bazhenov, M., Sejnowski,
T.J. and Steriade, M. (2004). European Journal of Neuroscience
20(1):111-119. <http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2004/22126/ch03.html>
- Goaillard, J. & Vincent, P. (2002). Serotonin suppresses the slow
afterhyperpolarization in rat intralaminar and midline thalamic
neurones by activating 5-HT7 receptors. Journal of Physiology
(2002), 541.2, pp. 453--465
<http://jp.physoc.org/cgi/content/full/541/2/453>
- Haggard, P. & Eimer, M. (1999) On the relation between brain
potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Exp. Brain Res.
126, 128--133 (1999).
- Haggard, P. (2008) Human volition:towards a neuroscience of will.
Nature Rev Neurosci 9, 934-946
- Haynes, J., Deichmann, R. and Rees, G. (2005). Eye-specific effects
of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate nucleus. Nature
438, 496-499 (24 November 2005)
- Hughes S.W., Blethyn K.L. , Cope D.W. , & Crunelli V. (2003).
Properties and origin of spikelets in thalamocortical neurones in
vitro. Neuroscience. 2002;110(3):395-401
- Iramina, K., Maeno, T., Kowatari, Y. and Ueno, S.. (2002). Effects
of Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation on EEG Activity .IEEE
TRANSACTIONS ON MAGNETICS, VOL. 38, NO. 5, SEPTEMBER 2002
- Ishai, A., Ungerleider, L.G., Haxby, J.V.. (2000) Distributed neural
systems for the generation of visual images. Neuron 28, 979-990.
- Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1980). Mental models in cognitive science.
Cognitive Science, 4, 71-115.
<http://cognitrn.psych.indiana.edu/rgoldsto/cogsci/classics.html>
- Keller, J. & Heckhausen, H. (1990). Readiness potentials preceding
spontaneous motor acts: voluntary vs. involuntary control.
Electroencephalography and Clinical Neuropsychology, 76, 351-361.
- King, C.C. (1991). Fractal and Chaotic Dynamics in Nervous Systems.
Progress in Neurobiology, 36, pp. 279--308, 1991.
<http://citeseer.nj.nec.com/king91fractal.html>
- Klein, S.A (2002). Libet's Temporal Anomalies: A Reassessment of the
Data.
Consciousness and Cognition 11, 198--214 (2002)
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/160.pdf>
- Klein, S. (2002). Libet\'s Timing of Mental Events: Commentary on
the Commentaries. Consciousness and Cognition. 11, 326-333.
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/ccog_2002_0580-Klein-Commentary_on_the_commentaries.pdf>
- Kleinschmidt, A., Bichel, C. Zeki, S. and Frackowiak, R.S.J. (1998).
Human brain activity during spontaneously reversing perception of
ambiguous figures. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 1998 Dec
22;265(1413):2427-33
- Konishi, S., Wheeler, M.E., Donaldson, D.I., Buckner, R.L.. (2000)
Neural correlates of episodic retrieval success. NeuroImage: 12:
276-286.
- Kornhuber HH, Deecke L: Hirnpotentialänderungen beim Menschen vor
und nach Willkürbewegungen, dargestellt mit Magnetbandspeicherung
und Rückwärtsanalyse. Pflügers Arch. ges. Physiol. 281 (1964) 52.
- Kosslyn, S.M., Thompson, W.L. (2003). When is early visual cortex
activated during visual mental imagery? Psychol. Bull. 129
(2003)723-746.
- Kreiman, G., Koch, C. and Fried, I. (2000). Imagery neurons in the
human brain. Nature (2000) 408: 357-361
<http://www.cns.caltech.edu/~gabriel/publications/imagination1.html>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I., & Koch, C. (2001). Single neuron responses
in humans during binocular rivalry and flash suppression. Journal of
Vision, 1(3), 131a, <http://journalofvision.org/1/3/131>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I. And Koch, C. (2002) Single Neuron responses
in the human brain during flash suppression. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Science USA, 99:8378-8383
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031015091920/http://www.ai.mit.edu/projects/cbcl/publications/ps/kreimanetal_flash-suppression.pdf>
- Larsen, A., Madsen, K.H., Lund, T.E., and Bundesen, C. (2006).
Images of Illusory Motion in Primary Visual Cortex. Journal of
Cognitive Neuroscience. 2006;18:1174-1180.
- Laureys, S. et al. (2002). Brain function in the vegetative state.
Acta neurol. belg., 2002, 102, 177-185
<http://www.jsmf.org/meetings/2003/nov/LaureysANB2002.pdf>
- Lee. S, and Blake, R. (2002). V1 activity is reduced during
binocular rivalry. Journal of Vision (2002) 2, 618-626
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030722173225/http://journalofvision.org/2/9/4/article.pdf>
- Leopold, D.A. and Logothetis, N.K. (1999). Multistable phenomena:
changing views in perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 3:
254-264.
<http://www.kyb.tuebingen.mpg.de/publications/pdfs/pdf201.pdf>
- Libet, B., Alberts, E.W., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B.(1967).
Responses of Human Somatosensory Cortex to Stimuli Below Threshold
for Conscious Sensation. Science 158, 1597-1600.
- Libet, B., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B., and Pearl, D.(1979).
Subjective referral of the timing for a conscious sensory
experience. Brain, 102, pp. 192--224.
<http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/entrez/query.fcgi?holding=npg&cmd=Retrieve&db=PubMed&list_uids=427530&dopt=Abstract>
- Linden, D.E.J. (2005) The P300: Where in the Brain Is It Produced
and What Does It Tell Us? The Neuroscientist, Vol. 11, No. 6,
563-576 (2005) <http://nro.sagepub.com/cgi/reprint/11/6/563.pdf>
- Llinas, R., Ribary, U., Contreras, D. & Pedroarena, C. (1998). The
neuronal basis for consciousness. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London Ser.
B.353, 1841-1849
<http://big.cs.uiuc.edu/anncbt-papers/fall05/Llinas.the-neuronal-basis-of-consciousness.pdf>
- Logothetis, N.K., Leopold, D.A. and Sheinberg, D.L. (1996). What is
Rivalling During Binocular Rivalry. Nature, 380:621-624.
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nature/journal/v380/n6575/abs/380621a0.html>
- Loveblad, KO. et al. (1999). Silent functional magnetic resonance
imaging demonstrates focal activation in rapid eye movement sleep.
Neurology 1999;53:2193Z
- Luce, R.D. (1986). Response times: their role in inferring
elementary mental organization. Oxford University Press, New York.
- Lumer, E.D., Friston, K.J. & Rees, G. (1998) Neural correlates of
perceptual rivalry in the human brain. Science. 280(5371):1930-4.
- Macdonald, K.D., Fifkova, E., Jones, M.S. and Barth, D.S. (1998)
Focal Stimulation of the Thalamic Reticular Nucleus Induces Focal
Gamma Waves in Cortex. The Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 79 No. 1
January 1998, pp. 474--477
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/79/1/474>
- Maia, T.V. & Cleeremans, A. (2005). Consciousness: converging
insights from connectionist modeling and neuroscience. TRENDS in
Cognitive Sciences Vol.9 No.8 August 2005
<http://srsc.ulb.ac.be/axcWWW/papers/pdf/05-TICS.pdf>
- Marcel AJ. (1998). Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of
visual consciousness or visual function? Brain 1998, 121, 1565-1588.
<http://brain.oupjournals.org/cgi/reprint/121/8/1565.pdf>
- Marois, R., Yi, D-J., & Chun, M.M. (2004). The Neural Fate of
Consciously Perceived and Missed Events in the Attentional Blink.
Neuron, 41, 3: 465-472.
- Mashour, G.A., Tononi, G. and Massimini, M. (2005). Cognitive
Unbinding in Sleep and Anesthesia. Science 16 December 2005:
1768-1769.
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
<http://juno.ingentaselect.com/vl=6492085/cl=26/nw=1/rpsv/cgi-bin/cgi?body=linker&ini=nlm&reqidx=issn=0962-8452vl=264is=1380yr=1997mn=Marpg=393>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). Responses of Spectrally
Selective Cells in Macaque Area V2 to Wavelengths and Colors. J
Neurophysiol 87: 2104-2112, 2002.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/87/4/2104>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). The relationship between
cortical activation and perception investigated with invisible
stimuli. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA, 99(14):9527-9532.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/99/14/9527>
- Muckli, L., Singer, W., Zanella, F.E. and Goebel, R. (2002)
Integration of multiple motion vectors over space: an fMRI study of
transparent motion perception. Neuroimage. 2002 Aug;16(4):843-56.
- Munhall, K.G. (2001). Functional Imaging During Speech Production.
Acta Psychologica 107 (2001) 95-117.
<http://pavlov.psyc.queensu.ca/~munhallk/07_acta_version.pdf>
- Munk MHJ, Roelfsema PR, König P, Engel AK, and Singer W. (1996).
Role of reticular activation in the modulation of intracortical
synchronization Science. 272, 271-274.
- Newman, J. & Baars, B.J. (1993) A neural attentional model for
access to consciousness: A Global Workspace perspective. Concepts in
Neuroscience, 4:2, 255-290
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000073/>
- Nieuwenhuis S, Aston-Jones G & Cohen JD (2005). Decision making, the
P3, and the locus coeruleus-norepinephrine system. Psychological
Bulletin, 131(4), 510-532.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051117045339/http://www.csbmb.princeton.edu/conte/pdfs/project5/Proj5Pub06.pdf>
- Nørretranders, T. (1991) Consciousness: The User Illusion
(translated from Danish), Penguin Books,
; 1999 revision:
<http://www.worldcat.org/title/user-illusion-cutting-consciousness-down-to-size/oclc/41311618>.
- Pantev C (1995) Evoked and induced gamma-band activity of the human
cortex. Brain Topogr 7:321-330
- Pasley BN, Mayes LC, Schultz RT (2004) Subcortical discrimination of
unperceived objects during binocular rivalry. Neuron 2004,
42:163-172.
- Pessoa, L. (2005) To what extent are emotional visual stimuli
processed without attention and awareness? Current Opinion in
Neurobiology 2005, 15:188-196
<http://web.archive.org/web/20060623004726/http://www.brown.edu/Research/LCE/publications_files/Pessoa_CONB_2005.pdf>
- Pettigrew, J.D. (2001) Searching for the Switch: Neural Bases for
Perceptual Rivalry Alternations. Brain and Mind 2: 85-118, 2001.
<http://www.uq.edu.au/nuq/jack/searchswitch.pdf>
- Raymond, J. E, Shapiro, K. L., & Arnell, K. M. (1992). Temporary
suppression of visual processing in an RSVP task: An attentional
blink? Journal of Experimental Psychology. Human Perception and
Performance, 18 (3), 849-60.
- Rektor, I., Bares, M., Kanovsky, P. and Kukleta, M. (2001)
Intracerebral recording of readiness potential induced by a complex
motor task. Movement Disorders, Volume 16, Issue 4, Pages 698-704
- Rees, G., Kreiman, G., & Koch, C. (2002) Neural Correlates of
Consciousness in Humans. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3, 261
-270 (2002)
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nrn/journal/v3/n4/abs/nrn783_fs.html&dynoptions=doi1069842948>
- Rensink, RA. (2000). When Good Observers Go Bad: Change Blindness,
Inattentional Blindness, and Visual Experience. PSYCHE, 6(09),
August 2000.
<http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v6/psyche-6-09-rensink.html>
- Roy, J.E. & Prichep, L.S. (2005) The Anesthetic Cascade: A Theory of
How Anesthesia Suppresses Consciousness Anesthesiology: Volume
102(2) February 2005 pp 447--471
<http://www.anesthesiology.org/pt/re/anes/fulltext.00000542-200502000-00030.htm>
- Schiff, N.D., & Plum F. 1999. The Neurology of Impaired
Consciousness: Global Disorders and Implied Models. \[Target
article\]. Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness.
<http://www.phil.vt.edu/assc/niko.html>
- Schiff ND, Plum F. (2000) The Role of Arousal and \"Gating\" Systems
in the Neurology of Impaired Consciousness. Journal of
Neurophysiology. 17(5):438-452. (
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030924010953/http://www.uni-tuebingen.de/cog/lehre/ss2003/seminar_bewusstsein/epapers/SchiffPlum00.pdf>
- Sheinberg, D.L. and Logothetis, N.K. (1997). The role of temporal
cortical areas in perceptual organization. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA 94, 3408-3413. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/7/3408>
- Simons, D.J. & Rensink, RA. (2005). Change blindness: Past, present,
and future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol.9, pp16--20, No.1
January 2005.
<http://www.psych.ubc.ca/~rensink/publications/download/S&R-TICS-05a.pdf>
- Singer, W. & Gray, C.W. (1995). Visual feature integration and the
temporal correlation hypothesis. Annu. Rev. Neurosci., 18,
pp. 555--86, 1995.
- Singer, W. (2001). Consciousness and the Binding Problem. Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences 929:123-146 (2001)
- Solms, Mark (2000) DREAMING AND REM SLEEP ARE CONTROLLED BY
DIFFERENT BRAIN MECHANISMS, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23
(6): 793.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/Preprints/OldArchive/bbs.solms.html>
- Soon, C.S., Brass, M., Heinze, H-J. and Haynes, J-D. (2008).
Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain.
Nature Neuroscience 11, 543 - 545 (2008)
- Sukov, W. & Barth, D.S. (2001). Cellular Mechanisms of Thalamically
Evoked Gamma Oscillations in Auditory Cortex. J Neurophysiol 85:
1235-1245, 2001;
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/85/3/1235>
- Takeuchi, T., Miyasita, A., Inugami, M. & Yamamoto, Y. (2001).
Intrinsic dreams are not produced without REM sleep mechanisms:
evidence through elicitation of sleep onset REM periods. Journal of
Sleep Research Volume 10 Issue 1 Page 43 - March 2001
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tamás, G., Buh, E.H., Lörincz, A., and Somogyi, P. (2000).
Proximally targeted GABAergic synapses and gap junctions synchronize
cortical interneurons. Nature Neuroscience volume 3 no 4 April 2000.
<http://mrcanu.pharm.ox.ac.uk/pdfs/TamasNatureNeurosci2000.pdf>
- Tanaka, Y. & Sagi, D. (1998). A perceptual memory for low contrast
visual signals. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol 95:12729-12733.
<http://www.weizmann.ac.il/~masagi/TS98b.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2001). Competing Theories of Binocular Rivalry: A Possible
Resolution. Brain and Mind 2: 55-83, 2001
<http://web.archive.org/web/20041212094810/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_Brain&Mind2001.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual Awareness. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030723135239/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
- Tootell, R.B., Reppas, J.B., Dale, A.M., Look, R.B., Sereno, M.I.,
Malach, R., Brady, T.J. and Rosen, B.R. (1995) Visual motion
aftereffect in human cortical area MT revealed by functional
magnetic resonance imaging. Nature. 1995 May 11;375(6527):139-41.
- Tononi, G., Srinivasan, R., Russell, P.D. & Edelman, G.M. (1998).
Investigating neural correlates of conscious perception by
frequency-tagged neuromagnetic responses . Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA. Vol. 95, Issue 6, 3198-3203, March 17, 1998
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/95/6/3198>
- Thornton, I.M., Pinto, J. and Shiffrar, M. (1998).
THE VISUAL PERCEPTION OF HUMAN LOCOMOTION. COGNITIVE NEUROPSYCHOLOGY,
1998, 15 (6/7/8 ), 535-552.
<http://psychology.rutgers.edu/~mag/TPS98.pdf>
- Traub, D.R., Whittington, M.A., Buhl, E.H., Jefferys, J.G.R., &
Faulkner, H.J. (1999). On the Mechanism of the Frequency Shift in
Neuronal Oscillations Induced in Rat Hippocampal Slices by Tetanic
Stimulation. The Journal of Neuroscience, February 1, 1999,
19(3):1088-1105
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/3/1088>
- Traub, R.D. (2003). Fast Oscillations and Epilepsy. Epilepsy Curr.
2003 May; 3(3): 77-79.
<http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/articlerender.fcgi?artid=321178>
- Trevena J & Miller, J (2002) Cortical Movement Preparation before
and after a Conscious Decision to Move. Consciousness and Cognition,
Volume 11, Issue 2, June 2002, Pages 162-190
- Trevena, J & Miller, J (2009) Brain preparation before a voluntary
action: Evidence against unconscious movement initiation. Conscious
Cogn. 2009 Sep 5. \[Epub ahead of print\]
- Tse, P.U., Susana Martinez-Conde, S., Schlegel, A.A. and Macknik,
S.L. (2005). Visibility, visual awareness, and visual masking of
simple unattended targets are confined to areas in the occipital
cortex beyond human V1/V2. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA November 22,
2005 vol. 102 no. 47. 17178-17183.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/102/47/17178>
- Uchida, N., Kepecs, A. and Mainen, Z.F. (2006) Seeing at a glance,
smelling in a whiff: rapid forms of perceptual decision making.
Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 7. 485-491.
- Uchida, N & Mainen, Z.F. (2003) Speed and accuracy of olfacory
discrimination in the rat. Nature Neurosci. 6, 1224-1229.
- Vogel, E.K., Luck, S.J. & Shapiro, K.L. (1998) Electrophysiological
Evidence for a Postperceptual Locus of Suppression During the
Attentional Blink. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
Perception and Performance 1998, Vol. 24. No. 6,1656-1674
<http://web.archive.org/web/20050304211722/http://www.psychology.uiowa.edu/faculty/Luck/lucklab/pdfs/Vogel_1998_JEPHPP.pdf>
- Wehrle, R., Czisch, M., Kaufmann, C., Wetter, T.C., Holsboer, F.,
Auer, D.P., and Pollmacher, T. (2005). Rapid eye movement-related
brain activation in human sleep: a functional magnetic resonance
imaging study. NeuroReport 16:853-857
<http://www.univie.ac.at/mcogneu/lit/wehrle.pdf>
- White, NS., Alkire, MT. (2003). Impaired thalamocortical
connectivity in humans during
general-anesthetic-induced unconsciousness. NeuroImage. Volume 19, Issue
2 , June 2003, Pages 402-411. <http://smallurl.com?i=2597>
(http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/B6WNP-48GP5CG-5/1/cedb33dc0bec4301d1960c7c27cea70f)
- Wheeler, M.E., Buckner, R.L.. (2003) Functional dissociation among
components
of remembering: control, perceived oldness, and content. J. Neurosci.
23, 3869-3880.
- Williams LM, Liddell BJ, Rathjen J, Brown KJ, Shevrin H, Gray JA,
Phillips M, Young A & Gordon E (2004). Mapping the time course of
nonconscious and conscious perception of fear: An integration of
central and peripheral measures. Human Brain Mapping,21, 64 - 74
<http://psychmed.iop.kcl.ac.uk/neuroscience-and-emotion/downloads/46.pdf>
- Wunderlich, K. Schneider, K.A., & Kastner, S. (2005).Neural
correlates of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate
nucleus. Nature Neuroscience 8, 1595 - 1602 (2005)
- Yamamoto, T. & Katayama, Y. (2005). Deep brain stimulation therapy
for the vegetative state. in Neuropsychol Rehabil. 2005 Jul-Sep ;
15(3-4): 406-13
- Zeki, S., & Bartel, A. (1999). Toward a Theory of Visual
Consciousness. Consciousness & Cognition, 8, 225-259.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 2#Global Workspace Theory
*Contributors: please include full data in the references section for
all references in the text.*
```{=html}
<div class="noprint">
```
Home
```{=html}
</div>
```
## Perceptual \"filling in\"
Perceptual \"filling in\" occurs when visual properties such as
textures, colours, brightness or motion are extended in the visual field
to areas where they do not have corresponding events in the world.
The filling in of the blind spot by the properties of the field in the
contralateral eye has already been discussed. The part of the visual
field represented by the blind spot is also \"filled in\" in the case of
monocular vision.
![](Constudblindill.png "Constudblindill.png")
Shut the right eye and focus on the pink cross with the left eye, if the
head is moved towards the pink cross there is a point at which the
yellow disk disappears but the white lines are still present. In this
\"filling in\" the visual field does not appear to be distorted.
Fiorani *et al.* (1992) developed a technique for probing the cortical
blind spot using vertical and horizontal bar stimuli. Matsumoto &
komatsu (2005) used this technique on macaque monkeys. In the monocular
case they found that as a bar was moved across the visual field so that
it crossed the blind spot there was a sudden change in neural activity
in the deep layers of the neurons in the blind spot area of V1. When the
bar was moved across the same part of the visual field of the
contralateral eye the neural activity in the blind spot area increased
steadily as the bar was moved. The authors found that there were neurons
in the deep layers of blind spot cortex that had elongated receptive
fields that could respond to stimuli outside the blind spot and transfer
this activation into the blind spot cortex.
Filling in of a slightly different type occurs in \"scotoma\". In
scotoma an area of the retina is damaged and unresonsive to visual
stimuli, immediately after the damage patients report an area of visual
field that is unresponsive to stimuli. After several months patients
report that the area of field represented by the scotoma contains visual
properties related to the physical world surrounding the area that would
have formed an image on the scotoma. This results in a distortion of the
visual field. (see for instance Gilbert(1993)). Direct measurements of
activity in cortical area V1 show that the neurons that represented the
area of the scotoma become sensitive to activity in the surrounding
visual field. At the cortical level the scotoma is literally \"filled
in\".
There are many stimuli that cause \"filling in\". These stimuli are
known as \"illusions\" because they produce phenomenal experience that
has no correlate in the world outside the body. In the \"neon colour
spreading illusion\" a lightly coloured circle appears where there
should be a white background. Sasaki and Watanabe (2004) used fMRI to
show that the part of the topographic map in cortical area V1
corresponding to the light coloured circle was activated.
![](Constudneon.jpg "Constudneon.jpg")
Fiorani, M., Rosa, M.G.P., Gattas, R. & Rocha-Miranda, C.E. (1992).
Dynamic surrounds of receptive fields in primate striate cortex: a
physiological basis for perceptual completion? Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
89, 8547-8551. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/abstract/89/18/8547>
Gilbert, C.D. (1993). Circuitry, architecture and functional dynamics of
visual cortex.
Matsumoto, M & Komatsu, H. (2005). Neural responses in the macaque V1 to
bar stimuli with various lengths presented on the blind spot. J
neurophysiol. 93. 2374-2387.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/abstract/93/5/2374>
Sasaki, Y & Watanabe, T. The primary visual cortex fills in colour.
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 101, 18251-18256. (2004).
## Binocular Rivalry, Pattern Rivalry and Binocular Fusion
Sir Charles Wheatstone (1838) was the first scientist to systematically
investigate binocular rivalry. Binocular rivalry occurs when different
images are presented to the left and right eyes. The subject sees
successively one image, a combined image and then the other image. The
swapping of images can take a second or more. Binocular rivalry is of
interest in consciousness research because the parts of the brain that
contain the dominant image should also be those parts that are
contributing to conscious experience. Binocular rivalry involves at
least two components; the first switches from one image to a merged
image and then to the other image and the second permits the view to be
part of conscious experience.
![](Constudrival.png "Constudrival.png")
The switching of one image for another may involve selecting one of the
images as the percept or selecting one of the eyes. Blake *et al.*
(1979) performed an experiment in which subjects could change the image
at a given eye by pressing a button. When a particular image became
dominant they pressed a button to change the image at the eye receiving
the dominant image for the non-dominant image. They found that the
subjects immediately experienced the second image as the dominant image.
This suggests that binocular rivalry is selecting between eyes rather
than images. Lehky in 1988 proposed that the switching may be occurring
as a result of feedback between visual cortical area V1 and the Lateral
Geniculate Nucleus (a thalamic relay - see Carandini *et al.* 2002) and
Blake in 1989 also proposed that the switching occurred at the level of
area V1. (Visual cortical area V1 receives visual input direct from the
LGN.)
Tong (2001) has argued that, in humans, the switching of images in
binocular rivalry may occur at the earliest levels in the visual cortex.
In particular, Tong and Engel (2001) used an elegant technique measuring
the activity in the visual cortex that represents the blind spot of the
eye to show that almost complete switching to the dominant image occurs
at the level of visual cortical area V1. In support of this idea of
switching at the level of V1 or even before the cortex, Kreimann *et
al.* (2001, 2002) used direct electrode recordings in human cortex and
found that the activity of most neurons changed with the percept. Other
experiments have not shown a single locus in the brain where the
suppressed sensory information gets switched out (Blake & Logothetis
2002, Leopold & Logothetis 1996, Gail et al., 2004).
Functional MRI has also shown cortical activity outside of sensory
visual cortex related to both images in binocular rivalry. Lumer *et
al.* (1998) found that only the fronto-parietal areas of cortex switched
with the percept, Fang & He (2005) found that activity relating to both
suppressed and unsuppressed images were present in the dorsal stream of
the visual system. Wunderlich *et al.* (2005) and Haynes *et al.* (2005)
have both found suppression at the level of the lateral geniculate
nucleus using fMRI in humans.
Pasley *et al.* (2004) have shown that, even during suppression, fearful
faces can produce activity in the amygdala (see Pessoa (2005) for a
review).
Rivalry alternations seem to be the result of widespread activity
changes that cover large parts of the brain, including but not
necessarily originating at the earliest sensory stages of visual
processing. Most investigators have found that, once switching has
occurred, there are areas of the brain that contain activity that is
solely related to the percept but this varies from most of the cortex to
largely more frontal regions depending upon the study. The most likely
explanation for binocular rivalry is that the switching occurs at the
level of the LGN as a result of feedback from the cortex.
Pattern Rivalry is also of interest in consciousness research for the
same reasons as binocular rivalry. In pattern rivalry a figure may have
two or more forms that replace each other. Typical examples of such
figures are the Necker cube and Rubin\'s face-vase. The similarity of
the time course of the switching between percepts in binocular rivalry
and pattern rivalry has led many authors to suggest that these involve
the same mechanism. Logothetis *et al.* (1996) used novel dichoptic
stimuli (different images to each eyes) to produce a form of rivalry
that seems to involve switching at levels in the cerebral cortex that
are more distal to the sensory stimulus than V1. Leopold and Logothetis
(1999), on the basis of their work with monkeys, state that \"..many
neurons throughout the visual system, both monocular and binocular,
continue to respond to a stimulus even when it is perceptually
suppressed.\". Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998) investigated pattern rivalry
with MRI and found activity in higher order visual areas during change
of dominant pattern. Pettigrew (2001) also describes effects on rivalry
due to thought and mood that may require involvement of large areas of
cortex in the switching operation and stresses the way that V1
represents different visual fields in different hemispheres of the brain
so that inter-hemispheric switching must also be considered.
It seems likely that the change of dominant pattern or percept is
associated with higher level cortical activity but once the dominant
percept is established many of the visually responsive neurons in the
cortex are switched over to the new percept. This might account for the
similarities in timing of binocular and pattern rivalry and the
disparate results found by the various groups of authors. In the words
of Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998):
\"The transient activity fluctuations we found suggest that perceptual
metastability elicited by ambiguous stimuli is associated with rapid
redistributions of neural activity between separate specialized cortical
and subcortical structures.\"
Which permits both the idea of selecting particular eyes or percepts,
perhaps by feedback that switches a thalamic relay on the basis of
cortical processing of patterns. Once the cortex has switched the
thalamic relay most of the neurons in V1 would become exposed to the
dominant percept but there would still be a few neurons in the cortical
visual system receiving data from the non dominant image.
The investigations of binocular and pattern rivalry provide evidence
that conscious visual experience is probably distal to V1 (i.e.: cortex
or thalamus).
Perceptual rivalry may be part of complex decision making rather than
being simply a switch to blank out unwelcome input. It is clear from the
Rubin face-vase that pattern rivalry is linked to recognition and would
involve a complex delineation of forms within cortical processing. This
would suggest that many areas of cortex should be involved before a
particular percept is made dominant. Pettigrew (2001) argues that
rivalry is the result of a complex phenomenon rather than being simply a
switching event. Pettigrew\'s discovery that laughter abolishes rivalry
also points to a complex cortical system for switching percepts.
Pettigrew proposes that complex cortical processes control rivalry and
that the actual switching of percepts is performed sub-cortically in the
Ventral Tegmental Area. He concludes his review of the problem by noting
that \"Rivalry may thus reflect fundamental aspects of perceptual
decision making..\" Pettigrew (2001).
Another effect, known as \"binocular fusion\", provides further
compelling evidence for the non-conscious nature of the cerebral cortex.
In binocular fusion images from both eyes are fused together to create a
single image in experience. Moutoussis and Zeki (2002) used a form of
binocular fusion in which images of faces were flashed at 100ms
intervals to both eyes simultaneously. When both eyes received images of
the same colour the subject could see the faces but when one eye
received a green image on a red background and the other a red image on
a green background the subjects reported seeing a uniform yellow field
that contained no faces.
fMRI scans of the subject\'s brains showed that when both eyes were
exposed to images of the same colour the part of the brain that deals
with faces was active and when each eye received images of different
colours the same areas of brain showed activity. In other words the
cortex contained strong activity related to faces whether or not faces
were experienced. Moutoussis and Zeki found a similar effect when they
used images of houses instead of images of faces. The authors concluded
that: \"The present study further suggests that there are no separate
processing and perceptual areas but rather that the same cortical
regions are involved in both the processing and, when certain levels of
activation are reached and probably in combination with the activation
of other areas as well, the generation of a conscious visual percept\".
This conclusion does not seem to be supported by the data. There is no
evidence that any area of cortex contains the percept itself. The
experiment shows that the cortex contains data relating to both red and
green faces which suggests that the cortex is not the site of the
conscious percept. The percept is most likely distal to the cortex
perhaps in the thalamus or some other area that receives cortical
sensory output.
It is interesting that Fries *et al.* (1997) found that neurons that
were activated by the dominant image in binocular rivalry fired
synchronously whereas those that were activated by the non-dominant
image did not. Thalamocorticothalamic oscillations are the most likely
source for synchronising neurons over whole areas of cortex, suggesting
that the conscious percept is located in the thalamus rather than the
cortex.
## Synchronisation of Neural Processes
Our experience seems to contain entities with their attributes attached
to them at the correct places in space and time. When a dog barks we see
its jaws open at the same time as the bark and both jaws and bark are at
the same location. We take this for granted but the brain must be
engaging in some complex processing to achieve this synchronised and
appropriately positioned set of objects and events. The illustration
below shows the two basic processes that might be used to synchronise
events between the different specialised processors in the cerebral
cortex and brain in general.
![](Constudsynch.gif "Constudsynch.gif")
In the first option a complete model of sensation, dream etc. may be
created and then allowed to become part of conscious experience. In the
second model events are released into experience as fast as possible but
are synchronous when recalled, having been synchronised in a storage
buffer. There is a third option in which there is no synchronisation of
events so that the output from different processors would occur at
different times.
The \'experience buffer\' would be a volume of brain in which a
succession of events could be recorded. The buffer might either be
updated in steps, the previous content being discarded, or continuously
updated with the oldest content being lost continuously.
In the first option events from different processes would always appear
to be simultaneous unless the experience buffer were updated as a series
of steps in which case any changes at around the moment of updating
might appear in successive buffers. For instance, if change of position
were processed before change in colour a circle on a screen that changed
from green to red at the start of a motion might seem to be briefly
green during the motion and then turn red.
In the second model events from different processors might appear
asynchronous at the moment of experience but synchronous when recalled.
Colour vision and motion vision are processed in different parts of the
visual cortex and in distinct parts of visual cortical areas V1 and V2.
They are different processes and hence ideal for studying the
synchronisation of cortical activity. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997)
presented subjects with moving coloured squares on a computer screen
that changed from red to green or vice versa as they changed direction
of movement. It was found that subjects seemed to perceive changes in
colour some 70-80 msecs before they perceived a change in the direction
of motion of the squares. Further work by Arnold *et al.* (2001) and
Arnold and Clifford (2001) have confirmed that colour changes seem to be
perceived before motion. Arnold and Clifford (2001) also found a
quantitative relationship between the colour/motion asynchrony and the
direction of change of motion, complete reversals of direction giving
rise to the greatest asynchrony between the detection of colour and
motion changes.
Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) conclude by stating that the asynchrony of
neural processes shows that \"..the perception of each attribute is
solely the result of the activity in the specialised system involved in
its processing..\". It seems more likely that the experiments simply
show that slow neural processes are not synchronised before they become
percepts (the third option above). The experiments are excellent
evidence for the concept of the cortex as a set of specialised
processors that deliver their output asynchronously to some other place
where the output becomes a percept.
These experiments on colour and motion suggest that there is no
synchronisation between the processes that deal with these two aspects
of vision. Another set of experiments by Clifford *et al.* (2003)
supports this idea of processing being asynchronous. They asked subjects
to perform a variety of judgements of when visual events occurred and
found that the degree of synchrony of one visual event with another
depends on the type of judgement. Different judgements probably use
processors in different areas of cortex and the output from these
arrives asynchronously at the part of the brain that supports the
percept.
When the percept is formed there must be feedback to the cortical
processes that create its content. Otherwise it would not be possible to
report about the percept and the cortex would be unable to direct
processing to the percept in preference to other, non-conscious cortical
data.
Although slow processes (20 milliseconds to 1 second) do not seem to be
synchronised there is some evidence for very rapid synchronisation.
Andrews *et al.* (1996) revisited a problem raised by the famous
physiologist Charles Sherrington. Sherrington considered the phenomenon
of \'flicker fusion\' in which a flickering light appears to be a
continuous steady light if it flashes on and off at frequencies of about
45 Hz or higher. He reasoned that if the images from both eyes are
brought together to form a single image then the frequency at which a
flickering light appears to be steady should depend on whether one or
two eyes are used. Flicker fusion should occur if each eye receives
alternate flashes at only half the normal flicker fusion frequency. The
flicker should disappear if the left eye receives flashes at 23 pulses
per second and the right eye receives alternate flashes at 23 pulses per
second. When Sherrington performed the experiment he found that this was
not the case, using approximate figures, each eye required 46 pulses per
second for fusion to occur. Sherrington proposed that the flicker fusion
in alternate binocular presentation was occurring \"psychically\",
outside of normal physiological processes.
Andrews *et al.* duplicated Sherrington\'s result but investigated it
further. They found that when lights were flashed in each eye
alternately at low frequences (2 Hz) the experience was the same as a
light being flashed in both eyes at this rate. At frequencies of four Hz
and higher the subjects began to report that the lights being flashed
alternately in both eyes seemed to flicker at the same rate as lights
being flashed in both eyes at half the frequency. It seemed as if a
flash in one eye followed by a flash in the other eye was being
perceived as a single flash or \"conflated\" as the authors put it. The
authors explained this effect by suggesting that the brain activity
corresponding to the flashes was sampled for a short period and any
number of flashes occurring during this period became perceived as a
single flash. The maximum rate of sampling would be about 45 Hz. This
idea is similar to option (1) above, where the buffer is filled and
emptied 40 - 50 times a second.
An experience buffer that is refreshed at 40-50 times a second might
also explain the results obtained with colour and motion asynchrony
because synchronisation between processes may well happen too quickly to
affect processes that occur at very slow rates. Singer and Gray (1995),
Singer (2001) have proposed that synchronisation between neurones at
about 45 Hz is the discriminator between those neurones with activity
that contributes to conscious experience and activity in other neurones.
A rapid refresh rate in a synchronising buffer agrees with the results
found by Fries *et al.* (1997) in which visual cortical neurones that
represent a percept underwent synchronous oscillations in the gamma
frequency range (39--63 Hz). Tononi *et al.* (1998) have also found
synchronisation of neural activity in neurones that represent the
percept.
The gamma frequency oscillations are intrinsic to the cortex but are
triggered by the thalamus and are part of the \'arousal system\'.
Readers should be wary of the term \'arousal system\' because it evokes
the idea of something waking up a conscious cortex. The cortex can be
fully active during sleep and even during pathological unconsciousness
such as persistent vegetative state so it is possible that the arousal
centres themselves or nearby structures actually host phenomenal
consciousness.
## EEG and synchronisation
If electrodes are placed on the scalp varying electrical potentials of a
few tens of microvolts can be recorded between the electrodes.
Recordings of potentials from electrodes on the scalp are known as
electroencephalograms (EEGs).
The potentials recorded in the EEG are due to postsynaptic potentials in
nerve cells. The EEG is insensitive to the activity of single cells and
occurs as a result of relatively slow, **synchronised**, changes in
large areas of cells. The differences in potential between two scalp
electrodes are largely due to depolarisation and hyperpolarisation of
the dendritic trees of cortical pyramidal cells. The folding of the
cortex (gyri) is problematical for recording and interpreting EEGs
because opposing layers of cortex can cancel any net potentials.
The EEG shows rhythmic activity. This is conventionally divided into the
following frequency bands:
Delta waves 0--4 Hz
Theta waves 4--8 Hz
Alpha waves 8--12 Hz
Beta waves \>10 Hz
Gamma waves (also called fast beta) 25--100 Hz
EEGs also contain short bursts of activity called spindles and very fast
oscillations (VFOs). Spindles last for 1--2 seconds and contain rhythmic
activity at 7--14 Hz. They are associated with the onset of sleep. The
VFOs consist of short bursts at frequencies of over 80 Hz.
When the eyes are closed the amplitude of activity from most pairs of
electrodes is increased compared with when the eyes are open. When
subjects are awake the EEG consists mainly of alpha and beta activity
with considerable low amplitude gamma when the eyes are open. In stage 1
sleep the EEG consists of theta waves, in stage 2 sleep of varied
activity and spindles, in stage 4 sleep of delta and during REM sleep of
beta and theta activity. In epileptic seizures there tends to be high
amplitude activity with pronounced synchronisation between many pairs of
electrodes.
The rhythmic electrical activity is due to cortical feedback loops,
cortico-cortical synchronisation, thalamic pacemakers and
thalamo-cortical synchronisation. VFOs have been attributed to the
activity of electrical connections between cells (dendro-dendritic gap
junctions) (Traub (2003)).
The gamma activity, centred on a frequency of 40 Hz appears to be
related to activity in cortical interneurons that form electrical
connections between their dendrites (Tamas *et al.* 2000). These
oscillations can be triggered by high frequency stimulation of the
posterior intralaminar nuclei of the thalamus (Barth and MacDonald 1996,
Sukov and Barth 2001) and as a result of activation of the reticular
system (Munk *et al.* 1996). This suggests that stimulation of cortex by
thalamic sensory relays triggers gamma band activity in the cortex. A
shift from gamma to beta waves can occur in human event related
potentials after about 0.2 secs (Pantev 1995, Traub *et al.* 1999).
The alpha activity is related to thalamic pacemakers, perhaps as a
result of intrinsic oscillatory activity in thalamic sensory relays (see
Roy & Prichep 2005 for a brief review). Theta activity, which occurs
during some cognitive tasks and mental arithmetic involves a loop from
the cortex to the non-specific thalamic nuclei. Delta activity seems to
be endogenous to cortex when input is suppressed during sleep. Beta
activity is due to cortico-cortical interactions, often after a brief
period of gamma activation. It should be noted that gamma and beta
activity can be expressed as impulses in cortico-thalamic pathways and
that when cortical and thalamic activity is correlated there is a
conscious state. In other words gamma or beta waves in the cortex are
not correlates of consciousness on their own - see for instance Laureys
*et al.* (2002).
## Event related potentials
After a sudden event there are a characteristic set of changes in EEG
activity known as **event related potentials** or ERPs. The time course
of the ERP is shown in the diagram below.
![](Constudevent.png "Constudevent.png")
ERPs occur in response to novel stimuli and are also produced by brief
transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS)(Iramina *et al.* 2002). The slow
component is known as the P3 or P300 phase of the ERP. It is due to
activation of areas of the brain that are relatively remote from the
primary sensory areas of brain.
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) have reviewed the origin of the P300 ERP:
\"To summarize, convergent evidence suggests that P3-like activity can
be recorded in several, widely separated brain areas. These include some
medial temporal and subcortical structures (e.g., the hippocampal
formation, amygdala, and thalamus), but these structures are unlikely to
contribute directly to the scalp-recorded P3.\". According to
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) the recorded P300 may be due to
temporo-parietal and prefrontal cortical activity. Linden (2005) has
also concluded that widespread, but specific, cortical activation is
correlated with the recorded P300 ERP.
The generator of the P300 is still obscure. Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005)
consider that the Locus coeruleus, a nucleus in the pons that regulates
task related attention and part of the sleep-wake cycle, may be
responsible. In line with this, Mashour *et al.* (2005) have discovered
that TMS induced P300 activity is reduced in unconscious states.
Whether the P300 is related to Libet\'s 0.5 second delay is still
obscure but the discovery that the P300 occurs in association with
subliminal stimuli (stimuli that do not enter awareness)(Bernat *et al.*
2001) suggests that it is associated with non-conscious cortical
processing. Williams *et al.* (2004), in an investigation of subliminal
and supraliminal fear perception, found that \"conscious fear perception
was distinguished by a more prominent N4, peaking around 400 msec\"; the
N4 component follows the P300 component in the succession of phases of
the ERP. Williams *et al.* considered that the earlier phases in the ERP
are probably related to non-conscious processing. In contrast Vogel *et
al.* (1998) found that suppression of the P300 was associated with
suppression of awareness.
## The integration delay
Psychological experiments often involve binary decisions where subjects
give one of two outputs in response to stimuli. It is found that if the
stimuli are made increasingly noisy or complex the response time tends
to increase. Psychophyicists have developed various mathematical models
to explain the increased response times due to noise such as the
Integrator and Accumulator models (cf: Luce(1986)). These models have
been fairly successful when explaining experiments such as judging the
net direction of movement of sets of dots on a screen when the dots are
given semi-random paths and different brightness etc. In these
circumstances it can take up to 2 seconds for an accurate decision.
There are many tasks however where the accuracy of decision making does
not improve after about 300 milliseconds. The accuracy of the
performance of rats when choosing between two alternatives when reacting
to odours peaks at about 300 ms (Uchida and Mainen(2003), Abraham *et
al.* (2004)). The accuracy of humans when performing vernier acuity
tasks, line detection, contrast sensitivity, motion velocity
discrimination and stereoscopic depth discrimination seems to peak at
300ms (Uchida *et al.* 2006).
Uchida, Kepecs and Mainen (2006) suggest that \"rapid and short
integration time is a sensible strategy for rapid processing of
low-level sensory information in order to form more complex sensory
images, both in vision and olfaction.\" Whether these authors regard
these derived sensory images as the content of consciousness is not
mentioned. The authors propose that the 300ms optimal integration time
may be partly due to the mechanics of sniffing (a sniff takes about
125-200ms) and the nature of optical fixation (inter-saccade intervals
are typically 200-400 ms ). The authors note that the animal or human
could, in principle, choose to integrate over longer intervals but if it
is moving this may not lead to information that is current for changed
circumstances.
An optimal processing time of about 300 ms would be consistent with the
delays observed before conscious awareness occurs in response to a
stimulus - an interval required to form \"more complex sensory images\".
## Global Workspace Theory
Global Workspace Theory is the idea that somewhere in the brain there is
a facility that integrates the processes that occur in the various
separate areas of the brain. The theory was first proposed by Descartes
as the *sensus communis*, the common sense, but the modern form of the
theory dispenses with the idea of a point soul looking at the brain. In
modern Global Workspace theory it is proposed that an area of brain
receives input from most of the cerebral cortex and broadcasts its
outputs to all of the unconscious modular information processors in the
brain.
Modern Global Workspace Theory has been championed by Baars (1983,
1988).
There is increasing evidence for a Global Workspace or Global Workspaces
in the brain. Much of this evidence comes from fMRI, single unit and
magnetoencephalography studies in which it is shown that non-conscious
or subliminal processing mainly occupies primary, sensory cortex whereas
conscious processing occupies large areas of cerebral cortex.
In binocular rivalry the stimulus that is consciously perceived is
responsible for relatively intense activation of large areas of brain
whereas the non-conscious stimulus is often suppressed (see above and
Sheinberg & Logothetis (1997), Tononi *et al.* (1998)). The suppression
is likely to occur in the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei which suggests a
role for the Thalamic Reticular Nuclei, which modulate LGN activity, in
the control of the percept.
### Masking and visual awareness
Word masking has also been used to investigate the idea of a Global
Workspace. When a word is presented on its own for a few tens of
milliseconds it remains readable but if it is immediately succeeded by,
or accompanied by, another word it becomes indistinct or invisible. This
effect is known as \"word masking\". Vogel *et al.* (1998) have
investigated a version of word masking known as the \"attentional
blink\". They found that when stimuli became invisible the P3 component
of the Event Related Potential, which peaks at around 300-500 millisecs
after a stimulus, was completely suppressed. The P3 component of the ERP
has been related to the lodging of data in working memory and also to
gamma band activity in the EEG. This strongly suggests the involvement
of a cortico-thalamic loop in the \"attentional blink\". The delay of
0.3 to 0.5 secs is typical of the time required for conscious awareness
(see above).
Word masking in conjunction with fMRI and Event Related Potential (ERP)
recordings has been used by Dehaene *et al.* (2001) to expose control by
a central mechanism. It was found that masked words activate mainly the
visual cortex and ventral stream (inferior temporal lobe) whereas
visible words also activated distant parietal, prefrontal and cingulate
sites.
Dehaene *et al.* (2003) and found that the dynamics of the loss of
visibility of words in an attentional blink experiment could be modelled
by a simulated cortico-thalamic loop. In their simulation a distributed
cortical process determined which events would receive attention and the
system used the thalamic gating systems to exclude those that did not
receive attention.
Tse *et al.* (2005) have used purely visual stimuli in masking
experiments and concluded that, in the case of purely visual stimuli,
the neural correlates of awareness were limited to the occipital cortex:
\"We suggest that there are both lower and upper bounds within the
visual hierarchy for the processing of visual masking and the
maintenance of visual awareness of simple unattended targets; the lower
bound is at least as high as the border between V2 and V3, and the upper
bound is within the occipital lobe, possibly somewhere downstream of
V4.\"
This discovery would mean that activation of large areas of cortex are
unnecessary for awareness.
Melloni *et al.* (2007) compared compared the electrophysiological
responses related to the processing of visible and invisible words in a
delayed matching to sample task. Both perceived and nonperceived words
caused a similar increase of local (gamma) oscillations in the EEG, but
only perceived words induced a transient long-distance synchronization
of gamma oscillations across widely separated regions of the brain.
After this transient period of temporal coordination, the electrographic
signatures of conscious and unconscious processes continue to diverge.
Only words reported as perceivedinduced (1) enhanced theta oscillations
over frontal regions during the maintenance interval, (2) an increase of
the P300 component of the event-related potential, and (3) an increase
in power and phase synchrony of gamma oscillationsbefore the anticipated
presentation of the test word. We propose that the critical process
mediating the access to conscious perception is the earlytransient
global increase of phase synchrony of oscillatory activity in the
gammafrequency.
Melloni L, Molina C, Pena M, Torres D, Singer W, Rodriguez E. (2007).
Synchronization of neural activity across cortical areas correlates
withconscious perception.J Neurosci. 2007 Mar 14;27(11):2858-65.
### Attention and the global workspace
Baars (2002) in his review of evidence for the Global Workspace Theory
quotes many other experiments that show activation of larger areas of
cortex in response to conscious stimuli compared with unconscious or
subliminal stimuli.The effect is also seen in change blindness, learning
and attention. Newman and Baars (1993) consider that the \"workspace\"
is fairly global in the brain:
\"This Neural Global Workspace (NGW) model views conscious processes in
terms of a globally integrative brain system. The neural circuitry
contributing to this system is not only widely distributed across the
neocortex, but includes key corticothalamic and midbrain circuits as
well. These cortico-subcortical circuits are hypothesized to be critical
to understanding the mechanisms of attentional control that provide an
essential basis for the conscious processing of information\".
However they focus particularly on the role of the thalamic Reticular
Nucleus and cortico-thalamic connectivity in the control of attention.
Other ideas for the location of the Global Workspace are the idea of
Singer et al. that gamma synchrony controls access to the content of
consciousness and Llinas et al. (1998) that the thalamus is the hub
through which communication occurs between areas of cortex.
One of the problems with Global Workspace theory is that it suggests
that attention, working memory, cognitive control and consciousness may
all be in the same area of the brain. It is likely that the mechanisms
of attention, working memory, and cognitive control may involve several,
interlinked systems perhaps co-opting the basal ganglia in the process.
In view of this Maia and Cleeremans (2005) propose that \".. attention,
working memory, cognitive control and consciousness are not distinct
functions implemented by separate brain systems. Attempting to find
separate neural correlates for each may therefore be the wrong approach.
Instead, we suggest that they should be understood in terms of the
dynamics of global competition, with biasing from PFC (prefrontal
cortex).\". The inclusion by Maia and Cleeremans of consciousness with
distributed attention, working memory and cognitive control is
reminiscent of Zeki & Bartel\'s idea of microconsciousness.
It should be noted that, in common with Libet\'s data, the percept seems
to be available to phenomenal consciousness some 0.3 to 0.5 secs after a
stimulus; this suggests that whatever determines the content of
phenomenal consciousness operates before events become part of
phenomenal consciousness. This relegates phenomenal consciousness from
being a controller of attention to being the recipient of content that
is the subject of attention. This finding is consistent with the
philosophical problem of the **apparently** epiphenomenal nature of
phenomenal consciousness.
Given the data on the timing of conscious awareness it seems that there
may be two \"workspaces\", an active workspace that models the world,
discarding and suppressing data during rivalry, and a passive workspace
that receives the final, edited product. The active workspace would
correlate with the cortical systems stressed by Dehaene *et al.* and
Maia and Cleermans although, given the results of Tse et al., the
workspace would be limited to small zones of cortex. The loading of the
passive workspace with the output of the active workspace would
correlate with thalamo-cortical activity during component P3 of the ERP
in which data is transferred from the cortex to the thalamus. This
workspace might constitute the source for reports of the content of
phenomenal consciousness.
Llinas *et al.* (1998) have proposed two parallel cortico-thalamic
attentional systems, one of which is related to the thalamic specific
nuclei and the other to the thalamic non-specific nuclei, especially the
ILN. The non-specific system would be related to consciousness itself.
## The \"cognitive map\" and the neural basis of perceptual space
Our bodies appear to be mobile within a constant space. We walk around a
room; the room does not rotate around us. The constancy of the location
of things gives us the feeling that we are directly viewing a constant
world. But how does the brain provide a constant world rather than a
world that rotates with the movement of the sense organs? Why is our
view of the world when we move our eyes so different from the disturbing
flow of images that occur when a video camera is waved around? Do our
brains contain a constant \"cognitive map\" (O\'Keefe and Nadel 1978) of
our surroundings?
Mittelstaedt & Mittelstaedt (1980, 1982) discovered that female gerbils
were able to recover their pups in darkened surroundings by searching in
a semi random fashion on the outbound journey and then proceeding
directly back to the nest on the inbound journey. The direct journey
back to the nest seemed to be due to an integration of the various
directions taken on the outward journey (**path integration**). If the
equipment being explored by the mother gerbil was rotated very slowly
the mother would make an error equivalent to the amount of rotation.
More rapid rotations that activated the vestibular system of the rat
(acceleration measurement) did not cause errors in navigation. This
demonstration that rodents could navigate accurately on the basis of
**idiothetic** cues (cues that are due to internal senses) led to
research on the neural basis of the navigation.
As early as 1971 O\'Keefe and Dostrovsky had discovered that there are
particular cells in the hippocampus that fire according to the position
of an animal in the environment. This has been complimented by research
that showed that changes in visual cues within the environment caused
changes in the firing rate of place cells in hippocampal area CA3 (.
![](Gray717.png "Gray717.png")
![](HippocampalRegions.jpg "HippocampalRegions.jpg")
!Entorhinal cortex approximately maps to areas 28 and
34{width="500"}
F. P. Battaglia and A. Treves. 1998 Attractor neural networks storing
multiple space representations: A model for hippocampal place fields.
PHYSICAL REVIEW E DECEMBER 1998 VOLUME 58, NUMBER 6
<http://www.sissa.it/~ale/Bat+98b.pdf>
Leutgeb, S., Leutgeb, J.K., Moser, M-B, and Moser, E.I. 2005. Place
cells, spatial maps and the population code for memory. Current Opinion
in Neurobiology 2005, 15:738--746.
<http://instruct1.cit.cornell.edu/courses/bionb720nejc/reprints/LeutgebEtAl2005.pdf>
Mittelstaedt, H. & Mittelstaedt, M-L. 1982. Avian Navigation. (ed. Papi,
F. & Wallraff, H.) 290-297. Springer, Berlin.
Mittelstaedt, M-L & Glasauer, S. 1991. Idiothetic Navigation in Gerbils
and Humans. Zool. Jb. Physiol. 95 (1991), 427-435
<http://web.archive.org/web/20110125132449/http://www.nefo.med.uni-muenchen.de/~sglasauer/MittelstaedtGlasauer1991.pdf>
O\'Keefe, J. & Dostrovsky, J. (1971). The hippocampus as a spatial map:
preliminary evidence from unit activity in the freely moving rat. Brain
Res. 34, 171-175.
O\'Keefe, J. & Nadel, L. (1978). The Hippocampus as a cognitive map.
(Oxford)
## Bibliography
Defining the States of Consciousness. Tassi, P., Muzet, A. (2001)
Neuroscience and Behavioural Reviews 25(2001) 175-191.
Neuroanatomy: \"Digital Slice of Life\" by Stensaas and Millhouse
<http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/subj2.html>
See also: <http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/index.html>
EEG\'s: Coles, M.G.H., Rugg, M.D. Event Related Brain Potentials: An
Introduction.
<http://whalen.psych.udel.edu/667/1.What_is_ERP/ColesRugg1995chpt1.pdf>
Visual System: Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual
Awareness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
Professor Bogen\'s Consciousness Page
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/toccons.htm>
Demonstrations of Auditory Illusions and Tricks. Yoshitaka Nakajima
<http://www.kyushu-id.ac.jp/~ynhome/ENG/Demo/illusions2nd.html>
## References
- Abraham, N.M. (2004) Maintaining accuracy at the expense of speed:
stimulus similarity defines odor discrimination time in mice. Neuron
44, 865-876.
- Aleman, A., Ramsey, N., Van Honk, J.E., Kessels, R.P.C., Hoogduin,
J., Schutter, D.L.G., Postma, A., Kahn, R.S., De Haan, E.H.F.
(submitted). Parietal cortex mediates visuospatial imagery: evidence
from fMRI and rTMS.
<http://igitur-archive.library.uu.nl/dissertations/1954455/c10.pdf>
- Alkire, M.T., Haier, R.J., Fallon, J.H., and Barker, S.J.(1996). PET
imaging of conscious and unconscious verbal memory. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, 3 ( 5-6) 1996 , pp. 448--462
<http://www.imprint.co.uk/jcs_3_5-6.html>
- Anderson, J. & Anderson, B. (1993). \"The Myth of Persistence of
Vision Revisited,\" Journal of Film and Video, Vol. 45, No. 1
(Spring 1993): 3-12.
<http://www.uca.edu/org/ccsmi/ccsmi/classicwork/Myth%20Revisited.htm>
- Andrews, T.J., White, L.E., Binder, D. & Purves, D. (1996). Temporal
events in cyclopean vision. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 93,
pp. 3689--3692, April 1996. Neurobiology.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030510095149/http://www.dur.ac.uk/tim.andrews/PNAS_93_3689.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G. (2001) Determinants of asynchronous
processing in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London,
Series B: Biological Sciences, 269, 579 - 583.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031205165920/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/AC02.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G, Wenderoth, P. (2001). Asynchronous
processing in vision: Color leads motion. Current Biology, 11,
596 - 600.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030617120017/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/ACW01.pdf>
- Austin, G.M. & Grant, F.C. (1958). Physiologic observations
following total hemispherectomy in man. Surgery 38, 239-258.
- Baars, B.J. (1983) Conscious contents provide the nervous system
with coherent, global information. In Consciousness and
Self-Regulation (Vol 3). Davidson, R.J. et al., editors. Plenum
Press.
- Baars, B.J. (1988) A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness, Cambridge
University Press.
- Baars, B., Newman, J., & Taylor, J. (1998) Neuronal mechanisms of
consciousness: A Relational Global Workspace framework., in
Hameroff, Stuart and Kaszniak, Al and Laukes, James, Eds. Toward a
Science of Consciousness II: The second Tucson discussions and
debates., chapter 24, pages 269-278. MIT Press.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000946/>
- Baars, B.J. (2002) The conscious access hypothesis: origins and
recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. Vol 6, No 1,
47-52. 2002. <http://www.cs.memphis.edu/~wrcm/BaarsTICS2002.pdf>
- Barth, D. S. and MacDonald, K. D. (1996) Thalamic modulation of
high-frequency oscillating potentials in auditory cortex. Nature.
383, 78-81.
- Bernat E, Shevrin H, Snodgrass M. (2001). Subliminal visual oddball
stimuli evoke a P300 component. Clin Neurophysiol. 2001
Jan;112(1):159-71.
- Blake, R., Westendorf, D. and Overton, R. (1979) What is suppressed
during binocular rivalry? Perception 9: 223-231.
- Blake, R. and Lee, S.-H. (1999). Rival ideas about binocular
rivalry. Vision Research. 39: 1447-1454
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/faculty/blake/PDFs/Lee_Blake_99VR.pdf>
- Blankenburg, F., Ruff, C.C., Deichmann, R., Rees, G. and
Driver, J. (2006) The cutaneous rabbit illusion affects human
primary sensory cortex somatotopically, PLoS Biol 2006;4(3):e69.
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness: I. An
overview. Consciousness and Cognition, 4, 52-62.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/bogen-95.pdf>
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness:
Part II. Constraining the semantic problem. Consciousness and
Cognition, 4, 137-158.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/concog95.htm>
- Bregman, A.S. (1990). Auditory scene analysis: The perceptual
organization of sound. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Budka, H. (1998). Fatal Familial Insomnia Around the World. Brain
Pathology, 8: 553-570.
<http://brainpath.medsch.ucla.edu/pdfs/0803pdf/budka.pdf>
- Carandini M, Heeger DJ, & Senn W, (2002). A synaptic explanation of
suppression in visual cortex, Journal of Neuroscience,
22:10053-10065, 2002.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031031214953/http://www.cns.nyu.edu/~david/ftp/reprints/Carandini-JNeurosci2002.pdf>
- Cariani, P. (2000). Anesthesia, Neural Information Processing, And
Conscious Awareness. Consciousness And Cognition Vol. 9, No. 3,
September 2000 p. 387-395
- Castro-Alamancos, M.A., Connors, B.W. (1997). Thalamo-cortical
synapses. Progress in Neurobiology, Vol.51, pp. 581 to 606, 1997
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051025163047/http://neurobio.drexel.edu/castroweb/progneurobio1.pdf>
- Christmann, C. & Leuthold, H. (2004). The Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Section A. Volume 57, Number 2 /
February 2004. 357-381.
- Claus, R. & Nel, W. (2006). Drug induced arousal from the permanent
vegetative state. NeuroRehabilitation. 2006;21(1):23-8.
- Clifford, C.W.G., Arnold, D.H., Pearson, J. (2003). A paradox of
temporal perception revealed by a stimulus oscillating in colour and
orientation. Vision Research 43 (2003) 2245-2253.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031102125210/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/CAP03.pdf>
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of
consciousness Seminars in the Neurosciences (1990) 2, 263-275
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1998). Consciousness and Neuroscience.
Cerebral Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
- Culham, J.C., Dukelow, S.P., Vilis, T., Hassard, F.A., Gati, J.S.,
Menon, R.S. and Goodale, M.A. (1999). Recovery of fMRI Activation in
Motion Area MT Following Storage of the Motion Aftereffect. The
Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 81 No. 1 January 1999, pp. 388--393.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/81/1/388>
- Deecke, L. (1996) Planning, preparation, execution, and imagery of
volitional action, (Introduction / Editorial) in: L. Deecke W.
Lang, A. Berthoz (Eds) Mental Representations of Motor Acts.
Cognitive Brain Res 3 / Special Issue (2) 59-64.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000015/00/COGBRAIN.html>
- Dehaene, S., Sergent, C., and Changeux, J. (2003) A neuronal network
model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data
during conscious perception. PNAS July 8, 2003 vol. 100 no. 14
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/DehaeneSergentChangeux_BlinkModel_PNAS2003.pdf>
- Dehaene, S. et al. (2001) Cerebral mechanisms of word masking and
unconscious repetition priming. Nat. Neurosci, 4, 752-758.
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/Dehaene_MaskedWords_NatureNeuroscience2001.pdf>
- Dennett, D. and Kinsbourne, M. (1992) Time and the Observer: the
Where and When of Consciousness in the Brain. (1992) Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 15, 183-247, 1992. Reprinted in The Philosopher\'s
Annual, Grim, Mar and Williams, eds., vol. XV-1992, 1994,
pp. 23--68; Noel Sheehy and Tony Chapman, eds., Cognitive Science,
Vol. I, Elgar, 1995,
pp. 210--274.http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/time&obs.htm
- Destexhe, A. (2000). Modelling corticothalamic feedback and the
gating of the thalamus by the cerebral cortex. J. Physiol (Paris),
94 (2000) 391-410. <http://cns.iaf.cnrs-gif.fr/files/Brem2000.pdf>
- Fang, F. & He, S. (2005).Cortical responses to invisible objects in
the human dorsal and ventral pathways. Nat Neurosci. 2005
Oct;8(10):1380-5. Epub 2005 Sep 4.
- Ffytche, D. H., Howard, R. J., Brammer, M. J., David, A., Woodruff,
P., & Williams, S. (1998). The anatomy of conscious vision: an fMRI
study of visual hallucinations. Nature Neuroscience, 1, 738--742.
- Fiset, P., Paus, T., Daloze, T., Plourde, G., Meuret, P., Bonhomme,
V., Hajj-Ali, N., Backman, S.B., and Evans, A.C. (1999). Brain
Mechanisms of Propofol-Induced Loss of Consciousness in Humans: a
Positron Emission Tomographic Study. The Journal of Neuroscience,
July 1, 1999, 19(13):5506-5513.
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/13/5506>
- Fu, C.H.Y., Morgan, K., Suckling, J., Williams, S.C.R., Andrew, C.,
Vythelingum, G.N., McGuire, P.K. (2002). A Functional Magnetic
Resonance Imaging Study of Overt Letter Verbal Fluency Using a
Clustered Acquisition Sequence: Greater Anterior Cingulate
Activation with Increased Task Demand. NeuroImage 17, 871-
879 (2002)
<http://www-bmu.psychiatry.cam.ac.uk/PUBLICATION_STORE/fu02fun.pdf>
- Ganis, G., Thomson, W.L. and Kosslyn, S.M. (2004). Brain areas
underlying visual mental imagery and visual perception: an fMRI
study. Cognitive Brain Research 20 (2004) 226--241
<http://www.wjh.harvard.edu/~kwn/Kosslyn_pdfs/2004Ganis_CogBrainRes20_BrainAreas.pdf>
- Hultin, L. (1997). On Neuromagnetic Assessment of the Contingent
Negative Variation.
<http://www2.lib.chalmers.se/cth/diss/doc/9697/HultinLeif.html>
- Fries, P.. Roelfsema, P.R., Engel, A.K., König, P. and Singer, W.
(1997). Synchronization of oscillatory responses in visual cortex
correlates with perception in interocular rivalry. Proc. Natl. Acad.
Sci. USA, Vol. 94, pp. 12699--12704, November 1997.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/23/12699>
- Fuentealba, P., Crochet, S., Timofeev, I., Bazhenov, M., Sejnowski,
T.J. and Steriade, M. (2004). European Journal of Neuroscience
20(1):111-119. <http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2004/22126/ch03.html>
- Goaillard, J. & Vincent, P. (2002). Serotonin suppresses the slow
afterhyperpolarization in rat intralaminar and midline thalamic
neurones by activating 5-HT7 receptors. Journal of Physiology
(2002), 541.2, pp. 453--465
<http://jp.physoc.org/cgi/content/full/541/2/453>
- Haggard, P. & Eimer, M. (1999) On the relation between brain
potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Exp. Brain Res.
126, 128--133 (1999).
- Haggard, P. (2008) Human volition:towards a neuroscience of will.
Nature Rev Neurosci 9, 934-946
- Haynes, J., Deichmann, R. and Rees, G. (2005). Eye-specific effects
of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate nucleus. Nature
438, 496-499 (24 November 2005)
- Hughes S.W., Blethyn K.L. , Cope D.W. , & Crunelli V. (2003).
Properties and origin of spikelets in thalamocortical neurones in
vitro. Neuroscience. 2002;110(3):395-401
- Iramina, K., Maeno, T., Kowatari, Y. and Ueno, S.. (2002). Effects
of Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation on EEG Activity .IEEE
TRANSACTIONS ON MAGNETICS, VOL. 38, NO. 5, SEPTEMBER 2002
- Ishai, A., Ungerleider, L.G., Haxby, J.V.. (2000) Distributed neural
systems for the generation of visual images. Neuron 28, 979-990.
- Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1980). Mental models in cognitive science.
Cognitive Science, 4, 71-115.
<http://cognitrn.psych.indiana.edu/rgoldsto/cogsci/classics.html>
- Keller, J. & Heckhausen, H. (1990). Readiness potentials preceding
spontaneous motor acts: voluntary vs. involuntary control.
Electroencephalography and Clinical Neuropsychology, 76, 351-361.
- King, C.C. (1991). Fractal and Chaotic Dynamics in Nervous Systems.
Progress in Neurobiology, 36, pp. 279--308, 1991.
<http://citeseer.nj.nec.com/king91fractal.html>
- Klein, S.A (2002). Libet's Temporal Anomalies: A Reassessment of the
Data.
Consciousness and Cognition 11, 198--214 (2002)
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/160.pdf>
- Klein, S. (2002). Libet\'s Timing of Mental Events: Commentary on
the Commentaries. Consciousness and Cognition. 11, 326-333.
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/ccog_2002_0580-Klein-Commentary_on_the_commentaries.pdf>
- Kleinschmidt, A., Bichel, C. Zeki, S. and Frackowiak, R.S.J. (1998).
Human brain activity during spontaneously reversing perception of
ambiguous figures. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 1998 Dec
22;265(1413):2427-33
- Konishi, S., Wheeler, M.E., Donaldson, D.I., Buckner, R.L.. (2000)
Neural correlates of episodic retrieval success. NeuroImage: 12:
276-286.
- Kornhuber HH, Deecke L: Hirnpotentialänderungen beim Menschen vor
und nach Willkürbewegungen, dargestellt mit Magnetbandspeicherung
und Rückwärtsanalyse. Pflügers Arch. ges. Physiol. 281 (1964) 52.
- Kosslyn, S.M., Thompson, W.L. (2003). When is early visual cortex
activated during visual mental imagery? Psychol. Bull. 129
(2003)723-746.
- Kreiman, G., Koch, C. and Fried, I. (2000). Imagery neurons in the
human brain. Nature (2000) 408: 357-361
<http://www.cns.caltech.edu/~gabriel/publications/imagination1.html>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I., & Koch, C. (2001). Single neuron responses
in humans during binocular rivalry and flash suppression. Journal of
Vision, 1(3), 131a, <http://journalofvision.org/1/3/131>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I. And Koch, C. (2002) Single Neuron responses
in the human brain during flash suppression. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Science USA, 99:8378-8383
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031015091920/http://www.ai.mit.edu/projects/cbcl/publications/ps/kreimanetal_flash-suppression.pdf>
- Larsen, A., Madsen, K.H., Lund, T.E., and Bundesen, C. (2006).
Images of Illusory Motion in Primary Visual Cortex. Journal of
Cognitive Neuroscience. 2006;18:1174-1180.
- Laureys, S. et al. (2002). Brain function in the vegetative state.
Acta neurol. belg., 2002, 102, 177-185
<http://www.jsmf.org/meetings/2003/nov/LaureysANB2002.pdf>
- Lee. S, and Blake, R. (2002). V1 activity is reduced during
binocular rivalry. Journal of Vision (2002) 2, 618-626
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030722173225/http://journalofvision.org/2/9/4/article.pdf>
- Leopold, D.A. and Logothetis, N.K. (1999). Multistable phenomena:
changing views in perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 3:
254-264.
<http://www.kyb.tuebingen.mpg.de/publications/pdfs/pdf201.pdf>
- Libet, B., Alberts, E.W., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B.(1967).
Responses of Human Somatosensory Cortex to Stimuli Below Threshold
for Conscious Sensation. Science 158, 1597-1600.
- Libet, B., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B., and Pearl, D.(1979).
Subjective referral of the timing for a conscious sensory
experience. Brain, 102, pp. 192--224.
<http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/entrez/query.fcgi?holding=npg&cmd=Retrieve&db=PubMed&list_uids=427530&dopt=Abstract>
- Linden, D.E.J. (2005) The P300: Where in the Brain Is It Produced
and What Does It Tell Us? The Neuroscientist, Vol. 11, No. 6,
563-576 (2005) <http://nro.sagepub.com/cgi/reprint/11/6/563.pdf>
- Llinas, R., Ribary, U., Contreras, D. & Pedroarena, C. (1998). The
neuronal basis for consciousness. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London Ser.
B.353, 1841-1849
<http://big.cs.uiuc.edu/anncbt-papers/fall05/Llinas.the-neuronal-basis-of-consciousness.pdf>
- Logothetis, N.K., Leopold, D.A. and Sheinberg, D.L. (1996). What is
Rivalling During Binocular Rivalry. Nature, 380:621-624.
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nature/journal/v380/n6575/abs/380621a0.html>
- Loveblad, KO. et al. (1999). Silent functional magnetic resonance
imaging demonstrates focal activation in rapid eye movement sleep.
Neurology 1999;53:2193Z
- Luce, R.D. (1986). Response times: their role in inferring
elementary mental organization. Oxford University Press, New York.
- Lumer, E.D., Friston, K.J. & Rees, G. (1998) Neural correlates of
perceptual rivalry in the human brain. Science. 280(5371):1930-4.
- Macdonald, K.D., Fifkova, E., Jones, M.S. and Barth, D.S. (1998)
Focal Stimulation of the Thalamic Reticular Nucleus Induces Focal
Gamma Waves in Cortex. The Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 79 No. 1
January 1998, pp. 474--477
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/79/1/474>
- Maia, T.V. & Cleeremans, A. (2005). Consciousness: converging
insights from connectionist modeling and neuroscience. TRENDS in
Cognitive Sciences Vol.9 No.8 August 2005
<http://srsc.ulb.ac.be/axcWWW/papers/pdf/05-TICS.pdf>
- Marcel AJ. (1998). Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of
visual consciousness or visual function? Brain 1998, 121, 1565-1588.
<http://brain.oupjournals.org/cgi/reprint/121/8/1565.pdf>
- Marois, R., Yi, D-J., & Chun, M.M. (2004). The Neural Fate of
Consciously Perceived and Missed Events in the Attentional Blink.
Neuron, 41, 3: 465-472.
- Mashour, G.A., Tononi, G. and Massimini, M. (2005). Cognitive
Unbinding in Sleep and Anesthesia. Science 16 December 2005:
1768-1769.
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
<http://juno.ingentaselect.com/vl=6492085/cl=26/nw=1/rpsv/cgi-bin/cgi?body=linker&ini=nlm&reqidx=issn=0962-8452vl=264is=1380yr=1997mn=Marpg=393>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). Responses of Spectrally
Selective Cells in Macaque Area V2 to Wavelengths and Colors. J
Neurophysiol 87: 2104-2112, 2002.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/87/4/2104>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). The relationship between
cortical activation and perception investigated with invisible
stimuli. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA, 99(14):9527-9532.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/99/14/9527>
- Muckli, L., Singer, W., Zanella, F.E. and Goebel, R. (2002)
Integration of multiple motion vectors over space: an fMRI study of
transparent motion perception. Neuroimage. 2002 Aug;16(4):843-56.
- Munhall, K.G. (2001). Functional Imaging During Speech Production.
Acta Psychologica 107 (2001) 95-117.
<http://pavlov.psyc.queensu.ca/~munhallk/07_acta_version.pdf>
- Munk MHJ, Roelfsema PR, König P, Engel AK, and Singer W. (1996).
Role of reticular activation in the modulation of intracortical
synchronization Science. 272, 271-274.
- Newman, J. & Baars, B.J. (1993) A neural attentional model for
access to consciousness: A Global Workspace perspective. Concepts in
Neuroscience, 4:2, 255-290
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000073/>
- Nieuwenhuis S, Aston-Jones G & Cohen JD (2005). Decision making, the
P3, and the locus coeruleus-norepinephrine system. Psychological
Bulletin, 131(4), 510-532.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051117045339/http://www.csbmb.princeton.edu/conte/pdfs/project5/Proj5Pub06.pdf>
- Nørretranders, T. (1991) Consciousness: The User Illusion
(translated from Danish), Penguin Books,
; 1999 revision:
<http://www.worldcat.org/title/user-illusion-cutting-consciousness-down-to-size/oclc/41311618>.
- Pantev C (1995) Evoked and induced gamma-band activity of the human
cortex. Brain Topogr 7:321-330
- Pasley BN, Mayes LC, Schultz RT (2004) Subcortical discrimination of
unperceived objects during binocular rivalry. Neuron 2004,
42:163-172.
- Pessoa, L. (2005) To what extent are emotional visual stimuli
processed without attention and awareness? Current Opinion in
Neurobiology 2005, 15:188-196
<http://web.archive.org/web/20060623004726/http://www.brown.edu/Research/LCE/publications_files/Pessoa_CONB_2005.pdf>
- Pettigrew, J.D. (2001) Searching for the Switch: Neural Bases for
Perceptual Rivalry Alternations. Brain and Mind 2: 85-118, 2001.
<http://www.uq.edu.au/nuq/jack/searchswitch.pdf>
- Raymond, J. E, Shapiro, K. L., & Arnell, K. M. (1992). Temporary
suppression of visual processing in an RSVP task: An attentional
blink? Journal of Experimental Psychology. Human Perception and
Performance, 18 (3), 849-60.
- Rektor, I., Bares, M., Kanovsky, P. and Kukleta, M. (2001)
Intracerebral recording of readiness potential induced by a complex
motor task. Movement Disorders, Volume 16, Issue 4, Pages 698-704
- Rees, G., Kreiman, G., & Koch, C. (2002) Neural Correlates of
Consciousness in Humans. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3, 261
-270 (2002)
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nrn/journal/v3/n4/abs/nrn783_fs.html&dynoptions=doi1069842948>
- Rensink, RA. (2000). When Good Observers Go Bad: Change Blindness,
Inattentional Blindness, and Visual Experience. PSYCHE, 6(09),
August 2000.
<http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v6/psyche-6-09-rensink.html>
- Roy, J.E. & Prichep, L.S. (2005) The Anesthetic Cascade: A Theory of
How Anesthesia Suppresses Consciousness Anesthesiology: Volume
102(2) February 2005 pp 447--471
<http://www.anesthesiology.org/pt/re/anes/fulltext.00000542-200502000-00030.htm>
- Schiff, N.D., & Plum F. 1999. The Neurology of Impaired
Consciousness: Global Disorders and Implied Models. \[Target
article\]. Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness.
<http://www.phil.vt.edu/assc/niko.html>
- Schiff ND, Plum F. (2000) The Role of Arousal and \"Gating\" Systems
in the Neurology of Impaired Consciousness. Journal of
Neurophysiology. 17(5):438-452. (
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030924010953/http://www.uni-tuebingen.de/cog/lehre/ss2003/seminar_bewusstsein/epapers/SchiffPlum00.pdf>
- Sheinberg, D.L. and Logothetis, N.K. (1997). The role of temporal
cortical areas in perceptual organization. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA 94, 3408-3413. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/7/3408>
- Simons, D.J. & Rensink, RA. (2005). Change blindness: Past, present,
and future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol.9, pp16--20, No.1
January 2005.
<http://www.psych.ubc.ca/~rensink/publications/download/S&R-TICS-05a.pdf>
- Singer, W. & Gray, C.W. (1995). Visual feature integration and the
temporal correlation hypothesis. Annu. Rev. Neurosci., 18,
pp. 555--86, 1995.
- Singer, W. (2001). Consciousness and the Binding Problem. Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences 929:123-146 (2001)
- Solms, Mark (2000) DREAMING AND REM SLEEP ARE CONTROLLED BY
DIFFERENT BRAIN MECHANISMS, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23
(6): 793.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/Preprints/OldArchive/bbs.solms.html>
- Soon, C.S., Brass, M., Heinze, H-J. and Haynes, J-D. (2008).
Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain.
Nature Neuroscience 11, 543 - 545 (2008)
- Sukov, W. & Barth, D.S. (2001). Cellular Mechanisms of Thalamically
Evoked Gamma Oscillations in Auditory Cortex. J Neurophysiol 85:
1235-1245, 2001;
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/85/3/1235>
- Takeuchi, T., Miyasita, A., Inugami, M. & Yamamoto, Y. (2001).
Intrinsic dreams are not produced without REM sleep mechanisms:
evidence through elicitation of sleep onset REM periods. Journal of
Sleep Research Volume 10 Issue 1 Page 43 - March 2001
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tamás, G., Buh, E.H., Lörincz, A., and Somogyi, P. (2000).
Proximally targeted GABAergic synapses and gap junctions synchronize
cortical interneurons. Nature Neuroscience volume 3 no 4 April 2000.
<http://mrcanu.pharm.ox.ac.uk/pdfs/TamasNatureNeurosci2000.pdf>
- Tanaka, Y. & Sagi, D. (1998). A perceptual memory for low contrast
visual signals. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol 95:12729-12733.
<http://www.weizmann.ac.il/~masagi/TS98b.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2001). Competing Theories of Binocular Rivalry: A Possible
Resolution. Brain and Mind 2: 55-83, 2001
<http://web.archive.org/web/20041212094810/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_Brain&Mind2001.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual Awareness. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030723135239/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
- Tootell, R.B., Reppas, J.B., Dale, A.M., Look, R.B., Sereno, M.I.,
Malach, R., Brady, T.J. and Rosen, B.R. (1995) Visual motion
aftereffect in human cortical area MT revealed by functional
magnetic resonance imaging. Nature. 1995 May 11;375(6527):139-41.
- Tononi, G., Srinivasan, R., Russell, P.D. & Edelman, G.M. (1998).
Investigating neural correlates of conscious perception by
frequency-tagged neuromagnetic responses . Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA. Vol. 95, Issue 6, 3198-3203, March 17, 1998
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/95/6/3198>
- Thornton, I.M., Pinto, J. and Shiffrar, M. (1998).
THE VISUAL PERCEPTION OF HUMAN LOCOMOTION. COGNITIVE NEUROPSYCHOLOGY,
1998, 15 (6/7/8 ), 535-552.
<http://psychology.rutgers.edu/~mag/TPS98.pdf>
- Traub, D.R., Whittington, M.A., Buhl, E.H., Jefferys, J.G.R., &
Faulkner, H.J. (1999). On the Mechanism of the Frequency Shift in
Neuronal Oscillations Induced in Rat Hippocampal Slices by Tetanic
Stimulation. The Journal of Neuroscience, February 1, 1999,
19(3):1088-1105
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/3/1088>
- Traub, R.D. (2003). Fast Oscillations and Epilepsy. Epilepsy Curr.
2003 May; 3(3): 77-79.
<http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/articlerender.fcgi?artid=321178>
- Trevena J & Miller, J (2002) Cortical Movement Preparation before
and after a Conscious Decision to Move. Consciousness and Cognition,
Volume 11, Issue 2, June 2002, Pages 162-190
- Trevena, J & Miller, J (2009) Brain preparation before a voluntary
action: Evidence against unconscious movement initiation. Conscious
Cogn. 2009 Sep 5. \[Epub ahead of print\]
- Tse, P.U., Susana Martinez-Conde, S., Schlegel, A.A. and Macknik,
S.L. (2005). Visibility, visual awareness, and visual masking of
simple unattended targets are confined to areas in the occipital
cortex beyond human V1/V2. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA November 22,
2005 vol. 102 no. 47. 17178-17183.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/102/47/17178>
- Uchida, N., Kepecs, A. and Mainen, Z.F. (2006) Seeing at a glance,
smelling in a whiff: rapid forms of perceptual decision making.
Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 7. 485-491.
- Uchida, N & Mainen, Z.F. (2003) Speed and accuracy of olfacory
discrimination in the rat. Nature Neurosci. 6, 1224-1229.
- Vogel, E.K., Luck, S.J. & Shapiro, K.L. (1998) Electrophysiological
Evidence for a Postperceptual Locus of Suppression During the
Attentional Blink. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
Perception and Performance 1998, Vol. 24. No. 6,1656-1674
<http://web.archive.org/web/20050304211722/http://www.psychology.uiowa.edu/faculty/Luck/lucklab/pdfs/Vogel_1998_JEPHPP.pdf>
- Wehrle, R., Czisch, M., Kaufmann, C., Wetter, T.C., Holsboer, F.,
Auer, D.P., and Pollmacher, T. (2005). Rapid eye movement-related
brain activation in human sleep: a functional magnetic resonance
imaging study. NeuroReport 16:853-857
<http://www.univie.ac.at/mcogneu/lit/wehrle.pdf>
- White, NS., Alkire, MT. (2003). Impaired thalamocortical
connectivity in humans during
general-anesthetic-induced unconsciousness. NeuroImage. Volume 19, Issue
2 , June 2003, Pages 402-411. <http://smallurl.com?i=2597>
(http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/B6WNP-48GP5CG-5/1/cedb33dc0bec4301d1960c7c27cea70f)
- Wheeler, M.E., Buckner, R.L.. (2003) Functional dissociation among
components
of remembering: control, perceived oldness, and content. J. Neurosci.
23, 3869-3880.
- Williams LM, Liddell BJ, Rathjen J, Brown KJ, Shevrin H, Gray JA,
Phillips M, Young A & Gordon E (2004). Mapping the time course of
nonconscious and conscious perception of fear: An integration of
central and peripheral measures. Human Brain Mapping,21, 64 - 74
<http://psychmed.iop.kcl.ac.uk/neuroscience-and-emotion/downloads/46.pdf>
- Wunderlich, K. Schneider, K.A., & Kastner, S. (2005).Neural
correlates of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate
nucleus. Nature Neuroscience 8, 1595 - 1602 (2005)
- Yamamoto, T. & Katayama, Y. (2005). Deep brain stimulation therapy
for the vegetative state. in Neuropsychol Rehabil. 2005 Jul-Sep ;
15(3-4): 406-13
- Zeki, S., & Bartel, A. (1999). Toward a Theory of Visual
Consciousness. Consciousness & Cognition, 8, 225-259.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Neuroscience 2#The "cognitive map" and the neural basis of perceptual space
*Contributors: please include full data in the references section for
all references in the text.*
```{=html}
<div class="noprint">
```
Home
```{=html}
</div>
```
## Perceptual \"filling in\"
Perceptual \"filling in\" occurs when visual properties such as
textures, colours, brightness or motion are extended in the visual field
to areas where they do not have corresponding events in the world.
The filling in of the blind spot by the properties of the field in the
contralateral eye has already been discussed. The part of the visual
field represented by the blind spot is also \"filled in\" in the case of
monocular vision.
![](Constudblindill.png "Constudblindill.png")
Shut the right eye and focus on the pink cross with the left eye, if the
head is moved towards the pink cross there is a point at which the
yellow disk disappears but the white lines are still present. In this
\"filling in\" the visual field does not appear to be distorted.
Fiorani *et al.* (1992) developed a technique for probing the cortical
blind spot using vertical and horizontal bar stimuli. Matsumoto &
komatsu (2005) used this technique on macaque monkeys. In the monocular
case they found that as a bar was moved across the visual field so that
it crossed the blind spot there was a sudden change in neural activity
in the deep layers of the neurons in the blind spot area of V1. When the
bar was moved across the same part of the visual field of the
contralateral eye the neural activity in the blind spot area increased
steadily as the bar was moved. The authors found that there were neurons
in the deep layers of blind spot cortex that had elongated receptive
fields that could respond to stimuli outside the blind spot and transfer
this activation into the blind spot cortex.
Filling in of a slightly different type occurs in \"scotoma\". In
scotoma an area of the retina is damaged and unresonsive to visual
stimuli, immediately after the damage patients report an area of visual
field that is unresponsive to stimuli. After several months patients
report that the area of field represented by the scotoma contains visual
properties related to the physical world surrounding the area that would
have formed an image on the scotoma. This results in a distortion of the
visual field. (see for instance Gilbert(1993)). Direct measurements of
activity in cortical area V1 show that the neurons that represented the
area of the scotoma become sensitive to activity in the surrounding
visual field. At the cortical level the scotoma is literally \"filled
in\".
There are many stimuli that cause \"filling in\". These stimuli are
known as \"illusions\" because they produce phenomenal experience that
has no correlate in the world outside the body. In the \"neon colour
spreading illusion\" a lightly coloured circle appears where there
should be a white background. Sasaki and Watanabe (2004) used fMRI to
show that the part of the topographic map in cortical area V1
corresponding to the light coloured circle was activated.
![](Constudneon.jpg "Constudneon.jpg")
Fiorani, M., Rosa, M.G.P., Gattas, R. & Rocha-Miranda, C.E. (1992).
Dynamic surrounds of receptive fields in primate striate cortex: a
physiological basis for perceptual completion? Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
89, 8547-8551. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/abstract/89/18/8547>
Gilbert, C.D. (1993). Circuitry, architecture and functional dynamics of
visual cortex.
Matsumoto, M & Komatsu, H. (2005). Neural responses in the macaque V1 to
bar stimuli with various lengths presented on the blind spot. J
neurophysiol. 93. 2374-2387.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/abstract/93/5/2374>
Sasaki, Y & Watanabe, T. The primary visual cortex fills in colour.
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 101, 18251-18256. (2004).
## Binocular Rivalry, Pattern Rivalry and Binocular Fusion
Sir Charles Wheatstone (1838) was the first scientist to systematically
investigate binocular rivalry. Binocular rivalry occurs when different
images are presented to the left and right eyes. The subject sees
successively one image, a combined image and then the other image. The
swapping of images can take a second or more. Binocular rivalry is of
interest in consciousness research because the parts of the brain that
contain the dominant image should also be those parts that are
contributing to conscious experience. Binocular rivalry involves at
least two components; the first switches from one image to a merged
image and then to the other image and the second permits the view to be
part of conscious experience.
![](Constudrival.png "Constudrival.png")
The switching of one image for another may involve selecting one of the
images as the percept or selecting one of the eyes. Blake *et al.*
(1979) performed an experiment in which subjects could change the image
at a given eye by pressing a button. When a particular image became
dominant they pressed a button to change the image at the eye receiving
the dominant image for the non-dominant image. They found that the
subjects immediately experienced the second image as the dominant image.
This suggests that binocular rivalry is selecting between eyes rather
than images. Lehky in 1988 proposed that the switching may be occurring
as a result of feedback between visual cortical area V1 and the Lateral
Geniculate Nucleus (a thalamic relay - see Carandini *et al.* 2002) and
Blake in 1989 also proposed that the switching occurred at the level of
area V1. (Visual cortical area V1 receives visual input direct from the
LGN.)
Tong (2001) has argued that, in humans, the switching of images in
binocular rivalry may occur at the earliest levels in the visual cortex.
In particular, Tong and Engel (2001) used an elegant technique measuring
the activity in the visual cortex that represents the blind spot of the
eye to show that almost complete switching to the dominant image occurs
at the level of visual cortical area V1. In support of this idea of
switching at the level of V1 or even before the cortex, Kreimann *et
al.* (2001, 2002) used direct electrode recordings in human cortex and
found that the activity of most neurons changed with the percept. Other
experiments have not shown a single locus in the brain where the
suppressed sensory information gets switched out (Blake & Logothetis
2002, Leopold & Logothetis 1996, Gail et al., 2004).
Functional MRI has also shown cortical activity outside of sensory
visual cortex related to both images in binocular rivalry. Lumer *et
al.* (1998) found that only the fronto-parietal areas of cortex switched
with the percept, Fang & He (2005) found that activity relating to both
suppressed and unsuppressed images were present in the dorsal stream of
the visual system. Wunderlich *et al.* (2005) and Haynes *et al.* (2005)
have both found suppression at the level of the lateral geniculate
nucleus using fMRI in humans.
Pasley *et al.* (2004) have shown that, even during suppression, fearful
faces can produce activity in the amygdala (see Pessoa (2005) for a
review).
Rivalry alternations seem to be the result of widespread activity
changes that cover large parts of the brain, including but not
necessarily originating at the earliest sensory stages of visual
processing. Most investigators have found that, once switching has
occurred, there are areas of the brain that contain activity that is
solely related to the percept but this varies from most of the cortex to
largely more frontal regions depending upon the study. The most likely
explanation for binocular rivalry is that the switching occurs at the
level of the LGN as a result of feedback from the cortex.
Pattern Rivalry is also of interest in consciousness research for the
same reasons as binocular rivalry. In pattern rivalry a figure may have
two or more forms that replace each other. Typical examples of such
figures are the Necker cube and Rubin\'s face-vase. The similarity of
the time course of the switching between percepts in binocular rivalry
and pattern rivalry has led many authors to suggest that these involve
the same mechanism. Logothetis *et al.* (1996) used novel dichoptic
stimuli (different images to each eyes) to produce a form of rivalry
that seems to involve switching at levels in the cerebral cortex that
are more distal to the sensory stimulus than V1. Leopold and Logothetis
(1999), on the basis of their work with monkeys, state that \"..many
neurons throughout the visual system, both monocular and binocular,
continue to respond to a stimulus even when it is perceptually
suppressed.\". Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998) investigated pattern rivalry
with MRI and found activity in higher order visual areas during change
of dominant pattern. Pettigrew (2001) also describes effects on rivalry
due to thought and mood that may require involvement of large areas of
cortex in the switching operation and stresses the way that V1
represents different visual fields in different hemispheres of the brain
so that inter-hemispheric switching must also be considered.
It seems likely that the change of dominant pattern or percept is
associated with higher level cortical activity but once the dominant
percept is established many of the visually responsive neurons in the
cortex are switched over to the new percept. This might account for the
similarities in timing of binocular and pattern rivalry and the
disparate results found by the various groups of authors. In the words
of Kleinschmidt *et al.* (1998):
\"The transient activity fluctuations we found suggest that perceptual
metastability elicited by ambiguous stimuli is associated with rapid
redistributions of neural activity between separate specialized cortical
and subcortical structures.\"
Which permits both the idea of selecting particular eyes or percepts,
perhaps by feedback that switches a thalamic relay on the basis of
cortical processing of patterns. Once the cortex has switched the
thalamic relay most of the neurons in V1 would become exposed to the
dominant percept but there would still be a few neurons in the cortical
visual system receiving data from the non dominant image.
The investigations of binocular and pattern rivalry provide evidence
that conscious visual experience is probably distal to V1 (i.e.: cortex
or thalamus).
Perceptual rivalry may be part of complex decision making rather than
being simply a switch to blank out unwelcome input. It is clear from the
Rubin face-vase that pattern rivalry is linked to recognition and would
involve a complex delineation of forms within cortical processing. This
would suggest that many areas of cortex should be involved before a
particular percept is made dominant. Pettigrew (2001) argues that
rivalry is the result of a complex phenomenon rather than being simply a
switching event. Pettigrew\'s discovery that laughter abolishes rivalry
also points to a complex cortical system for switching percepts.
Pettigrew proposes that complex cortical processes control rivalry and
that the actual switching of percepts is performed sub-cortically in the
Ventral Tegmental Area. He concludes his review of the problem by noting
that \"Rivalry may thus reflect fundamental aspects of perceptual
decision making..\" Pettigrew (2001).
Another effect, known as \"binocular fusion\", provides further
compelling evidence for the non-conscious nature of the cerebral cortex.
In binocular fusion images from both eyes are fused together to create a
single image in experience. Moutoussis and Zeki (2002) used a form of
binocular fusion in which images of faces were flashed at 100ms
intervals to both eyes simultaneously. When both eyes received images of
the same colour the subject could see the faces but when one eye
received a green image on a red background and the other a red image on
a green background the subjects reported seeing a uniform yellow field
that contained no faces.
fMRI scans of the subject\'s brains showed that when both eyes were
exposed to images of the same colour the part of the brain that deals
with faces was active and when each eye received images of different
colours the same areas of brain showed activity. In other words the
cortex contained strong activity related to faces whether or not faces
were experienced. Moutoussis and Zeki found a similar effect when they
used images of houses instead of images of faces. The authors concluded
that: \"The present study further suggests that there are no separate
processing and perceptual areas but rather that the same cortical
regions are involved in both the processing and, when certain levels of
activation are reached and probably in combination with the activation
of other areas as well, the generation of a conscious visual percept\".
This conclusion does not seem to be supported by the data. There is no
evidence that any area of cortex contains the percept itself. The
experiment shows that the cortex contains data relating to both red and
green faces which suggests that the cortex is not the site of the
conscious percept. The percept is most likely distal to the cortex
perhaps in the thalamus or some other area that receives cortical
sensory output.
It is interesting that Fries *et al.* (1997) found that neurons that
were activated by the dominant image in binocular rivalry fired
synchronously whereas those that were activated by the non-dominant
image did not. Thalamocorticothalamic oscillations are the most likely
source for synchronising neurons over whole areas of cortex, suggesting
that the conscious percept is located in the thalamus rather than the
cortex.
## Synchronisation of Neural Processes
Our experience seems to contain entities with their attributes attached
to them at the correct places in space and time. When a dog barks we see
its jaws open at the same time as the bark and both jaws and bark are at
the same location. We take this for granted but the brain must be
engaging in some complex processing to achieve this synchronised and
appropriately positioned set of objects and events. The illustration
below shows the two basic processes that might be used to synchronise
events between the different specialised processors in the cerebral
cortex and brain in general.
![](Constudsynch.gif "Constudsynch.gif")
In the first option a complete model of sensation, dream etc. may be
created and then allowed to become part of conscious experience. In the
second model events are released into experience as fast as possible but
are synchronous when recalled, having been synchronised in a storage
buffer. There is a third option in which there is no synchronisation of
events so that the output from different processors would occur at
different times.
The \'experience buffer\' would be a volume of brain in which a
succession of events could be recorded. The buffer might either be
updated in steps, the previous content being discarded, or continuously
updated with the oldest content being lost continuously.
In the first option events from different processes would always appear
to be simultaneous unless the experience buffer were updated as a series
of steps in which case any changes at around the moment of updating
might appear in successive buffers. For instance, if change of position
were processed before change in colour a circle on a screen that changed
from green to red at the start of a motion might seem to be briefly
green during the motion and then turn red.
In the second model events from different processors might appear
asynchronous at the moment of experience but synchronous when recalled.
Colour vision and motion vision are processed in different parts of the
visual cortex and in distinct parts of visual cortical areas V1 and V2.
They are different processes and hence ideal for studying the
synchronisation of cortical activity. Moutoussis and Zeki (1997)
presented subjects with moving coloured squares on a computer screen
that changed from red to green or vice versa as they changed direction
of movement. It was found that subjects seemed to perceive changes in
colour some 70-80 msecs before they perceived a change in the direction
of motion of the squares. Further work by Arnold *et al.* (2001) and
Arnold and Clifford (2001) have confirmed that colour changes seem to be
perceived before motion. Arnold and Clifford (2001) also found a
quantitative relationship between the colour/motion asynchrony and the
direction of change of motion, complete reversals of direction giving
rise to the greatest asynchrony between the detection of colour and
motion changes.
Moutoussis and Zeki (1997) conclude by stating that the asynchrony of
neural processes shows that \"..the perception of each attribute is
solely the result of the activity in the specialised system involved in
its processing..\". It seems more likely that the experiments simply
show that slow neural processes are not synchronised before they become
percepts (the third option above). The experiments are excellent
evidence for the concept of the cortex as a set of specialised
processors that deliver their output asynchronously to some other place
where the output becomes a percept.
These experiments on colour and motion suggest that there is no
synchronisation between the processes that deal with these two aspects
of vision. Another set of experiments by Clifford *et al.* (2003)
supports this idea of processing being asynchronous. They asked subjects
to perform a variety of judgements of when visual events occurred and
found that the degree of synchrony of one visual event with another
depends on the type of judgement. Different judgements probably use
processors in different areas of cortex and the output from these
arrives asynchronously at the part of the brain that supports the
percept.
When the percept is formed there must be feedback to the cortical
processes that create its content. Otherwise it would not be possible to
report about the percept and the cortex would be unable to direct
processing to the percept in preference to other, non-conscious cortical
data.
Although slow processes (20 milliseconds to 1 second) do not seem to be
synchronised there is some evidence for very rapid synchronisation.
Andrews *et al.* (1996) revisited a problem raised by the famous
physiologist Charles Sherrington. Sherrington considered the phenomenon
of \'flicker fusion\' in which a flickering light appears to be a
continuous steady light if it flashes on and off at frequencies of about
45 Hz or higher. He reasoned that if the images from both eyes are
brought together to form a single image then the frequency at which a
flickering light appears to be steady should depend on whether one or
two eyes are used. Flicker fusion should occur if each eye receives
alternate flashes at only half the normal flicker fusion frequency. The
flicker should disappear if the left eye receives flashes at 23 pulses
per second and the right eye receives alternate flashes at 23 pulses per
second. When Sherrington performed the experiment he found that this was
not the case, using approximate figures, each eye required 46 pulses per
second for fusion to occur. Sherrington proposed that the flicker fusion
in alternate binocular presentation was occurring \"psychically\",
outside of normal physiological processes.
Andrews *et al.* duplicated Sherrington\'s result but investigated it
further. They found that when lights were flashed in each eye
alternately at low frequences (2 Hz) the experience was the same as a
light being flashed in both eyes at this rate. At frequencies of four Hz
and higher the subjects began to report that the lights being flashed
alternately in both eyes seemed to flicker at the same rate as lights
being flashed in both eyes at half the frequency. It seemed as if a
flash in one eye followed by a flash in the other eye was being
perceived as a single flash or \"conflated\" as the authors put it. The
authors explained this effect by suggesting that the brain activity
corresponding to the flashes was sampled for a short period and any
number of flashes occurring during this period became perceived as a
single flash. The maximum rate of sampling would be about 45 Hz. This
idea is similar to option (1) above, where the buffer is filled and
emptied 40 - 50 times a second.
An experience buffer that is refreshed at 40-50 times a second might
also explain the results obtained with colour and motion asynchrony
because synchronisation between processes may well happen too quickly to
affect processes that occur at very slow rates. Singer and Gray (1995),
Singer (2001) have proposed that synchronisation between neurones at
about 45 Hz is the discriminator between those neurones with activity
that contributes to conscious experience and activity in other neurones.
A rapid refresh rate in a synchronising buffer agrees with the results
found by Fries *et al.* (1997) in which visual cortical neurones that
represent a percept underwent synchronous oscillations in the gamma
frequency range (39--63 Hz). Tononi *et al.* (1998) have also found
synchronisation of neural activity in neurones that represent the
percept.
The gamma frequency oscillations are intrinsic to the cortex but are
triggered by the thalamus and are part of the \'arousal system\'.
Readers should be wary of the term \'arousal system\' because it evokes
the idea of something waking up a conscious cortex. The cortex can be
fully active during sleep and even during pathological unconsciousness
such as persistent vegetative state so it is possible that the arousal
centres themselves or nearby structures actually host phenomenal
consciousness.
## EEG and synchronisation
If electrodes are placed on the scalp varying electrical potentials of a
few tens of microvolts can be recorded between the electrodes.
Recordings of potentials from electrodes on the scalp are known as
electroencephalograms (EEGs).
The potentials recorded in the EEG are due to postsynaptic potentials in
nerve cells. The EEG is insensitive to the activity of single cells and
occurs as a result of relatively slow, **synchronised**, changes in
large areas of cells. The differences in potential between two scalp
electrodes are largely due to depolarisation and hyperpolarisation of
the dendritic trees of cortical pyramidal cells. The folding of the
cortex (gyri) is problematical for recording and interpreting EEGs
because opposing layers of cortex can cancel any net potentials.
The EEG shows rhythmic activity. This is conventionally divided into the
following frequency bands:
Delta waves 0--4 Hz
Theta waves 4--8 Hz
Alpha waves 8--12 Hz
Beta waves \>10 Hz
Gamma waves (also called fast beta) 25--100 Hz
EEGs also contain short bursts of activity called spindles and very fast
oscillations (VFOs). Spindles last for 1--2 seconds and contain rhythmic
activity at 7--14 Hz. They are associated with the onset of sleep. The
VFOs consist of short bursts at frequencies of over 80 Hz.
When the eyes are closed the amplitude of activity from most pairs of
electrodes is increased compared with when the eyes are open. When
subjects are awake the EEG consists mainly of alpha and beta activity
with considerable low amplitude gamma when the eyes are open. In stage 1
sleep the EEG consists of theta waves, in stage 2 sleep of varied
activity and spindles, in stage 4 sleep of delta and during REM sleep of
beta and theta activity. In epileptic seizures there tends to be high
amplitude activity with pronounced synchronisation between many pairs of
electrodes.
The rhythmic electrical activity is due to cortical feedback loops,
cortico-cortical synchronisation, thalamic pacemakers and
thalamo-cortical synchronisation. VFOs have been attributed to the
activity of electrical connections between cells (dendro-dendritic gap
junctions) (Traub (2003)).
The gamma activity, centred on a frequency of 40 Hz appears to be
related to activity in cortical interneurons that form electrical
connections between their dendrites (Tamas *et al.* 2000). These
oscillations can be triggered by high frequency stimulation of the
posterior intralaminar nuclei of the thalamus (Barth and MacDonald 1996,
Sukov and Barth 2001) and as a result of activation of the reticular
system (Munk *et al.* 1996). This suggests that stimulation of cortex by
thalamic sensory relays triggers gamma band activity in the cortex. A
shift from gamma to beta waves can occur in human event related
potentials after about 0.2 secs (Pantev 1995, Traub *et al.* 1999).
The alpha activity is related to thalamic pacemakers, perhaps as a
result of intrinsic oscillatory activity in thalamic sensory relays (see
Roy & Prichep 2005 for a brief review). Theta activity, which occurs
during some cognitive tasks and mental arithmetic involves a loop from
the cortex to the non-specific thalamic nuclei. Delta activity seems to
be endogenous to cortex when input is suppressed during sleep. Beta
activity is due to cortico-cortical interactions, often after a brief
period of gamma activation. It should be noted that gamma and beta
activity can be expressed as impulses in cortico-thalamic pathways and
that when cortical and thalamic activity is correlated there is a
conscious state. In other words gamma or beta waves in the cortex are
not correlates of consciousness on their own - see for instance Laureys
*et al.* (2002).
## Event related potentials
After a sudden event there are a characteristic set of changes in EEG
activity known as **event related potentials** or ERPs. The time course
of the ERP is shown in the diagram below.
![](Constudevent.png "Constudevent.png")
ERPs occur in response to novel stimuli and are also produced by brief
transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS)(Iramina *et al.* 2002). The slow
component is known as the P3 or P300 phase of the ERP. It is due to
activation of areas of the brain that are relatively remote from the
primary sensory areas of brain.
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) have reviewed the origin of the P300 ERP:
\"To summarize, convergent evidence suggests that P3-like activity can
be recorded in several, widely separated brain areas. These include some
medial temporal and subcortical structures (e.g., the hippocampal
formation, amygdala, and thalamus), but these structures are unlikely to
contribute directly to the scalp-recorded P3.\". According to
Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005) the recorded P300 may be due to
temporo-parietal and prefrontal cortical activity. Linden (2005) has
also concluded that widespread, but specific, cortical activation is
correlated with the recorded P300 ERP.
The generator of the P300 is still obscure. Nieuwenhuis *et al.* (2005)
consider that the Locus coeruleus, a nucleus in the pons that regulates
task related attention and part of the sleep-wake cycle, may be
responsible. In line with this, Mashour *et al.* (2005) have discovered
that TMS induced P300 activity is reduced in unconscious states.
Whether the P300 is related to Libet\'s 0.5 second delay is still
obscure but the discovery that the P300 occurs in association with
subliminal stimuli (stimuli that do not enter awareness)(Bernat *et al.*
2001) suggests that it is associated with non-conscious cortical
processing. Williams *et al.* (2004), in an investigation of subliminal
and supraliminal fear perception, found that \"conscious fear perception
was distinguished by a more prominent N4, peaking around 400 msec\"; the
N4 component follows the P300 component in the succession of phases of
the ERP. Williams *et al.* considered that the earlier phases in the ERP
are probably related to non-conscious processing. In contrast Vogel *et
al.* (1998) found that suppression of the P300 was associated with
suppression of awareness.
## The integration delay
Psychological experiments often involve binary decisions where subjects
give one of two outputs in response to stimuli. It is found that if the
stimuli are made increasingly noisy or complex the response time tends
to increase. Psychophyicists have developed various mathematical models
to explain the increased response times due to noise such as the
Integrator and Accumulator models (cf: Luce(1986)). These models have
been fairly successful when explaining experiments such as judging the
net direction of movement of sets of dots on a screen when the dots are
given semi-random paths and different brightness etc. In these
circumstances it can take up to 2 seconds for an accurate decision.
There are many tasks however where the accuracy of decision making does
not improve after about 300 milliseconds. The accuracy of the
performance of rats when choosing between two alternatives when reacting
to odours peaks at about 300 ms (Uchida and Mainen(2003), Abraham *et
al.* (2004)). The accuracy of humans when performing vernier acuity
tasks, line detection, contrast sensitivity, motion velocity
discrimination and stereoscopic depth discrimination seems to peak at
300ms (Uchida *et al.* 2006).
Uchida, Kepecs and Mainen (2006) suggest that \"rapid and short
integration time is a sensible strategy for rapid processing of
low-level sensory information in order to form more complex sensory
images, both in vision and olfaction.\" Whether these authors regard
these derived sensory images as the content of consciousness is not
mentioned. The authors propose that the 300ms optimal integration time
may be partly due to the mechanics of sniffing (a sniff takes about
125-200ms) and the nature of optical fixation (inter-saccade intervals
are typically 200-400 ms ). The authors note that the animal or human
could, in principle, choose to integrate over longer intervals but if it
is moving this may not lead to information that is current for changed
circumstances.
An optimal processing time of about 300 ms would be consistent with the
delays observed before conscious awareness occurs in response to a
stimulus - an interval required to form \"more complex sensory images\".
## Global Workspace Theory
Global Workspace Theory is the idea that somewhere in the brain there is
a facility that integrates the processes that occur in the various
separate areas of the brain. The theory was first proposed by Descartes
as the *sensus communis*, the common sense, but the modern form of the
theory dispenses with the idea of a point soul looking at the brain. In
modern Global Workspace theory it is proposed that an area of brain
receives input from most of the cerebral cortex and broadcasts its
outputs to all of the unconscious modular information processors in the
brain.
Modern Global Workspace Theory has been championed by Baars (1983,
1988).
There is increasing evidence for a Global Workspace or Global Workspaces
in the brain. Much of this evidence comes from fMRI, single unit and
magnetoencephalography studies in which it is shown that non-conscious
or subliminal processing mainly occupies primary, sensory cortex whereas
conscious processing occupies large areas of cerebral cortex.
In binocular rivalry the stimulus that is consciously perceived is
responsible for relatively intense activation of large areas of brain
whereas the non-conscious stimulus is often suppressed (see above and
Sheinberg & Logothetis (1997), Tononi *et al.* (1998)). The suppression
is likely to occur in the Lateral Geniculate Nuclei which suggests a
role for the Thalamic Reticular Nuclei, which modulate LGN activity, in
the control of the percept.
### Masking and visual awareness
Word masking has also been used to investigate the idea of a Global
Workspace. When a word is presented on its own for a few tens of
milliseconds it remains readable but if it is immediately succeeded by,
or accompanied by, another word it becomes indistinct or invisible. This
effect is known as \"word masking\". Vogel *et al.* (1998) have
investigated a version of word masking known as the \"attentional
blink\". They found that when stimuli became invisible the P3 component
of the Event Related Potential, which peaks at around 300-500 millisecs
after a stimulus, was completely suppressed. The P3 component of the ERP
has been related to the lodging of data in working memory and also to
gamma band activity in the EEG. This strongly suggests the involvement
of a cortico-thalamic loop in the \"attentional blink\". The delay of
0.3 to 0.5 secs is typical of the time required for conscious awareness
(see above).
Word masking in conjunction with fMRI and Event Related Potential (ERP)
recordings has been used by Dehaene *et al.* (2001) to expose control by
a central mechanism. It was found that masked words activate mainly the
visual cortex and ventral stream (inferior temporal lobe) whereas
visible words also activated distant parietal, prefrontal and cingulate
sites.
Dehaene *et al.* (2003) and found that the dynamics of the loss of
visibility of words in an attentional blink experiment could be modelled
by a simulated cortico-thalamic loop. In their simulation a distributed
cortical process determined which events would receive attention and the
system used the thalamic gating systems to exclude those that did not
receive attention.
Tse *et al.* (2005) have used purely visual stimuli in masking
experiments and concluded that, in the case of purely visual stimuli,
the neural correlates of awareness were limited to the occipital cortex:
\"We suggest that there are both lower and upper bounds within the
visual hierarchy for the processing of visual masking and the
maintenance of visual awareness of simple unattended targets; the lower
bound is at least as high as the border between V2 and V3, and the upper
bound is within the occipital lobe, possibly somewhere downstream of
V4.\"
This discovery would mean that activation of large areas of cortex are
unnecessary for awareness.
Melloni *et al.* (2007) compared compared the electrophysiological
responses related to the processing of visible and invisible words in a
delayed matching to sample task. Both perceived and nonperceived words
caused a similar increase of local (gamma) oscillations in the EEG, but
only perceived words induced a transient long-distance synchronization
of gamma oscillations across widely separated regions of the brain.
After this transient period of temporal coordination, the electrographic
signatures of conscious and unconscious processes continue to diverge.
Only words reported as perceivedinduced (1) enhanced theta oscillations
over frontal regions during the maintenance interval, (2) an increase of
the P300 component of the event-related potential, and (3) an increase
in power and phase synchrony of gamma oscillationsbefore the anticipated
presentation of the test word. We propose that the critical process
mediating the access to conscious perception is the earlytransient
global increase of phase synchrony of oscillatory activity in the
gammafrequency.
Melloni L, Molina C, Pena M, Torres D, Singer W, Rodriguez E. (2007).
Synchronization of neural activity across cortical areas correlates
withconscious perception.J Neurosci. 2007 Mar 14;27(11):2858-65.
### Attention and the global workspace
Baars (2002) in his review of evidence for the Global Workspace Theory
quotes many other experiments that show activation of larger areas of
cortex in response to conscious stimuli compared with unconscious or
subliminal stimuli.The effect is also seen in change blindness, learning
and attention. Newman and Baars (1993) consider that the \"workspace\"
is fairly global in the brain:
\"This Neural Global Workspace (NGW) model views conscious processes in
terms of a globally integrative brain system. The neural circuitry
contributing to this system is not only widely distributed across the
neocortex, but includes key corticothalamic and midbrain circuits as
well. These cortico-subcortical circuits are hypothesized to be critical
to understanding the mechanisms of attentional control that provide an
essential basis for the conscious processing of information\".
However they focus particularly on the role of the thalamic Reticular
Nucleus and cortico-thalamic connectivity in the control of attention.
Other ideas for the location of the Global Workspace are the idea of
Singer et al. that gamma synchrony controls access to the content of
consciousness and Llinas et al. (1998) that the thalamus is the hub
through which communication occurs between areas of cortex.
One of the problems with Global Workspace theory is that it suggests
that attention, working memory, cognitive control and consciousness may
all be in the same area of the brain. It is likely that the mechanisms
of attention, working memory, and cognitive control may involve several,
interlinked systems perhaps co-opting the basal ganglia in the process.
In view of this Maia and Cleeremans (2005) propose that \".. attention,
working memory, cognitive control and consciousness are not distinct
functions implemented by separate brain systems. Attempting to find
separate neural correlates for each may therefore be the wrong approach.
Instead, we suggest that they should be understood in terms of the
dynamics of global competition, with biasing from PFC (prefrontal
cortex).\". The inclusion by Maia and Cleeremans of consciousness with
distributed attention, working memory and cognitive control is
reminiscent of Zeki & Bartel\'s idea of microconsciousness.
It should be noted that, in common with Libet\'s data, the percept seems
to be available to phenomenal consciousness some 0.3 to 0.5 secs after a
stimulus; this suggests that whatever determines the content of
phenomenal consciousness operates before events become part of
phenomenal consciousness. This relegates phenomenal consciousness from
being a controller of attention to being the recipient of content that
is the subject of attention. This finding is consistent with the
philosophical problem of the **apparently** epiphenomenal nature of
phenomenal consciousness.
Given the data on the timing of conscious awareness it seems that there
may be two \"workspaces\", an active workspace that models the world,
discarding and suppressing data during rivalry, and a passive workspace
that receives the final, edited product. The active workspace would
correlate with the cortical systems stressed by Dehaene *et al.* and
Maia and Cleermans although, given the results of Tse et al., the
workspace would be limited to small zones of cortex. The loading of the
passive workspace with the output of the active workspace would
correlate with thalamo-cortical activity during component P3 of the ERP
in which data is transferred from the cortex to the thalamus. This
workspace might constitute the source for reports of the content of
phenomenal consciousness.
Llinas *et al.* (1998) have proposed two parallel cortico-thalamic
attentional systems, one of which is related to the thalamic specific
nuclei and the other to the thalamic non-specific nuclei, especially the
ILN. The non-specific system would be related to consciousness itself.
## The \"cognitive map\" and the neural basis of perceptual space
Our bodies appear to be mobile within a constant space. We walk around a
room; the room does not rotate around us. The constancy of the location
of things gives us the feeling that we are directly viewing a constant
world. But how does the brain provide a constant world rather than a
world that rotates with the movement of the sense organs? Why is our
view of the world when we move our eyes so different from the disturbing
flow of images that occur when a video camera is waved around? Do our
brains contain a constant \"cognitive map\" (O\'Keefe and Nadel 1978) of
our surroundings?
Mittelstaedt & Mittelstaedt (1980, 1982) discovered that female gerbils
were able to recover their pups in darkened surroundings by searching in
a semi random fashion on the outbound journey and then proceeding
directly back to the nest on the inbound journey. The direct journey
back to the nest seemed to be due to an integration of the various
directions taken on the outward journey (**path integration**). If the
equipment being explored by the mother gerbil was rotated very slowly
the mother would make an error equivalent to the amount of rotation.
More rapid rotations that activated the vestibular system of the rat
(acceleration measurement) did not cause errors in navigation. This
demonstration that rodents could navigate accurately on the basis of
**idiothetic** cues (cues that are due to internal senses) led to
research on the neural basis of the navigation.
As early as 1971 O\'Keefe and Dostrovsky had discovered that there are
particular cells in the hippocampus that fire according to the position
of an animal in the environment. This has been complimented by research
that showed that changes in visual cues within the environment caused
changes in the firing rate of place cells in hippocampal area CA3 (.
![](Gray717.png "Gray717.png")
![](HippocampalRegions.jpg "HippocampalRegions.jpg")
!Entorhinal cortex approximately maps to areas 28 and
34{width="500"}
F. P. Battaglia and A. Treves. 1998 Attractor neural networks storing
multiple space representations: A model for hippocampal place fields.
PHYSICAL REVIEW E DECEMBER 1998 VOLUME 58, NUMBER 6
<http://www.sissa.it/~ale/Bat+98b.pdf>
Leutgeb, S., Leutgeb, J.K., Moser, M-B, and Moser, E.I. 2005. Place
cells, spatial maps and the population code for memory. Current Opinion
in Neurobiology 2005, 15:738--746.
<http://instruct1.cit.cornell.edu/courses/bionb720nejc/reprints/LeutgebEtAl2005.pdf>
Mittelstaedt, H. & Mittelstaedt, M-L. 1982. Avian Navigation. (ed. Papi,
F. & Wallraff, H.) 290-297. Springer, Berlin.
Mittelstaedt, M-L & Glasauer, S. 1991. Idiothetic Navigation in Gerbils
and Humans. Zool. Jb. Physiol. 95 (1991), 427-435
<http://web.archive.org/web/20110125132449/http://www.nefo.med.uni-muenchen.de/~sglasauer/MittelstaedtGlasauer1991.pdf>
O\'Keefe, J. & Dostrovsky, J. (1971). The hippocampus as a spatial map:
preliminary evidence from unit activity in the freely moving rat. Brain
Res. 34, 171-175.
O\'Keefe, J. & Nadel, L. (1978). The Hippocampus as a cognitive map.
(Oxford)
## Bibliography
Defining the States of Consciousness. Tassi, P., Muzet, A. (2001)
Neuroscience and Behavioural Reviews 25(2001) 175-191.
Neuroanatomy: \"Digital Slice of Life\" by Stensaas and Millhouse
<http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/subj2.html>
See also: <http://medlib.med.utah.edu/kw/sol/sss/index.html>
EEG\'s: Coles, M.G.H., Rugg, M.D. Event Related Brain Potentials: An
Introduction.
<http://whalen.psych.udel.edu/667/1.What_is_ERP/ColesRugg1995chpt1.pdf>
Visual System: Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual
Awareness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/tonglab/publications/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
Professor Bogen\'s Consciousness Page
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/toccons.htm>
Demonstrations of Auditory Illusions and Tricks. Yoshitaka Nakajima
<http://www.kyushu-id.ac.jp/~ynhome/ENG/Demo/illusions2nd.html>
## References
- Abraham, N.M. (2004) Maintaining accuracy at the expense of speed:
stimulus similarity defines odor discrimination time in mice. Neuron
44, 865-876.
- Aleman, A., Ramsey, N., Van Honk, J.E., Kessels, R.P.C., Hoogduin,
J., Schutter, D.L.G., Postma, A., Kahn, R.S., De Haan, E.H.F.
(submitted). Parietal cortex mediates visuospatial imagery: evidence
from fMRI and rTMS.
<http://igitur-archive.library.uu.nl/dissertations/1954455/c10.pdf>
- Alkire, M.T., Haier, R.J., Fallon, J.H., and Barker, S.J.(1996). PET
imaging of conscious and unconscious verbal memory. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, 3 ( 5-6) 1996 , pp. 448--462
<http://www.imprint.co.uk/jcs_3_5-6.html>
- Anderson, J. & Anderson, B. (1993). \"The Myth of Persistence of
Vision Revisited,\" Journal of Film and Video, Vol. 45, No. 1
(Spring 1993): 3-12.
<http://www.uca.edu/org/ccsmi/ccsmi/classicwork/Myth%20Revisited.htm>
- Andrews, T.J., White, L.E., Binder, D. & Purves, D. (1996). Temporal
events in cyclopean vision. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 93,
pp. 3689--3692, April 1996. Neurobiology.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030510095149/http://www.dur.ac.uk/tim.andrews/PNAS_93_3689.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G. (2001) Determinants of asynchronous
processing in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London,
Series B: Biological Sciences, 269, 579 - 583.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031205165920/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/AC02.pdf>
- Arnold, D.H., Clifford, C.W.G, Wenderoth, P. (2001). Asynchronous
processing in vision: Color leads motion. Current Biology, 11,
596 - 600.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030617120017/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/ACW01.pdf>
- Austin, G.M. & Grant, F.C. (1958). Physiologic observations
following total hemispherectomy in man. Surgery 38, 239-258.
- Baars, B.J. (1983) Conscious contents provide the nervous system
with coherent, global information. In Consciousness and
Self-Regulation (Vol 3). Davidson, R.J. et al., editors. Plenum
Press.
- Baars, B.J. (1988) A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness, Cambridge
University Press.
- Baars, B., Newman, J., & Taylor, J. (1998) Neuronal mechanisms of
consciousness: A Relational Global Workspace framework., in
Hameroff, Stuart and Kaszniak, Al and Laukes, James, Eds. Toward a
Science of Consciousness II: The second Tucson discussions and
debates., chapter 24, pages 269-278. MIT Press.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000946/>
- Baars, B.J. (2002) The conscious access hypothesis: origins and
recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. Vol 6, No 1,
47-52. 2002. <http://www.cs.memphis.edu/~wrcm/BaarsTICS2002.pdf>
- Barth, D. S. and MacDonald, K. D. (1996) Thalamic modulation of
high-frequency oscillating potentials in auditory cortex. Nature.
383, 78-81.
- Bernat E, Shevrin H, Snodgrass M. (2001). Subliminal visual oddball
stimuli evoke a P300 component. Clin Neurophysiol. 2001
Jan;112(1):159-71.
- Blake, R., Westendorf, D. and Overton, R. (1979) What is suppressed
during binocular rivalry? Perception 9: 223-231.
- Blake, R. and Lee, S.-H. (1999). Rival ideas about binocular
rivalry. Vision Research. 39: 1447-1454
<http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/faculty/blake/PDFs/Lee_Blake_99VR.pdf>
- Blankenburg, F., Ruff, C.C., Deichmann, R., Rees, G. and
Driver, J. (2006) The cutaneous rabbit illusion affects human
primary sensory cortex somatotopically, PLoS Biol 2006;4(3):e69.
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness: I. An
overview. Consciousness and Cognition, 4, 52-62.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/bogen-95.pdf>
- Bogen, J.E. (1995). On the neurophysiology of consciousness:
Part II. Constraining the semantic problem. Consciousness and
Cognition, 4, 137-158.
<http://www.its.caltech.edu/~jbogen/text/concog95.htm>
- Bregman, A.S. (1990). Auditory scene analysis: The perceptual
organization of sound. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Budka, H. (1998). Fatal Familial Insomnia Around the World. Brain
Pathology, 8: 553-570.
<http://brainpath.medsch.ucla.edu/pdfs/0803pdf/budka.pdf>
- Carandini M, Heeger DJ, & Senn W, (2002). A synaptic explanation of
suppression in visual cortex, Journal of Neuroscience,
22:10053-10065, 2002.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031031214953/http://www.cns.nyu.edu/~david/ftp/reprints/Carandini-JNeurosci2002.pdf>
- Cariani, P. (2000). Anesthesia, Neural Information Processing, And
Conscious Awareness. Consciousness And Cognition Vol. 9, No. 3,
September 2000 p. 387-395
- Castro-Alamancos, M.A., Connors, B.W. (1997). Thalamo-cortical
synapses. Progress in Neurobiology, Vol.51, pp. 581 to 606, 1997
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051025163047/http://neurobio.drexel.edu/castroweb/progneurobio1.pdf>
- Christmann, C. & Leuthold, H. (2004). The Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Section A. Volume 57, Number 2 /
February 2004. 357-381.
- Claus, R. & Nel, W. (2006). Drug induced arousal from the permanent
vegetative state. NeuroRehabilitation. 2006;21(1):23-8.
- Clifford, C.W.G., Arnold, D.H., Pearson, J. (2003). A paradox of
temporal perception revealed by a stimulus oscillating in colour and
orientation. Vision Research 43 (2003) 2245-2253.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031102125210/http://www.psych.usyd.edu.au/staff/colinc/Reprints/CAP03.pdf>
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of
consciousness Seminars in the Neurosciences (1990) 2, 263-275
- Crick, F and Koch, C.(1998). Consciousness and Neuroscience.
Cerebral Cortex, 8:97-107, 1998
<http://www.klab.caltech.edu/~koch/crick-koch-cc-97.html>
- Culham, J.C., Dukelow, S.P., Vilis, T., Hassard, F.A., Gati, J.S.,
Menon, R.S. and Goodale, M.A. (1999). Recovery of fMRI Activation in
Motion Area MT Following Storage of the Motion Aftereffect. The
Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 81 No. 1 January 1999, pp. 388--393.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/81/1/388>
- Deecke, L. (1996) Planning, preparation, execution, and imagery of
volitional action, (Introduction / Editorial) in: L. Deecke W.
Lang, A. Berthoz (Eds) Mental Representations of Motor Acts.
Cognitive Brain Res 3 / Special Issue (2) 59-64.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000015/00/COGBRAIN.html>
- Dehaene, S., Sergent, C., and Changeux, J. (2003) A neuronal network
model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data
during conscious perception. PNAS July 8, 2003 vol. 100 no. 14
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/DehaeneSergentChangeux_BlinkModel_PNAS2003.pdf>
- Dehaene, S. et al. (2001) Cerebral mechanisms of word masking and
unconscious repetition priming. Nat. Neurosci, 4, 752-758.
<http://www.unicog.org/publications/Dehaene_MaskedWords_NatureNeuroscience2001.pdf>
- Dennett, D. and Kinsbourne, M. (1992) Time and the Observer: the
Where and When of Consciousness in the Brain. (1992) Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 15, 183-247, 1992. Reprinted in The Philosopher\'s
Annual, Grim, Mar and Williams, eds., vol. XV-1992, 1994,
pp. 23--68; Noel Sheehy and Tony Chapman, eds., Cognitive Science,
Vol. I, Elgar, 1995,
pp. 210--274.http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/time&obs.htm
- Destexhe, A. (2000). Modelling corticothalamic feedback and the
gating of the thalamus by the cerebral cortex. J. Physiol (Paris),
94 (2000) 391-410. <http://cns.iaf.cnrs-gif.fr/files/Brem2000.pdf>
- Fang, F. & He, S. (2005).Cortical responses to invisible objects in
the human dorsal and ventral pathways. Nat Neurosci. 2005
Oct;8(10):1380-5. Epub 2005 Sep 4.
- Ffytche, D. H., Howard, R. J., Brammer, M. J., David, A., Woodruff,
P., & Williams, S. (1998). The anatomy of conscious vision: an fMRI
study of visual hallucinations. Nature Neuroscience, 1, 738--742.
- Fiset, P., Paus, T., Daloze, T., Plourde, G., Meuret, P., Bonhomme,
V., Hajj-Ali, N., Backman, S.B., and Evans, A.C. (1999). Brain
Mechanisms of Propofol-Induced Loss of Consciousness in Humans: a
Positron Emission Tomographic Study. The Journal of Neuroscience,
July 1, 1999, 19(13):5506-5513.
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/13/5506>
- Fu, C.H.Y., Morgan, K., Suckling, J., Williams, S.C.R., Andrew, C.,
Vythelingum, G.N., McGuire, P.K. (2002). A Functional Magnetic
Resonance Imaging Study of Overt Letter Verbal Fluency Using a
Clustered Acquisition Sequence: Greater Anterior Cingulate
Activation with Increased Task Demand. NeuroImage 17, 871-
879 (2002)
<http://www-bmu.psychiatry.cam.ac.uk/PUBLICATION_STORE/fu02fun.pdf>
- Ganis, G., Thomson, W.L. and Kosslyn, S.M. (2004). Brain areas
underlying visual mental imagery and visual perception: an fMRI
study. Cognitive Brain Research 20 (2004) 226--241
<http://www.wjh.harvard.edu/~kwn/Kosslyn_pdfs/2004Ganis_CogBrainRes20_BrainAreas.pdf>
- Hultin, L. (1997). On Neuromagnetic Assessment of the Contingent
Negative Variation.
<http://www2.lib.chalmers.se/cth/diss/doc/9697/HultinLeif.html>
- Fries, P.. Roelfsema, P.R., Engel, A.K., König, P. and Singer, W.
(1997). Synchronization of oscillatory responses in visual cortex
correlates with perception in interocular rivalry. Proc. Natl. Acad.
Sci. USA, Vol. 94, pp. 12699--12704, November 1997.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/23/12699>
- Fuentealba, P., Crochet, S., Timofeev, I., Bazhenov, M., Sejnowski,
T.J. and Steriade, M. (2004). European Journal of Neuroscience
20(1):111-119. <http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2004/22126/ch03.html>
- Goaillard, J. & Vincent, P. (2002). Serotonin suppresses the slow
afterhyperpolarization in rat intralaminar and midline thalamic
neurones by activating 5-HT7 receptors. Journal of Physiology
(2002), 541.2, pp. 453--465
<http://jp.physoc.org/cgi/content/full/541/2/453>
- Haggard, P. & Eimer, M. (1999) On the relation between brain
potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Exp. Brain Res.
126, 128--133 (1999).
- Haggard, P. (2008) Human volition:towards a neuroscience of will.
Nature Rev Neurosci 9, 934-946
- Haynes, J., Deichmann, R. and Rees, G. (2005). Eye-specific effects
of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate nucleus. Nature
438, 496-499 (24 November 2005)
- Hughes S.W., Blethyn K.L. , Cope D.W. , & Crunelli V. (2003).
Properties and origin of spikelets in thalamocortical neurones in
vitro. Neuroscience. 2002;110(3):395-401
- Iramina, K., Maeno, T., Kowatari, Y. and Ueno, S.. (2002). Effects
of Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation on EEG Activity .IEEE
TRANSACTIONS ON MAGNETICS, VOL. 38, NO. 5, SEPTEMBER 2002
- Ishai, A., Ungerleider, L.G., Haxby, J.V.. (2000) Distributed neural
systems for the generation of visual images. Neuron 28, 979-990.
- Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1980). Mental models in cognitive science.
Cognitive Science, 4, 71-115.
<http://cognitrn.psych.indiana.edu/rgoldsto/cogsci/classics.html>
- Keller, J. & Heckhausen, H. (1990). Readiness potentials preceding
spontaneous motor acts: voluntary vs. involuntary control.
Electroencephalography and Clinical Neuropsychology, 76, 351-361.
- King, C.C. (1991). Fractal and Chaotic Dynamics in Nervous Systems.
Progress in Neurobiology, 36, pp. 279--308, 1991.
<http://citeseer.nj.nec.com/king91fractal.html>
- Klein, S.A (2002). Libet's Temporal Anomalies: A Reassessment of the
Data.
Consciousness and Cognition 11, 198--214 (2002)
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/160.pdf>
- Klein, S. (2002). Libet\'s Timing of Mental Events: Commentary on
the Commentaries. Consciousness and Cognition. 11, 326-333.
<http://cornea.berkeley.edu/pubs/ccog_2002_0580-Klein-Commentary_on_the_commentaries.pdf>
- Kleinschmidt, A., Bichel, C. Zeki, S. and Frackowiak, R.S.J. (1998).
Human brain activity during spontaneously reversing perception of
ambiguous figures. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 1998 Dec
22;265(1413):2427-33
- Konishi, S., Wheeler, M.E., Donaldson, D.I., Buckner, R.L.. (2000)
Neural correlates of episodic retrieval success. NeuroImage: 12:
276-286.
- Kornhuber HH, Deecke L: Hirnpotentialänderungen beim Menschen vor
und nach Willkürbewegungen, dargestellt mit Magnetbandspeicherung
und Rückwärtsanalyse. Pflügers Arch. ges. Physiol. 281 (1964) 52.
- Kosslyn, S.M., Thompson, W.L. (2003). When is early visual cortex
activated during visual mental imagery? Psychol. Bull. 129
(2003)723-746.
- Kreiman, G., Koch, C. and Fried, I. (2000). Imagery neurons in the
human brain. Nature (2000) 408: 357-361
<http://www.cns.caltech.edu/~gabriel/publications/imagination1.html>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I., & Koch, C. (2001). Single neuron responses
in humans during binocular rivalry and flash suppression. Journal of
Vision, 1(3), 131a, <http://journalofvision.org/1/3/131>
- Kreiman, G., Fried, I. And Koch, C. (2002) Single Neuron responses
in the human brain during flash suppression. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Science USA, 99:8378-8383
<http://web.archive.org/web/20031015091920/http://www.ai.mit.edu/projects/cbcl/publications/ps/kreimanetal_flash-suppression.pdf>
- Larsen, A., Madsen, K.H., Lund, T.E., and Bundesen, C. (2006).
Images of Illusory Motion in Primary Visual Cortex. Journal of
Cognitive Neuroscience. 2006;18:1174-1180.
- Laureys, S. et al. (2002). Brain function in the vegetative state.
Acta neurol. belg., 2002, 102, 177-185
<http://www.jsmf.org/meetings/2003/nov/LaureysANB2002.pdf>
- Lee. S, and Blake, R. (2002). V1 activity is reduced during
binocular rivalry. Journal of Vision (2002) 2, 618-626
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030722173225/http://journalofvision.org/2/9/4/article.pdf>
- Leopold, D.A. and Logothetis, N.K. (1999). Multistable phenomena:
changing views in perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 3:
254-264.
<http://www.kyb.tuebingen.mpg.de/publications/pdfs/pdf201.pdf>
- Libet, B., Alberts, E.W., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B.(1967).
Responses of Human Somatosensory Cortex to Stimuli Below Threshold
for Conscious Sensation. Science 158, 1597-1600.
- Libet, B., Wright, E. W., Jr., Feinstein, B., and Pearl, D.(1979).
Subjective referral of the timing for a conscious sensory
experience. Brain, 102, pp. 192--224.
<http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/entrez/query.fcgi?holding=npg&cmd=Retrieve&db=PubMed&list_uids=427530&dopt=Abstract>
- Linden, D.E.J. (2005) The P300: Where in the Brain Is It Produced
and What Does It Tell Us? The Neuroscientist, Vol. 11, No. 6,
563-576 (2005) <http://nro.sagepub.com/cgi/reprint/11/6/563.pdf>
- Llinas, R., Ribary, U., Contreras, D. & Pedroarena, C. (1998). The
neuronal basis for consciousness. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London Ser.
B.353, 1841-1849
<http://big.cs.uiuc.edu/anncbt-papers/fall05/Llinas.the-neuronal-basis-of-consciousness.pdf>
- Logothetis, N.K., Leopold, D.A. and Sheinberg, D.L. (1996). What is
Rivalling During Binocular Rivalry. Nature, 380:621-624.
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nature/journal/v380/n6575/abs/380621a0.html>
- Loveblad, KO. et al. (1999). Silent functional magnetic resonance
imaging demonstrates focal activation in rapid eye movement sleep.
Neurology 1999;53:2193Z
- Luce, R.D. (1986). Response times: their role in inferring
elementary mental organization. Oxford University Press, New York.
- Lumer, E.D., Friston, K.J. & Rees, G. (1998) Neural correlates of
perceptual rivalry in the human brain. Science. 280(5371):1930-4.
- Macdonald, K.D., Fifkova, E., Jones, M.S. and Barth, D.S. (1998)
Focal Stimulation of the Thalamic Reticular Nucleus Induces Focal
Gamma Waves in Cortex. The Journal of Neurophysiology Vol. 79 No. 1
January 1998, pp. 474--477
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/79/1/474>
- Maia, T.V. & Cleeremans, A. (2005). Consciousness: converging
insights from connectionist modeling and neuroscience. TRENDS in
Cognitive Sciences Vol.9 No.8 August 2005
<http://srsc.ulb.ac.be/axcWWW/papers/pdf/05-TICS.pdf>
- Marcel AJ. (1998). Blindsight and shape perception: deficit of
visual consciousness or visual function? Brain 1998, 121, 1565-1588.
<http://brain.oupjournals.org/cgi/reprint/121/8/1565.pdf>
- Marois, R., Yi, D-J., & Chun, M.M. (2004). The Neural Fate of
Consciously Perceived and Missed Events in the Attentional Blink.
Neuron, 41, 3: 465-472.
- Mashour, G.A., Tononi, G. and Massimini, M. (2005). Cognitive
Unbinding in Sleep and Anesthesia. Science 16 December 2005:
1768-1769.
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (1997). A direct demonstration of
perceptual asynchrony in vision. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 264, 393 - 399.
<http://juno.ingentaselect.com/vl=6492085/cl=26/nw=1/rpsv/cgi-bin/cgi?body=linker&ini=nlm&reqidx=issn=0962-8452vl=264is=1380yr=1997mn=Marpg=393>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). Responses of Spectrally
Selective Cells in Macaque Area V2 to Wavelengths and Colors. J
Neurophysiol 87: 2104-2112, 2002.
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/87/4/2104>
- Moutoussis, K. and Zeki, S. (2002). The relationship between
cortical activation and perception investigated with invisible
stimuli. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA, 99(14):9527-9532.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/99/14/9527>
- Muckli, L., Singer, W., Zanella, F.E. and Goebel, R. (2002)
Integration of multiple motion vectors over space: an fMRI study of
transparent motion perception. Neuroimage. 2002 Aug;16(4):843-56.
- Munhall, K.G. (2001). Functional Imaging During Speech Production.
Acta Psychologica 107 (2001) 95-117.
<http://pavlov.psyc.queensu.ca/~munhallk/07_acta_version.pdf>
- Munk MHJ, Roelfsema PR, König P, Engel AK, and Singer W. (1996).
Role of reticular activation in the modulation of intracortical
synchronization Science. 272, 271-274.
- Newman, J. & Baars, B.J. (1993) A neural attentional model for
access to consciousness: A Global Workspace perspective. Concepts in
Neuroscience, 4:2, 255-290
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000073/>
- Nieuwenhuis S, Aston-Jones G & Cohen JD (2005). Decision making, the
P3, and the locus coeruleus-norepinephrine system. Psychological
Bulletin, 131(4), 510-532.
<http://web.archive.org/web/20051117045339/http://www.csbmb.princeton.edu/conte/pdfs/project5/Proj5Pub06.pdf>
- Nørretranders, T. (1991) Consciousness: The User Illusion
(translated from Danish), Penguin Books,
; 1999 revision:
<http://www.worldcat.org/title/user-illusion-cutting-consciousness-down-to-size/oclc/41311618>.
- Pantev C (1995) Evoked and induced gamma-band activity of the human
cortex. Brain Topogr 7:321-330
- Pasley BN, Mayes LC, Schultz RT (2004) Subcortical discrimination of
unperceived objects during binocular rivalry. Neuron 2004,
42:163-172.
- Pessoa, L. (2005) To what extent are emotional visual stimuli
processed without attention and awareness? Current Opinion in
Neurobiology 2005, 15:188-196
<http://web.archive.org/web/20060623004726/http://www.brown.edu/Research/LCE/publications_files/Pessoa_CONB_2005.pdf>
- Pettigrew, J.D. (2001) Searching for the Switch: Neural Bases for
Perceptual Rivalry Alternations. Brain and Mind 2: 85-118, 2001.
<http://www.uq.edu.au/nuq/jack/searchswitch.pdf>
- Raymond, J. E, Shapiro, K. L., & Arnell, K. M. (1992). Temporary
suppression of visual processing in an RSVP task: An attentional
blink? Journal of Experimental Psychology. Human Perception and
Performance, 18 (3), 849-60.
- Rektor, I., Bares, M., Kanovsky, P. and Kukleta, M. (2001)
Intracerebral recording of readiness potential induced by a complex
motor task. Movement Disorders, Volume 16, Issue 4, Pages 698-704
- Rees, G., Kreiman, G., & Koch, C. (2002) Neural Correlates of
Consciousness in Humans. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3, 261
-270 (2002)
<http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nrn/journal/v3/n4/abs/nrn783_fs.html&dynoptions=doi1069842948>
- Rensink, RA. (2000). When Good Observers Go Bad: Change Blindness,
Inattentional Blindness, and Visual Experience. PSYCHE, 6(09),
August 2000.
<http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v6/psyche-6-09-rensink.html>
- Roy, J.E. & Prichep, L.S. (2005) The Anesthetic Cascade: A Theory of
How Anesthesia Suppresses Consciousness Anesthesiology: Volume
102(2) February 2005 pp 447--471
<http://www.anesthesiology.org/pt/re/anes/fulltext.00000542-200502000-00030.htm>
- Schiff, N.D., & Plum F. 1999. The Neurology of Impaired
Consciousness: Global Disorders and Implied Models. \[Target
article\]. Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness.
<http://www.phil.vt.edu/assc/niko.html>
- Schiff ND, Plum F. (2000) The Role of Arousal and \"Gating\" Systems
in the Neurology of Impaired Consciousness. Journal of
Neurophysiology. 17(5):438-452. (
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030924010953/http://www.uni-tuebingen.de/cog/lehre/ss2003/seminar_bewusstsein/epapers/SchiffPlum00.pdf>
- Sheinberg, D.L. and Logothetis, N.K. (1997). The role of temporal
cortical areas in perceptual organization. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA 94, 3408-3413. <http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/94/7/3408>
- Simons, D.J. & Rensink, RA. (2005). Change blindness: Past, present,
and future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol.9, pp16--20, No.1
January 2005.
<http://www.psych.ubc.ca/~rensink/publications/download/S&R-TICS-05a.pdf>
- Singer, W. & Gray, C.W. (1995). Visual feature integration and the
temporal correlation hypothesis. Annu. Rev. Neurosci., 18,
pp. 555--86, 1995.
- Singer, W. (2001). Consciousness and the Binding Problem. Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences 929:123-146 (2001)
- Solms, Mark (2000) DREAMING AND REM SLEEP ARE CONTROLLED BY
DIFFERENT BRAIN MECHANISMS, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23
(6): 793.
<http://www.bbsonline.org/Preprints/OldArchive/bbs.solms.html>
- Soon, C.S., Brass, M., Heinze, H-J. and Haynes, J-D. (2008).
Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain.
Nature Neuroscience 11, 543 - 545 (2008)
- Sukov, W. & Barth, D.S. (2001). Cellular Mechanisms of Thalamically
Evoked Gamma Oscillations in Auditory Cortex. J Neurophysiol 85:
1235-1245, 2001;
<http://jn.physiology.org/cgi/content/full/85/3/1235>
- Takeuchi, T., Miyasita, A., Inugami, M. & Yamamoto, Y. (2001).
Intrinsic dreams are not produced without REM sleep mechanisms:
evidence through elicitation of sleep onset REM periods. Journal of
Sleep Research Volume 10 Issue 1 Page 43 - March 2001
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
- Tamás, G., Buh, E.H., Lörincz, A., and Somogyi, P. (2000).
Proximally targeted GABAergic synapses and gap junctions synchronize
cortical interneurons. Nature Neuroscience volume 3 no 4 April 2000.
<http://mrcanu.pharm.ox.ac.uk/pdfs/TamasNatureNeurosci2000.pdf>
- Tanaka, Y. & Sagi, D. (1998). A perceptual memory for low contrast
visual signals. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol 95:12729-12733.
<http://www.weizmann.ac.il/~masagi/TS98b.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2001). Competing Theories of Binocular Rivalry: A Possible
Resolution. Brain and Mind 2: 55-83, 2001
<http://web.archive.org/web/20041212094810/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_Brain&Mind2001.pdf>
- Tong, F. (2002). Primary Visual Cortex and Visual Awareness. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience 4, 219 (2003)
<http://web.archive.org/web/20030723135239/http://www.princeton.edu/~ftong/Tong_NRN2003.pdf>
- Tootell, R.B., Reppas, J.B., Dale, A.M., Look, R.B., Sereno, M.I.,
Malach, R., Brady, T.J. and Rosen, B.R. (1995) Visual motion
aftereffect in human cortical area MT revealed by functional
magnetic resonance imaging. Nature. 1995 May 11;375(6527):139-41.
- Tononi, G., Srinivasan, R., Russell, P.D. & Edelman, G.M. (1998).
Investigating neural correlates of conscious perception by
frequency-tagged neuromagnetic responses . Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
USA. Vol. 95, Issue 6, 3198-3203, March 17, 1998
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/95/6/3198>
- Thornton, I.M., Pinto, J. and Shiffrar, M. (1998).
THE VISUAL PERCEPTION OF HUMAN LOCOMOTION. COGNITIVE NEUROPSYCHOLOGY,
1998, 15 (6/7/8 ), 535-552.
<http://psychology.rutgers.edu/~mag/TPS98.pdf>
- Traub, D.R., Whittington, M.A., Buhl, E.H., Jefferys, J.G.R., &
Faulkner, H.J. (1999). On the Mechanism of the Frequency Shift in
Neuronal Oscillations Induced in Rat Hippocampal Slices by Tetanic
Stimulation. The Journal of Neuroscience, February 1, 1999,
19(3):1088-1105
<http://www.jneurosci.org/cgi/content/full/19/3/1088>
- Traub, R.D. (2003). Fast Oscillations and Epilepsy. Epilepsy Curr.
2003 May; 3(3): 77-79.
<http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/articlerender.fcgi?artid=321178>
- Trevena J & Miller, J (2002) Cortical Movement Preparation before
and after a Conscious Decision to Move. Consciousness and Cognition,
Volume 11, Issue 2, June 2002, Pages 162-190
- Trevena, J & Miller, J (2009) Brain preparation before a voluntary
action: Evidence against unconscious movement initiation. Conscious
Cogn. 2009 Sep 5. \[Epub ahead of print\]
- Tse, P.U., Susana Martinez-Conde, S., Schlegel, A.A. and Macknik,
S.L. (2005). Visibility, visual awareness, and visual masking of
simple unattended targets are confined to areas in the occipital
cortex beyond human V1/V2. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA November 22,
2005 vol. 102 no. 47. 17178-17183.
<http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/102/47/17178>
- Uchida, N., Kepecs, A. and Mainen, Z.F. (2006) Seeing at a glance,
smelling in a whiff: rapid forms of perceptual decision making.
Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 7. 485-491.
- Uchida, N & Mainen, Z.F. (2003) Speed and accuracy of olfacory
discrimination in the rat. Nature Neurosci. 6, 1224-1229.
- Vogel, E.K., Luck, S.J. & Shapiro, K.L. (1998) Electrophysiological
Evidence for a Postperceptual Locus of Suppression During the
Attentional Blink. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
Perception and Performance 1998, Vol. 24. No. 6,1656-1674
<http://web.archive.org/web/20050304211722/http://www.psychology.uiowa.edu/faculty/Luck/lucklab/pdfs/Vogel_1998_JEPHPP.pdf>
- Wehrle, R., Czisch, M., Kaufmann, C., Wetter, T.C., Holsboer, F.,
Auer, D.P., and Pollmacher, T. (2005). Rapid eye movement-related
brain activation in human sleep: a functional magnetic resonance
imaging study. NeuroReport 16:853-857
<http://www.univie.ac.at/mcogneu/lit/wehrle.pdf>
- White, NS., Alkire, MT. (2003). Impaired thalamocortical
connectivity in humans during
general-anesthetic-induced unconsciousness. NeuroImage. Volume 19, Issue
2 , June 2003, Pages 402-411. <http://smallurl.com?i=2597>
(http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/B6WNP-48GP5CG-5/1/cedb33dc0bec4301d1960c7c27cea70f)
- Wheeler, M.E., Buckner, R.L.. (2003) Functional dissociation among
components
of remembering: control, perceived oldness, and content. J. Neurosci.
23, 3869-3880.
- Williams LM, Liddell BJ, Rathjen J, Brown KJ, Shevrin H, Gray JA,
Phillips M, Young A & Gordon E (2004). Mapping the time course of
nonconscious and conscious perception of fear: An integration of
central and peripheral measures. Human Brain Mapping,21, 64 - 74
<http://psychmed.iop.kcl.ac.uk/neuroscience-and-emotion/downloads/46.pdf>
- Wunderlich, K. Schneider, K.A., & Kastner, S. (2005).Neural
correlates of binocular rivalry in the human lateral geniculate
nucleus. Nature Neuroscience 8, 1595 - 1602 (2005)
- Yamamoto, T. & Katayama, Y. (2005). Deep brain stimulation therapy
for the vegetative state. in Neuropsychol Rehabil. 2005 Jul-Sep ;
15(3-4): 406-13
- Zeki, S., & Bartel, A. (1999). Toward a Theory of Visual
Consciousness. Consciousness & Cognition, 8, 225-259.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Behaviourism And Consciousness
References
- Behaviourism. Graham, G. (2002) Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy
- Watson, J.B. (1907) Studying the Mind of Animals The World Today,
12,
421-426.
- Watson, J.B. (1913) Psychology as the Behaviorist Views it.
Psychological Review, 20,
158-177
- Lektorsky, V.A. (1980)Subject Object
Cognition.
- Vygotsky L.S. (1925) "Consciousness as a problem in the psychology
of behavior" Undiscovered Vygotsky: Etudes on the pre-history of
cultural-historical psychology (European Studies in the History of
Science and Ideas. Vol. 8), pp.
251-281
- Gibson, J. J. (1950). The perception of the visual world. Boston:
Houghton-Mifflin
- Gibson, J. J.(1979). The ecological approach to visual perception.
Boston: Houghton-Mifflin
- Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Harmondsworth, Middlesex:
Penguin.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Models Of Access Consciousness
There have been numerous attempts to model reflex and access
consciousness. These models, being connectionist and information systems
based, do not model phenomenal consciousness but are essential steps in
understanding global brain function.
## Neural networks
Neural networks achieve information processing by establishing
connections between processing units in a system of processors that have
similar characteristics. Neural networks are used for classifying data.
The processing units serve the function of both filtering and storing
information.
*This is a stub and requires expansion*
### Classification of sensory stimuli
*The path from transducers to a single neuron that responds to a single
complex stimulus.*
*This is a stub and requires expansion*
### Classification of motor control
*From premotor activity to skilled behaviour.*
*This is a stub and requires expansion*
### Olfaction: classification out of chaos?
*This is a stub and requires expansion*
## Quantum information processing
*This is a **stub** and needs expanding*
|
# Consciousness Studies/Models Of Access Consciousness#Neural networks
There have been numerous attempts to model reflex and access
consciousness. These models, being connectionist and information systems
based, do not model phenomenal consciousness but are essential steps in
understanding global brain function.
## Neural networks
Neural networks achieve information processing by establishing
connections between processing units in a system of processors that have
similar characteristics. Neural networks are used for classifying data.
The processing units serve the function of both filtering and storing
information.
*This is a stub and requires expansion*
### Classification of sensory stimuli
*The path from transducers to a single neuron that responds to a single
complex stimulus.*
*This is a stub and requires expansion*
### Classification of motor control
*From premotor activity to skilled behaviour.*
*This is a stub and requires expansion*
### Olfaction: classification out of chaos?
*This is a stub and requires expansion*
## Quantum information processing
*This is a **stub** and needs expanding*
|
# Consciousness Studies/Models Of Access Consciousness#Quantum information processing
There have been numerous attempts to model reflex and access
consciousness. These models, being connectionist and information systems
based, do not model phenomenal consciousness but are essential steps in
understanding global brain function.
## Neural networks
Neural networks achieve information processing by establishing
connections between processing units in a system of processors that have
similar characteristics. Neural networks are used for classifying data.
The processing units serve the function of both filtering and storing
information.
*This is a stub and requires expansion*
### Classification of sensory stimuli
*The path from transducers to a single neuron that responds to a single
complex stimulus.*
*This is a stub and requires expansion*
### Classification of motor control
*From premotor activity to skilled behaviour.*
*This is a stub and requires expansion*
### Olfaction: classification out of chaos?
*This is a stub and requires expansion*
## Quantum information processing
*This is a **stub** and needs expanding*
|
# Consciousness Studies/Contemporary Explanations
*This section is about the types of theory that have been advanced to
explain consciousness. Specific explanations should be entered as
separate pages.*
## Introduction
Explanations of consciousness fall into three broad categories, those
that attempt to explain the empirical experience called consciousness
with scientific theories, those that seek to find some way in which
consciousness could be explained by digital computers or nineteenth
century materialism by redefining or eliminating experience and those
that regard consciousness as inexplicable or supernatural.
## Identity theory of mind
The identity theory of mind, or type physicalism, holds that the mind is
identical to the brain. Type physicalists identify qualia and the form
of experience with brain activity. They argue that \"mind states\" have
physical causes and physical effects - thus the mind states themselves
must be physical; a non-physical \"middle step\" is superfluous.
Type physicalism has not yet gained widespread support because although
brain activity that correlates with experience has been found everywhere
in the brain, no set of brain activity that is phenomenal consciousness
itself has yet been found - although this is not surprising because
neuronal spike activity is unlikely to host phenomenal consciousness -
see scientific theories of
consciousness.
## Functionalism
Functionalism was developed as a theory of the mind-body problem because
of objections to identity theory and logical behaviourism. Its core idea
is that the mental states can be accounted for without taking into
account the underlying physical medium (the neurons), instead attending
to higher-level functions such as beliefs, desires, and emotions. It is
a theory of behaviour and access consciousness and so from the outset
avoids any explanation of phenomenal consciousness, substituting beliefs
and judgements (functions) for entities such as qualia.
According to functionalism, the mental states that make up consciousness
can essentially be defined as complex interactions between different
functional processes. Because these processes are not limited to a
particular physical state or physical medium, they can be realized in
multiple ways, including, theoretically, within non-biological
systems.This affords consciousness the opportunity to exist in non-human
minds that are based on algorithmic processors such as digital
computers. This is a highly contentious conjecture although
non-functionalist physicalists might agree that machines that are not
digital computers could possess consciousness through an identity theory
of mind - see The problem of machine and digital
consciousness.
Functionalism\'s explanation of consciousness, or the mental, is best
understood when considering the analogy made by functionalists between
the mind and the modern digital computer. More specifically, the analogy
is made to a \"machine\" capable of computing any given algorithm (i.e.
a Turing machine). This machine would involve:
Data input (the senses in humans), data output (both behaviour and
memory), functional states (mental states), the ability to move from one
functional state into another, and the definition of functional states
with reference to the part they play in the operation of the entire
entity - i.e. in reference to the other functional states. So long as
the same process was achieved, the \"physical stuff\" \-- that being
computer hardware or biological structure \-- could achieve
consciousness.
This variety of functionalism was developed by Hilary Putnam. One of the
major proponents of functionalism is Jerry Fodor.
Further reading:
Block, N. (1996). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Supplement, Macmillan,
1996
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/functionalism.pdf>
## Dualism
### Substance dualism
This theory proposes that phenomenal experience occurs in a non-physical
place. In Cartesian Dualism the non-physical place is an unextended soul
that looks out at the brain. In Reid\'s Natural Dualism the non-physical
place is a point-soul that looks out at the world.
### Property dualism
Property dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the
appropriate way (i.e., organized in the way that living human bodies are
organized), mental properties emerge. Property dualism is a branch of
emergent materialism. The appeal to emergentism deserves closer
attention. Scientific theories often deal with emergent phenomena, for
instance an enzyme consists of carbon, hydrogen, nitrogen, manganese and
oxygen and from this catalytic action emerges. The theory of enzyme
structure and the action of this structure on the substrate explains how
this emergence occurs. Notice that the theory of enzymes explains the
emergence of catalytic activity; emergence does not explain the theory.
In science the statement that some property will \'emerge\' means that
there will be a theory that accounts for this property. Property
dualism, by appealing to emergence, is stating that some theory of
consciousness will be possible. In other words it is an explanation that
proposes that the explanation is yet to be known.
## Intentionalism
## Higher order thought
*This section is a stub and needs expansion*
## Eliminativism
Eliminative materialism is the school of thought that argues for an
absolute version of materialism with respect to mental entities and
mental vocabulary. It principally argues that our common-sense
understanding of the mind (often called \'folk psychology\') is not a
viable theory on which to base scientific investigation, and therefore
no coherent neural basis will be found for many such everyday
psychological concepts (such as belief or intention) and that behaviour
and experience can only be adequately explained on the biological level.
Eliminative materialists therefore believe that consciousness does not
exist and that the concept will eventually be eliminated as neuroscience
progresses. Similarly, they argue that folk psychological concepts such
as belief, desire and intention do not have any consistent neurological
substrate.
Proponents of this view often make parallels to previous scientific
theories which have been eliminated, such as the four humours theory of
medicine, the phlogiston theory of combustion and \'vital force\' theory
of life. In these cases, science has not produced more detailed versions
of these theories, but rejected them as obsolete. Eliminative
materialists argue that folk psychology is headed the same way.
According to W.V. Quine it will take tens of years before folk
psychology will be replaced with real science. (see Phenomenal
consciousness and access
consciousness).
Eliminative materialism was first defended by W.V. Quine, Paul
Feyerabend, and Richard Rorty. This view is most associated with
philosophers Paul and Patricia Churchland although philosophers such as
Daniel Dennett would also consider themselves eliminativists for many
aspects of psychology. Philosopher Dale Jacquette has claimed that
Occam\'s Razor is the rationale behind eliminativism and reductionism.
The most common argument against eliminative materialism is the argument
from qualia, which is deployed in various forms by Thomas Nagel, Frank
Jackson, and many others. Perhaps the most powerful argument against
eliminativism is that experience itself is many things simultaneously;
it is, as Aristotle points out, immediate and hence is not composed of
judgements.
## Mysterianism
New Mysterianism is a philosophy proposing that certain problems (in
particular, consciousness) will never be explained.
Owen Flanagan noted in his 1991 book \"Science of the Mind\" that some
modern thinkers have suggested that consciousness might never be
completely explained. Flanagan called them \"the new mysterians\" after
the rock group ? and the Mysterians. The term originated with the
Japanese alien-invasion film The Mysterians. The \"old mysterians\" are
thinkers throughout history who have put forward a similar position.
They include Leibniz, Dr Johnson, and Thomas Huxley. The latter said,
\"How is it that anything so remarkable as a state of consciousness
comes about as a result of irritating nervous tissue, is just as
unaccountable as the appearance of the Djin, when Aladdin rubbed his
lamp.\" \[6, p. 229, quote\]
Noam Chomsky distinguishes between problems, which seem solvable, at
least in principle, through scientific methods, and mysteries which do
not, even in principle. He notes that the cognitive capabilities of all
organisms are limited by biology, e.g. a mouse will never speak. In the
same way, certain problems may be beyond our understanding.
The term New Mysterianism has been extended by some writers to encompass
the wider philosophical position that humans don\'t have the
intellectual ability to understand many hard problems, not just the
problem of consciousness, at a scientific level. This position is also
known as Anti-Constructive Naturalism.
For example, in the mind-body problem, emergent materialism claims that
humans aren\'t smart enough to determine \"the relationship between mind
and matter.\" \[4\] Strong agnosticism is a religious application of
this position.
Colin McGinn is the leading proponent of the New Mysterian position.
Critics argue this philosophy isn\'t useful and encourages capitulation.
One critic noted:
the extreme \"Mysterian\" position, that there are vital issues forever
beyond our reach, is in many ways deeply unsatisfying. \[7\]
References
\[1\] McGinn, Colin - The Problem of Consciousness
\[2\] McGinn, Colin - Problems in Philosophy: the limits of enquiry
\[3\] McGinn, Colin - The Mysterious Flame
\[4\] Blackburn, Simon - Think: A compelling introduction to philosophy,
chapter two
\[5\] Flanagan, Owen - The Science of the Mind (1991) 2ed MIT Press,
Cambridge
\[6\] Horgan, John - The Undiscovered Mind (1999), Phoenix,
## Idealism and panpsychism
### Idealism
|
# Consciousness Studies/Contemporary Explanations#The identity theory of mind
*This section is about the types of theory that have been advanced to
explain consciousness. Specific explanations should be entered as
separate pages.*
## Introduction
Explanations of consciousness fall into three broad categories, those
that attempt to explain the empirical experience called consciousness
with scientific theories, those that seek to find some way in which
consciousness could be explained by digital computers or nineteenth
century materialism by redefining or eliminating experience and those
that regard consciousness as inexplicable or supernatural.
## Identity theory of mind
The identity theory of mind, or type physicalism, holds that the mind is
identical to the brain. Type physicalists identify qualia and the form
of experience with brain activity. They argue that \"mind states\" have
physical causes and physical effects - thus the mind states themselves
must be physical; a non-physical \"middle step\" is superfluous.
Type physicalism has not yet gained widespread support because although
brain activity that correlates with experience has been found everywhere
in the brain, no set of brain activity that is phenomenal consciousness
itself has yet been found - although this is not surprising because
neuronal spike activity is unlikely to host phenomenal consciousness -
see scientific theories of
consciousness.
## Functionalism
Functionalism was developed as a theory of the mind-body problem because
of objections to identity theory and logical behaviourism. Its core idea
is that the mental states can be accounted for without taking into
account the underlying physical medium (the neurons), instead attending
to higher-level functions such as beliefs, desires, and emotions. It is
a theory of behaviour and access consciousness and so from the outset
avoids any explanation of phenomenal consciousness, substituting beliefs
and judgements (functions) for entities such as qualia.
According to functionalism, the mental states that make up consciousness
can essentially be defined as complex interactions between different
functional processes. Because these processes are not limited to a
particular physical state or physical medium, they can be realized in
multiple ways, including, theoretically, within non-biological
systems.This affords consciousness the opportunity to exist in non-human
minds that are based on algorithmic processors such as digital
computers. This is a highly contentious conjecture although
non-functionalist physicalists might agree that machines that are not
digital computers could possess consciousness through an identity theory
of mind - see The problem of machine and digital
consciousness.
Functionalism\'s explanation of consciousness, or the mental, is best
understood when considering the analogy made by functionalists between
the mind and the modern digital computer. More specifically, the analogy
is made to a \"machine\" capable of computing any given algorithm (i.e.
a Turing machine). This machine would involve:
Data input (the senses in humans), data output (both behaviour and
memory), functional states (mental states), the ability to move from one
functional state into another, and the definition of functional states
with reference to the part they play in the operation of the entire
entity - i.e. in reference to the other functional states. So long as
the same process was achieved, the \"physical stuff\" \-- that being
computer hardware or biological structure \-- could achieve
consciousness.
This variety of functionalism was developed by Hilary Putnam. One of the
major proponents of functionalism is Jerry Fodor.
Further reading:
Block, N. (1996). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Supplement, Macmillan,
1996
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/functionalism.pdf>
## Dualism
### Substance dualism
This theory proposes that phenomenal experience occurs in a non-physical
place. In Cartesian Dualism the non-physical place is an unextended soul
that looks out at the brain. In Reid\'s Natural Dualism the non-physical
place is a point-soul that looks out at the world.
### Property dualism
Property dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the
appropriate way (i.e., organized in the way that living human bodies are
organized), mental properties emerge. Property dualism is a branch of
emergent materialism. The appeal to emergentism deserves closer
attention. Scientific theories often deal with emergent phenomena, for
instance an enzyme consists of carbon, hydrogen, nitrogen, manganese and
oxygen and from this catalytic action emerges. The theory of enzyme
structure and the action of this structure on the substrate explains how
this emergence occurs. Notice that the theory of enzymes explains the
emergence of catalytic activity; emergence does not explain the theory.
In science the statement that some property will \'emerge\' means that
there will be a theory that accounts for this property. Property
dualism, by appealing to emergence, is stating that some theory of
consciousness will be possible. In other words it is an explanation that
proposes that the explanation is yet to be known.
## Intentionalism
## Higher order thought
*This section is a stub and needs expansion*
## Eliminativism
Eliminative materialism is the school of thought that argues for an
absolute version of materialism with respect to mental entities and
mental vocabulary. It principally argues that our common-sense
understanding of the mind (often called \'folk psychology\') is not a
viable theory on which to base scientific investigation, and therefore
no coherent neural basis will be found for many such everyday
psychological concepts (such as belief or intention) and that behaviour
and experience can only be adequately explained on the biological level.
Eliminative materialists therefore believe that consciousness does not
exist and that the concept will eventually be eliminated as neuroscience
progresses. Similarly, they argue that folk psychological concepts such
as belief, desire and intention do not have any consistent neurological
substrate.
Proponents of this view often make parallels to previous scientific
theories which have been eliminated, such as the four humours theory of
medicine, the phlogiston theory of combustion and \'vital force\' theory
of life. In these cases, science has not produced more detailed versions
of these theories, but rejected them as obsolete. Eliminative
materialists argue that folk psychology is headed the same way.
According to W.V. Quine it will take tens of years before folk
psychology will be replaced with real science. (see Phenomenal
consciousness and access
consciousness).
Eliminative materialism was first defended by W.V. Quine, Paul
Feyerabend, and Richard Rorty. This view is most associated with
philosophers Paul and Patricia Churchland although philosophers such as
Daniel Dennett would also consider themselves eliminativists for many
aspects of psychology. Philosopher Dale Jacquette has claimed that
Occam\'s Razor is the rationale behind eliminativism and reductionism.
The most common argument against eliminative materialism is the argument
from qualia, which is deployed in various forms by Thomas Nagel, Frank
Jackson, and many others. Perhaps the most powerful argument against
eliminativism is that experience itself is many things simultaneously;
it is, as Aristotle points out, immediate and hence is not composed of
judgements.
## Mysterianism
New Mysterianism is a philosophy proposing that certain problems (in
particular, consciousness) will never be explained.
Owen Flanagan noted in his 1991 book \"Science of the Mind\" that some
modern thinkers have suggested that consciousness might never be
completely explained. Flanagan called them \"the new mysterians\" after
the rock group ? and the Mysterians. The term originated with the
Japanese alien-invasion film The Mysterians. The \"old mysterians\" are
thinkers throughout history who have put forward a similar position.
They include Leibniz, Dr Johnson, and Thomas Huxley. The latter said,
\"How is it that anything so remarkable as a state of consciousness
comes about as a result of irritating nervous tissue, is just as
unaccountable as the appearance of the Djin, when Aladdin rubbed his
lamp.\" \[6, p. 229, quote\]
Noam Chomsky distinguishes between problems, which seem solvable, at
least in principle, through scientific methods, and mysteries which do
not, even in principle. He notes that the cognitive capabilities of all
organisms are limited by biology, e.g. a mouse will never speak. In the
same way, certain problems may be beyond our understanding.
The term New Mysterianism has been extended by some writers to encompass
the wider philosophical position that humans don\'t have the
intellectual ability to understand many hard problems, not just the
problem of consciousness, at a scientific level. This position is also
known as Anti-Constructive Naturalism.
For example, in the mind-body problem, emergent materialism claims that
humans aren\'t smart enough to determine \"the relationship between mind
and matter.\" \[4\] Strong agnosticism is a religious application of
this position.
Colin McGinn is the leading proponent of the New Mysterian position.
Critics argue this philosophy isn\'t useful and encourages capitulation.
One critic noted:
the extreme \"Mysterian\" position, that there are vital issues forever
beyond our reach, is in many ways deeply unsatisfying. \[7\]
References
\[1\] McGinn, Colin - The Problem of Consciousness
\[2\] McGinn, Colin - Problems in Philosophy: the limits of enquiry
\[3\] McGinn, Colin - The Mysterious Flame
\[4\] Blackburn, Simon - Think: A compelling introduction to philosophy,
chapter two
\[5\] Flanagan, Owen - The Science of the Mind (1991) 2ed MIT Press,
Cambridge
\[6\] Horgan, John - The Undiscovered Mind (1999), Phoenix,
## Idealism and panpsychism
### Idealism
|
# Consciousness Studies/Table Of Theories
## Theories of Consciousness
Some recent scientific theories of consciousness are tabulated below.
The extent to which they account for the phenomenon of consciousness is
shown.
It is remarkable that many of the theories are consistent with one
another. As in the tale of the \'blind men and the elephant\' some of
the theories seem to describe the trunk, some the tail etc. but they all
seem to be part of the same elephant! The convergence of the theories is
shown in the illustration below:
![](constudsumm.gif "constudsumm.gif")
## Table of theories
```{=html}
<TABLE CELLSPACING=0 BORDER=0 CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=829>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="31%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}A = Model of observer\'s view
B = Model of Anaesthetic Action in thalamus
C = Explanation of Libet\'s data`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="33%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
D = Explanation of unconscious but active cerebral cortex
E = Explanation of knowing you know
F = Explanation of non-computability`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="36%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
G = Binding (simultaneous processing of relevant data)
H = Extended present
I = Quantum state vector reduction`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
```{=html}
<TABLE BORDER CELLSPACING=1 CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=607>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}Name`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
Author/Ref`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
A`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
B`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
C`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
D`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
E`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
F`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
G`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
H`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
I`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Microconsciousness
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Zeki, S., & Bartel, A. (1999)
Toward a Theory of Visual Consciousness. Consciousness & Cognition, 8,
225-259.
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Geometrical Phenomenalism
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Green, A. (2003)
Geometrical
phenomenalism
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
?
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
ORCH-R
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Hameroff, S & Penrose, R. 1989
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Quantum Brain Model
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Ricciardi, L. M. and H. Umezawa, 1967. Brain physics and many-body
problems, Kibernetik 4, 44-48.
<http://arXiv.org/abs/q-bio/0309009>
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
?
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Many Minds
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Donald, M. 1990. Quantum Theory and the Brain. Proc R Soc Lond. A427
43-93.
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
?
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
?
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
```{=html}
<TABLE CELLSPACING=0 BORDER=0 CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=829>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="31%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}A = Model of observer\'s view
B = Model of Anaesthetic Action in thalamus
C = Explanation of Libet\'s data`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="33%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
D = Explanation of unconscious but active cerebral cortex
E = Explanation of knowing you know
F = Explanation of non-computability`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="36%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
G = Binding (simultaneous processing of relevant data)
H = Extended present
I = Quantum state vector reduction`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
```{=html}
<TABLE BORDER CELLSPACING=1 CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=607>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}Name`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
Author/Ref`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
A`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
B`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
C`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
D`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
E`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
F`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
G`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
H`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
I`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Dual-Time Supercausality
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
King, C.C. 1989. Physics Essays 2/2 128-151.
<http://www.math.auckland.ac.nz/~king/Preprints/Transup.htm>
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
?
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Spin Mediated Consciousness
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Hu, H. & Wu, M. 2002. Spin-Mediated Consciousness Theory: An Approach
Based On Pan-Protopsychism.
<http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00002579/>
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
?
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Quantum Theory of Consciousness (synaptic cleft)
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Walker, E.W. 1998. the `<I>`{=html}Noetic Journal`</I>`{=html},
`<I>`{=html}1`</I>`{=html}, 100-107, 1998
<http://users.erols.com/wcri/CONSCIOUSNESS.html>
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
```{=html}
<TABLE CELLSPACING=0 BORDER=0 CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=829>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="31%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}A = Model of observer\'s view
B = Model of Anaesthetic Action in thalamus
C = Explanation of Libet\'s data`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="33%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
D = Explanation of unconscious but active cerebral cortex
E = Explanation of knowing you know
F = Explanation of non-computability`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="36%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
G = Binding (simultaneous processing of relevant data)
H = Extended present
I = Quantum state vector reduction`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
```{=html}
<TABLE BORDER CELLSPACING=1 CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=607>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}Name`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
Author/Ref`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
A`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
B`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
C`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
D`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
E`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
F`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
G`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
H`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
I`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Global Workspace Theory
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Baars, B. 1988. A cognitive theory of consciousness. Cambridge
University Press, New York
<http://www.ceptualinstitute.com/genre/baars/baarsBrain.htm>
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
Y`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
Y`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
Y`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
Y`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
Y`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Topological Geometrodynamics (TGD) Inspired Theory of Consciousness
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Pitkänen, M. 199?. Topological Geometrodynamics
<http://www.physics.helsinki.fi/~matpitka/mainpage.html>
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
?
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
Y`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
Y`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
The Conscious Electromagnetic Field Theory
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
McFadden, J.J. 2002
<http://www.surrey.ac.uk/qe/cemi.htm>
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
?
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
?
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
```{=html}
<TABLE CELLSPACING=0 BORDER=0 CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=829>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="31%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}A = Model of observer\'s view
B = Model of Anaesthetic Action in thalamus
C = Explanation of Libet\'s data`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="33%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
D = Explanation of unconscious but active cerebral cortex
E = Explanation of knowing you know
F = Explanation of non-computability`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="36%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
G = Binding (simultaneous processing of relevant data)
H = Extended present
I = Quantum state vector reduction`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
```{=html}
<TABLE BORDER CELLSPACING=1 CELLPADDING=7 WIDTH=612>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}Name`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
Author/Ref`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
A`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
B`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
C`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
D`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
E`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
F`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
G`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
H`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
`<B>`{=html}
I`</B>`{=html}
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Real Time Consciousness
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Smythies, J. 2003. Journal of Consciousness Studies 10:3 47-56
<http://www.imprint.co.uk/pdf/smythies.pdf>
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
?
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
?
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Consciousness as memory
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Gerald Edelman\'s theory
Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A. 2003 April 29; 100(9):
5520--5524
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
<TR>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="29%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Single neuron theories of consciousness
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="28%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Edwards, J. (2006)
`How Many Pople Are There In My Head, And In Hers, Imprint Academic. ``http://www.ucl.ac.uk/~regfjxe/aw.htm`
Sevush, S. (2006)
SINGLE-NEURON THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS. Journal of Theoretical Biology.
238(3), 704-725.
<http://cogprints.org/4432/01/single%5Fneuron%5Ftheory.htm>
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="4%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
Y
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
<TD WIDTH="5%" VALIGN="TOP">
```
N
```{=html}
</TD>
```
```{=html}
</TR>
```
```{=html}
</TABLE>
```
|
# Consciousness Studies/Contemporary Explanations#Functionalism
*This section is about the types of theory that have been advanced to
explain consciousness. Specific explanations should be entered as
separate pages.*
## Introduction
Explanations of consciousness fall into three broad categories, those
that attempt to explain the empirical experience called consciousness
with scientific theories, those that seek to find some way in which
consciousness could be explained by digital computers or nineteenth
century materialism by redefining or eliminating experience and those
that regard consciousness as inexplicable or supernatural.
## Identity theory of mind
The identity theory of mind, or type physicalism, holds that the mind is
identical to the brain. Type physicalists identify qualia and the form
of experience with brain activity. They argue that \"mind states\" have
physical causes and physical effects - thus the mind states themselves
must be physical; a non-physical \"middle step\" is superfluous.
Type physicalism has not yet gained widespread support because although
brain activity that correlates with experience has been found everywhere
in the brain, no set of brain activity that is phenomenal consciousness
itself has yet been found - although this is not surprising because
neuronal spike activity is unlikely to host phenomenal consciousness -
see scientific theories of
consciousness.
## Functionalism
Functionalism was developed as a theory of the mind-body problem because
of objections to identity theory and logical behaviourism. Its core idea
is that the mental states can be accounted for without taking into
account the underlying physical medium (the neurons), instead attending
to higher-level functions such as beliefs, desires, and emotions. It is
a theory of behaviour and access consciousness and so from the outset
avoids any explanation of phenomenal consciousness, substituting beliefs
and judgements (functions) for entities such as qualia.
According to functionalism, the mental states that make up consciousness
can essentially be defined as complex interactions between different
functional processes. Because these processes are not limited to a
particular physical state or physical medium, they can be realized in
multiple ways, including, theoretically, within non-biological
systems.This affords consciousness the opportunity to exist in non-human
minds that are based on algorithmic processors such as digital
computers. This is a highly contentious conjecture although
non-functionalist physicalists might agree that machines that are not
digital computers could possess consciousness through an identity theory
of mind - see The problem of machine and digital
consciousness.
Functionalism\'s explanation of consciousness, or the mental, is best
understood when considering the analogy made by functionalists between
the mind and the modern digital computer. More specifically, the analogy
is made to a \"machine\" capable of computing any given algorithm (i.e.
a Turing machine). This machine would involve:
Data input (the senses in humans), data output (both behaviour and
memory), functional states (mental states), the ability to move from one
functional state into another, and the definition of functional states
with reference to the part they play in the operation of the entire
entity - i.e. in reference to the other functional states. So long as
the same process was achieved, the \"physical stuff\" \-- that being
computer hardware or biological structure \-- could achieve
consciousness.
This variety of functionalism was developed by Hilary Putnam. One of the
major proponents of functionalism is Jerry Fodor.
Further reading:
Block, N. (1996). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Supplement, Macmillan,
1996
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/functionalism.pdf>
## Dualism
### Substance dualism
This theory proposes that phenomenal experience occurs in a non-physical
place. In Cartesian Dualism the non-physical place is an unextended soul
that looks out at the brain. In Reid\'s Natural Dualism the non-physical
place is a point-soul that looks out at the world.
### Property dualism
Property dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the
appropriate way (i.e., organized in the way that living human bodies are
organized), mental properties emerge. Property dualism is a branch of
emergent materialism. The appeal to emergentism deserves closer
attention. Scientific theories often deal with emergent phenomena, for
instance an enzyme consists of carbon, hydrogen, nitrogen, manganese and
oxygen and from this catalytic action emerges. The theory of enzyme
structure and the action of this structure on the substrate explains how
this emergence occurs. Notice that the theory of enzymes explains the
emergence of catalytic activity; emergence does not explain the theory.
In science the statement that some property will \'emerge\' means that
there will be a theory that accounts for this property. Property
dualism, by appealing to emergence, is stating that some theory of
consciousness will be possible. In other words it is an explanation that
proposes that the explanation is yet to be known.
## Intentionalism
## Higher order thought
*This section is a stub and needs expansion*
## Eliminativism
Eliminative materialism is the school of thought that argues for an
absolute version of materialism with respect to mental entities and
mental vocabulary. It principally argues that our common-sense
understanding of the mind (often called \'folk psychology\') is not a
viable theory on which to base scientific investigation, and therefore
no coherent neural basis will be found for many such everyday
psychological concepts (such as belief or intention) and that behaviour
and experience can only be adequately explained on the biological level.
Eliminative materialists therefore believe that consciousness does not
exist and that the concept will eventually be eliminated as neuroscience
progresses. Similarly, they argue that folk psychological concepts such
as belief, desire and intention do not have any consistent neurological
substrate.
Proponents of this view often make parallels to previous scientific
theories which have been eliminated, such as the four humours theory of
medicine, the phlogiston theory of combustion and \'vital force\' theory
of life. In these cases, science has not produced more detailed versions
of these theories, but rejected them as obsolete. Eliminative
materialists argue that folk psychology is headed the same way.
According to W.V. Quine it will take tens of years before folk
psychology will be replaced with real science. (see Phenomenal
consciousness and access
consciousness).
Eliminative materialism was first defended by W.V. Quine, Paul
Feyerabend, and Richard Rorty. This view is most associated with
philosophers Paul and Patricia Churchland although philosophers such as
Daniel Dennett would also consider themselves eliminativists for many
aspects of psychology. Philosopher Dale Jacquette has claimed that
Occam\'s Razor is the rationale behind eliminativism and reductionism.
The most common argument against eliminative materialism is the argument
from qualia, which is deployed in various forms by Thomas Nagel, Frank
Jackson, and many others. Perhaps the most powerful argument against
eliminativism is that experience itself is many things simultaneously;
it is, as Aristotle points out, immediate and hence is not composed of
judgements.
## Mysterianism
New Mysterianism is a philosophy proposing that certain problems (in
particular, consciousness) will never be explained.
Owen Flanagan noted in his 1991 book \"Science of the Mind\" that some
modern thinkers have suggested that consciousness might never be
completely explained. Flanagan called them \"the new mysterians\" after
the rock group ? and the Mysterians. The term originated with the
Japanese alien-invasion film The Mysterians. The \"old mysterians\" are
thinkers throughout history who have put forward a similar position.
They include Leibniz, Dr Johnson, and Thomas Huxley. The latter said,
\"How is it that anything so remarkable as a state of consciousness
comes about as a result of irritating nervous tissue, is just as
unaccountable as the appearance of the Djin, when Aladdin rubbed his
lamp.\" \[6, p. 229, quote\]
Noam Chomsky distinguishes between problems, which seem solvable, at
least in principle, through scientific methods, and mysteries which do
not, even in principle. He notes that the cognitive capabilities of all
organisms are limited by biology, e.g. a mouse will never speak. In the
same way, certain problems may be beyond our understanding.
The term New Mysterianism has been extended by some writers to encompass
the wider philosophical position that humans don\'t have the
intellectual ability to understand many hard problems, not just the
problem of consciousness, at a scientific level. This position is also
known as Anti-Constructive Naturalism.
For example, in the mind-body problem, emergent materialism claims that
humans aren\'t smart enough to determine \"the relationship between mind
and matter.\" \[4\] Strong agnosticism is a religious application of
this position.
Colin McGinn is the leading proponent of the New Mysterian position.
Critics argue this philosophy isn\'t useful and encourages capitulation.
One critic noted:
the extreme \"Mysterian\" position, that there are vital issues forever
beyond our reach, is in many ways deeply unsatisfying. \[7\]
References
\[1\] McGinn, Colin - The Problem of Consciousness
\[2\] McGinn, Colin - Problems in Philosophy: the limits of enquiry
\[3\] McGinn, Colin - The Mysterious Flame
\[4\] Blackburn, Simon - Think: A compelling introduction to philosophy,
chapter two
\[5\] Flanagan, Owen - The Science of the Mind (1991) 2ed MIT Press,
Cambridge
\[6\] Horgan, John - The Undiscovered Mind (1999), Phoenix,
## Idealism and panpsychism
### Idealism
|
# Consciousness Studies/Contemporary Explanations#Property dualism
*This section is about the types of theory that have been advanced to
explain consciousness. Specific explanations should be entered as
separate pages.*
## Introduction
Explanations of consciousness fall into three broad categories, those
that attempt to explain the empirical experience called consciousness
with scientific theories, those that seek to find some way in which
consciousness could be explained by digital computers or nineteenth
century materialism by redefining or eliminating experience and those
that regard consciousness as inexplicable or supernatural.
## Identity theory of mind
The identity theory of mind, or type physicalism, holds that the mind is
identical to the brain. Type physicalists identify qualia and the form
of experience with brain activity. They argue that \"mind states\" have
physical causes and physical effects - thus the mind states themselves
must be physical; a non-physical \"middle step\" is superfluous.
Type physicalism has not yet gained widespread support because although
brain activity that correlates with experience has been found everywhere
in the brain, no set of brain activity that is phenomenal consciousness
itself has yet been found - although this is not surprising because
neuronal spike activity is unlikely to host phenomenal consciousness -
see scientific theories of
consciousness.
## Functionalism
Functionalism was developed as a theory of the mind-body problem because
of objections to identity theory and logical behaviourism. Its core idea
is that the mental states can be accounted for without taking into
account the underlying physical medium (the neurons), instead attending
to higher-level functions such as beliefs, desires, and emotions. It is
a theory of behaviour and access consciousness and so from the outset
avoids any explanation of phenomenal consciousness, substituting beliefs
and judgements (functions) for entities such as qualia.
According to functionalism, the mental states that make up consciousness
can essentially be defined as complex interactions between different
functional processes. Because these processes are not limited to a
particular physical state or physical medium, they can be realized in
multiple ways, including, theoretically, within non-biological
systems.This affords consciousness the opportunity to exist in non-human
minds that are based on algorithmic processors such as digital
computers. This is a highly contentious conjecture although
non-functionalist physicalists might agree that machines that are not
digital computers could possess consciousness through an identity theory
of mind - see The problem of machine and digital
consciousness.
Functionalism\'s explanation of consciousness, or the mental, is best
understood when considering the analogy made by functionalists between
the mind and the modern digital computer. More specifically, the analogy
is made to a \"machine\" capable of computing any given algorithm (i.e.
a Turing machine). This machine would involve:
Data input (the senses in humans), data output (both behaviour and
memory), functional states (mental states), the ability to move from one
functional state into another, and the definition of functional states
with reference to the part they play in the operation of the entire
entity - i.e. in reference to the other functional states. So long as
the same process was achieved, the \"physical stuff\" \-- that being
computer hardware or biological structure \-- could achieve
consciousness.
This variety of functionalism was developed by Hilary Putnam. One of the
major proponents of functionalism is Jerry Fodor.
Further reading:
Block, N. (1996). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Supplement, Macmillan,
1996
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/functionalism.pdf>
## Dualism
### Substance dualism
This theory proposes that phenomenal experience occurs in a non-physical
place. In Cartesian Dualism the non-physical place is an unextended soul
that looks out at the brain. In Reid\'s Natural Dualism the non-physical
place is a point-soul that looks out at the world.
### Property dualism
Property dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the
appropriate way (i.e., organized in the way that living human bodies are
organized), mental properties emerge. Property dualism is a branch of
emergent materialism. The appeal to emergentism deserves closer
attention. Scientific theories often deal with emergent phenomena, for
instance an enzyme consists of carbon, hydrogen, nitrogen, manganese and
oxygen and from this catalytic action emerges. The theory of enzyme
structure and the action of this structure on the substrate explains how
this emergence occurs. Notice that the theory of enzymes explains the
emergence of catalytic activity; emergence does not explain the theory.
In science the statement that some property will \'emerge\' means that
there will be a theory that accounts for this property. Property
dualism, by appealing to emergence, is stating that some theory of
consciousness will be possible. In other words it is an explanation that
proposes that the explanation is yet to be known.
## Intentionalism
## Higher order thought
*This section is a stub and needs expansion*
## Eliminativism
Eliminative materialism is the school of thought that argues for an
absolute version of materialism with respect to mental entities and
mental vocabulary. It principally argues that our common-sense
understanding of the mind (often called \'folk psychology\') is not a
viable theory on which to base scientific investigation, and therefore
no coherent neural basis will be found for many such everyday
psychological concepts (such as belief or intention) and that behaviour
and experience can only be adequately explained on the biological level.
Eliminative materialists therefore believe that consciousness does not
exist and that the concept will eventually be eliminated as neuroscience
progresses. Similarly, they argue that folk psychological concepts such
as belief, desire and intention do not have any consistent neurological
substrate.
Proponents of this view often make parallels to previous scientific
theories which have been eliminated, such as the four humours theory of
medicine, the phlogiston theory of combustion and \'vital force\' theory
of life. In these cases, science has not produced more detailed versions
of these theories, but rejected them as obsolete. Eliminative
materialists argue that folk psychology is headed the same way.
According to W.V. Quine it will take tens of years before folk
psychology will be replaced with real science. (see Phenomenal
consciousness and access
consciousness).
Eliminative materialism was first defended by W.V. Quine, Paul
Feyerabend, and Richard Rorty. This view is most associated with
philosophers Paul and Patricia Churchland although philosophers such as
Daniel Dennett would also consider themselves eliminativists for many
aspects of psychology. Philosopher Dale Jacquette has claimed that
Occam\'s Razor is the rationale behind eliminativism and reductionism.
The most common argument against eliminative materialism is the argument
from qualia, which is deployed in various forms by Thomas Nagel, Frank
Jackson, and many others. Perhaps the most powerful argument against
eliminativism is that experience itself is many things simultaneously;
it is, as Aristotle points out, immediate and hence is not composed of
judgements.
## Mysterianism
New Mysterianism is a philosophy proposing that certain problems (in
particular, consciousness) will never be explained.
Owen Flanagan noted in his 1991 book \"Science of the Mind\" that some
modern thinkers have suggested that consciousness might never be
completely explained. Flanagan called them \"the new mysterians\" after
the rock group ? and the Mysterians. The term originated with the
Japanese alien-invasion film The Mysterians. The \"old mysterians\" are
thinkers throughout history who have put forward a similar position.
They include Leibniz, Dr Johnson, and Thomas Huxley. The latter said,
\"How is it that anything so remarkable as a state of consciousness
comes about as a result of irritating nervous tissue, is just as
unaccountable as the appearance of the Djin, when Aladdin rubbed his
lamp.\" \[6, p. 229, quote\]
Noam Chomsky distinguishes between problems, which seem solvable, at
least in principle, through scientific methods, and mysteries which do
not, even in principle. He notes that the cognitive capabilities of all
organisms are limited by biology, e.g. a mouse will never speak. In the
same way, certain problems may be beyond our understanding.
The term New Mysterianism has been extended by some writers to encompass
the wider philosophical position that humans don\'t have the
intellectual ability to understand many hard problems, not just the
problem of consciousness, at a scientific level. This position is also
known as Anti-Constructive Naturalism.
For example, in the mind-body problem, emergent materialism claims that
humans aren\'t smart enough to determine \"the relationship between mind
and matter.\" \[4\] Strong agnosticism is a religious application of
this position.
Colin McGinn is the leading proponent of the New Mysterian position.
Critics argue this philosophy isn\'t useful and encourages capitulation.
One critic noted:
the extreme \"Mysterian\" position, that there are vital issues forever
beyond our reach, is in many ways deeply unsatisfying. \[7\]
References
\[1\] McGinn, Colin - The Problem of Consciousness
\[2\] McGinn, Colin - Problems in Philosophy: the limits of enquiry
\[3\] McGinn, Colin - The Mysterious Flame
\[4\] Blackburn, Simon - Think: A compelling introduction to philosophy,
chapter two
\[5\] Flanagan, Owen - The Science of the Mind (1991) 2ed MIT Press,
Cambridge
\[6\] Horgan, John - The Undiscovered Mind (1999), Phoenix,
## Idealism and panpsychism
### Idealism
|
# Consciousness Studies/Contemporary Explanations#Intentionalism
*This section is about the types of theory that have been advanced to
explain consciousness. Specific explanations should be entered as
separate pages.*
## Introduction
Explanations of consciousness fall into three broad categories, those
that attempt to explain the empirical experience called consciousness
with scientific theories, those that seek to find some way in which
consciousness could be explained by digital computers or nineteenth
century materialism by redefining or eliminating experience and those
that regard consciousness as inexplicable or supernatural.
## Identity theory of mind
The identity theory of mind, or type physicalism, holds that the mind is
identical to the brain. Type physicalists identify qualia and the form
of experience with brain activity. They argue that \"mind states\" have
physical causes and physical effects - thus the mind states themselves
must be physical; a non-physical \"middle step\" is superfluous.
Type physicalism has not yet gained widespread support because although
brain activity that correlates with experience has been found everywhere
in the brain, no set of brain activity that is phenomenal consciousness
itself has yet been found - although this is not surprising because
neuronal spike activity is unlikely to host phenomenal consciousness -
see scientific theories of
consciousness.
## Functionalism
Functionalism was developed as a theory of the mind-body problem because
of objections to identity theory and logical behaviourism. Its core idea
is that the mental states can be accounted for without taking into
account the underlying physical medium (the neurons), instead attending
to higher-level functions such as beliefs, desires, and emotions. It is
a theory of behaviour and access consciousness and so from the outset
avoids any explanation of phenomenal consciousness, substituting beliefs
and judgements (functions) for entities such as qualia.
According to functionalism, the mental states that make up consciousness
can essentially be defined as complex interactions between different
functional processes. Because these processes are not limited to a
particular physical state or physical medium, they can be realized in
multiple ways, including, theoretically, within non-biological
systems.This affords consciousness the opportunity to exist in non-human
minds that are based on algorithmic processors such as digital
computers. This is a highly contentious conjecture although
non-functionalist physicalists might agree that machines that are not
digital computers could possess consciousness through an identity theory
of mind - see The problem of machine and digital
consciousness.
Functionalism\'s explanation of consciousness, or the mental, is best
understood when considering the analogy made by functionalists between
the mind and the modern digital computer. More specifically, the analogy
is made to a \"machine\" capable of computing any given algorithm (i.e.
a Turing machine). This machine would involve:
Data input (the senses in humans), data output (both behaviour and
memory), functional states (mental states), the ability to move from one
functional state into another, and the definition of functional states
with reference to the part they play in the operation of the entire
entity - i.e. in reference to the other functional states. So long as
the same process was achieved, the \"physical stuff\" \-- that being
computer hardware or biological structure \-- could achieve
consciousness.
This variety of functionalism was developed by Hilary Putnam. One of the
major proponents of functionalism is Jerry Fodor.
Further reading:
Block, N. (1996). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Supplement, Macmillan,
1996
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/functionalism.pdf>
## Dualism
### Substance dualism
This theory proposes that phenomenal experience occurs in a non-physical
place. In Cartesian Dualism the non-physical place is an unextended soul
that looks out at the brain. In Reid\'s Natural Dualism the non-physical
place is a point-soul that looks out at the world.
### Property dualism
Property dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the
appropriate way (i.e., organized in the way that living human bodies are
organized), mental properties emerge. Property dualism is a branch of
emergent materialism. The appeal to emergentism deserves closer
attention. Scientific theories often deal with emergent phenomena, for
instance an enzyme consists of carbon, hydrogen, nitrogen, manganese and
oxygen and from this catalytic action emerges. The theory of enzyme
structure and the action of this structure on the substrate explains how
this emergence occurs. Notice that the theory of enzymes explains the
emergence of catalytic activity; emergence does not explain the theory.
In science the statement that some property will \'emerge\' means that
there will be a theory that accounts for this property. Property
dualism, by appealing to emergence, is stating that some theory of
consciousness will be possible. In other words it is an explanation that
proposes that the explanation is yet to be known.
## Intentionalism
## Higher order thought
*This section is a stub and needs expansion*
## Eliminativism
Eliminative materialism is the school of thought that argues for an
absolute version of materialism with respect to mental entities and
mental vocabulary. It principally argues that our common-sense
understanding of the mind (often called \'folk psychology\') is not a
viable theory on which to base scientific investigation, and therefore
no coherent neural basis will be found for many such everyday
psychological concepts (such as belief or intention) and that behaviour
and experience can only be adequately explained on the biological level.
Eliminative materialists therefore believe that consciousness does not
exist and that the concept will eventually be eliminated as neuroscience
progresses. Similarly, they argue that folk psychological concepts such
as belief, desire and intention do not have any consistent neurological
substrate.
Proponents of this view often make parallels to previous scientific
theories which have been eliminated, such as the four humours theory of
medicine, the phlogiston theory of combustion and \'vital force\' theory
of life. In these cases, science has not produced more detailed versions
of these theories, but rejected them as obsolete. Eliminative
materialists argue that folk psychology is headed the same way.
According to W.V. Quine it will take tens of years before folk
psychology will be replaced with real science. (see Phenomenal
consciousness and access
consciousness).
Eliminative materialism was first defended by W.V. Quine, Paul
Feyerabend, and Richard Rorty. This view is most associated with
philosophers Paul and Patricia Churchland although philosophers such as
Daniel Dennett would also consider themselves eliminativists for many
aspects of psychology. Philosopher Dale Jacquette has claimed that
Occam\'s Razor is the rationale behind eliminativism and reductionism.
The most common argument against eliminative materialism is the argument
from qualia, which is deployed in various forms by Thomas Nagel, Frank
Jackson, and many others. Perhaps the most powerful argument against
eliminativism is that experience itself is many things simultaneously;
it is, as Aristotle points out, immediate and hence is not composed of
judgements.
## Mysterianism
New Mysterianism is a philosophy proposing that certain problems (in
particular, consciousness) will never be explained.
Owen Flanagan noted in his 1991 book \"Science of the Mind\" that some
modern thinkers have suggested that consciousness might never be
completely explained. Flanagan called them \"the new mysterians\" after
the rock group ? and the Mysterians. The term originated with the
Japanese alien-invasion film The Mysterians. The \"old mysterians\" are
thinkers throughout history who have put forward a similar position.
They include Leibniz, Dr Johnson, and Thomas Huxley. The latter said,
\"How is it that anything so remarkable as a state of consciousness
comes about as a result of irritating nervous tissue, is just as
unaccountable as the appearance of the Djin, when Aladdin rubbed his
lamp.\" \[6, p. 229, quote\]
Noam Chomsky distinguishes between problems, which seem solvable, at
least in principle, through scientific methods, and mysteries which do
not, even in principle. He notes that the cognitive capabilities of all
organisms are limited by biology, e.g. a mouse will never speak. In the
same way, certain problems may be beyond our understanding.
The term New Mysterianism has been extended by some writers to encompass
the wider philosophical position that humans don\'t have the
intellectual ability to understand many hard problems, not just the
problem of consciousness, at a scientific level. This position is also
known as Anti-Constructive Naturalism.
For example, in the mind-body problem, emergent materialism claims that
humans aren\'t smart enough to determine \"the relationship between mind
and matter.\" \[4\] Strong agnosticism is a religious application of
this position.
Colin McGinn is the leading proponent of the New Mysterian position.
Critics argue this philosophy isn\'t useful and encourages capitulation.
One critic noted:
the extreme \"Mysterian\" position, that there are vital issues forever
beyond our reach, is in many ways deeply unsatisfying. \[7\]
References
\[1\] McGinn, Colin - The Problem of Consciousness
\[2\] McGinn, Colin - Problems in Philosophy: the limits of enquiry
\[3\] McGinn, Colin - The Mysterious Flame
\[4\] Blackburn, Simon - Think: A compelling introduction to philosophy,
chapter two
\[5\] Flanagan, Owen - The Science of the Mind (1991) 2ed MIT Press,
Cambridge
\[6\] Horgan, John - The Undiscovered Mind (1999), Phoenix,
## Idealism and panpsychism
### Idealism
|
# Consciousness Studies/Contemporary Explanations#Higher order thought
*This section is about the types of theory that have been advanced to
explain consciousness. Specific explanations should be entered as
separate pages.*
## Introduction
Explanations of consciousness fall into three broad categories, those
that attempt to explain the empirical experience called consciousness
with scientific theories, those that seek to find some way in which
consciousness could be explained by digital computers or nineteenth
century materialism by redefining or eliminating experience and those
that regard consciousness as inexplicable or supernatural.
## Identity theory of mind
The identity theory of mind, or type physicalism, holds that the mind is
identical to the brain. Type physicalists identify qualia and the form
of experience with brain activity. They argue that \"mind states\" have
physical causes and physical effects - thus the mind states themselves
must be physical; a non-physical \"middle step\" is superfluous.
Type physicalism has not yet gained widespread support because although
brain activity that correlates with experience has been found everywhere
in the brain, no set of brain activity that is phenomenal consciousness
itself has yet been found - although this is not surprising because
neuronal spike activity is unlikely to host phenomenal consciousness -
see scientific theories of
consciousness.
## Functionalism
Functionalism was developed as a theory of the mind-body problem because
of objections to identity theory and logical behaviourism. Its core idea
is that the mental states can be accounted for without taking into
account the underlying physical medium (the neurons), instead attending
to higher-level functions such as beliefs, desires, and emotions. It is
a theory of behaviour and access consciousness and so from the outset
avoids any explanation of phenomenal consciousness, substituting beliefs
and judgements (functions) for entities such as qualia.
According to functionalism, the mental states that make up consciousness
can essentially be defined as complex interactions between different
functional processes. Because these processes are not limited to a
particular physical state or physical medium, they can be realized in
multiple ways, including, theoretically, within non-biological
systems.This affords consciousness the opportunity to exist in non-human
minds that are based on algorithmic processors such as digital
computers. This is a highly contentious conjecture although
non-functionalist physicalists might agree that machines that are not
digital computers could possess consciousness through an identity theory
of mind - see The problem of machine and digital
consciousness.
Functionalism\'s explanation of consciousness, or the mental, is best
understood when considering the analogy made by functionalists between
the mind and the modern digital computer. More specifically, the analogy
is made to a \"machine\" capable of computing any given algorithm (i.e.
a Turing machine). This machine would involve:
Data input (the senses in humans), data output (both behaviour and
memory), functional states (mental states), the ability to move from one
functional state into another, and the definition of functional states
with reference to the part they play in the operation of the entire
entity - i.e. in reference to the other functional states. So long as
the same process was achieved, the \"physical stuff\" \-- that being
computer hardware or biological structure \-- could achieve
consciousness.
This variety of functionalism was developed by Hilary Putnam. One of the
major proponents of functionalism is Jerry Fodor.
Further reading:
Block, N. (1996). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Supplement, Macmillan,
1996
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/functionalism.pdf>
## Dualism
### Substance dualism
This theory proposes that phenomenal experience occurs in a non-physical
place. In Cartesian Dualism the non-physical place is an unextended soul
that looks out at the brain. In Reid\'s Natural Dualism the non-physical
place is a point-soul that looks out at the world.
### Property dualism
Property dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the
appropriate way (i.e., organized in the way that living human bodies are
organized), mental properties emerge. Property dualism is a branch of
emergent materialism. The appeal to emergentism deserves closer
attention. Scientific theories often deal with emergent phenomena, for
instance an enzyme consists of carbon, hydrogen, nitrogen, manganese and
oxygen and from this catalytic action emerges. The theory of enzyme
structure and the action of this structure on the substrate explains how
this emergence occurs. Notice that the theory of enzymes explains the
emergence of catalytic activity; emergence does not explain the theory.
In science the statement that some property will \'emerge\' means that
there will be a theory that accounts for this property. Property
dualism, by appealing to emergence, is stating that some theory of
consciousness will be possible. In other words it is an explanation that
proposes that the explanation is yet to be known.
## Intentionalism
## Higher order thought
*This section is a stub and needs expansion*
## Eliminativism
Eliminative materialism is the school of thought that argues for an
absolute version of materialism with respect to mental entities and
mental vocabulary. It principally argues that our common-sense
understanding of the mind (often called \'folk psychology\') is not a
viable theory on which to base scientific investigation, and therefore
no coherent neural basis will be found for many such everyday
psychological concepts (such as belief or intention) and that behaviour
and experience can only be adequately explained on the biological level.
Eliminative materialists therefore believe that consciousness does not
exist and that the concept will eventually be eliminated as neuroscience
progresses. Similarly, they argue that folk psychological concepts such
as belief, desire and intention do not have any consistent neurological
substrate.
Proponents of this view often make parallels to previous scientific
theories which have been eliminated, such as the four humours theory of
medicine, the phlogiston theory of combustion and \'vital force\' theory
of life. In these cases, science has not produced more detailed versions
of these theories, but rejected them as obsolete. Eliminative
materialists argue that folk psychology is headed the same way.
According to W.V. Quine it will take tens of years before folk
psychology will be replaced with real science. (see Phenomenal
consciousness and access
consciousness).
Eliminative materialism was first defended by W.V. Quine, Paul
Feyerabend, and Richard Rorty. This view is most associated with
philosophers Paul and Patricia Churchland although philosophers such as
Daniel Dennett would also consider themselves eliminativists for many
aspects of psychology. Philosopher Dale Jacquette has claimed that
Occam\'s Razor is the rationale behind eliminativism and reductionism.
The most common argument against eliminative materialism is the argument
from qualia, which is deployed in various forms by Thomas Nagel, Frank
Jackson, and many others. Perhaps the most powerful argument against
eliminativism is that experience itself is many things simultaneously;
it is, as Aristotle points out, immediate and hence is not composed of
judgements.
## Mysterianism
New Mysterianism is a philosophy proposing that certain problems (in
particular, consciousness) will never be explained.
Owen Flanagan noted in his 1991 book \"Science of the Mind\" that some
modern thinkers have suggested that consciousness might never be
completely explained. Flanagan called them \"the new mysterians\" after
the rock group ? and the Mysterians. The term originated with the
Japanese alien-invasion film The Mysterians. The \"old mysterians\" are
thinkers throughout history who have put forward a similar position.
They include Leibniz, Dr Johnson, and Thomas Huxley. The latter said,
\"How is it that anything so remarkable as a state of consciousness
comes about as a result of irritating nervous tissue, is just as
unaccountable as the appearance of the Djin, when Aladdin rubbed his
lamp.\" \[6, p. 229, quote\]
Noam Chomsky distinguishes between problems, which seem solvable, at
least in principle, through scientific methods, and mysteries which do
not, even in principle. He notes that the cognitive capabilities of all
organisms are limited by biology, e.g. a mouse will never speak. In the
same way, certain problems may be beyond our understanding.
The term New Mysterianism has been extended by some writers to encompass
the wider philosophical position that humans don\'t have the
intellectual ability to understand many hard problems, not just the
problem of consciousness, at a scientific level. This position is also
known as Anti-Constructive Naturalism.
For example, in the mind-body problem, emergent materialism claims that
humans aren\'t smart enough to determine \"the relationship between mind
and matter.\" \[4\] Strong agnosticism is a religious application of
this position.
Colin McGinn is the leading proponent of the New Mysterian position.
Critics argue this philosophy isn\'t useful and encourages capitulation.
One critic noted:
the extreme \"Mysterian\" position, that there are vital issues forever
beyond our reach, is in many ways deeply unsatisfying. \[7\]
References
\[1\] McGinn, Colin - The Problem of Consciousness
\[2\] McGinn, Colin - Problems in Philosophy: the limits of enquiry
\[3\] McGinn, Colin - The Mysterious Flame
\[4\] Blackburn, Simon - Think: A compelling introduction to philosophy,
chapter two
\[5\] Flanagan, Owen - The Science of the Mind (1991) 2ed MIT Press,
Cambridge
\[6\] Horgan, John - The Undiscovered Mind (1999), Phoenix,
## Idealism and panpsychism
### Idealism
|
# Consciousness Studies/Contemporary Explanations#Eliminativism
*This section is about the types of theory that have been advanced to
explain consciousness. Specific explanations should be entered as
separate pages.*
## Introduction
Explanations of consciousness fall into three broad categories, those
that attempt to explain the empirical experience called consciousness
with scientific theories, those that seek to find some way in which
consciousness could be explained by digital computers or nineteenth
century materialism by redefining or eliminating experience and those
that regard consciousness as inexplicable or supernatural.
## Identity theory of mind
The identity theory of mind, or type physicalism, holds that the mind is
identical to the brain. Type physicalists identify qualia and the form
of experience with brain activity. They argue that \"mind states\" have
physical causes and physical effects - thus the mind states themselves
must be physical; a non-physical \"middle step\" is superfluous.
Type physicalism has not yet gained widespread support because although
brain activity that correlates with experience has been found everywhere
in the brain, no set of brain activity that is phenomenal consciousness
itself has yet been found - although this is not surprising because
neuronal spike activity is unlikely to host phenomenal consciousness -
see scientific theories of
consciousness.
## Functionalism
Functionalism was developed as a theory of the mind-body problem because
of objections to identity theory and logical behaviourism. Its core idea
is that the mental states can be accounted for without taking into
account the underlying physical medium (the neurons), instead attending
to higher-level functions such as beliefs, desires, and emotions. It is
a theory of behaviour and access consciousness and so from the outset
avoids any explanation of phenomenal consciousness, substituting beliefs
and judgements (functions) for entities such as qualia.
According to functionalism, the mental states that make up consciousness
can essentially be defined as complex interactions between different
functional processes. Because these processes are not limited to a
particular physical state or physical medium, they can be realized in
multiple ways, including, theoretically, within non-biological
systems.This affords consciousness the opportunity to exist in non-human
minds that are based on algorithmic processors such as digital
computers. This is a highly contentious conjecture although
non-functionalist physicalists might agree that machines that are not
digital computers could possess consciousness through an identity theory
of mind - see The problem of machine and digital
consciousness.
Functionalism\'s explanation of consciousness, or the mental, is best
understood when considering the analogy made by functionalists between
the mind and the modern digital computer. More specifically, the analogy
is made to a \"machine\" capable of computing any given algorithm (i.e.
a Turing machine). This machine would involve:
Data input (the senses in humans), data output (both behaviour and
memory), functional states (mental states), the ability to move from one
functional state into another, and the definition of functional states
with reference to the part they play in the operation of the entire
entity - i.e. in reference to the other functional states. So long as
the same process was achieved, the \"physical stuff\" \-- that being
computer hardware or biological structure \-- could achieve
consciousness.
This variety of functionalism was developed by Hilary Putnam. One of the
major proponents of functionalism is Jerry Fodor.
Further reading:
Block, N. (1996). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Supplement, Macmillan,
1996
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/functionalism.pdf>
## Dualism
### Substance dualism
This theory proposes that phenomenal experience occurs in a non-physical
place. In Cartesian Dualism the non-physical place is an unextended soul
that looks out at the brain. In Reid\'s Natural Dualism the non-physical
place is a point-soul that looks out at the world.
### Property dualism
Property dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the
appropriate way (i.e., organized in the way that living human bodies are
organized), mental properties emerge. Property dualism is a branch of
emergent materialism. The appeal to emergentism deserves closer
attention. Scientific theories often deal with emergent phenomena, for
instance an enzyme consists of carbon, hydrogen, nitrogen, manganese and
oxygen and from this catalytic action emerges. The theory of enzyme
structure and the action of this structure on the substrate explains how
this emergence occurs. Notice that the theory of enzymes explains the
emergence of catalytic activity; emergence does not explain the theory.
In science the statement that some property will \'emerge\' means that
there will be a theory that accounts for this property. Property
dualism, by appealing to emergence, is stating that some theory of
consciousness will be possible. In other words it is an explanation that
proposes that the explanation is yet to be known.
## Intentionalism
## Higher order thought
*This section is a stub and needs expansion*
## Eliminativism
Eliminative materialism is the school of thought that argues for an
absolute version of materialism with respect to mental entities and
mental vocabulary. It principally argues that our common-sense
understanding of the mind (often called \'folk psychology\') is not a
viable theory on which to base scientific investigation, and therefore
no coherent neural basis will be found for many such everyday
psychological concepts (such as belief or intention) and that behaviour
and experience can only be adequately explained on the biological level.
Eliminative materialists therefore believe that consciousness does not
exist and that the concept will eventually be eliminated as neuroscience
progresses. Similarly, they argue that folk psychological concepts such
as belief, desire and intention do not have any consistent neurological
substrate.
Proponents of this view often make parallels to previous scientific
theories which have been eliminated, such as the four humours theory of
medicine, the phlogiston theory of combustion and \'vital force\' theory
of life. In these cases, science has not produced more detailed versions
of these theories, but rejected them as obsolete. Eliminative
materialists argue that folk psychology is headed the same way.
According to W.V. Quine it will take tens of years before folk
psychology will be replaced with real science. (see Phenomenal
consciousness and access
consciousness).
Eliminative materialism was first defended by W.V. Quine, Paul
Feyerabend, and Richard Rorty. This view is most associated with
philosophers Paul and Patricia Churchland although philosophers such as
Daniel Dennett would also consider themselves eliminativists for many
aspects of psychology. Philosopher Dale Jacquette has claimed that
Occam\'s Razor is the rationale behind eliminativism and reductionism.
The most common argument against eliminative materialism is the argument
from qualia, which is deployed in various forms by Thomas Nagel, Frank
Jackson, and many others. Perhaps the most powerful argument against
eliminativism is that experience itself is many things simultaneously;
it is, as Aristotle points out, immediate and hence is not composed of
judgements.
## Mysterianism
New Mysterianism is a philosophy proposing that certain problems (in
particular, consciousness) will never be explained.
Owen Flanagan noted in his 1991 book \"Science of the Mind\" that some
modern thinkers have suggested that consciousness might never be
completely explained. Flanagan called them \"the new mysterians\" after
the rock group ? and the Mysterians. The term originated with the
Japanese alien-invasion film The Mysterians. The \"old mysterians\" are
thinkers throughout history who have put forward a similar position.
They include Leibniz, Dr Johnson, and Thomas Huxley. The latter said,
\"How is it that anything so remarkable as a state of consciousness
comes about as a result of irritating nervous tissue, is just as
unaccountable as the appearance of the Djin, when Aladdin rubbed his
lamp.\" \[6, p. 229, quote\]
Noam Chomsky distinguishes between problems, which seem solvable, at
least in principle, through scientific methods, and mysteries which do
not, even in principle. He notes that the cognitive capabilities of all
organisms are limited by biology, e.g. a mouse will never speak. In the
same way, certain problems may be beyond our understanding.
The term New Mysterianism has been extended by some writers to encompass
the wider philosophical position that humans don\'t have the
intellectual ability to understand many hard problems, not just the
problem of consciousness, at a scientific level. This position is also
known as Anti-Constructive Naturalism.
For example, in the mind-body problem, emergent materialism claims that
humans aren\'t smart enough to determine \"the relationship between mind
and matter.\" \[4\] Strong agnosticism is a religious application of
this position.
Colin McGinn is the leading proponent of the New Mysterian position.
Critics argue this philosophy isn\'t useful and encourages capitulation.
One critic noted:
the extreme \"Mysterian\" position, that there are vital issues forever
beyond our reach, is in many ways deeply unsatisfying. \[7\]
References
\[1\] McGinn, Colin - The Problem of Consciousness
\[2\] McGinn, Colin - Problems in Philosophy: the limits of enquiry
\[3\] McGinn, Colin - The Mysterious Flame
\[4\] Blackburn, Simon - Think: A compelling introduction to philosophy,
chapter two
\[5\] Flanagan, Owen - The Science of the Mind (1991) 2ed MIT Press,
Cambridge
\[6\] Horgan, John - The Undiscovered Mind (1999), Phoenix,
## Idealism and panpsychism
### Idealism
|
# Consciousness Studies/Contemporary Explanations#Mysterianism
*This section is about the types of theory that have been advanced to
explain consciousness. Specific explanations should be entered as
separate pages.*
## Introduction
Explanations of consciousness fall into three broad categories, those
that attempt to explain the empirical experience called consciousness
with scientific theories, those that seek to find some way in which
consciousness could be explained by digital computers or nineteenth
century materialism by redefining or eliminating experience and those
that regard consciousness as inexplicable or supernatural.
## Identity theory of mind
The identity theory of mind, or type physicalism, holds that the mind is
identical to the brain. Type physicalists identify qualia and the form
of experience with brain activity. They argue that \"mind states\" have
physical causes and physical effects - thus the mind states themselves
must be physical; a non-physical \"middle step\" is superfluous.
Type physicalism has not yet gained widespread support because although
brain activity that correlates with experience has been found everywhere
in the brain, no set of brain activity that is phenomenal consciousness
itself has yet been found - although this is not surprising because
neuronal spike activity is unlikely to host phenomenal consciousness -
see scientific theories of
consciousness.
## Functionalism
Functionalism was developed as a theory of the mind-body problem because
of objections to identity theory and logical behaviourism. Its core idea
is that the mental states can be accounted for without taking into
account the underlying physical medium (the neurons), instead attending
to higher-level functions such as beliefs, desires, and emotions. It is
a theory of behaviour and access consciousness and so from the outset
avoids any explanation of phenomenal consciousness, substituting beliefs
and judgements (functions) for entities such as qualia.
According to functionalism, the mental states that make up consciousness
can essentially be defined as complex interactions between different
functional processes. Because these processes are not limited to a
particular physical state or physical medium, they can be realized in
multiple ways, including, theoretically, within non-biological
systems.This affords consciousness the opportunity to exist in non-human
minds that are based on algorithmic processors such as digital
computers. This is a highly contentious conjecture although
non-functionalist physicalists might agree that machines that are not
digital computers could possess consciousness through an identity theory
of mind - see The problem of machine and digital
consciousness.
Functionalism\'s explanation of consciousness, or the mental, is best
understood when considering the analogy made by functionalists between
the mind and the modern digital computer. More specifically, the analogy
is made to a \"machine\" capable of computing any given algorithm (i.e.
a Turing machine). This machine would involve:
Data input (the senses in humans), data output (both behaviour and
memory), functional states (mental states), the ability to move from one
functional state into another, and the definition of functional states
with reference to the part they play in the operation of the entire
entity - i.e. in reference to the other functional states. So long as
the same process was achieved, the \"physical stuff\" \-- that being
computer hardware or biological structure \-- could achieve
consciousness.
This variety of functionalism was developed by Hilary Putnam. One of the
major proponents of functionalism is Jerry Fodor.
Further reading:
Block, N. (1996). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Supplement, Macmillan,
1996
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/functionalism.pdf>
## Dualism
### Substance dualism
This theory proposes that phenomenal experience occurs in a non-physical
place. In Cartesian Dualism the non-physical place is an unextended soul
that looks out at the brain. In Reid\'s Natural Dualism the non-physical
place is a point-soul that looks out at the world.
### Property dualism
Property dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the
appropriate way (i.e., organized in the way that living human bodies are
organized), mental properties emerge. Property dualism is a branch of
emergent materialism. The appeal to emergentism deserves closer
attention. Scientific theories often deal with emergent phenomena, for
instance an enzyme consists of carbon, hydrogen, nitrogen, manganese and
oxygen and from this catalytic action emerges. The theory of enzyme
structure and the action of this structure on the substrate explains how
this emergence occurs. Notice that the theory of enzymes explains the
emergence of catalytic activity; emergence does not explain the theory.
In science the statement that some property will \'emerge\' means that
there will be a theory that accounts for this property. Property
dualism, by appealing to emergence, is stating that some theory of
consciousness will be possible. In other words it is an explanation that
proposes that the explanation is yet to be known.
## Intentionalism
## Higher order thought
*This section is a stub and needs expansion*
## Eliminativism
Eliminative materialism is the school of thought that argues for an
absolute version of materialism with respect to mental entities and
mental vocabulary. It principally argues that our common-sense
understanding of the mind (often called \'folk psychology\') is not a
viable theory on which to base scientific investigation, and therefore
no coherent neural basis will be found for many such everyday
psychological concepts (such as belief or intention) and that behaviour
and experience can only be adequately explained on the biological level.
Eliminative materialists therefore believe that consciousness does not
exist and that the concept will eventually be eliminated as neuroscience
progresses. Similarly, they argue that folk psychological concepts such
as belief, desire and intention do not have any consistent neurological
substrate.
Proponents of this view often make parallels to previous scientific
theories which have been eliminated, such as the four humours theory of
medicine, the phlogiston theory of combustion and \'vital force\' theory
of life. In these cases, science has not produced more detailed versions
of these theories, but rejected them as obsolete. Eliminative
materialists argue that folk psychology is headed the same way.
According to W.V. Quine it will take tens of years before folk
psychology will be replaced with real science. (see Phenomenal
consciousness and access
consciousness).
Eliminative materialism was first defended by W.V. Quine, Paul
Feyerabend, and Richard Rorty. This view is most associated with
philosophers Paul and Patricia Churchland although philosophers such as
Daniel Dennett would also consider themselves eliminativists for many
aspects of psychology. Philosopher Dale Jacquette has claimed that
Occam\'s Razor is the rationale behind eliminativism and reductionism.
The most common argument against eliminative materialism is the argument
from qualia, which is deployed in various forms by Thomas Nagel, Frank
Jackson, and many others. Perhaps the most powerful argument against
eliminativism is that experience itself is many things simultaneously;
it is, as Aristotle points out, immediate and hence is not composed of
judgements.
## Mysterianism
New Mysterianism is a philosophy proposing that certain problems (in
particular, consciousness) will never be explained.
Owen Flanagan noted in his 1991 book \"Science of the Mind\" that some
modern thinkers have suggested that consciousness might never be
completely explained. Flanagan called them \"the new mysterians\" after
the rock group ? and the Mysterians. The term originated with the
Japanese alien-invasion film The Mysterians. The \"old mysterians\" are
thinkers throughout history who have put forward a similar position.
They include Leibniz, Dr Johnson, and Thomas Huxley. The latter said,
\"How is it that anything so remarkable as a state of consciousness
comes about as a result of irritating nervous tissue, is just as
unaccountable as the appearance of the Djin, when Aladdin rubbed his
lamp.\" \[6, p. 229, quote\]
Noam Chomsky distinguishes between problems, which seem solvable, at
least in principle, through scientific methods, and mysteries which do
not, even in principle. He notes that the cognitive capabilities of all
organisms are limited by biology, e.g. a mouse will never speak. In the
same way, certain problems may be beyond our understanding.
The term New Mysterianism has been extended by some writers to encompass
the wider philosophical position that humans don\'t have the
intellectual ability to understand many hard problems, not just the
problem of consciousness, at a scientific level. This position is also
known as Anti-Constructive Naturalism.
For example, in the mind-body problem, emergent materialism claims that
humans aren\'t smart enough to determine \"the relationship between mind
and matter.\" \[4\] Strong agnosticism is a religious application of
this position.
Colin McGinn is the leading proponent of the New Mysterian position.
Critics argue this philosophy isn\'t useful and encourages capitulation.
One critic noted:
the extreme \"Mysterian\" position, that there are vital issues forever
beyond our reach, is in many ways deeply unsatisfying. \[7\]
References
\[1\] McGinn, Colin - The Problem of Consciousness
\[2\] McGinn, Colin - Problems in Philosophy: the limits of enquiry
\[3\] McGinn, Colin - The Mysterious Flame
\[4\] Blackburn, Simon - Think: A compelling introduction to philosophy,
chapter two
\[5\] Flanagan, Owen - The Science of the Mind (1991) 2ed MIT Press,
Cambridge
\[6\] Horgan, John - The Undiscovered Mind (1999), Phoenix,
## Idealism and panpsychism
### Idealism
|
# Consciousness Studies/Contemporary Explanations#Idealism and panpsychism
*This section is about the types of theory that have been advanced to
explain consciousness. Specific explanations should be entered as
separate pages.*
## Introduction
Explanations of consciousness fall into three broad categories, those
that attempt to explain the empirical experience called consciousness
with scientific theories, those that seek to find some way in which
consciousness could be explained by digital computers or nineteenth
century materialism by redefining or eliminating experience and those
that regard consciousness as inexplicable or supernatural.
## Identity theory of mind
The identity theory of mind, or type physicalism, holds that the mind is
identical to the brain. Type physicalists identify qualia and the form
of experience with brain activity. They argue that \"mind states\" have
physical causes and physical effects - thus the mind states themselves
must be physical; a non-physical \"middle step\" is superfluous.
Type physicalism has not yet gained widespread support because although
brain activity that correlates with experience has been found everywhere
in the brain, no set of brain activity that is phenomenal consciousness
itself has yet been found - although this is not surprising because
neuronal spike activity is unlikely to host phenomenal consciousness -
see scientific theories of
consciousness.
## Functionalism
Functionalism was developed as a theory of the mind-body problem because
of objections to identity theory and logical behaviourism. Its core idea
is that the mental states can be accounted for without taking into
account the underlying physical medium (the neurons), instead attending
to higher-level functions such as beliefs, desires, and emotions. It is
a theory of behaviour and access consciousness and so from the outset
avoids any explanation of phenomenal consciousness, substituting beliefs
and judgements (functions) for entities such as qualia.
According to functionalism, the mental states that make up consciousness
can essentially be defined as complex interactions between different
functional processes. Because these processes are not limited to a
particular physical state or physical medium, they can be realized in
multiple ways, including, theoretically, within non-biological
systems.This affords consciousness the opportunity to exist in non-human
minds that are based on algorithmic processors such as digital
computers. This is a highly contentious conjecture although
non-functionalist physicalists might agree that machines that are not
digital computers could possess consciousness through an identity theory
of mind - see The problem of machine and digital
consciousness.
Functionalism\'s explanation of consciousness, or the mental, is best
understood when considering the analogy made by functionalists between
the mind and the modern digital computer. More specifically, the analogy
is made to a \"machine\" capable of computing any given algorithm (i.e.
a Turing machine). This machine would involve:
Data input (the senses in humans), data output (both behaviour and
memory), functional states (mental states), the ability to move from one
functional state into another, and the definition of functional states
with reference to the part they play in the operation of the entire
entity - i.e. in reference to the other functional states. So long as
the same process was achieved, the \"physical stuff\" \-- that being
computer hardware or biological structure \-- could achieve
consciousness.
This variety of functionalism was developed by Hilary Putnam. One of the
major proponents of functionalism is Jerry Fodor.
Further reading:
Block, N. (1996). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Supplement, Macmillan,
1996
<http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/functionalism.pdf>
## Dualism
### Substance dualism
This theory proposes that phenomenal experience occurs in a non-physical
place. In Cartesian Dualism the non-physical place is an unextended soul
that looks out at the brain. In Reid\'s Natural Dualism the non-physical
place is a point-soul that looks out at the world.
### Property dualism
Property dualism asserts that when matter is organized in the
appropriate way (i.e., organized in the way that living human bodies are
organized), mental properties emerge. Property dualism is a branch of
emergent materialism. The appeal to emergentism deserves closer
attention. Scientific theories often deal with emergent phenomena, for
instance an enzyme consists of carbon, hydrogen, nitrogen, manganese and
oxygen and from this catalytic action emerges. The theory of enzyme
structure and the action of this structure on the substrate explains how
this emergence occurs. Notice that the theory of enzymes explains the
emergence of catalytic activity; emergence does not explain the theory.
In science the statement that some property will \'emerge\' means that
there will be a theory that accounts for this property. Property
dualism, by appealing to emergence, is stating that some theory of
consciousness will be possible. In other words it is an explanation that
proposes that the explanation is yet to be known.
## Intentionalism
## Higher order thought
*This section is a stub and needs expansion*
## Eliminativism
Eliminative materialism is the school of thought that argues for an
absolute version of materialism with respect to mental entities and
mental vocabulary. It principally argues that our common-sense
understanding of the mind (often called \'folk psychology\') is not a
viable theory on which to base scientific investigation, and therefore
no coherent neural basis will be found for many such everyday
psychological concepts (such as belief or intention) and that behaviour
and experience can only be adequately explained on the biological level.
Eliminative materialists therefore believe that consciousness does not
exist and that the concept will eventually be eliminated as neuroscience
progresses. Similarly, they argue that folk psychological concepts such
as belief, desire and intention do not have any consistent neurological
substrate.
Proponents of this view often make parallels to previous scientific
theories which have been eliminated, such as the four humours theory of
medicine, the phlogiston theory of combustion and \'vital force\' theory
of life. In these cases, science has not produced more detailed versions
of these theories, but rejected them as obsolete. Eliminative
materialists argue that folk psychology is headed the same way.
According to W.V. Quine it will take tens of years before folk
psychology will be replaced with real science. (see Phenomenal
consciousness and access
consciousness).
Eliminative materialism was first defended by W.V. Quine, Paul
Feyerabend, and Richard Rorty. This view is most associated with
philosophers Paul and Patricia Churchland although philosophers such as
Daniel Dennett would also consider themselves eliminativists for many
aspects of psychology. Philosopher Dale Jacquette has claimed that
Occam\'s Razor is the rationale behind eliminativism and reductionism.
The most common argument against eliminative materialism is the argument
from qualia, which is deployed in various forms by Thomas Nagel, Frank
Jackson, and many others. Perhaps the most powerful argument against
eliminativism is that experience itself is many things simultaneously;
it is, as Aristotle points out, immediate and hence is not composed of
judgements.
## Mysterianism
New Mysterianism is a philosophy proposing that certain problems (in
particular, consciousness) will never be explained.
Owen Flanagan noted in his 1991 book \"Science of the Mind\" that some
modern thinkers have suggested that consciousness might never be
completely explained. Flanagan called them \"the new mysterians\" after
the rock group ? and the Mysterians. The term originated with the
Japanese alien-invasion film The Mysterians. The \"old mysterians\" are
thinkers throughout history who have put forward a similar position.
They include Leibniz, Dr Johnson, and Thomas Huxley. The latter said,
\"How is it that anything so remarkable as a state of consciousness
comes about as a result of irritating nervous tissue, is just as
unaccountable as the appearance of the Djin, when Aladdin rubbed his
lamp.\" \[6, p. 229, quote\]
Noam Chomsky distinguishes between problems, which seem solvable, at
least in principle, through scientific methods, and mysteries which do
not, even in principle. He notes that the cognitive capabilities of all
organisms are limited by biology, e.g. a mouse will never speak. In the
same way, certain problems may be beyond our understanding.
The term New Mysterianism has been extended by some writers to encompass
the wider philosophical position that humans don\'t have the
intellectual ability to understand many hard problems, not just the
problem of consciousness, at a scientific level. This position is also
known as Anti-Constructive Naturalism.
For example, in the mind-body problem, emergent materialism claims that
humans aren\'t smart enough to determine \"the relationship between mind
and matter.\" \[4\] Strong agnosticism is a religious application of
this position.
Colin McGinn is the leading proponent of the New Mysterian position.
Critics argue this philosophy isn\'t useful and encourages capitulation.
One critic noted:
the extreme \"Mysterian\" position, that there are vital issues forever
beyond our reach, is in many ways deeply unsatisfying. \[7\]
References
\[1\] McGinn, Colin - The Problem of Consciousness
\[2\] McGinn, Colin - Problems in Philosophy: the limits of enquiry
\[3\] McGinn, Colin - The Mysterious Flame
\[4\] Blackburn, Simon - Think: A compelling introduction to philosophy,
chapter two
\[5\] Flanagan, Owen - The Science of the Mind (1991) 2ed MIT Press,
Cambridge
\[6\] Horgan, John - The Undiscovered Mind (1999), Phoenix,
## Idealism and panpsychism
### Idealism
|
# Consciousness Studies/Other Explanations
Consciousness-only is the foundation of a buddhist theory known as
vijnanavada. Proponents, notably the Yogacara school, suggest that the
sum of experience exists only in our minds. Philosophers recognition of
this view as subjective idealism is a matter of discussion because these
traditions often deny the existence of ontological subject. These views
are rooted in the denial of existence of any kind of ontological
substance (as Matter, Soul, God, etc.). Consciousness-only views can
also be found in taoist philosophy, notably Lao Tzu and Chuang Tzu.
|
# Consciousness Studies/Other Explanations#Consciousness-only
Consciousness-only is the foundation of a buddhist theory known as
vijnanavada. Proponents, notably the Yogacara school, suggest that the
sum of experience exists only in our minds. Philosophers recognition of
this view as subjective idealism is a matter of discussion because these
traditions often deny the existence of ontological subject. These views
are rooted in the denial of existence of any kind of ontological
substance (as Matter, Soul, God, etc.). Consciousness-only views can
also be found in taoist philosophy, notably Lao Tzu and Chuang Tzu.
|
# Consciousness Studies/BioPsychoSociology
This brief summary is an illustration of an attempt to model a
multidisciplinary biopsychosocial (bps) understanding of
self-consciousness seen from the perspective of both scientific
methodology and metaphysical logic where the empirical and the
inferential provide a seamless blend of the ontological brain with the
epistemological mind.
The achievement of self consciousness is the crucial mental state
allowing the human species to monitor the equilibrium state of
biopsychosocial ongoing contingencies especially when confronting
life-threatening circumstances. The inherited proto-semantics and
acquired language guide the required recursive co-generation of the
appropriate language and thought to meet the contingency. Thus informed,
it allows humans to elaborate effective adaptive short and long range
responses.
## Definition of terms
Bps model uses some unusual definitions of terms. These are explained
below.
\"Sense-phenomenal awareness\" is defined as an unconscious,
life-preserving, adaptive reflex response which may occur without
qualia. It originates at a sensory receptor, wherever located in the
body economy, and ends at an effector organ, glandular or muscular. -
Phenomenal consciousness/awareness is a term normally reserved for
experience containing qualia in other analyses.
System/network \"awareness\" is defined in the bps model as that
unconscious processing occurring during the integration of the
participating neural network modules leading to a stereotyped adaptive
response. - normally awareness is defined as knowledge that a conscious
state is present.
Sense-phenomenal awareness may become a conscious experience when
relevant inferential networks (e.g., memory, emotions, etc.)are
subsequently accessed, including inner-language processors. When
experiences are recalled the qualia that arise are called \"conceptual
qualia\".
\"Access consciousness\" is described as being initially an unconscious
process that makes it possible for a life-preserving, reflex-driven and
\'unconscious\' sense-phenomenal state of mind to become conscious by
making use of available, pertinent and concurrent mental states to
interact with the novel sense-phenomenal input, a potentially
life-threatening event.
\"Proto-linguistic organ\" or \'plo\' is described as the first line of
defense to guard against life-threatening stimuli arising from
sense-phenomenal inputs (external, visceral or proprioceptive). Housed
in the amygdaloidal complex, it represents the inherited proto-semantic
(primitive \'meanings\') database responsible for activating the
corresponding unconscious fight/flight adaptive Cannon effector
response.
\"Proto-semantic\" input from plo is described as a required initial
participant in the subsequent recursive co-generation of inner language
and thought as may be required in the eventual elaboration of
\"conceptual consciousness\".
## Higher order consciousness theory
The \'bps\' model of \'consciousness\' is a high order consciousness
theory in which an unconscious, non inferential phenomenal state
(established from either online sensory receptor input or offline memory
input), when confronting a novel life-threatening event, triggers an
initially unconscious access intermediate stage where relevant modular
networks are incorporated including Broca\'s language processor
recursively co-generating in the process the \'inner language\'
narrative state and accompanying thought, a conscious high order mental
state, all of which causally precedes (or is simultaneous with) the
adaptive response (if any, as we see in dreams).
Notice that bps considers phenomenal states to be non-conscious, this
would confuse the ordinary reader who expects the Kantian term
\"phenomenal\" to be equivalent to the term \"conscious experience\".
Only the higher order mental state is regarded as \"conscious\".
The \'bps\' model basically describes two co-existing, ongoing mental
states, one non-inferential subconscious \'gut feeling\' inner sense
(BOP, a variant of Lycan\'s 1996 HOP) and an initially non-inferential
unconscious accessing of narrative pathways leading to (recursive
co-generation of \'inner language\' and thought is an open option) the
eventual production of higher order thought (HOT) whose content is the
feeling that oneself is the subject of self-consciousness.
In other words, according to the \'bps\' theory, feelings are not part
of consciousness until higher order thought occurs, i.e., qualia needs a
context.
In \'bps\' theory not even self-consciousness, of which \'qualia\' may
arguably be considered a subset of, has revealed its constitutive
secrets. This means that bps is a theory of brain processing rather than
a theory of the content of consciousness (qualia) or consciousness
itself except when it ventures into the postulate that language and
self-consciousness are recursively co-generated or co-causal. More
controversial is the mediation of the amygdaloid complex (plo) in
providing inherited primitive \'meanings\' (protosemantic codelets) to
initiate Chomskian language processing and thought co-generation, i.e.,
protosemantics precedes syntax structuring. For a more complete
exposition see:
Further Reading: <http://delaSierra-Sheffer.net> For a quantum field
perspective see also: <http://www.biopsychosociology.org>
<http://spaces.msn.com/angelldls/>
|
# Miskito/Introduction
## Welcome to *Miskitu Aisas!*
!Flag of the Miskito
Nation{width="250"}
*Miskitu Aisas!* (\"Speak Miskito!\"), a language course in Wikibooks,
is an elementary introduction to the Miskito language, spoken in parts
of Nicaragua and Honduras. The course focuses primarily on presenting
the grammar basics through carefully graded and didactically presented
lessons. *Miskitu Aisas!* assumes no prior knowledge of the language and
no specialised knowledge of linguistics, although at least a general
background in \"school grammar\" will no doubt be helpful, as will any
previous experience at learning foreign languages.
As well as an understanding of the language\'s overall structure,
*Miskitu Aisas!* will also provide you with a knowledge of some basic
vocabulary, and will give you the essential preparation needed to
continue studying Miskito by other means, if you should wish to do so. A
variety of exercises at every step in the learning path will help you
gradually to assimilate both grammar and vocabulary, and to check your
progress through comparison of the answers provided. A handy feature
that makes this on-line course more interactive is found in the
Show/Hide toggle switches that accompany model sentences, exercises and
vocabularies. These allow you to customise each page and adapt it to
your progress and learning pace by either displaying or concealing
translations, answers and meanings.
In the rest of this introduction you can read about who the Miskito
people are and what their language is, and how to use this course, as
well as quick links to some key pages in the course.
## The Miskito people and their language
!Location of Central America and the
Caribbean{width="250"}
!Map of Central America and the
Caribbean{width="220"}
The Miskito people inhabit an area along the Caribbean (Atlantic) coast
of Central America. This area, known as the Mosquito Coast, is mostly
within the state of Nicaragua, with a northern section in a neighbouring
region of Honduras. The territory extends from Cape Cameron in the north
to Río Grande in the south. In origin the Miskitos were a local
indigenous people, but in the post-colonial era a great deal of racial
mixing occurred. A major component of the present population is
descended from escaped slaves from other areas who sought refuge among
the Miskito people.
Because of the inaccessibility of the Miskitos\' territory, Spanish
settlers did not begin to arrive until 1787 and even after this the
Miskitos, who already had an experienced army and an established
political structure, continued to dominate the land, which consequently
suffered only limited influence from the Spanish conquest. The Miskitos
remained independent until 1894 when their land became part of
Nicaragua, but the Nicaraguans, like the Spanish before them, exercised
little control and many Miskitos, even today, do not consider themselves
Nicaraguan. !Former British
Protectorate{width="415"
height="415"} On the other hand, the Miskito people entered into contact
with British colonists as early as the beginning of the seventeenth
century, and during the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries they
continued to be influenced by the British, who had economic interests in
the area, particularly in the territory of Belize to the northwest (the
colonial name for which was British Honduras). As allies of the British
the Miskitos were sucked into the slave trade, often being involved in
raids against Spanish settlements in Honduras. Such activities brought
the Miskitos into contact with other indigenous groups, to whom the
Miskitos tended to consider themselves culturally superior. The Miskitos
were ruled by their own kings who took on English names (the earliest
recorded king, named Oldman, received an audience with king Charles I),
and emulated European dress. Following a formal Treaty of Friendship and
Alliance between the Miskitos and Britain in 1740, the Miskito Nation
was formally a British protectorate until 1787, and British interest in
the region continued until the mid-nineteenth century.
In addition to the Miskitos\' native language, Miskito, large numbers of
Miskitos speak other languages, particularly Miskito Creole English
(which arose through contact with the British), neighbouring indigenous
languages such as Rama, and Spanish.
```{=html}
<table cellspacing=0 cellpadding=6 style="background:#ecf3f7; float:left; width:331px; margin:2px; clear:both;">
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td width=28% bgcolor="#ffffff">
```
`<big>`{=html}`<b>`{=html}Miskito word:`</b>`{=html}`</big>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td width=40% bgcolor="#ffffff">
```
`<big>`{=html}`<b>`{=html}Meaning:`</b>`{=html}`</big>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td bgcolor="#ffffff">
```
`<b>`{=html}English source:`</b>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**buk**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*book*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}book`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**dur**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*door*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}door`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**hilp**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*help*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}help`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**kî**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*key*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}key`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**laik**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*like*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}like`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**lalah**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*money*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}dollar`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**lan**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*learn*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}learn`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**nu**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*know*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}know`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**pain**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*well*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}fine`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**prias**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*religious observance*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}prayers`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**sap**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*shop, store*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}shop`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**skul**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*school*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}school`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**tibil**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*table*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}table`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**truk**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*car, vehicle*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}truck`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**want**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*want*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}want`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**wark**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*work*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}work`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</tr>
```
```{=html}
<tr>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
**windar**
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
*window*
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
<td>
```
`<small>`{=html}window`</small>`{=html}
```{=html}
</td>
```
```{=html}
</table>
```
With nearly 200,000 speakers, Miskito is the most widely spoken of a
family of languages of Nicaragua and Honduras that has come to be known
as Misumalpan. This name is formed from parts of the names of the
family\'s subgroups: MIskito, SUmo, MAtagaLPAN. Although some aspects of
the internal family tree within this family are uncertain, it is clear
that Miskito stands apart from Sumo and Matagalpan, which seem to share
a common lower node, and that in the past Miskito was heavily influenced
by other Misumalpan languages. Sumo is thought to have been dominant in
the area before the period of Miskito ascendancy. Today the relationship
has been reversed: many former Sumo speakers have shifted to Miskito,
which has in turn heavily influenced the Sumo dialects. Several of these
(Tawahka, Panamahka and Tuahka) constitute the Mayangna sub-branch of
Sumo, while the Ulwa language is in another sub-branch. The Matagalpan
branch of Misumalpan contains two languages that are now extinct:
Matagalpa and Cacaopera. The latter was formerly spoken in parts of
eastern El Salvador.
In addition to many elements borrowed from other Misumalpan languages,
Miskito has a large number of loanwords from English via Creole, such as
those in the table on the left. All the above words occur in the first
ten lessons of *Miskitu Aisas!* Notice how their sounds are adapted to
the Miskito language, which only has three vowels: *a, i, u*.
Even though Spanish is the official language of Nicaragua and Honduras,
its influence on Miskito is much more recent and hence more
superficial.\
\
\
\
## How to use the course
### Contents and navigation
There are basically two ways to move around inside this course: (1) use
the Table of Contents, or (2) move from page to page using the
navigation links.
#### The table of contents
You can get to the table of contents from the course\'s front page, and
also from any other page in the course through a navigation link (see
below). You can look at the table of contents
right now, if you wish. You are recommended to open it up in a separate
browser window so that you can continue reading this page while you
inspect the table of contents.
Every page that you need to see as part of the course has a link from
the table of contents. Notice how the table of contents page is
organised. On the right-hand side there is a list with a darker
background, with the heading **\"The project\"** at the top. This
section has information about the project of creating this course which
may or may not interest you as a user (rather than an author) of the
course. A little lower down you see another section, **\"Author\'s
workbench\"**, which contains more technical information that is
important for people working on development of the course, but probably
unnecessary for other readers. The rest of the table of contents, with a
paler blue background, includes everything that people using the course
to learn (or learn about) Miskito will need. This is also divided into
several sections which will now be mentioned.
The **\"Getting started\"** section is where you are now, and as well as
this introduction it also includes a guide to pronouncing and spelling
the language. These are the pages you will probably want to have at
least a quick look at before starting on the lessons. You can always
come back to them later on for more detailed study whenever you feel the
need.
Next comes the biggest and most important section, **\"The lessons\"**.
The links to the first ten lessons are placed where you can\'t miss
them: in the middle of the screen, immediately after the \"Getting
started\" section. When you get through those, you can scroll down a
little to see the rest of the lessons currently available.
Near the bottom of the table of contents there are two more sections:
**\"Reference section\"** (with vocabularies, appendices, a list of
abbreviations and a subject index) and **\"More about Miskito\"** (an
external links page and a discussion page).
#### Page-to-page navigation
At the top of every page in the course you will see the flag of the
historical Miskito Nation, which is the logo of the course, together
with the title of the page or lesson. Notice the three links to the left
of the flag logo:
- a \"backwards\" link which will usually take you to the previous
page (assuming you are following the pages of the course in order)
- a \"forwards\" link (marked **\>Next**) which takes you to the next
page in order
- a \"Contents\" link, which takes you back to the table of contents
from any page in the course
You can use these to get around the course. If the \"backwards\" or
\"forwards\" link takes you where you want to go, you are there with one
click. If not, you can go to the table of contents and from there to
wherever you want (two clicks away!).
Notice too that there are some links over the vocabulary lists in each
lesson providing short cuts to the general vocabularies, the list of
abbreviations and the subject index. These will often help you to look
up things that you can\'t remember and are not in the lesson\'s
vocabulary list.
### Structure of the course
If you are a new user of this course, it would be a good idea to open up
**Lesson 1** (or any other lesson, if you
prefer) in a separate browser window so that you can examine it while
reading the following description.
Each lesson consists of several learning points, which form the main
part of the lesson. At the end of the lesson there is a final section
containing a list of the new words in the lesson (the Vocabulary) and a
practice activity (a review exercise or a reading). At the beginning of
the lesson the table of contents lists the learning points.
Each learning point consists of three components: (1) model sentences,
(2) comments and (3) a short practice activity or exercise. Different
people learn in different ways, so it is up to each learner to decide
exactly how to use these. If we think of the comments as \"rules\", then
the model sentences act as \"examples\" to illustrate them. Some people
like to study the examples first and read the rules afterwards. If you
are able to infer the rule from the model sentences, then the comment
will serve to confirm your hypothesis, if it was right, or correct it,
if it wasn\'t. If you follow this procedure, you will probably want to
look at the translations of the model sentences, unless you can guess
them, by clicking on the \"Show\" switch on the right.
If, on the other hand, you prefer to work from rules to examples, then
leave the translations hidden at first. After reading the comments, see
if you can work out what the examples mean before looking up their
meanings. You may like to consult the vocabulary at the end of the
lesson as you do this; it will give you a better chance of getting them
right.
Don\'t skip the practice activity. You can use it to check whether you
understand the point, to test yourself, or to get accustomed to the
mechanisms of the language. The exercises will also help you to acquire
the vocabulary. Always try the exercise with the answers hidden first
before clicking on \"Show\" to see if you were right.
When you come to the vocabulary list, if you have already worked through
the preceding points and gone through the model sentences and exercises
you should already know most of the words on the list by now. In fact,
you can easily give yourself a vocabulary test, since the meaning of
each word will not be visible until you click on the corresponding
\"Show\" button.
The exercise or reading that follows the vocabulary will touch on
several of the points you have studied in the lesson and also reviews
both old and new vocabulary items. Once again, hide or display the
answers as it suits you.
## Where to next?
|
# Japanese/Introduction
Japanese is spoken by 130 million people. This makes it the ninth most
spoken language by
native speakers. Linguists debate over the classification of the
Japanese language, and one general theory asserts that Japanese is an
isolated language and thus a language family of its own, known as
Japonic languages. Another major theory includes Japanese as part of a
hypothetical Altaic language family which spans most of Central Asia and
would also include Turkic, Mongolic, Tungusic, and Korean languages.
Neither of these theories has yet been generally accepted.
Japan is the only country where Japanese is the sole official language
(though the island of Angaur has Japanese as one
of three official languages). There are, however, numerous speakers in
other countries. These are largely due to emigration, most notably to
the United States of America (California and Hawaii, in particular),
Brazil and the Philippines. Furthermore, when Japan occupied and
colonized much of East Asia, Southeast Asia, and the Pacific, the locals
were educated in the Japanese language. Many elderly locals in Korea,
Taiwan, and parts of China still speak Japanese.
Japan has steadily developed for many centuries and, unlike many other
cultures, has not been seriously affected by any major invasions until
recent times. A substantial part of the vocabulary, though, has been
borrowed over the years from Chinese, Portuguese, Dutch, German, French,
and most recently English.
## Grammar
While Japanese grammar is very regular, it is markedly different from
English. Japanese has been deemed a subject--object--verb (SOV) and
topic-prominent language, whereas English is a subject--verb--object
(SVO) and subject-prominent language.
To illustrate, the English sentence "Cats eat mice" contains a subject
(cats), a verb (eat), and an object (mice), in an SVO order, where the
"-s" is a *plural marker*, and "mouse" → "mice" is a plural marker by
ablaut, but only the word order indicates which
is the subject and the object---i.e. which is dining and which is the
meal.
+-------------------+----+---------------------+----+-------------------+
| Japanese culture and society is based on a hierarchy of higher status
(目上 *meue*) and lower status (目下 *meshita*). As such, there are
three varying levels of politeness. Because Japanese is primarily a
\"vertical\" society, all relationships contain an element of relative
station. For example, a student is a lower station than a teacher, and
therefore a student would use polite language when speaking to a
teacher, but the teacher would use plain language when speaking to a
student. A salesperson talking to a customer would place himself/herself
far below the customer, and would therefore use honorific language,
whereas the customer would use either plain or polite language.
Honorific language is not a separate category from plain and polite
language, but a separate concept that uses different rules. When using
honorific language, a Japanese speaker modifies nouns, verbs, and
adjectives to either lower himself/herself and their associates, or
exalt someone else and that individual\'s associates. Whereas the use of
plain or polite language is determined by the relative station of the
person *to* whom you are speaking, the use of honorific language is
determined by the relative station of the person *about* whom you are
speaking. Exalted language is applied when you are speaking about
someone who is due respect, such as a professor, an executive, a
political official, or a customer. Exalted language is only applied to
other people, never to oneself. Humble language, however, is *only*
applied to oneself and people associated with oneself. It would be
inappropriate, for example, to use humble language to describe a beggar,
even though they would be extremely low on the social ladder.
## The Japanese writing system
Japanese is written mostly using three writing scripts, *kanji*,
*hiragana* and *katakana*. Kanji are Chinese characters that were first
introduced to Japan in the 4th century. Unlike Chinese, Japanese is a
highly inflected language with words changing their ending depending on
case, number, etc. For this reason, the hiragana and katakana
syllabaries were created. The hiragana serve largely to show the
inflection of words, as conjunctions and such. The katakana are mainly
used for loan-words from other languages.
### Kanji
The Japanese writing system is derived from the Chinese ideographic
character set (Japanese: 漢字 *kanji*, Mandarin: 汉字 *hanzi*). They are
usually very similar to Traditional Chinese characters. Though kanji are
Chinese in origin their use is dictated by Japanese grammar. Each
character may be read in different ways depending on the context it is
in.
The number of existing Chinese characters has been variously estimated
at between 40,000 and 80,000; however, only a small subset is commonly
used in modern Japanese. An educated Japanese person will generally be
able to read between 2,000 and 4,000 characters. In order to be literate
in the Japanese language, the student should strive to master at least
the 2,136 general-use characters (常用漢字 -- *jōyō
kanji*) established by the Ministry of
Education.
### Hiragana and katakana
The syllabaries, known as *kana* (),
were developed around 900 AD by simplifying kanji to form the *hiragana*
(ひらがな, or 平仮名) and the more angular *katakana* (カタカナ, or
片仮名). Hiragana can be recognized by the characteristic curved shapes,
while katakana are identifiable by their sharp edges and straight lines.
The creation of one of the scripts has been attributed to Kūkai
(774-835, alias Kōbō Daishi) the famous monk who introduced Shingon
Buddhism to Japan.
Hiragana and katakana are almost completely phonetic---much more so than
the English alphabet. Each set, however, is referred to as a *syllabary*
rather than an alphabet because each character represents an entire
syllable with only a single consonant (which is a more recent addition)
(see ../Pronunciation/ for more). The
syllabary charts in Japanese are referred to as the *gojūon*
(), meaning \"fifty sounds\"
because they are written in a five by ten chart. However, there are a
few gaps in the table where certain sounds have fallen out of use.
Modern Japanese can be written using 46 kana.
In practical use, hiragana is used to write, for example,
inflectional endings for adjectives and verbs
(送り仮名 *okurigana*), grammatical particles (助詞 *joshi*) and
auxiliaries (助動詞 *jodōshi*), Japanese words that have no kanji (or
not commonly known kanji), and annotations to kanji to indicate
pronunciation (振り仮名 *furigana*). Katakana is used to write, for
example, foreign words and names,
onomatopoeia, emphasized words (somewhat
like italicized words in English text), and technical and scientific
words, such as plant, animal, and mineral names.
Contents
## References
[^1]: 「食べる」
|
# Japanese/Study methods
As with the study of any subject, you need to have self-discipline. Set
a certain amount of time that will be devoted to the study of Japanese,
and try to make a regular schedule. Don\'t rush yourself and set
yourself achievable goals. The ideal method to study a language is to be
exposed to the native environment with access to native speakers and
have your own personal tutor. These are, however, not necessary and
self-study can be rewarding in itself.
## Setting Goals
Setting goals is vital.
## Kana
If you are serious about learning to read and write Japanese, you must
first master kana (hiragana & katakana). These are the two syllabaries,
and are phonetic just like the English alphabet. Unlike English,
however, Japanese pronunciation is almost perfectly regular, meaning
that for the most part, one symbol stands for one sound, and there are
very few pronunciation rules to learn. As a result, hiragana and
katakana can easily be mastered, though fluency in reading will take
longer.
The kana are few enough that one can learn them by rote. To reach
fluency, one eventually has to drop mnemonic devices anyway. For that
transition period, or even for the few that prove difficult to memorise,
mnemonics can come in handy.
Once you have mastered the kana, you will be able to pronounce all the
kana characters you come across, even if you don\'t know the meaning.
Not to worry, though, once you build up your vocabulary, you\'ll be
amazed how much more you can comprehend.
## Kanji
You should begin to learn kanji immediately, as it is very
time-consuming. The sooner you start, the sooner you will become
proficient.
There are a number of ways to learn the kanji.
- In Japanese skills, they are taught by
**rote.**
- One can learn the **radicals**.
- There are **etymology-based** mnemonics, and
- **pictorial-based** mnemonics.
- Calligraphy (書道 shodō) can be a mnemonic and pleasurable way to
practice kanji.
To learn via *radicals* (the pieces that make them up), you only need to
learn the relatively few components (approximately 200), and pretty soon
you will be able to guess the meaning and pronunciation of a new
character with some accuracy just by looking at it.
Writing kanji is an entirely different business; think of kanji as
something elegant, an art. Calligraphy is commonly studied and a highly
revered art in Japan. Skillfully written characters and proverbs are
often hung on walls or displayed in museums, and sell for as much as
paintings do in the West.
A good strategy to learning all of these characters is to realize that
it isn\'t anything like English, Spanish, or other European languages.
When memorizing the sounds of a character, try to forget your native
language, and think phonetically, rather than in your native alphabet.
**Note:** As mentioned earlier, it is important not to rush yourself.
The more you try to learn in one go, the easier it is for you to forget.
## See also
- How to Learn a Language
- Lang Infinity; Write in Japanese, or any
language, and get your entries critiqued by natives.
|
# Japanese/Practical Lessons
## Lesson Plan
A Syllabus exists for
this lesson plan.
### Lesson Structure
Each lesson *should* have the following sections specified:
1. **Lesson:** Lesson name.
1. **Function:** One or more functions, appropriate to the stage of
learning, chosen from the
Syllabus.
2. **Topic:** A topic, appropriate to the stage of learning, chosen
from the
Syllabus.
3. **Vocabulary:** Number of new words covered in the lesson,
chosen from the
Syllabus.
4. **Kanji:** Number of new Kanji covered in the lesson, chosen
from the
Syllabus.
5. **Grammar:** One or more grammar topics covered in lesson,
chosen from the
Syllabus.
### Stage I Lessons
#### Reading and Writing Hiragana
1. **Lesson:** Hiragana
overview
1. Voiced Consonants
2. Long vowel sounds
3. Consonant doubling: small つ
4. small や、ゆ、よ
2. **Lesson:** Hiragana
vowels
1. あいうえお
2. Long vowel sounds
3. **Lesson:** Hiragana k
row
1. かきくけこ
2. Voiced Consonants
3. がぎぐげご
4. **Lesson:** Hiragana s
row
1. さしすせそ
2. ざじずぜぞ
5. **Lesson:** Hiragana t
row
1. たちつてと
2. だぢづでど
3. Consonant doubling: small つ
6. **Lesson:** Hiragana n
row
1. なにぬねの
7. **Lesson:** Hiragana h
row
1. はひふへほ
2. ばびぶべぼ
3. ぱぴぷぺぽ
8. **Lesson:** Hiragana m
row
1. まみむめも
9. **Lesson:** Hiragana y
row
1. や、ゆ、よ
2. small や、ゆ、よ
10. **Lesson:** Hiragana r
row
1. らりるれろ
11. **Lesson:** Hiragana wa, wo,
n
1. わをん
12. **Lesson:** Historical
Hiragana
1. ゐゑ
#### Reading and Writing Katakana
1. **Lesson:** Katakana
overview
1. Voiced Consonants
2. Long vowel sounds
3. Consonant doubling: small つ
4. small ヤユヨ
2. **Lesson:** Katakana
vowels
1. アイウエオ
2. Long vowel sounds
3. small アイウエオ
3. **Lesson:** Katakana k
row
1. カキクケコ
2. ガギグゲゴ
4. **Lesson:** Katakana s
row
1. サシスセソ
2. ザジズゼゾ
5. **Lesson:** Katakana t
row
1. タチツテト
2. ダヂヅデド
6. **Lesson:** Katakana n
row
1. ナニヌネノ
7. **Lesson:** Katakana h
row
1. ハヒフヘホ
2. バビブベボ
3. パピプペポ
8. **Lesson:** Katakana m
row
1. マミムメモ
9. **Lesson:** Katakana y
row
1. ヤユヨ
2. small ヤユヨ
10. **Lesson:** Katakana r
row
1. ラリルレロ
11. **Lesson:** Katakana wa, wo,
n
1. ワヲン
12. **Lesson:** Historical
Katakana
1. ヰヱ
13. **Lesson:** Differences between Katakana and English
#### Dialogue Lessons
1. **Lesson:** Will you be my
friend?
1. **Topic:** Friends
2. **Function:** Greet and respond to greetings
1. \"Good morning/afternoon/evening.\" (Goodstuff:
Unnecessary?)
2. \"How are you?\" (Goodstuff: Unnecessary?)
3. **Function:** Introduce and respond to introductions
1. \"Nice to meet you.\" (Goodstuff: Unnecessary?)
4. **Vocabulary:** 20 Words
5. **Kanji:** 10 Kanji
6. **Grammar:** (Goodstuff: grammar topic chosen from syllabus,
need help here!)
1. The declarative 「だ」
2. The copula 「です」
1. Negative Tense
3. The question marker 「か」
4. Introduction to particles
1. Topic Particle 「は」
2. Inclusive Topic Particle 「は」
2. **Lesson:** Hobbies
1. **Topic:** Hobbies
2. **Function:** Express like and dislike
1. \"What are your hobbies?\"
2. \"What kind of \[noun\] do you like?\"
3. **Vocabulary:** 25 Words
4. **Kanji:** 10 Kanji
5. **Grammar:** (Goodstuff: grammar topic chosen from syllabus,
need help here!)
1. Na-adjectives and i-adjectives
1. Negative Tense
2. Identifier Particle 「が」
3. **Lesson:** Sports
1. **Topic:** sport
2. **Function:** expressing action
3. **Vocabulary:** 20 Words
4. **Kanji:** 10 Kanji
1. 音読み and 訓読み
2. Stroke Orders
5. **Grammar**
1. Ru-verbs(一段動詞)/u-verbs(五段動詞)/exception verbs
1. Negative Verbs Tenses
2. Polite conjugations (~ます)
2. Object Particle 「を」
3. Target Particle 「に」
4. Directional Particle 「へ」
5. Context Particle 「で」
6. Specifying Time and Date
1. Numbers and Counters
7. Using 「から」 and 「まで」
4. **Lesson:** I\'m a Cat
Person
1. **Topic:** Pets and Animals
2. **Function:** Expressing Ownership
1. \"Whose cat is this?\"
2. \"This is my cat\"
3. **Grammar**
1. The 「の」 particle
1. Nominalizing subordinate clauses (のが/のは)
2. Numbers and Counters
5. **Lesson:** Not
Today
1. **Topic:** health
2. **Function:** obtain information, begin to provide information
1. \"What did you do yesterday?\"
2. \"I didn\'t feel good last night.\"
3. **Grammar**
1. Past tense conjugations
1. Nouns/Adjectives
2. Verbs
|
# Japanese/Pronunciation
Japanese is characterised largely by its small number of vowels and
consonants (five and fourteen, respectively). Pronunciation of each
syllable is highly regular with the written system and there are only a
few exceptions such as vowel devoicing. This is in stark contrast to
English where the written and spoken language can differ a great deal
(e.g. the vowel digraph \"ou\" in \"noun\" and \"cough\" and the
consonant \"g\" in \"goat\" and \"giraffe\").
Apart from a single isolated consonant (the moraic nasal, \"n\") and
double consonants (e.g. \"i**tt**e\" and \"ke**kk**on\") all consonants
must be followed by a vowel to form syllables. Double consonants are
always a pair of the same consonant, though vowel devoicing sometimes
makes different consonants sound one after the other (e.g.
\"**s**u**ki**\" and \"**s**u**teki**\").
Japanese has a great deal of homophones that make correct pronunciation
quite important. While language learners may have difficulty hearing the
difference between nuances like long and short vowels, native speakers
are used to these and might not understand incorrectly pronounced words.
## The syllabary
There are five vowels in Japanese, normally transcribed into the English
alphabet as: \"a\", \"i\", \"u\", \"e\" and \"o\".
+----------+----------+----------+----------+----------+----------+
| Vowel | **a** | **i** | ```{=me | **e** | ```{=me |
| | | | diawiki} | | diawiki} |
| | | | {{ | | {{ |
| | | | Audio|Ja | | Audio|Ja |
| | | | -U.oga|' | | -O.oga|' |
| | | | ''u'''|h | | ''o'''|h |
| | | | elp=no}} | | elp=no}} |
| | | | ``` | | ``` |
| | | | \* | | |
+==========+==========+==========+==========+==========+==========+
| App | f | meat`<u> | f`<u> | `<u>`{ | `<u>`{ |
| roximate | `<u>`{=h | `{=html} | `{=html} | =html}*e | =html}*o |
| sound | tml}*a*` | *y*`</u> | oo`</u>` | *`</u>`{ | *`</u>`{ |
| | </u>`{=h | `{=html} | {=html}d | =html}gg | =html}ld |
| | tml}ther | | | | |
+----------+----------+----------+----------+----------+----------+
\*This sound is pronounced
compressed, for
which there is no approximation in English. See:
<http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Close_back_rounded_vowel#Close_back_compressed_vowel>
Spanish and Italian speakers may note that Japanese vowels produce the
same sounds as their Spanish and Italian equivalents.
Japanese vowels always represent distinct phonemes and don\'t form
digraphs --- i.e. they don\'t blend together or sound differently when
joined. When one vowel follows another they are pronounced separately.
Examples are the names *Sae* (sa.e) and *Aoi* (a.o.i)
The rest of the syllabary is formed by combining the above vowels with a
consonant.
<table>
<thead>
<tr class="header">
<th><p>Clear</p></th>
<th><p> </p></th>
<th><p>Voiced</p></th>
<th><p> </p></th>
<th><p>Plosive</p></th>
<th><p> </p></th>
<th><p>Clear medial y</p></th>
<th><p> </p></th>
<th><p>Voiced medial y</p></th>
<th><p> </p></th>
<th><p>Plosive medial y</p></th>
</tr>
</thead>
<tbody>
<tr class="odd">
<td><p> </p></td>
<td><p>a</p></td>
<td><p>i</p></td>
<td><p>u</p></td>
<td><p>e</p></td>
<td><p>o</p></td>
<td><p> </p></td>
<td><p>a</p></td>
<td><p>i</p></td>
<td><p>u</p></td>
<td><p>e</p></td>
</tr>
<tr class="even">
<td><p>k</p></td>
<td><p>ka</p></td>
<td><p>ki</p></td>
<td><p>ku</p></td>
<td><p>ke</p></td>
<td><p>ko</p></td>
<td><p>g</p></td>
<td><p>ga</p></td>
<td><p>gi</p></td>
<td><p>gu</p></td>
<td><p>ge</p></td>
</tr>
<tr class="odd">
<td><p>s</p></td>
<td><p>sa</p></td>
<td></td>
<td><p>su</p></td>
<td><p>se</p></td>
<td><p>so</p></td>
<td><p>z</p></td>
<td><p>za</p></td>
<td><p><strong>ji</strong></p></td>
<td><p>zu</p></td>
<td><p>ze</p></td>
</tr>
<tr class="even">
<td><p>t</p></td>
<td><p>ta</p></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td><p>te</p></td>
<td><p>to</p></td>
<td><p>d</p></td>
<td><p>da</p></td>
<td><p><strong>ji</strong></p></td>
<td><p><strong>zu</strong></p></td>
<td><p>de</p></td>
</tr>
<tr class="odd">
<td><p>n</p></td>
<td><p>na</p></td>
<td></td>
<td><p>nu</p></td>
<td><p>ne</p></td>
<td><p>no</p></td>
<td><p> </p></td>
<td><p>ni</p></td>
<td><p>nya</p></td>
<td><p>nyu</p></td>
<td><p>nyo</p></td>
</tr>
<tr class="even">
<td><p>h</p></td>
<td><p>ha</p></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td><p>he</p></td>
<td><p>ho</p></td>
<td><p>b</p></td>
<td><p>ba</p></td>
<td><p>bi</p></td>
<td><p>bu</p></td>
<td><p>be</p></td>
</tr>
<tr class="odd">
<td><p>m</p></td>
<td><p>ma</p></td>
<td><p>mi</p></td>
<td><p>mu</p></td>
<td><p>me</p></td>
<td><p>mo</p></td>
<td><p> </p></td>
<td><p> </p></td>
<td><p>mi</p></td>
<td><p>mya</p></td>
<td><p>myu</p></td>
</tr>
<tr class="even">
<td><p>y</p></td>
<td><p>ya</p></td>
<td></td>
<td><p>yu</p></td>
<td></td>
<td><p>yo</p></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
</tr>
<tr class="odd">
<td><p>r</p></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td><p>ri</p></td>
<td><p>rya</p></td>
<td><p>ryu</p></td>
<td><p>ryo</p></td>
<td></td>
</tr>
<tr class="even">
<td><p>w</p></td>
<td><p>wa</p></td>
<td></td>
<td><p><strong>o</strong></p></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
<td></td>
</tr>
</tbody>
</table>
Note that the sound which is written with a \"y\" is not considered a
vowel, but a consonant. This will come as little surprise to German
speakers where the same sound is written with a \"j\".
The -i line (ki, gi, shi, ji, chi, ni, hi, bi, pi, mi, ri) can be
combined with the y- line (ya, yu, yo) to create the *medial y*
combinations. These are just like regular consonant + vowel syllables,
in that they should be pronounced as one mora (syllabic sound).
```{=html}
<div style="border: 2px solid #fd9;">
```
From this table one can see that the Japanese syllabary is highly
systematic. There are a few exceptions, though, and these have been
bolded in the table:
- \"si\" becomes \"**shi**\"
- \"ti\" becomes \"**chi**\" and \"tu\" becomes \"**tsu**\"
- \"zi\" and \"di\" become \"**ji**\", and \"du\" becomes \"**zu**\"
- \"hu\" becomes \"**fu**\"
- \"wo\" becomes \"**o**\"
```{=html}
</div>
```
## Mora
Japanese is quite regular in the timing and stress of its syllables. The
basic timing unit is called mora. Each mora is pronounced with equal
stress and should take about the same amount of time. Two morae should
sound twice as long as a single one.
The following take up one mora:
- a short vowel
- a consonant followed by a short vowel
- a medial y
- a moraic nasal
Whereas these take up two morae:
- a long vowel
- a double consonant
### Examples
- *a-o-i* / あおい (*e.* blue): three morae, each vowel is short
- *mi-do-ri* / みどり (*e.* green): three morae.
- *sha-shu* / しゃしゅ (*e.* car model): two morae.
- *ni-n-ji-n* / にんじん (*e.* a carrot): four morae.
- *ī-e* / いいえ (*e.* no): three morae (note the long vowel \"i\",
denoted by a macron)
- *a-k-ka* / あっか (*e.* to worsen): three morae (note that the
double consonant isn\'t pronounced twice, just twice as long).
The medial y often takes a long vowel.
- *gyūnyū* / ぎゅうにゅう (*e.* milk): four morae.
## Long vowels
A long vowel takes two morae. In rōmaji it\'s written with a macron: *ā,
ī, ū, ē and ō*.
In hiragana, it\'s written with an extra
\"あ\" (a), \"い\" (i) or \"う\" (u) depending on the vowel. In
katakana, it\'s marked by appending a
dash-like symbol \"ー\".
+----------+----------+------------+--------------------------------+
| Word | Japanese | Meaning | Soundbyte |
+==========+==========+============+================================+
| *Ōsaka* | 大阪 | Osaka city | There are a couple of consonants that are pronounced differently from
English:
Consonant Approximate sound Notes
----------- -------------------------------------------------------------------- ----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
g _*g*_ive or si_*ng*_ approximately halfway between these sounds, it is made almost like *ng* depending on the age of the speaker and, in certain cases, dialect. Nowadays, it is beginning to sound more like our guttural g, but the older folks may still say *ng*, which was also taught in many Japanese grammar classes.
sh, ch, j sound is made further back along the tongue than in English
ts ba_*ts*_ try saying \"fatso\" without the \"fa\"
f _*wh*_o (in British English) blown between the lips, not between the lips and teeth; as if it were a combination of both H+F
r similar to a rolling *r*, but only trilled once making it sound deceptively like a *D* to untrained listeners. The sound is often described as being between \"r\" and \"l\".
Except for the doubled consonants and the *n* (which we will cover
later), consonants can never end a syllable. They can only begin it.
## Moraic nasal
Normally, Japanese consonants must be followed by a vowel except where
they double. There is an exception to this: the *moraic nasal* which is
transliterated as n. It is usually found at the end of words, but can be
found in the middle of composite words.
The difference between the moraic nasal and the syllables \"na\",
\"ni\", \"nu\", \"ne\" and \"no\" can be difficult for language learners
to spot, while native speakers may have difficulty understanding
incorrect pronunciation.
- *kin\'en* (*ki-n-e-n*) no smoking vs. *kinen* (*ki-ne-n*)
commemoration.
- *hon\'ya* (*ho-n-ya-*) bookstore (not *ho-nya*)
The pronunciation of the moraic nasal changes depending on what sound
follows it. This is not so much an irregularity as a shortcut to bridge
the sounds between the two morae. When followed by the bilabial
plosives, \"b\" and \"p\", the moraic nasal is pronounced like an \"m\".
An example:
- \"shinbun\" is read as: *shi**m**bun*
(OggVorbis, 151 KB)
1. At the end of a word:
- *dan* 段 \"level\"
- *kin* 金 \"gold\"
- *fun* 糞 \"dung\"
- *zen* 善 \"goodness\"
- *hon* 本 \"book\"
2. Directly before a consonant:
- *banzai* 万歳 \"hurrah\", \"long live (the Emperor)\"
- *kingyo* 金魚 \"goldfish\" (pronounced like \"ng\")
- *kunrei* 訓令 \"directive\"
- *zenchi* 全知 \"omniscience\" (pronounced like \"n\")
- *honten* 本店 \"main office\" (pronounced like \"n\")
3. Before *m*, *b*, *p*
- *genmai* 玄米 \"unmilled rice\"
- *honbu* 本部 \"headquarters\"
- *tenpura* 天ぷら (battered and fried vegetables or fish)
4. Before *a*, *i*, *e*, *y*
- *zen\'aku* 善悪 \"good and evil\"
- *ken\'i* 権威 \"authority\"
- *han\'ei* 反映 \"reflection\"
- *sen\'you* 専用 \"exclusive use\"
5. Note that before *a*, *i*, *e*, and *y*, moraic n is written *n*\'
(with an apostrophe). This is to distinguish it from the regular
consonant *n*, which is pronounced differently and can produce
different words. Some examples of cases where this becomes important
are:
- *kani* 蟹 \"crab\" **vs.** *kan\'i* 簡易 \"simplicity\"
- *kinyuu* 記入 \"fill in\" **vs.** *kin\'yuu* 金融 \"finances\"
- *konyakku* コニャック \"cognac\" **vs.** *kon\'yaku* 婚約
\"engagement (to be married)\"
## Consonant doubling (gemination)
There are four consonants that can become geminates (get doubled) in
native Japanese words: /p/, /t/, /k/, and /s/. The geminate (represented
linguistically as \"Q\") takes up an extra mora, with the general effect
being to insert a pause that sounds as long as a regular syllable with a
short vowel. The geminate is /t/ before ch and ts, /s/ before sh.
+--------------+---------------------+---------------------------------------+
| Word | Meaning | Soundbyte |
+==============+=====================+=======================================+
| ta**kk**yū | table tennis | (OggVorbis, 75 KB)
Word Japanese Meaning
------------- ---------- ------------------------------------------------
akai 赤 red
*iro* 色 color
*egaku* 描く draw (a picture)
*utsu* 打つ hit, beat
*osameru* 治める govern
*oya* 親 parent(s)
*wabi* 侘び (the Japanese aesthetic of subdued refinement)
*pari* パリ Paris (France)
*tomodach*i 友達 friend
*hana* 花 flower
*shiji* 指示 instruction
*hiza* 膝 knee
*tsumori* 積もり intention
### Long and double vowels
(OggVorbis, 125 KB) Note in particular that \"deiri\" and \"koushi\" are
not long vowels since the vowels are split between composite words.
Word Japanese Meaning
------------------------ ---------- ------------------
*sā* さあ come now
*ai* 愛 love
*au* 会う meet
*hae* 蠅 fly (insect)
*aoi* 青い blue, green
*ī* いい good
*iu* 言う say
*ie* 家 house
*shio* 塩 salt
*shurui* 種類 type, kind
*nū* 縫う sew
*ue* 上 above
*uo* 魚 fish
*rē* 例 example
*supein* スペイン Spain
*urei* 憂い grief
*deiri* (*de* + *iri*) 出入り coming and going
*dēta* データ data
*oi* 甥 nephew
*sō* そう that way, so
*omou* 思う think
*koushi* 仔牛 calf (baby cow)
*moeru* 燃える burn
*hō* 頬 cheek (facial)
### Compound consonants
Audio missing
Word Japanese Meaning
------------ ---------- ----------------------------------
*toukyou* 東京 Tokyo
*gyouza* 餃子 pot-stickers (Chinese dumplings)
*gyuunyuu* 牛乳 milk (from a cow)
*hyou* 表 chart
*byouin* 病院 hospital
*denpyou* 伝票 voucher
*myou* 妙 strange
*muryou* 無料 free (as in beer)
*ryuu* 龍 dragon
*takkyuu* 卓球 table tennis
*happyou* 発表 announcement
### Moraic nasal
- (OggVorbis, 91 KB)
Word Japanese Meaning
------------ ---------- ------------------------------
*tenki* 天気 weather
*renshuu* 練習 practice
*zangyou* 残業 overtime (work)
*anshin* 安心 relief
*sunnari* すんなり slender
*denpa* 電波 reception (cell phone, etc.)
*senbei* 煎餅 Japanese hard rice cake
*genmai* 玄米 unprocessed rice
*sen* 千 thousand
*hon* 本 book
*sen\'you* 専用 exclusive use
*hon\'ya* 本屋 bookstore
*san\'en* 三円 three yen
*tan\'i* 単位 unit, (course) credit
### Comparisons of similarly pronounced words
(OggVorbis, 190 KB)
1. *yuki* 雪 \"snow\" and *yuuki* 勇気 \"courage\"
2. *soto* 外 \"outside\" and *souto* 僧徒 \"Buddhist disciple\"
3. *soto* 外 \"outside\" and *sotou* 粗糖 \"unrefined sugar\"
4. *soto* 外 \"outside\" and *soutou* 相当 \"suitable\"
5. *soto* 外 \"outside\" and *sotto* そっと \"softly\"
6. *sotto* そっと \"softly\" and *sottou* 卒倒 \"fainting\"
7. *maki* 巻 \"scroll\" and *makki* 末期 \"last period\"
8. *hako* 箱 \"box\" and *hakkou* 発行 \"publish\"
9. *issei* 一斉 \"all at once\" and *isei* 異性 \"opposite sex\"
10. *tani* 谷 \"valley\" and *tan\'i* 単位 \"unit\", \"(course) credit\"
11. *san\'en* 三円 \"three yen\" and *sannen* 三年 \"three years\"
12. *kinyuu* 記入 \"fill out\" and *kin\'yuu* 金融 \"finances\"
13. *kinen* 記念 \"commemoration\" and *kin\'en* 禁煙 \"no smoking\"
### Normal speech
The narration of the following excerpt of Natsume
Soseki\'s classic novel
*Botchan* is spoken at a
natural pace which may be difficult to follow for unaccustomed
listeners.
- (OggVorbis, 674KB)
: *Oyayuzuri no muteppou de kodomo no toki kara son bakari shite iru.
Shougakkou ni iru jibun gakkou no nikai kara tobiorite isshuukan
hodo koshi o nukashita koto ga aru. Naze sonna muyami o shita to
kiku hito ga aru kamoshirenu. Betsudan fukai riyuu demo nai.
Shinchiku no nikai kara kubi o dashite itara, doukyuusei no hitori
ga joudan ni, \"Ikura ibatte mo, soko kara tobioriru koto wa
dekimai. Yowamushi yaai,\" to hayakashita kara de aru. Kozukai ni
obusatte kaette kita toki, oyaji ga ookina me o shite \"Nikai gurai
kara tobiorite koshi o nukasu yatsu ga aru ka,\" to itta kara,
\"Kono tsugi wa nukasazu ni tonde misemasu,\" to kotaeta.*
```{=html}
<!-- -->
```
: *Shinrui no mono kara seiyousei no naifu o moratte kirei na ha o hi
ni kazashite, tomodachi ni misete itara, hitori ga \"Hikaru koto wa
hikaru ga, kiresou mo nai,\" to itta. \"Kirenu koto ga aru ka,
nandemo kitte miseru,\" to ukeatta. \"Sonnara, kimi no yubi o kitte
miro,\" to chuumon shita kara, \"Nan da yubi gurai kono toori da,\"
to migi no te no oyayubi no kou o hasu ni kirikonda. Saiwai naifu ga
chiisai no to, oyayubi no hone ga katakatta node, imadani oyayubi wa
te ni tsuite iru. Shikashi kizuato wa shinu made kienu.*
|
# Japanese/Pitch accent
Japanese uses **pitch accent**, where every mora can either be
pronounced with a high or low pitch. Not all dictionaries will indicate
this, but pitch accent is certainly important, because it can make the
difference between different words.
For example, using **bold** for high pitches:
**い**ま (今) - \"now\"\
い**ま** (居間) - \"living room\"
Pitch is, however, to some extent a characteristic of regional accents,
so a Kanto speaker may be using the opposite pitches to a Kansai
speaker. Where pitch is taught, it will be standard Japanese
(essentially the Tokyo dialect). Pitchless Japanese is easily understood
by native speakers and incorrect pitch will at most sound somewhat odd.
Studying pitch, therefore, isn\'t essential to the learning Japanese and
is perhaps best picked up by conversing with native speakers.
Linguists, however, tend to classify Japanese as having a falling pitch
following what is considered the stressed vowel.
## Mora Counting
A common misconception is that moras in Japanese are the same as
syllables in English. Moras differ from syllables because of how they
are counted.
Consonant-Vowel Combinations written as Digraphs count as 1 mora. These
are cases where you have き、ぎ、し、じ、ち、に、ひ、び、ぴ、み、り
combined with や、ゆ、and よ to form Digraphs like きゃ, しゅ, ちょ,
etc.
So, the **ちゅ** in 中国\[**ちゅ**うごく\] accounts for **1 mora**. The
whole word is 4 moras.
A vowel combination counts as 2 moras. Combinations like おう、えい are
2 moras. This also includes a vowel being written or said twice, like
おお、いい, etc.
Ex. the **せい** in the word 人生\[じん**せい**\] or the おう in だろう
would count as **2 moras**.
The mora **ん** counts as **1 mora**
Ex. The **ん** in 先生\[せんせい\] is the 2nd mora in the word, and the
whole word has 4 moras.
The small tsu (**っ**) which doubles a consonant adds **1 mora**.
Ex. the word 学校(がっこう) has 4 moras.
There is a unique set of mora known as \"special mora\" (特殊拍) which
consist of small tsu \"っ\", the kana \"ん\" and long vowel symbol
\"ー\", the last high pitch can not occur on any of these \"special
mora\".
This is all important information to know when reading pitch accent, and
counting Japanese moras.
## Pitch classification
When dictionaries give pitch accent, they\'ll usually indicate it with a
number. The number tells you the mora where the **last high pitch** is.
To figure out the pitch pattern, put a low onto the first mora (unless
the last high pitch is on that mora), put high pitches onto all the mora
that follows, until you hit the last high pitch. After that, put low
pitches.
Even more helpful dictionaries will do all of this work for you, by
telling you exactly where all the pitches rise or fall.
So, to give some examples.
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| `<span style="font-weight: normal">`{=html}low`</span>`{=html} |
| **HIGH HIGH\...** |
| |
| ```{=html} |
| <div style="float: left"> |
| ``` |
| \(0\) |
| |
| ```{=html} |
| </div> |
| ``` |
+======================================================================+
| こ**ども** |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| わ**たし** |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| と**もだち** |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| ざ**っし** |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| あ**かい** |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| が**っこう** |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| **HIGH** `<span style="font-weight: normal">`{=html}low |
| low\...`</span>`{=html} |
| |
| ```{=html} |
| <div style="float: left"> |
| ``` |
| \(1\) |
| |
| ```{=html} |
| </div> |
| ``` |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| **ちゅ**うごく |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| **じ**しょ |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| **な**に |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| **は**し |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| **パン**フレット |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| `<span style="font-weight: normal">`{=html}low`</span>`{=html} |
| **HIGH** `<span style="font-weight: normal">`{=html}low |
| low\...`</span>`{=html} |
| |
| ```{=html} |
| <div style="float: left"> |
| ``` |
| \(2\) |
| |
| ```{=html} |
| </div> |
| ``` |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| こ**こ**ろ |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| じ**て**んしゃ |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| プ**レ**ゼント |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| `<span style="font-weight: normal">`{=html}low`</span>`{=html} |
| **HIGH HIGH** `<span style="font-weight: normal">`{=html}low |
| low\...`</span>`{=html} |
| |
| ```{=html} |
| <div style="float: left"> |
| ``` |
| \(3\) |
| |
| ```{=html} |
| </div> |
| ``` |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| せ**んせ**い |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| お**おき**い |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| た**くさ**ん |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| `<span style="font-weight: normal">`{=html}low`</span>`{=html} |
| **HIGH HIGH HIGH** `<span style="font-weight: normal">`{=html}low |
| low\...`</span>`{=html} |
| |
| ```{=html} |
| <div style="float: left"> |
| ``` |
| \(4\) |
| |
| ```{=html} |
| </div> |
| ``` |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| あ**たらし**い |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| う**つくし**い |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| お**とうと** |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
| |
+----------------------------------------------------------------------+
Notice how と**もだち** (0) and お**とうと** (4) look as though they
have the same pitch pattern despite the different numbers. The
difference is based on the grammatical pattern like -は added afterward.
Therefore, the continuation of both pitch pattern becomes と**もだちは**
and お**とうと**は.
|