text
stringlengths
0
1.71k
otherwise, so long as the probability of God ’ s existence is greater than 0.
It is foolish not to lead the Christian life.
Parts of the wager argument – whether in Pascal ’ s own version or this
modern one – are best presented using a device called a β€œ decision table ”
(below). The words at the top of each column describe a possible state of
the world or universe. There are just two, and each one has some chance
or probability of being the truth. We can ’ t eliminate either, according to
Pascal. Each box tells the result you get if the state named in the column
is true and you make the choice in the row. So, for example, the result for
you if the Christian God exists and you lead the Christian life and believe
this God exists is a gain or benefi t of all – in Pascal ’ s words – or infi nite
positive value – in the words of the modern argument – and a loss of either
nothing – which seems to be what Pascal thinks – or something very small,
some worldly pleasure – as the modern argument has it. Pascal doesn ’ t
explicitly tell us what goes into some of the boxes. For example, he doesn ’ t
say what the results for you are if the Christian God exists but you don ’ t
believe this. The modern statement of the wager fi lls this in for us.
The third and fourth premises of the argument below are implicit or
hidden. This argument is certainly deductively valid once these hidden
premises are added. Each simple step in the reasoning in the argument is
truth - functionally valid. So any criticism of the argument must tell us that
one or more of the premises are false. Here are some examples of
criticisms:
(a) The fi rst premise says that anyone who leads the Christian life and
believes, no matter why he does this, gets the benefi t. That ’ s what is
in Table 1 and the fi rst premise tells us that everything in the table is
true. But it ’ s false. The Christian God would not reward someone who
believes or leads the life of a believer solely in order to gain the benefi t
of infi nite happiness.
(b) According to the reasoning, the table completely describes the possible
states of the world and says what will result in each of these states if
you do believe and lead an appropriate life or you don ’ t believe and
do not lead the Christian life. But is that correct? Suppose, when the
Christian God doesn ’ t exist, it is also true that another type of god
does. This god punishes severely those who believe in the Christian
God or lead a Christian life. This is a possibility; it is not ruled out by
logic any more than the existence of the Christian God is ruled in or
out by logic. If that happens, then what is said in Table 1 down column
2 aren ’ t certain results. They are merely one among many possible sets
of results. These are the results that would happen when the Christian
30 Leslie Burkholder
God doesn ’ t exist and no other god does either. What is said about
the state when the Christian God doesn ’ t exist also holds for when
that God does exist. Other kinds of gods could possibly exist as well,
even when the Christian God exists. The results listed in column 1 of
the table are only the ones that happen when the Christian God exists
and no other kind of god does. So either premise 1 is false because
what the table states is that the results are really only one of indefi nitely
many possible results, or premise 2 is false because the columns do
not cover all the possibilities. They only really cover the case when the
Christian God exists and no other does and the case when the Christian
God does not exist and no other does either.
(c) Suppose that there is no problem with either premise 1 or premise 2.
Then there is a problem with the implicit or hidden premise 3.
According to the table, the benefi t gained from believing in the case
when the Christian God exists is infi nitely positive and the loss from
not believing in this case is infi nitely negative. Using these facts and
the rest in the table, we are supposed to be able to calculate that we
are better off believing in the existence of the Christian God than not
believing. But there is no way to make sound calculations involving
infi nite gains and losses. So premise 3 may be false – or at least it is
very uncertain that it is true.
God is, or He is not. Reason can decide nothing here. [ . . . ] A game is
being played at the extremity of this infi nite distance where heads or tails will
turn up. [ . . . ] Which will you choose then? [ . . . ] Let us weigh the gain and
the loss in wagering that God is. [ . . . ] If you gain, you gain all; if you lose,
you lose nothing. Wager, then, without hesitation that He is. ( Β§ 233)
P1. The information in Table 1 is true.
P2. The information in Table 1 is complete.
C1. The information in Table 1 is true and the information in Table 1
is complete (conjunction, P1, P2).
Table 1
Christian God exists
(Prob > 0)
Christian God doesn ’ t
exist (Prob > 0)
Lead Christian life
and believe
Christian God exists
Gain = all, infi nite
good; loss = small
or nothing
Gain = nothing;
loss = small or nothing
Don ’ t lead Christian
life and believe
Christian God exists
Gain = nothing;
loss = all, infi nite bad
Gain = nothing;
loss = nothing
Pascal’s Wager 31
P3. If the information in Table 1 is true and the information in Table 1 is
complete, then you are better off having the life of a believer and believing
in the Christian God than not doing so.
C2. You are better off having the life of a believer and believing in the
Christian God than not doing so ( modus ponens , C1, P3).
P4. If you are better off having the life of a believer and believing in the
Christian God than not doing so, then you logically should choose the
Christian kind of life and believe in God.