text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
C3. You logically should choose the Christian kind of life and believe in |
God ( modus ponens , C2, P4). |
6 |
James β Will to Believe Argument |
A. T. Fyfe |
William James (1842 β 1910), in his 1896 lecture, β The Will to Believe, β |
gave an argument for holding onto religious belief even in the face of insuffi |
cient evidence that is second in prominence only to Pascal β s Wager (#5). |
James β stated target in his lecture is W. K. Clifford (1845 β 79), a philosopher |
who had recently argued in his β The Ethics of Belief β that β It is wrong |
always, everywhere and for everyone to believe anything upon insuffi cient |
evidence. β James β strategy in β The Will to Believe β is fi rst to identify what |
he thought would be a point of agreement with Clifford; specifi cally, that |
our two fundamental duties as believers are to believe truth and avoid falsehood. |
James then goes on to agree partially with Clifford that at least |
ordinarily, when someone believes upon insuffi cient evidence, he is irrational. |
This is because while believing upon insuffi cient evidence does con- |
James , William. The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy . |
New York : Dover , 1956 . |
Welchman , Jennifer. β William James β s β The Will to Believe β and the Ethics of |
Self - Experimentation . β Transactions of the Charles S. Pierce Society 42 , |
2 (Spring 2006 ): 229 β 41 . |
Wernham , James C. S. James β Will - to - Believe Doctrine: A Heretical View . |
Montreal : McGill - Queen β s University Press , 1987 . |
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, |
First Edition. Edited by Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone. |
Β© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Published 2011 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd. |
Jamesβ Will to Believe Argument 33 |
tribute to the pursuit of true belief (since the belief might be true), when |
someone believes upon insuffi cient evidence, he is usually violating his duty |
to avoid false belief (since he didn β t wait for suffi cient evidence before |
believing). |
Where James disagrees with Clifford is on whether believing upon insuffi |
cient evidence always involves violating our duty to avoid false belief. |
Specifi cally, James argues that there exist beliefs for which the evidence of |
their truth (if they were true) would only become available after we believed |
them and, therefore, waiting to believe until we had suffi cient evidence |
would be a self - defeating wait. To illustrate with an example, suppose that |
you have just fi nished medical school and that you are trying to decide |
whether to join a research team working to discover a cure for cancer. Now, |
to make such a substantial commitment to the search for a cure, James |
would argue that you must believe that a cure exists to be found. That is, |
you β d be fooling yourself if you thought you could make such a momentous |
career choice while continuing to suspend belief about the existence of the |
cure you β re looking for. At the very least, most people would need such a |
belief to sustain them during the times in which their research was going |
poorly. That being said, suffi cient evidence that such a cure exists won β t be |
available until well into the search for one. Therefore, a belief in the existence |
of a cure for cancer is a belief for which the evidence of its truth (if it |
is true) only becomes available after we believe a cure exists. |
Similar to a cancer researcher β s belief in the existence of a cure, James |
holds that religious belief is required before evidence of its truth (if it is |
true) can become available. While this would seem to justify religious belief |
only for those who make a career of religious research, James argues that |
religious belief is justifi ed even for ordinary believers in virtue of the peculiar |
way its evidence depends upon their belief. In the preface to the published |
version of his β The Will to Believe β lecture, James fi lls in this last step of |
his argument: |
If religious hypotheses about the universe be in order at all, then the active |
faiths of individuals in them, freely expressing themselves in life, are the |
experimental tests by which they are verifi ed, and the only means by which |
their truth or falsehood can be wrought out. The truest scientifi c hypothesis |
is that which, as we say, β works β best; and it can be no otherwise with religious |
hypotheses. Religious history proves that one hypothesis after another has |
worked ill, has crumbled at contact with a widening knowledge of the world, |
and has lapsed from the minds of men. Some articles of faith, however, have |
maintained themselves through every vicissitude, and possess even more vitality |
to - day than ever before [ β¦ ]. [T]he freest competition of the various faiths |
with one another, and their openest application to life by their several champions, |
are the most favorable conditions under which the survival of the fi ttest |
can proceed. (XII) |
34 A. T. Fyfe |
P1. It is not rational to have religious belief without suffi cient evidence if |
and only if having religious belief without suffi cient evidence violates our |
duty to avoid false belief. |
P2. Having religious belief without suffi cient evidence violates our duty to |
avoid false belief if and only if I could withhold religious belief for the |
purpose of waiting until I had suffi cient evidence. |
C1. If it is not rational to have religious belief without suffi cient evidence, |
then having religious belief without suffi cient evidence violates our |
duty to avoid false belief (equivalence, simplifi cation, P1). |
C2. If having religious belief without suffi cient evidence violates our duty |
to avoid false belief, then I could withhold religious belief for the |
purpose of waiting until I had suffi cient evidence (equivalence, simplifi |
cation, P2). |
C3. If it is not rational to have religious belief without suffi cient evidence, |
then I could withhold religious belief for the purpose of waiting until |
I had suffi cient evidence (hypothetical syllogism, C1, C2). |
P3. Access to the evidence for religious belief requires already having religious |
belief. |
P4. If access to the evidence for religious belief requires already having |
religious belief, then I cannot withhold belief for the purpose of waiting |
until I had suffi cient evidence. |
C4. I cannot withhold religious belief for the purpose of waiting until I |
had suffi cient evidence ( modus ponens , P3, P4). |
C5. It is rational to have religious belief without suffi cient evidence |
( modus tollens , C3, C4). |
7 |
The Problem of Evil |
Michael Bruce and Steven Barbone |
Subsets and Splits